1 the scottish philosopher david hume (1711-1776): an introduction into the ethical theory of david...

68
1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics; ethics is ultimately based on our feelings; Natural moral sentiments is where moral decision-making is grounded.

Upload: kristopher-miller

Post on 17-Dec-2015

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

1

The Scottish Philosopher

David Hume (1711-1776):

An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume.

If you want truth look to science or mathematics; ethics is ultimately based on our feelings; Natural moral sentiments is

where moral decision-making is grounded.

Page 2: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

2

Consider the following quote…

“Tis not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the

scratching of my finger.”

~ A Treatise on Human Reason, edited by L.A. Selby-Rigge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), 416.

Page 3: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

3

Consider the following quote…

“Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to any

other office to serve and obey them.”

~ A Treatise on Human Reason, edited by L.A. Selby-Rigge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), 416.

Page 4: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

4

Consider the following quote:

“Take any action allowed to be vicious: willful murder, for instance. Examine it in all its lights and see if you can find that matter of fact, or real existence, which you call vice…. You never can find it, till you turn your affection into your own breast, and find a sentiment of disapprobation, which arises in you, towards this action. Here is a matter of fact; but it is the object of feeling, not of reason. It lies in your self, not in the object. So that which you pronounce any action or character to be vicious, you mean nothing, but that from the constitution of your nature you have a feeling or sentiment of blame from the contemplation of it.”

~ A Treatise of Human Nature, Everyman’s Library (New York: E.P. Dutton, 1956) 2:177.

Page 5: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

5

Consider the following quote…

“When we run over libraries, persuaded of these principles what havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any volume-of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance-let us ask, Does

it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning

concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames, for it can contain nothing but sophistry

[literalism] and illusion.”

~ Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding, 12.3.173.

Page 6: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

6

I. Major Tenets:

(1) Reason alone cannot be a motive to the will, but rather is the “slave of the passions” In other words, reason alone cannot motivate to action; the impulse to act itself must come from moral sentiments.

(2) Morals are not derived from reason; they are derived from the experience of people.

(3) Morals are generated from moral sentiments: feelings of approbation (approval, esteem, praise) & disapprobation (disapproval,, blame) felt by spectators who consider a

character trait or action;

Page 7: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

7

I. Major Tenets:

(4) While some virtues and vices are natural, others, including justice, are artificial.

(5) The human psychological makeup of man is similar. Therefore, moral judgments will tend to be similar.

(6) Since morals will tend to be similar, moralities may be conceived in terms of “social utility”

Page 8: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

8

I. Major Tenets:

(7) Hume’s ethics comes out of the worldview of empiricism: only matters of fact are those discernible by the senses.

(8) Moral facts do not exist; rules of morality are not derived from reason.

(9) Vice and virtue are perceptions in the mind and that is all that is needed to regulate moral behavior.

(10) Moral distinctions are constituted by their pleasantness and usefulness (he did not synthesize how the relate to each other).

Page 9: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

9

Overview of Enquiry:

An Enquiry Concerning the Principle of Morals (1751) is broken down into 9 Units of thought:

1. Of the Great Principle of Morals2. Of Benevolence3. Of Justice4. Of Political Society5. Why Utility Pleases6. Of Qualities Useful to Ourselves7. Of Qualities Immediately Agreeable to Ourselves8. Of Qualities Immediately Agreeable to Others9. Conclusion

Page 10: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

10

What is the aim of book?

Thesis Statement: Moral sense makes the ultimate distinction between vice & virtue; both moral sense and reason play a role in the formation of moral judgments. The basis of virtue lies in its utility (usefulness), fulfilling two requirements for moral sentiments: (1) It is useful to ourselves (agreeable) or (2) to others. Therefore, the purpose of this book is the contributions moral sense and reason make in our moral judgments.

Page 11: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

11

What is the aim of book?

Complimentary Statement: Reason is important because we make moral judgments about what is useful to us or to others; it plays the role of an advisor, not decision-maker. In other words, reason does not motivate us to action. Rather, the capacity of sympathy (moral sentiments), which is rooted in our human constitution, motivate us to act or ignore those judgments.

Page 12: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

12

Central Points to Hume’s Ethics:

Hume’s list of virtues are:

Qualities useful (pleasurable) to others: benevolence, justice, fidelity.

Qualities useful to their possessor: discretion, industry, frugality, strength of mind, good sense.

Qualities agreeable (immediately pleasurable) to their possessor: cheerfulness, magnanimity, courage, tranquility.

Qualities agreeable to others: politeness, modesty, decency.

Page 13: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

13

Hume’s Distinction between artificial & natural virtues:

Artificial virtues depend on social structures and include the following:

a. Justice and fidelity to promises; b. Allegiance; c. Chastity and modesty; d. Duties of sovereign states to keep

treaties, to respect boundaries, to protect ambassadors, and to otherwise

subject themselves to the law of nations.

Artificial virtues may vary from society to society.

Page 14: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

14

Hume’s Distinction between artificial & natural virtues:

Natural virtues, originate in human nature, thus tend to be more universal:

Compassion Prudence Temperance GenerosityGratitude Friendship Fidelity CharityBeneficence Clemency Cleanliness DecorumTemperance Frugality Pride ModestyGood Sense Wit Humor ArticulatenessPerseverance Patience Good nature Sensitivity to poetry Self-assertivenessElusive quality that makes a person lovely or valuable

Involuntary virtues (e.g., good sense) voluntary virtues (e.g., ambition)

Page 15: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

15

Related to purpose are three questions (chapter 1):

(1) Is morality derived from reason or sentiment?

(2) What is the process whereby we obtain knowledge of moral judgments: chain of arguments and induction or by some internal sense?

(3) Are moral judgments the same for every rational intelligent person? In his pursuit for the origins of morality he presupposes an anti-supernatural claim, thus dismissing any theological metaphysical perspectives of this matter and advances a utilitarian model.

Page 16: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

16

Chapters 2-5:

In chapters 2-5 Hume surveys three kinds of conduct that are virtuous; they are virtuous because they are useful:

Benevolence;

Justice;

Political Society.

Page 17: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

17

Chapter 2: On Benevolence:

“On benevolence,” “nothing can bestow more merit on any human creature than the sentiment of benevolence in an eminent degree; and that a part, at least, of its merit arises from its tendency to promote the interests of our species, and bestow happiness on human society” (2.2.14).

Page 18: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

18

Chapter 3: On Justice:

“On Justice”, Hume writes, “public utility is the sole origin of justice, and that reflections on the beneficial consequence of this virtue are the sole foundation of its merit” (3.1.15). This particular virtue is the considerable source of merit ascribed to “humanity, benevolence, friendship, public spirit, and other social virtues of that stamp [justice]” (3.2. 38).

Page 19: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

19

Chapter 4: Of Political Society:

“Of Political Society,” the fundamental value of the duty of allegiance is the “advantage, which it procures to so society, by preserving peace and order among mankind” (4. 39). He concludes that “common interest and utility begets infallibly a standard of right and wrong among the parties concerned” (4. 45).

Page 20: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

20

Chapters 5-7

Chapter 5: Why utility pleases is because we are social beings.

Chapter 6: Qualities that are USEFUL to us INDIVIDUALLY include happiness, joy, triumph, prosperity, honesty, fidelity, truth, temperance, patience, perseverance, sobriety, and physical fitness.

In chapter 7 what is immediately AGREEABLE to OURSELVES include pleasure accompanied with temperance and decency; greatness of mind, character, philosophical tranquility or magnanimous predisposition, benevolence, and bravery.

Page 21: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

21

Chapter 8: Of Qualities Immediately Agreeable to Others:

What is immediately agreeable to others: wit, politeness, modesty, decency, or any agreeable quality which one possesses which we characterizes as good manners and character.

How one determines those qualities is whether they have a beneficial, useful, extensive, and positive influence; not only will they harmonize with the moral sensibilities of others and ourselves, but will produce pleasure personally and socially.

To be sure, no quality is absolutely either blamable or praiseworthy; it is all according to its degree and coherence (6.1. 68). But for those that produce public affection, they must be pursued (e.g., self-love vs. community-centered) (5.1. 48-49).

Page 22: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

22

Chapter 9: Conclusion:

Reason does not cause our actions.

Our actions are caused by a combination of utility and sentiment whereby reason is embedded in the passions, desires, habits, and sentiments of mind. In other words, morality cannot be separated from psychology.

There is no such thing as good and evil outside of human sentiments.

What promotes happiness among our fellow humans “is good” and what tends to their misery “is evil”; we do not need to go any further in our reflection or deliberation on these matters.

What is virtuous is useful.

Page 23: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

23

Chapter 9: Conclusion:

Hume writes:

“What more, therefore, can we ask to distinguish these sentiments, dependent on humanity, from those connected with any other passion , or to satisfy us, why the former are the origin of morals, not the latter? Whatever conduct gains my approbation, by touching my humanity, procures also the applause of all mankind, by affecting the same principle in them; but what serves my avarice or ambition pleases these passions in me alone, and affects not the avarice and ambition of the rest of mankind. There is no circumstance of conduct in any man, provided it has a beneficial tendency that is not agreeable to my humanity…” (9.1.112-13).

Page 24: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

24

Central Ideas:

1. Moral sentiment is where moral decision-making is grounded.

2. Sympathy is the capacity to be moved or affected by the happiness & suffering of others-to be pleased when others prosper and distressed when others suffer.

3. The inclination for this capacity is experienced to be a principle of human nature (V.17).

Page 25: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

25

Central Ideas:

4. Sympathy is not a virtue but the source of moral approval.

5. When we ascribe moral praise or blame, the praise or blame derives from an attitude of sympathy.

6. Sympathy, if not universal, is a feature for any normal human being.

7. Hume attempts to describe and explain how we do in fact make moral judgments; he does not tell us how we ought to make them. In other words, he is concerned with judgments about personal qualities rather than judgments about actions.

Page 26: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

26

8. Three Stages of Judgments:

First Stage: Sympathy induces us to take into account the happiness and suffering others and ourselves.

Second Stage: General standards correct the operation of sympathy so that we attach the same moral importance to the happiness or suffering of anyone, ourselves, or others, close to us or remote to us.

Third stage: In some cases we need to take into account not merely the utility or particular acts, but the usefulness to society of a whole system of general rules and conventions.

Page 27: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

27

8. Three Stages of Judgments:

Each of these three is a move from a limited to a more generalized standpoint.

Together they challenge the Platonic-Aristotelian view that one’s moral assessments are necessarily made from the standpoint of a concern for one’s own well-being.

Page 28: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

28

9. Significant Quotes on Sympathy:

“When a man dominates another his enemy, his rival, his antagonist, his adversary, he is understood to speak the language of self-love, and to express sentiments peculiar to himself and arising form his particular circumstances and situation. But when he bestows on any man the epithets of vicious or odious or depraved, he then speaks another language, and expresses sentiments in which he expects all his audience are to concur with him. He must therefore, depart, from his private and particular situation and must choose a point of view common to him with others; he must move some universal principle of the human frame (IX.6).”

Page 29: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

29

9. Significant Quotes on Sympathy:

“This universal principle is the sentiment of humanity or sympathy. And though this affection of humanity may not generally be esteemed so strong as vanity or ambition, yet, being common to all men, it can alone be the formulation of morals or of any general system of blame or praise (Ibid).”

Page 30: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

30

10. A Similarity:

Hume agrees with Plato and Aristotle on the following:

A. Moral judgments are primarily about virtues and vices. We praise people insofar as they exhibit virtues and blame then insofar as they exhibit vices. Only secondarily are our moral judgments concerned with specific actions. We praise or blame others because they reveal morally admirable qualities in the agent.

B. Virtues would not be virtues unless possession of them were in some sense an advantage. In fact, Hume, an action is only virtuous if it proceeds from a virtuous motive. So if an action lacks a virtuous motive, that action is not virtuous even if it is the same type of action as a genuinely virtuous action.

Page 31: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

31

An Additional

Look at David Hume

Page 32: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

32

II. Overview of Significant Points:

1. Primacy of feelings over reason as a guide to ethics;

2. Hume was profoundly influenced by Newtonian scientific revolution;

3. Empirical science nor science can offer us ethical truths; only genuine knowledge comes from pure mathematics or empirical science. It is not because reason is flawed, but because basic ethical preferences are generated from feelings passions;

4. Factual knowledge arises exclusively from the data supplied by the senses and is extended in usefulness by means of inferences based on a belief in cause-and-effect relations.

Page 33: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

33

II. Overview:

5. Feelings cannot provide an objective foundation for ethics; In fact, feelings are not subject to reason.

6. Hume attacks the idea of a necessary “metaphysical” connection between cause and effect.

7. The basis of moral assertion is sourced in feelings of approval (pleasure) or disapproval (pain or uneasiness).

8. Hume is a compatibilist regarding free-will and Newtonian determinism (he is a strict empiricist).

Page 34: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

34

II. Overview:

9. Hume agrees with the moral sense theorists such as Shaftesbury and Hutcheson (moral sense) and Butler (conscience) that all requirements to pursue goodness and avoid evil as consequent upon human nature, which is so structured that a particular feature of our consciousness (whether moral sense or conscience) evaluates the rest.

10.Because we are the kinds of creatures we are, with the dispositions for pain and pleasure, the kinds of familial and friendly interdependence that make up our life together, and our approvals and disapprovals of these, Hume believes we can escape radical relativism, generate natural and artificial virtues are socially agreeable.

Page 35: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

35

II. Overview:

Natural and Artificial Virtues:

Artificial virtues are dependent upon social structures (justice*; fidelity to promises, chastity, modesty, duties to sovereign states);

Natural virtues originate in nature and are more universal (compassion, generosity, gratitude, friendship, fidelity, charity, benevolence, clemency, equity, prudence, etc).

Page 36: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

36

On Justice*

On Justice*

It is natural for justice to arise, but we will come together and establish conventions of justice.

Page 37: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

37

II. Overview:

11. This view of moral grounding in “moral sense”, “emotions,” or “passional nature” is contrary to rationalists like Locke, Hobbes, and Clarke, who believed that good and evil were discovered by reason.

12. Locke, Hobbes, and Clarke believed, in some moods, that moral standards or requirements are requirements of reason.

Page 38: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

38

II. Overview:

13. Hume takes an intermediate view regarding whether morality is conventional (Hobbes) or natural (Locke). Hume thinks natural impulses of humanity and dispositions to approve cannot entirely account for our virtue of justice; a correct analysis of that requires the thesis that mankind, an

“inventive species,” has cooperatively constructed rules of property and promise.

Page 39: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

39

II. Overview:

14. Hume disagrees with Hobbes regarding the following:

a. Necessary psychological Egoism;

b. Necessary violent view of a state of nature whereby without an organized state “all is in a war against all”

Page 40: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

40

II. Overview:

15. Hume disagrees with Locke (and Rawls) about the idea of humanity being involved in a highly cooperative domain of law-governing citizens for the following reasons:

a It is a hypothetical condition in which we would care for our friends and cooperate with them;

b. Self-interest and preference for friends over strangers would make any wider cooperation impossible.

One of the central themes of Hume’s political philosophy is that we are both fundamentally loving and selfish.

Page 41: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

41

II. Overview:

16. Turning from reason to sentiment Hume believes that has avoided radical relativism or mere subjectivism.

a. Since people have the same psychological makeup, their moral responses will be similar.

b. If provided the same data, people will tend to respond similarly. That does mean that all people will agree

about the moral worth of an action.

c. Ethical disagreements generally stem not from differences in our “passional” nature or feelings but from (a)

misunderstandings regarding circumstantial evidence or from (b) incomplete analyses.

Page 42: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

42

II. Overview:

17. Study of individual assessments reveal that “socially useful acts are approved while those which are socially detrimental are disapproved.

18. Since we judge acts generally by their conformity to social utility (rather than by immediate, personal preferences), impartiality will tend to prevail in moral judgments.

Page 43: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

43

II. Overview:

18. Conjoined events do not prove they are causally connected any more than there is a causal connection between the “rooster crowing” and the “sun rising.” All one can do is extrapolate based on oft-repeated occurrences. He does not deny the principle of causality; he denies the basis on which some people try to prove causality.

19. All objections of human inquiry are relations of ideas (mathematics; definitions) or matters of fact (everything known through one or more of the senses).

Page 44: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

44

II. Overview:

20.Laws of nature are habits formed in our minds on what has occurred in the past and the expectation of similar experiences will occur in the future.

Page 45: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

45

III. The Nature of Moral Judgment:3 Textual Interpretations:

1.Non-propositional View: a moral evaluation does not express any proposition or state any fact. Either it gives vent to a feeling, or it is itself a feeling. (A more refined form of this interpretation allows that moral evaluations have some propositional content, but claims that for Hume their essential feature, as evaluations, is non-propositional).

Page 46: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

46

III. The Nature of Moral Judgment:3 Textual Interpretations:

2. Description of the Feelings of the Spectator: Hume is describing the feelings of the spectator, or the feelings a spectator would have were she to contemplate the trait or action from the common point of view.

Page 47: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

47

III. The Nature of Moral Judgment:3 Textual Interpretations:

3. Dispositional interpretation: Evaluated trait or action is so constituted as to cause feelings of approval or disapproval in a (suitably characterized) spectator. On the dispositional view, in saying some trait is good we attribute to the trait the dispositional property of being such as to elicit approval.

Page 48: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

48

IV. Moral Sentiments:

1. Moral sentiments are emotions which possess unique phenomenological quality, and special set of causes.

2. Moral Sentiments are caused by contemplating the person or action.

3. Moral sentiments tend to be clarified or brought into focus by social utility which is a common moral sentiments or similar responses (collectively).

Page 49: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

49

IV. Moral Sentiments:

Moral sentiments are the sort of pleasure & uneasiness which are associated with 4 passions:

1. Pride;

2. humility;

3. Love;

4. Hatred.

Some argue that pleasure and pain cause these 4 passions others believe these 4 passions make up the pleasure or pain.

Thus, when we feel moral approval we tend to love or esteem, and when we approve a trait of our own we are proud of it.

Page 50: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

50

IV. Moral Sentiments:

Because we share a similar psychological makeup, thus share common moral sentiments, we are able to generate or invent artificial virtues because we find them to be pleasant and not painful (e.g.,):

1. Justice with respect to property, 2. Allegiance to government, 3. The laws of nations,4. Modesty, and5. Good manners), which (Hume argues) are inventions

contrived solely for the interest of society.

Page 51: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

51

IV. Sentiments: Sympathy and Benevolence.

Sympathy is not seen as a mental capacity in the Inquiry as it is in the State of Nature (as a mirror to yourself).

Rather he replaces sympathy with a general benevolence in Inquiry. We care about our species of such but not as a mental capacity.

Example, in Human Treatise, he states, “there is no such passion in human minds, as the love of mankind, merely as such, independent of personal qualities, of service, or of relation to ourseit ‘Tis true, there is no human, and indeed no sensible, creature, whose happiness or misery does not, in some measure, affect us when brought near to us and represented in lively colours” (pg. 13).

But in Inquiry he doesn’t talk about a mental capacity as a mirror to yourself but we have a benevolence which is part of our species.

Page 52: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

52

V. Kant vs. Hume

1. Similarity: Hume and Kant recognized the difference between pure reason (understanding) from practical reason (work of the will). In other words, they both recognized an important difference between judgments of facts and judgments of value.

2. Difference: Kant was a rationalist in his conception of morals; Hume was an empiricist. A rationalist derives principles of morality from metaphysical assumptions. Stated differently, Kant grounds his morality in rationalism and Hume on natural moral sentiments.

3. Difference: According to Kant, no matter how unpleasant the command makes you feel, you are obligated to fulfill it.

Page 53: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

53

VI. Kant vs. Bentham and Mill on “utility”

Jeremy Bentham argued that the standard of goodness in the greatest amount of happiness for the greatest number of persons is intrinsically valuable.

1 While Hume and Bentham agree that happiness is good, Hume does not admit that it is the only thing that is good. Human beings

are complex organisms, and their total welfare includes more than the satisfaction of the one need for happiness.

2. Mill recognizes the cultural, intellectual, and spiritual pleasures are of greater value than mere physical pleasure. While Hume will agree that we are complex humans, he would reject Mill’s finite godism and would reject his utilitarianism because he grounds morality not in utility but in moral sentiments which all humans

share.

Page 54: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

54

VII. Hume on Justice:

1. The purposes of justice can be realized only by adapting the methods that are used to the particular situation that is involved.

a. Justice is a relative virtue in contrast to a deontological version of justice, one that is not influenced by the situational setting.

b. He believes our human understanding of justice does vary from one time to another and that the application of the principles of justice will vary with the circumstances under which they are

applied.

c. Hume implies that there is an unchanging element in justice: The purpose is always that of meeting the needs of society.

Page 55: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

55

VII. Hume on Justice:

“As justice evidently tends to promote public utility and to support civil society, the sentiment of justice is either derived from our reflecting on that tendency, or like hunger, thirst, and other appetites, resentment, love of life, attachment to offspring, and other passions, arises from a simple original instinct in the human breast, which nature has implanted for like salutary purposes.”

~ An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, (Chicago: Open Court, 1966), 35.

Page 56: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

56

VII. Hume on Justice:

2. Justice is “dynamic”:

a. Justice is expressed in laws and customs which are generated when the need arises for them.

b. The nature of justice varies in view of situational setting (illust. Sexual morality may vary depending upon setting).

Page 57: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

57

VII. Hume on Justice:

3. In view of his appendix on justice in An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals that there are certain principles which may be recognized that can advance justice:

A. Avoid giving special privileges to some but not others;

B. Take into account the long-range interests of others rather than immediate satisfactions; personal and immediate needs may need to be sacrificed in order to achieve the well-being of society.

C. Seek to meet the needs of society as a whole.

Page 58: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

58

VII. Hume on Justice:

4. On Distributive Justice: Justice exists for meeting the needs of society; Justice will be stated in general rules of conduct but particular situations and other

factors may arise whereby the needs and meeting those needs will mean change (e.g., war).

Distributing justice is quite impossible to meet every need. Justice is for the purpose of distributing goods in an equitable manner; there is no

exact formula for doing this that will meet the needs of every situations that comes about.

Neither extreme wealth or poverty are in the best interests of others. Believes in a moderate view of property rights. Justice is a relative virtue; nothing remains constant about the nature of justice. In dire circumstances, scarce resources, there is no justice and no benevolence. Because of our human nature we have limited benevolent and limited justice.

Page 59: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

59

VIII. Hume on Altruism and Selfishness:

1. Altruism and selfishness are not necessarily opposed to one another. 2. We possess a humanitarian sentiment which naturally approves of

what is beneficial and useful to society. 3. Since we share a common morality derived from our nature, principles of

morality are not derived from self-love alone. 4. What gains the admiration and respect of others is by acting upon the

pleasing moral sentiments that fellow-humans share; this is virtuous and meritorious.

Human nature includes both selfish and unselfish sentiments. Human nature is selfish to some extent. Human nature also has the capacity to act beyond one’s selfishness. We can feel the pain of others and their misfortune. Selfishness can over shadow good intentions but does not necessarily have to.

Page 60: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

60

IX. In Summary:

“About Hume's ethics: we have a moral sentiment or feeling of approval or disapproval (approbation or disapprobation) about actions that we find pleasing or agreeable. We find actions agreeable (and thus approve of them) not because of the utility of such actions but because we ‘naturally’ have an inclination to approve of what we are attracted to. In thinking about the pleasures or pains of other people, we (along with all other normal human beings) are attracted to what arouses in us natural sentiments of humanity and benevolence. Such sentiments are not derived from self-love but from a sense of identifying with other human beings. That sense of fellow-feeling, not the perception of the utility of actions, is the basis on which we feel moral obligation. Of course, promoting social utility is in our own self-interest, but acting for the sake of promoting our own self-interest is not a good enough reason for acting in a moral way.” ~ Dr. Steve Daniel

Page 61: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

61

X. Advantages that have been offered on this view

1. Some will appreciate the fact that it removes “metaphysical mysteries” from realm of ethics because it grounds morality in moral sentiments which all humans share.

2. Pleasure and pain are important considerations in ethical judgments.

3. It attempts to balance both selfishness and altruism.

4. It seems to avoid pure egoism, utilitarianism, and radical relativism.

Page 62: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

62

XI: Objections Raised against Hume:

1. Hume reduces ethics to a matter of taste (e.g., A.J. Ayer & C.L. Stevenson), relativism, and subjectivism.

Hume replies: since people have the same psychological makeup, moral responses will be comparable. To be sure, this doesn’t mean everyone will agree about but if provided the same data, they will generally tend to respond similarly:

a. Common Natureb. Same Data;= Similar response.

Ethical differences stem not from differences in our “feelings or “passional” nature but from misunderstandings about the actual circumstances surrounding a given act or from incomplete analyses of the consequences accruing from the act.

Page 63: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

63

XI. Objections:

2. Those who embrace “objectivist feelings” will reject Hume’s account of subjectivist feelings. Some believe feelings can be a source of objective truths of ethics. Consider Blaise Pascal’s famous statement:

“The heart has its reasons that the reason know not”

For those who embrace objective feelings they would argue that while feelings may not be an infallible guide to ethics, feelings are not distractions on the path to ethical truth. Rather, feelings can be a source of ethical insight.

Do you agree? Can ethical feelings be objectively true or are they more like tastes?

Page 64: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

64

XI. Objections:

3. Moral sentiments cannot provide an adequate basis for moral obligations (e.g., justice).

Hume’s response: It is obligatory, for example, to be just…but the reason we adopt the concept of justice and guide our actions in conformity to it is because it comes from the moral sentiments we all share.

Hume doesn’t deny a specific instance of injustice could be more beneficial to society than its corresponding instance of justice in some odd case, but by conforming ourselves to the moral sentiments of justice, humanity can be served.

Response: Still justice is not absolute, fixed upon absolutes; it is sourced in moral sentiments that can change (justice becomes somewhat relative even if it is not radical relativism).

Page 65: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

65

XI. Objections:

4. Borrowing the notion of social utility to find a way to maintain social order is using reason. Social utility is powerful enough to incite action to actually do the good.

Hume would respond by saying that the source of utility is not reason but “moral sentiment” that we naturally share; we identify with other beings on that sense of “fellow feelings”. Thus, it is not from “social utility” but moral sentiments that ground our morality. Secondly, reasons of social utility is not powerful enough to incite action; it is the “moral sentiments” of feelings of approval or disapproval that motivates action, not the perception of social utility.

5. Hume’s skepticism is self-defeating because he did not suspend moral judgments regarding God, miracles, and metaphysics.

Page 66: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

66

XI. Objections:

6. Metaphysical problem: According to Hume, meaningful propositions are empirical. But this is self-defeating, for the statement that “only analytic or empirical propositions are meaningful” is not itself an analytic statement. If one allows that such statements are meaningful, then why cannot metaphysical statements be meaningful? Stated differently, to say there is no metaphysics is itself a metaphysical statement, namely that you know that metaphysics doesn’t exist.

7. Causality can be experienced internally. I am the cause of this sentence I am typing, and I experience that fact. Everyone experiences their own thoughts and actions.

Page 67: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

67

XI. Objections:

8. Fundamentally it fails to explain what is wrong with a wrong action because it is solely based on human experience. Reason only reveals matters of fact.

a. Good in the moral sense of the term is reduced to feelings or moral sentiments.

b. Evil in the moral sense of the term is reduced to feelings or moral sentiments.

1. Hume’s response is that there is no other way to judge morality. Moreover, we are naturally constituted in such a way that there is present in us a “sense of humanity” which always approves of that which promotes human welfare and is useful in society because we all share it.

Page 68: 1 The Scottish Philosopher David Hume (1711-1776): An Introduction into the ethical theory of David Hume. If you want truth look to science or mathematics;

68

XI. Objections:

9. Hume is subject to the postmodern critique that are our “emotions” are not a product of “moral sentiments”. Rather, we are morally scripted by our sub-culture. How does Hume know that our moral sentiments are natural and not socially inscribed values?

10. Doesn’t the idea that we all share a “similar constitution of moral sentiments” beg the question that we are “designed” by God (e.g., Thomas Reid)?