1-s2.0-s0264999315002114-main

Upload: vieriu-alexandra

Post on 11-Feb-2018

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/23/2019 1-s2.0-S0264999315002114-main

    1/6

    Production and hedging decisions under regret aversion

    Xu Guo a, Wing-Keung Wong b, Qunfang Xu c,, Xuehu Zhu d

    a College of Economics and Management, Nanjing University of Aeronautics and Astronautics, Nanjing, Chinab Department of Economics, Hong Kong Baptist University, Hong Kongc Business School of Ningbo University, Ningbo, Chinad School of Mathematics and Statistics, Xi'an Jiaotong University, Xi'an, China

    a b s t r a c ta r t i c l e i n f o

    Article history:

    Accepted 8 August 2015Available online xxxx

    JEL classication:

    D21

    D24

    D81

    Keywords:

    Production

    Hedging

    Regret aversion

    Risk aversion

    Competitiverms

    In this paper, we investigate regret-averse rms' production and hedging behaviors. We rst show that the

    separation theorem is still alive under regret aversion by proving that regret aversion is independent of thelevel of optimal production. On the other hand, we nd that the full-hedging theorem does not always hold

    under regret aversion as the regret-averse rms take hedged positions different from those of risk-averse rms

    in some situations. With more regret aversion, regret-averse rms will hold smaller optimal hedging positions

    in an unbiased futures market. Furthermore, contrary to the conventional expectations, we show that banning

    rms from forward trading affects their production level in both directions.

    2015 Published by Elsevier B.V.

    1. Introduction

    Since the seminal work ofSandmo (1971),Holthausen (1979),Katz

    and Paroush (1979)and others, there has been much theoretical and

    empirical research on the economic behavior of the competitive rm

    under price risk. In classical economic theory under uncertainty, two

    main results are derived: the separation theorem and the full-hedging

    theorem. The separation theorem documents that for risk-averse

    rms, their risk attitude and the distribution of prices are independent

    of their optimal production decision. On the other hand, the full-

    hedging theorem tells us that if the futures price is unbiased, risk-

    averse rms take a fully hedged position to eliminate the risk of price

    uncertainty. For reference, seeBroll and Zilcha (1992),Adam-Mller(1997),Broll and Eckwert (1998, 2000), andLien (2000).

    In this paper,we extendthe theoryby examiningthe production and

    hedging behavior of a competitive rm under the premise that therm

    demonstrates both risk-averse behavior and regret-averse attitude. In

    recent years, there has been a growing literature on rm behavior that

    assumes not only risk aversion but also regret aversion. For example,

    ifrms' prices turn out to be very high and sales turn out to be very

    good, rms might regret not producing more. Conversely, if prices

    turn out to be low and sales are poor, rms might regret over-

    producing.Savage (1951)is the rst to propose that decision makers

    include regret in their decision-making processes. Bell (1982),

    Fishburn (1982), and Loomes and Sugden (1982, 1987) develop a

    formal analysis of regret theory, which is later extended bySugden

    (1993)andQuiggin (1994). Following the pioneering work ofSandmo

    (1971)on the optimal output of a risk-averse rm under price uncer-

    tainty, Paroush and Venezia (1979) rst assume that competitive

    rms have a regret-averse utility. Nonetheless,Braun and Muermann

    (2004)propose using a more specic regret-averse utility function

    that is easily managed.Egozcue and Wong (2012)andWong (2014)

    are therst to study the behavior of a competitive rm when price is

    unknown with the regret-averse utility introduced by Braun and

    Muermann.Niu et al. (2014)further examine the production decision

    of a competitiverm with a regret-averse utility. Broll et al. (2015)

    study the behavior of a regret-averse rm when the exchange rate is

    uncertain. There are other applications of regret aversion, for example,

    Economic Modelling 51 (2015) 153158

    The authors thankthe Editor, Professor PareshNarayan,the Associate Editor, Professor

    Niklas Wagner, and two anonymous referees for their constructive comments and

    suggestions, which help us clarify more precisely the results and lead to the substantialimprovement of an early manuscript. The authors are grateful to Professors Donald Lien,

    Agnar Sandmo, Robert I. Webb, and Kit Pong Wong for their valuable comments, which

    have signicantly improved this manuscript. The second author would like to thank

    Professors Robert B. Miller and Howard E. Thompson for their continual guidance and

    encouragement. This research is partially supported by the Fundamental Research Funds

    for the Central Universities (NR2015001), Hong Kong Baptist University (FRG2/14-15/

    106, FRG2/14-15/040), Research Grants Council of Hong Kong (Project Number

    12502814), Natural Science Foundation of Zhejiang Province (LY15A010006) Grants,

    Research Project of the National Statistics (2013LY119), and Ningbo University Talent

    Project (ZX2014000781).

    Corresponding author at: Business School of Ningbo University, China. Tel.: + 86 186

    0574 87600396.

    E-mail address:[email protected](Q. Xu).

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.econmod.2015.08.007

    0264-9993/ 2015 Published by Elsevier B.V.

    Contents lists available atScienceDirect

    Economic Modelling

    j o u r n a l h o m e p a g e : w w w . e l s e v i e r . c o m / l o c a t e / e c m o d

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.econmod.2015.08.007http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.econmod.2015.08.007http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.econmod.2015.08.007mailto:[email protected]://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.econmod.2015.08.007http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/02649993http://www.elsevier.com/locate/ecmodhttp://www.elsevier.com/locate/ecmodhttp://www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/02649993http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.econmod.2015.08.007mailto:[email protected]://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.econmod.2015.08.007http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1016/j.econmod.2015.08.007&domain=pdf
  • 7/23/2019 1-s2.0-S0264999315002114-main

    2/6

    the demandfor insurance(Wong, 2012), portfolio investment (Barberis

    et al., 2006; Muermann et al., 2006), auctions (Engelbrecht-Wiggans

    and Katok, 2008; Feliz-Ozbay and Ozbay, 2007), newsvendor model

    (Perakis and Roels, 2008), and banking issues (Tsai, 2012). To apply

    the regret theory tonance,Wagner (2002)derives a Markowitz-type

    model of portfolio choice with variable regret aversion. Readers may

    refer toBleichrodt and Wakker (2015)for a comprehensive review of

    the development of the regret theory.

    As discussed above, some authors extend the production theory ofthe risk-averserm to that of the regret-averse rm to investigate the

    optimal production decision without considering the presence of a

    futures market. On the other hand, some authors study the production

    and hedging behaviors of the risk-averserm. In addition,Michenaud

    and Solnik (2008) apply regret theory to get solutions to optimal

    currency hedging choices. As far as we know, there is no previous

    work that studies the production and hedging behaviors of the regret-

    averse rm. Nonetheless, it is of great interest to study the effect of

    regret aversion on the optimal production and hedging decisions

    when a futures market exists. For example, it would be interesting to

    know whether the two notable resultsthe separation and full-

    hedging theoremsare still valid ifrms are regret averse. Our paper

    provides a natural extension ofWong (2014) by adding the opportunity

    for regret-averserms to trade in futures contracts. This is in the same

    spirit as Holthausen (1979), who adds this opportunity to Sandmo

    (1971)for risk-averse rms.

    We rst examine whether the separation theorem still holds for the

    regret-averse rm. It is well known (Niu, et al., 2014; Wong, 2014) that

    under certain sufcient conditions and without hedging, the optimal

    output level is smaller under uncertainty than under certainty. When

    a futures market exists, we nd that regret aversion has no effect on

    the optimal production decision. To be precise, optimal output levels

    are the same for both risk-averse and regret-averse rms that will

    choose their optimal outputs when their marginal costs are equal to

    the futures price. These results imply that the separation theorem is

    still alive under regret aversion.

    Thereafter, we examine the full-hedging theorem for the regret-

    averse rm. We nd that sometimes both regret-averse and risk-

    averse competitive rms behave similarly, but, in other situations,they behave differently. For example, when the futures price is smaller

    than the expected price (contango market), both risk-averse and

    regret-aversermswill take under-hedgedpositions. When the expect-

    edprice and the futures price are the same (unbiased futures market),

    the risk-averse competitive rm will take a fully hedged position,

    while the regret-averse competitive rm will still take an under-

    hedged position. Furthermore, when the futures price is slightly higher

    than the expected price (backwardation futures market), risk-averse

    rms will take an over-hedged position, but regret-averse rms

    could take an under-hedged, a fully hedged, or an over-hedged

    position, depending on the degree of regret aversion. These results

    imply that under regret aversion, the full-hedging theorem does not

    hold.

    We conduct a comparative statics analysis and nd that withmore regret aversion, the optimal hedging position will become smaller

    in an unbiased futures market. Moreover, wend that the regret-averse

    rm optimally produces more or less in the absence than in the

    presence of a futures market. This result is different from the traditional

    wisdom that forward hedging always promotes production. The theory

    developed in our paper is not only useful for rms in managing their

    production levels and hedging positions, but it also aids rms' compet-

    itors, business partners, shareholders, and stock and bond investors in

    their investment decisions as well as assisting policy makers in their

    policy setting processes.

    InSection 2,we state the assumptions and the model setup for a

    competitiverm that is not only risk averse but also regret averse. In

    Section 3, we derive the theory to describe the production and hedging

    behaviors for regret-averse competitive rms and compare the results

    with those for risk-averse competitive rms. The nal section offers

    some discussions and conclusions.

    2. Assumptions and the model setup

    Suppose that a competitive rm producesQunits of a product at

    time 0 and will sell all units at time 1. We followBroll et al. (2006)

    andothers by assuming that theproduction cost, C(Q), is strictly convex,

    such thatC(0) =C

    (0) = 0,C

    ()N

    0 andC

    ()N

    0, to re

    ect the

    rm'sproduction technology to have decreasing returns to scale. The price, ~P,

    is random at time 1 with support on PP, such that 0 b Pb Pb . In ad-

    dition, there is a corresponding futures contract that matures at time 1

    with pricePf at time 0. We also assume that the producer wants to

    hedge against the risk that the price of his/her produced goods may

    drop so that he/she sellsX1 units of the product under the futures con-

    tract and he/she will deliverXunits of the product against the futures

    contract at time 1. Lettingbe the prot at time 1, we have

    ~ ~P QX PfXC Q : 2:1

    To address the notion of regret, we followBraun and Muermann

    (2004) and others by employing the following bivariate (two-attribute)

    regret-averse utility functionVto get the ex-post suboptimal decision:

    V ;max U gmax ; 2:2

    in which the rst term is the von NeumannMorgenstern utility

    function U to reect risk aversion satisfying U0 N0 and Ub 0. The

    second term takes care of therm's regret prospect. The regret function

    g() indicates the regret-averse attribute in which g(0) = 0, g() N 0,

    andg() N 0. The parameter 0 is the weight of the regret attribute

    or regret coefcient measuring the extent of regret aversion. max is

    the ex-post optimal prot that the rm could have earned if there

    were no price uncertainty.

    In our framework, when the realized output pricePis observed,X

    will be zero since there is no uncertainty. The optimal Qis calculatedby maximizing the following function

    maxQ 0

    U maxQ 0

    U PQC Q f g

    and getting C(Q) = P. When the value ofPchanges, the optimal Q

    changes accordingly. Thus, max(P) appears in the form ofPQ(P)

    C[Q(P)] withC[Q(P)] = P. For example, if the value of the uncertain

    price ~Pis realizedto be P1, the managerwill make production and hedg-

    ing decisions based on P1. In other words, the manager will make the

    optimal decision based on the realized product price. However, in

    practice thepriceis unknown and random. Thus, themax is also random

    and depends on every possible value of the price ~P.

    In order to compare the difference between regret-averse and risk-averse rms, in this paper we also investigate production and hedging

    decisions when the competitive rm is risk averse. To get a risk-averse

    utility function, one could simply set = 0 in (2.2).

    3. The theory

    We will use the term propositionto state new results obtained

    in this paper and propertyto state some well-known results or the

    inference drawn from the propositions obtained in this paper.

    1 We note that the hedging positionXin our paper is different from the hedge ratio,

    which is set to be between 0 and 1, while Xcan be negative as well as greater than one.

    Readersmay refer to Michenaud and Solnik(2008) formorediscussion onthe hedge ratio.

    We would like to show our appreciation to the anonymous reviewer who point out this

    problem.

    154 X. Guo et al. / Economic Modelling 51 (2015) 153158

  • 7/23/2019 1-s2.0-S0264999315002114-main

    3/6

    To obtain the optimal production and hedging for the regret-averse

    competitiverm, we maximize the expectation ofVin (2.2) such that:

    maxQ 0;X

    Eh

    V;max

    i max

    Q 0;XE U ~P

    h ig max ~P

    ~P

    h in o:

    3:1

    The expectationE() is with respect to the cumulative distribution

    function,F(P), of the random output price ~P.

    Therst-order conditions are then given by:

    E U0 ~P h i

    g0 max ~P

    ~P h in o

    ~PC0 Q h in o

    0; 3:2

    E U0 ~P h i

    g0 max ~P

    ~P h in o

    Pf~Ph in o

    0; 3:3

    where an asterisk () indicates an optimal level.

    Summing up Eqs. in(3.2) and (3.3), we getPf =C' (Q*). Thus, we

    nd that the optimal output decision is solely determined by the cost

    function and the forward price as stated in the following proposition:

    Proposition 1. Under the assumptions described inSection 2, the optimal

    production decision is independent of the regret aversion and the optimal

    output level, Q*,of the regret-averse rm is the unique solution obtainedfrom the following equation:

    Pf C0 Q ;

    regardless of whetherPf is smaller than, equal to, or larger than E~P.

    FromProposition 1, one could nd that the risk-averserm obtains

    its optimal output level by setting = 0 in (2.2). We state this well-

    known result in the following property:

    Property 2. Under the assumptions described in Section2,the optimal

    output level, Q, of the risk-averse rm is the unique solution obtained

    from the following equation:

    Pf C0 Q ;

    regardless of whetherPf is smaller than, equal to, or larger than E~P.

    In this paper, we set Q andQto be the optimal output levels of

    the regret-averse and the risk-averse rms, respectively. We note

    that the difference betweenProposition 1and Property 2 is that the

    former states the result for regret-averserms, while the latter states

    the result for risk-averse rms. FromProposition 1and Property 2, it

    is clear that Q is always equal to Q, and thus, we conclude that

    regret aversion has no effect on the optimal production decision, so that

    the optimal output levels are the same for both risk-averse and regret-

    averserms.

    It is well-known (Egozcue and Wong, 2012) thatwhen a risk-averse

    rm faces the certain priceP, it will choose an optimal outputQ

    , suchthat its marginal revenue (=P) equals its marginal cost C(Q). Howev-

    er, Wong (2014) and Niu, et al. (2014) have shown that a sufcient con-

    dition is needed to obtain the traditional result in which the optimal

    output level will be smaller under uncertainty than under certainty

    when there is no hedging.

    From Proposition 1and Property 2, we conclude thatwhen a futures

    market exists, the presence of hedging can eliminate the effect of regret

    aversion on the optimalproduction level, so that it is similarto the certainty

    case in which the price P is known, and in this situation, Pf serves as the

    known price P. This situation holds for risk-averserms also.

    The intuition ofProposition 1is as follows: Given that there exists a

    futures market, the rm can set the random output price, ~P, to be the

    predetermined futures price,Pf. At the optimum, the rm must equate

    the known marginal revenue, Pf

    , from selling the last unit to the

    marginal cost, C(Q*), of producing that unit, thereby yielding theoptimality condition,C0Q Pf.

    In the following, we study the properties of the optimal hedging

    position. It is well-known thatPf could be smaller than, equal to, or

    greater thanE~P(Hirshleifer, 1988). We rst study the situation forPf

    E~P. To do so, we only need to consider the rst-order condition in

    (3.3).

    We note that the following second-order condition:

    E U ~P h i

    g00 max ~P

    ~P h in o

    Pf~Ph i2

    b 0 3:4

    will hold automatically given that all the assumed properties ofU and

    g() are satised. This implies that the solutions obtained from the rst-

    order condition in (3.3) are indeed the optimal values.

    From the Eq. in(3.3), we get:

    GX; Q Cov U0 ~P h i

    ;~P

    Cov g0 max ~P

    ~P

    h i;~P

    E U0 ~P

    h ig0 max ~P

    ~P

    h in o PfE ~P

    h in o 0;

    3:5

    whenX=XandQ=Q.

    Now, we evaluate GX; Q atX= Q= Q. Notice that in this situation,

    we have ~P PfQCQ, which is a xed value. This implies that

    CovU0~P; ~P 0:On the other hand,

    dg0 max ~P

    ~P h i

    d~Pg max ~P

    ~P

    h idmax ~P d~P

    g max ~P

    ~P h i

    Q ~P

    N0:

    As a result, we can conclude that

    Cov g0 max ~P

    ~P h i

    ;~P

    N0:

    Theabove resultimplies that GQ; Q b 0when PfE~P. RecallthatGX; Q 0, and from the second-order condition, we can conclude

    thatX b Qwhen PfE~P. We summarize thending in the following

    proposition:

    Proposition 3. When PfE ~P, the regret-averserm's optimal hedging

    position, X, will be smaller than the rm's optimal output level, Q, in the

    presence of regret aversion.

    To explore the intuition for Proposition 3, we look into the following

    equation by settingX=Q=QinGX; Qfrom (3.5) and it becomes

    GQ; Q E U0 ~P h i

    g0 max ~P

    ~P h in o

    PfE ~P h i

    Cov g0 max ~P ~P h i; ~P :3:6

    Therst term on the right-hand side of (3.6) is the product of the

    expected marginal utility of the regret-averse utility function V;

    and the difference betweenPf and E~P . In a contango or unbiased

    market, this term cannot be positive. The second term measures the

    co-movement of the uncertain price ~P and marginal effect for the

    regret-averse attribute. With an increase in the output price, the ex-

    post loss,max~P~P, will increase atX=Q=Qand the feeling of

    regret for not producing more and for selling less in the futures market

    would increase too. These wouldnally lead to the nding that the

    optimal production levelQis larger than the optimal hedging position

    X, even in an unbiased market.

    We turn to studying the behavior of the risk-averserm under the

    same situation as stated inProposition 3. Similarly, we set X

    andXto

    155X. Guo et al. / Economic Modelling 51 (2015) 153158

  • 7/23/2019 1-s2.0-S0264999315002114-main

    4/6

    be the optimal hedging positions for the regret-averse and risk-averse

    rms, respectively. We rst state the following well-known property

    of the optimal hedging position for risk-averse rms (Holthausen,

    1979) for comparison:

    Property 4. The risk-averse rm's optimal hedging position, Xwill be

    smaller than, equal to, or larger than the rm's optimal output level Qwhen Pf is smaller than, equal to, or larger than E~P, respectively.

    In the following, we consider the situation with PfNE

    ~P . From

    Eq.(3.6)to getGQ; Qto be positive, there are two situations: rst,

    considering the termEfg0max~P~PgPfE~PCovg0max~P

    ~P; ~P. When

    PfE ~P

    Cov g0 max ~P

    ~P

    h i;~P

    E g0 max ~P

    ~P h in o ; 3:7

    GQ; Q will be positive, which, in turn, implies that X N Q. In

    addition, we get

    Cov g0 max ~P ~P h i; ~P E g0 max ~P

    ~P

    h in o

    E g0 max ~P ~P h i~Pn oE g0 max ~P

    ~P

    h in oE

    ~

    P

    N0:

    We dene the following function:

    p

    ZP

    p g0 max ~P

    ~P h i

    E g0 max ~P

    ~P h in o dF ~P 3:8

    for all pPP . Since (p) N0, P 0, and P 1, there is an

    increasing function,H, of~Psuch that ~Pis a cumulative distribution

    function ofH~Pand we useE~Pto denoteEH~P. Hence, the condi-

    tionin (3.7) can beexpressed asP

    f

    E~

    PN

    E~

    P. Thus, with regretaver-sion, different from the situation in which the managers are only risk

    averse, the conditionPfNE~Pis not enough to ensure that the optimal

    hedging position X is larger than the optimal production level Q.

    Instead, it requires the conditionPf to be larger than a transformed

    expectationE~Pof~Pwith respect to the regret functiong().

    On theother hand, ifPfis not larger thanE~P, the regret parameter

    is required to be small enough to ensure that the rm's optimal

    hedging position is larger than the rm's optimal output level. To

    achieve this, we rewriteGQ; Qin (3.6) to be:

    GQ; Q E U0 ~P h in o

    PfE ~P h i

    E g0 max ~P ~P h i P

    f~P n o: 3:9

    Ifis small enough such that

    bE U0 ~P

    h in o PfE ~P

    h i

    E g0 max ~P

    ~P h i

    ~PPf n o ; 3:10

    from (3.9) one could easily conclude that GQ; QN0, and thus,X* N Q*.

    Now we provide some explanations for the condition in (3.10). It is easy

    to see that the numerator EfU0~PgPfE~P measures the risk-

    aversion effect, while the denominator Efg0max~P~P~PPfg

    can explain the regret-aversion effect. Thus, when the regret parameter

    is bounded by the relative effect of both risk aversion and regret

    aversion, the risk-aversion effect will play a leading role and the rm

    will perform similar to a rm with only risk aversion. As a result,

    X N Q when PfNE~P . We summarize the results in the following

    proposition.

    Proposition 5. Under the assumptions described inSection2,

    a. if the futures contract price Pf is larger than the transformed

    expectation of~P,E~P, such thatPfE~P, or

    b. if the futures contract pricePf

    is larger than the expected price E~P

    with the following two conditions:

    E ~P

    b Pfb E ~P

    and

    bE U0 ~P

    h in o PfE ~P

    h i

    E g0 max ~P

    ~P h i

    ~PPf n o ; 3:11

    then the regret-averse rm's optimal hedging position,X, will be

    larger than the rm's optimal output level, Q, in the presence of

    regret aversion.

    For the optimal hedging decision, we summarize the ndings from

    Propositions 3 and 5and Property 4 in the following property:

    Property 6. Under the assumptions described inSection2,

    a. when Pf b E~P, both regret-averse and risk-averse competitiverms

    will take an under-hedged position;

    b. when Pf E~P , risk-averse competitive rms will take a fully

    hedged position, while regret-averse competitive rms will still

    take an under-hedged position;

    c. when E~P b Pf b E~P, risk-averse competitive rms will take

    an over-hedged position but regret-averse rms may take either

    an under-hedged, fully hedged, or over-hedged position,

    depending on the size of the regret coefcient(see condition(3.11); and

    d. when E~P with PfE~P, both regret-averse and risk-averse

    competitive rms will take an over-hedged position.

    From Property 6, it is clear that different from the purely risk-averse

    rm, the optimal hedging position X is still less than the optimal

    production level Q under regret aversion in an unbiased market.

    Thus, the full-hedging theorem fails under regret aversion. As explained

    above, regret aversion plays an important role. Another important

    nding in our paper is that different from the risk-averse rm, the

    regret-averse rm may still take an under-hedged position in the

    backwardation futures market. Due to regret aversion, PfNE~Pis not

    sufcient enough to ensure that X N Q

    . Instead, it requires eitherthe condition that the futures price Pf is bigger than EH~P in the

    sense that PfE~P or the condition that the regret coefcient

    is bounded from above. Under either condition, the risk-aversion

    effect prevails, and thus, X NQ. However, ifPf is slightly higher

    than E~P in the sense that E~P b Pf b E~P and is large enough

    with N EfU0 ~PgPfE~P

    Efg0 max ~P~P~PPfg, the regret-aversion effect will dominate

    the risk-aversion effect. In this situation,the rm will regretnot produc-

    ing more and selling less in the futures market. This will lead to the

    optimal production levelQ, which is larger than the optimal hedging

    positionX.

    It is interesting to know whether regret-averse rms will

    take a higher or lower optimal hedging position when their regret-

    averse attribute changes. To answer this question, we study the

    156 X. Guo et al. / Economic Modelling 51 (2015) 153158

  • 7/23/2019 1-s2.0-S0264999315002114-main

    5/6

    comparative statics of the optimal hedging position when the regret

    coefcientvaries as shown in the following proposition:

    Proposition 7. The regret-averse rm's optimal hedging position, X,

    satises the followingifPf E~P, thenX will surely decrease with an

    increase in the regret coefcient.

    Proof. Denote~P ~PQX PfXCQ. From the rst-order

    condition in (3.3), we get

    f X; E U0 ~P h i

    g0 max ~P

    ~P h in o

    Pf~Ph in o

    0

    whenX=X. Applying the implicit function theorem and the second-

    order condition, we obtain

    sign dX

    d

    sign

    f

    sign E g0 max ~P

    ~P

    h i Pf~Ph in o

    :

    From Proposition 3, we can obtain thatX b Qwhen Pf E~P, and

    thus,CovU0~P; ~P b 0. On the other hand, from the rst-order con-

    dition in (3.3), we know that

    E g0 max ~P ~P h i Pf~Ph in o 1

    E U0 ~P h i Pf~Ph in o

    1

    Cov U0 ~P

    h i;~P

    b 0:

    Thereafter,Proposition 7holds.

    We give some explanations forProposition 7here. From the proof,

    we know that

    sign dX

    d

    sign E g0 max ~P

    ~P

    h i Pf~Ph in o

    sign Cov g0 max ~P

    ~P h i

    ;~P

    b 0:

    We note thatCovg0max~P~P; ~Pmeasures the co-movement

    of the uncertain price

    ~

    Pand marginal effect for the regret-averse attri-bute. The above result implies that with an increase in the output

    price, the ex-post loss, max~P~P, will also increase atX=Xand

    Q= Q. The feeling of regret for not selling less in futures market

    would increase too. In addition, when increases, rms will become

    more regretaverse. This will eventually lead to a decrease in theoptimal

    hedging positionX.

    Last, we compare the results using hedging with the results in which

    rms cannot hedge; for example, there is no futures market so that

    rms cannot hedge (Niu et al., 2014; Wong, 2014). That is, X 0 in

    (2.1). Under this situation, we denote the corresponding prot

    and optimal output level to be0 and Q0, respectively, such that0~P ~PQ0CQ0. The corresponding rst-order condition then becomes

    E U0 0 ~P h i

    g0 max ~P

    0 ~P h in o

    ~PC0 Q0 h in o

    0 : 3:12

    Differentiating EV;max in (3.1) with respect to Q and

    evaluating the resulting derivative atQ=QandX= 0 yields

    A:E U0 ~PQC Q h i

    g0 max ~P

    ~PQC Q h in o

    ~PC0 Q h in o

    :

    3:13

    If the above term is negative (positive), then, from Eq. (3.12) and the

    corresponding second-order condition, we haveQ0 b(N)Q. On the

    other hand, differentiatingEV;max in (3.1) with respect toX

    and evaluating the resulting derivative atQ= Qand X= 0 yields

    AIfX N (b) 0, it follows from the rst-order condition stated in (3.3)

    and the corresponding second-order condition that A is positive

    (negative), and thus, the term (3.13) is negative (positive) and Q0 b

    (N)Q. We summarize the result in the following proposition:

    Proposition 8. If regret-averserm's optimal hedging position X N(b) 0,

    banning therm from forward trading will lead the rm to get a lower

    (higher) optimal output level, i.e., Q0 b(N) Q.

    From Proposition 5 and Property 6, we nd thatX NQ 0 ifthe fu-

    tures price is considerably higher than the expected price. Under this

    situation, from Proposition 8, we can conclude that Q0b

    Q

    . On theother hand, ifPfE~P, we show that X bQ. SinceXcan be positive

    or negative, fromProposition 8,Q0can be smaller or larger than Q.

    The result is different from that for the purely risk-averse rm.

    To be precise, we set = 0 and Pf E~P, A can be rewritten

    as CovU0~PQCQ; ~PN0, and thus, X N0 and Q0bQ.

    2 This is

    the well-known result inHolthausen (1979). That is,if Pf E~P, the

    optimal output level for the purely risk-averse rm with hedging, Q,

    must be larger than that without hedging, Q0. In other words, in an

    unbiased forward market, forward hedging always promotes production

    for the purelyrisk-averserm. However,for the regret-averserm, banning

    therm from forward trading may induce therm to produce more or less,

    even in an unbiased forward market.As explained above, for the regret-

    averse rm, even in an unbiased forward market,X b Q, and thus,X

    can be negative or positive. Thereafter, we apply Proposition 8andobtain the result thatQ0 can be smaller or larger than Q.

    To see the intuition forProposition 8, we recast Eq.(3.12)as

    C0 Q0

    E ~P

    Cov U0 0 ~P

    h ig0 max ~P

    0 ~P

    h i;~P

    n o

    E U0 0 ~P h i

    g0 max ~P

    0 ~P h in o :

    This equation states that the rm's optimal output level,Q0, is the

    onethat equates themarginal cost of production, C(Q0), to the certainty

    equivalent output price that takes both the rm's risk aversion and

    regret aversion preferences into account. Indeed, the second term on

    the right-hand side of the above equation captures the price risk

    premium, which must be negative (positive) if the

    rm optimally sells(purchases) its output forward, i.e., X N(b)0, thereby implying that

    Q0 b(N)Q.

    In the absence of regret aversion, i.e., 0, theriskpremium of price

    is unambiguously negative sinceUb0. In this case,X N 0, and thus,

    Q0 bQwhich is the well-known result ofHolthausen (1979). When

    regret aversion prevails, the risk premium of price could be positive or

    negative. This is due to the existence of the regret function g(). With

    an increase in the output price, the ex-post loss, max~P0~P, will

    increase. The co-movement of the uncertain price ~Pand the marginal

    effect for the regret-averse attribute Covfg0max~P0~P; ~Pg will

    then be positive.

    4. Conclusion and discussion

    In this paper, we extend previous studies on risk-averse competitive

    rmsto examine the production andhedging behaviorsof regret-averse

    competitive rms when there is a futures market. We rst nd that

    regret aversion has no effect on the optimal production decision so

    that the separation theorem is still alive under regret aversion. In addi-

    tion, we show that with an unbiased futures price, the regret-averse

    rm will take an under-hedged position. This implies that under regret

    aversion, the full-hedging theorem does not hold. We nd that with

    more regret aversion, regret-averse managers will take a smaller

    optimal hedging position in an unbiased futures market. Last, we com-

    pare the results using hedging with the results in which rms cannot

    2 Recall that the optimal output level and hedging position for the risk-averse rm are

    given byQandX, respectively.

    157X. Guo et al. / Economic Modelling 51 (2015) 153158

  • 7/23/2019 1-s2.0-S0264999315002114-main

    6/6

    hedge. We nd that when regret-averse rms take a positive (negative)

    optimal hedging position, banning the rm from forward trading will

    lead the rm to produce a lower (higher) optimal output level. This

    result is different from the traditional wisdom that forward hedging

    always promotes production.

    In this paper, we develop some properties of production and hedg-

    ing behaviors when the competitive rm is not only risk averse but

    also regret averse by assuming that the regret-averserm has decided

    to hedge. However, solving it is important and interesting to notewhether a regret-averserm should hedge or not. To start answering

    this issue, we develop proposition 8 to compare the optimal production

    levels with and without the use of futures/forward contracts. In study-

    ing whether to hedge or not, one may compare the expected regret-

    averse utility functions under the optimal decisions with and without

    hedging. In addition, we also note that the optimal choice of the

    nancial hedging instruments (futures and options) is an interesting

    extension of the theory with regret aversion developed in our paper

    and others.3 We leave this to further study in the future.

    References

    Adam-Mller, A.F.A., 1997.Export and hedging decisions under revenue and exchangerate risk: a note. Eur. Econ. Rev. 41, 14211426.

    Barberis, N., Huang, M., Thaler, R.H., 2006.Individual preferences, monetary gambles, andstock market participation: a case for narrow framing. Am. Econ. Rev. 96 (4),10691090.

    Bell, D.E., 1982.Regret in decision making under uncertainty. Oper. Res. 30, 961981.Bleichrodt, H., Wakker, P.P., 2015.Regret theory: a bold alternative to the alternatives.

    Econ. J. 125, 493532.Braun, M., Muermann, A., 2004.The impact of regret on the demand for insurance. J. Risk

    Insur. 71, 737767.Broll, U., Eckwert, B., 1998. Export and hedging decision with state-dependent utility. Int.

    Rev. Econ. Financ. 7, 247253.Broll, U., Eckwert, B., 2000. Market structure and multiperiod hedging. Int. Rev. Econ.

    Financ. 9, 291298.Broll, U.,Zilcha, I., 1992. Exchange rate uncertainty, futuresmarkets and the multinational

    rm. Eur. Econ. Rev. 36, 815826.Broll, U., Wahl, J.E., Wong, W.K., 2006.Elasticity of risk aversion and international trade.

    Econ. Lett. 91 (1), 126130.

    Broll, U.,Welzel, P.,Wong,K.P.,2015. Exchange rate risk andthe impact of regret ontrade.Open Econ. Rev. 26, 109119.

    Egozcue, M., Wong, W.K., 2012.Optimal output for the regret-averse competitive rmunder price uncertainty. Social Science Research Network Working Paper Series2006122.

    Engelbrecht-Wiggans, R., Katok, E., 2008.Regret and feedback information in rst-pricesealed-bid auctions. Manag. Sci. 54 (4), 808819.

    Feliz-Ozbay, E., Ozbay, E.Y., 2007. Auctions with anticipated regret: theory andexperiment. Am. Econ. Rev. 97 (4), 14071418.

    Fishburn, P.C., 1982.Nontransitive measurable utility. J. Math. Psychol. 26, 3167.Hirshleifer, D., 1988. Risk, futures pricing, and the organization of production in

    commodity markets. J. Polit. Econ. 96 (6), 1206

    1220.Holthausen, D.M., 1979.Hedging and the competitiverm under price uncertainty. Am.Econ. Rev. 69 (5), 989995.

    Katz, E., Paroush, J., 1979.The effect of forward markets on exporting rms. Econ. Lett. 4,272274.

    Lien, D., 2000.Production and hedging under knightian uncertainty. J. Futur. Mark. 20,397404.

    Loomes,G., Sugden, R., 1982. Regret theory: an alternative theoryof rational choiceunderuncertainty. Econ. J. 92, 805824.

    Loomes, G., Sugden, R., 1987.Testing for regret and disappointment in choice underuncertainty. Econ. J. 97, 118129.

    Michenaud, S., Solnik, B., 2008. Applying regret theory to investment choices: currencyhedging decisions. J. Int. Money Financ. 27, 677694.

    Muermann, A., Mitchell,O.S., Volkman, J.M., 2006. Regret, portfolio choice and guaranteesin dened contribution schemes. Insur. Math. Econ. 39, 219229.

    Niu, C.Z., Guo, X., Wang, T., Xu, P.R., 2014. Regret theory and the competitive rm: acomment. Econ. Model. 41, 313315.

    Paroush, J., Venezia, I., 1979.On the theory of the competitive rm with a utility functiondened on prots and regret. Eur. Econ. Rev. 12, 193202.

    Perakis, G., Roels, G., 2008.Regret in the newsvendor model with partial information.Oper. Res. 56 (1), 188203.

    Quiggin, J., 1994.Regret theory with general choice sets. J. Risk Uncertain. 8, 153165.Sandmo, A., 1971.On the theory of the competitive rm under price uncertainty. Am.

    Econ. Rev. 61, 6573.Savage, L., 1951.The theory of statistical decision. J. Am. Stat. Assoc. 46, 5567.Sugden, R., 1993.An axiomatic foundation of regret. J. Econ. Theory 60, 159180.Tsai, J.Y., 2012.Risk and regret aversion on optimal bank interest margin under capital

    regulation. Econ. Model. 29, 21902197.Wagner, N., 2002.On a model of portfolio selection with benchmark. J. Asset Manag. 3,

    5565.Wong, K.P., 2012. Production and insurance under regret aversion. Econ. Model. 29,

    11541160.Wong, K.P., 2014.Regret theory and the competitive rm. Econ. Model. 36, 172175.

    3 We would like to show our appreciation to the anonymous reviewer who point out

    this problem.

    158 X. Guo et al. / Economic Modelling 51 (2015) 153158

    http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0005http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0005http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0005http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0005http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0010http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0010http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0010http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0010http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0010http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0015http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0015http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0015http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0020http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0020http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0020http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0020http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0025http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0025http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0025http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0025http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0030http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0030http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0030http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0030http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0035http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0035http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0035http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0035http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0040http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0040http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0040http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0040http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0040http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0045http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0045http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0045http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0045http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0050http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0050http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0050http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0050http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0055http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0055http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0055http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0055http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0055http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0060http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0060http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0060http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0060http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0060http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0060http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0065http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0065http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0065http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0065http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0070http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0070http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0070http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0075http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0075http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0075http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0075http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0080http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0080http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0080http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0080http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0080http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0080http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0085http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0085http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0085http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0085http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0085http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0085http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0090http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0090http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0090http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0090http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0095http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0095http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0095http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0095http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0100http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0100http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0100http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0100http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0105http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0105http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0105http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0105http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0110http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0110http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0110http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0110http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0110http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0110http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0115http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0115http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0115http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0115http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0115http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0115http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0120http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0120http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0120http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0120http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0120http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0120http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0120http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0120http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0120http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0120http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0125http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0125http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0125http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0125http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0130http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0130http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0130http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0135http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0135http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0135http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0135http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0135http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0135http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0140http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0140http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0140http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0145http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0145http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0145http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0150http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0150http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0150http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0150http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0155http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0155http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0155http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0155http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0160http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0160http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0160http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0160http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0165http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0165http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0165http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0165http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0165http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0165http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0160http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0160http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0155http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0155http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0150http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0150http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0145http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0140http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0135http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0135http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0130http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0125http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0125http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0120http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0120http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0115http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0115http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0110http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0110http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0105http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0105http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0100http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0100http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0095http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0095http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0090http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0090http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0085http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0085http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0080http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0080http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0075http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0075http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0070http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0065http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0065http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0060http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0060http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0055http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0055http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0055http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0050http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0050http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0045http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0045http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0040http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0040http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0035http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0035http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0030http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0030http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0025http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0025http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0020http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0020http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0015http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0010http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0010http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0010http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0005http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0264-9993(15)00211-4/rf0005