20116622

Upload: assass

Post on 06-Jul-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    1/27

     

    The Origins of Wittgenstein's VerificationismAuthor(s): Michael WrigleySource: Synthese , Vol. 78, No. 3 (Mar., 1989), pp. 265-290Published by: SpringerStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20116622Accessed: 21-05-2016 19:37 UTC

     

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

    http://about.jstor.org/terms

     

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted

    digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about

    JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    Springer  is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Synthese 

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    2/27

     MICH EL WRIGLEY

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEINS

     VERIFICATIONISM

     ABSTRACT. The question is raised of the source of the extreme verificationist views

     which Wittgenstein put forward immediately after his return to philosophy in 1929. Since

     these views appear to be radically different from the ideas put forward in the Tractatus

     some explanation of this dramatic new turn in Wittgenstein's thought certainly seems to

     be called for. Wittgenstein's very low level of interest in philosophy between 1918 and

     shortly before his return to philosophy is documented. Attention then focuses on the

     crucial period immediately before Wittgenstein's return to Cambridge, and it is shown

     that in this period he encountered only two new philosophical influences. These were the

     ideas of Brouwer and the ideas of the Vienna Circle. Each of these is examined and

     neither is found capable of providing an explanation of the source of Wittgenstein's

     verificationism. This leads to a reconsideration of the underlying assumption that

     Wittgenstein's verificationism does represent the radical departure from the ideas of the

     Tractatus which it appears to. It is argued that the only way we can account for

     Wittgenstein's evident approval of the reading of the Tractatus which he must have

     encountered in his meetings with members of the Vienna Circle is by concluding that,

     far from being incompatible with his earlier ideas, some form of verificationism must

     always have been implicit in the Tractatus.

     Few positions seem further removed from the ideas of the later

     Wittgenstein than the verificationist theory of meaning. Indeed if there

     is one position which the later Wittgenstein would have regarded as

     committing about every possible philosophical mistake this is surely it.

     So it comes as something of a surprise to discover that in the period

     immediately after his return to philosophy in 1929 Wittgenstein him

     self held views about the relation of meaning and verification which

     could have come straight out of the writings of the Vienna Circle. Yet

     even the most cursory examination of the texts which he wrote in the

     early Thirties leaves little room for doubt that this was indeed the

     case, and that at that time Wittgenstein was whole-heartedly com

     mitted to a verificationism of the most extreme kind.

     1. THE IMPORTANCE OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM

     Not surprisingly it did not take Wittgenstein long to appreciate the

     implausibility of this position and his period of radical verificationism

     was as short-lived as it was extreme. Nonetheless the fact that Witt

     Synthese 78: 265-290, 1989.

     ? 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    3/27

     266

     MICH EL WRIGLEY

     genstein accepted such views, even if only very briefly, raises one very

     important question. Why did he ever accept them in the first place?

     This question needs to be answered not merely because it would be

     interesting to know what it was that attracted Wittgenstein to such

     manifestly implausible views, but, more importantly, because the views

     he had held before adopting these views appear to have been

     diametrically opposed to any form of verificationism. Certainly there is

     no explicit reference to verificationism in the Tractatus, and one of the

     principal conclusions of recent work on the Tractatus has been that

     this is no accident, since any form of verificationism is incompatible

     with some of the most fundamental ideas of the Tractatus. If this is

     right then Wittgenstein's rejection of his earlier view of meaning in

     favour of verificationism marks nothing less than one of the crucial

     turning points in the development of his thought. And in that case if

     we want to understand any of his subsequent ideas we obviously need

     to understand what brought about this radical transformation. Unless

     we can answer this question we are running the risk of seeing all his

     subsequent views in a completely mistaken perspective. So it is this

     question that I shall be focusing on in this paper. I hope to show that

     answering it will indeed have far-reaching implications for the under

     standing of Wittgenstein's ideas beyond his brief period of explicit

     verificationism, although in rather a different way from what might be

     expected.

     Before going any further let me dispel any doubts that Wittgenstein

     really did hold such extreme verificationist views by quoting a few

     representative passages from texts which he wrote in the early Thir

     ties:1

     Every proposition is a signpost for a verification.

     The verification is not one token of the truth, it is the sense of the proposition.

     In order to determine the sense of a proposition, I should have to know a very specific

     procedure for when to count the proposition as verified. In this respect ordinary

     language oscillates very much, much more so than scientific language ... this means that

     the symbols of ordinary language are not unambiguously defined.

     Where there are different verifications there are also different meanings.

     The sense of a proposition is the method of its verification.

     If someone familiar only with Wittgenstein's later writings were

     presented with these remarks I think he would almost certainly assume

     that they came from the writings of Carnap, Schlick or some other

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    4/27

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM 267

     member of the Vienna Circle. Yet in fact they are all from Witt

     genstein. Nor are these a few isolated aberrations taken out of context.

     On the contrary, they are entirely typical of the statements linking

     meaning and verification in the closest possible way which are to be

     found throughout the texts which Wittgenstein wrote during the early

     Thirties. His degree of commitment to these ideas is illustrated parti

     cularly strikingly by the fact that he did not hesitate to accept one of

     the most controversial and radical consequences of this view of

     meaning, its implications for the status of evaluative language. Yet

     Wittgenstein made it quite clear that he did accept them when he

     remarked in his 1930/1931 lectures that 'ethical and aesthetic judge

     ments are not propositions because they cannot be verified'2 (my

     emphasis). So, even though he was later somewhat coy about admit

     ting it,3 there can, I think, be little room for serious doubt that in the

     early Thirties Wittgenstein was whole-heartedly committed to a form

     of verificationism which was every bit as radical as anything put

     forward by the Vienna Circle. The question is why?

     At the moment all we know is that in 1918 when he completed the

     Tractatus Wittgenstein appears to have been anything but a

     verificationist. But by 1929 when he returned to Cambridge and

     resumed philosophical research he most definitely was. Clearly the key

     to discovering what brought about this change in Wittgenstein's views

     must lie in something which happened during those intervening years.

     So the first thing we must do is to look at what was and was not

     happening to Wittgenstein intellectually during this long period away

     from the world of academic philosophy.

     2. THE FALLOW YEARS, 1918-1929

     By 1918 the Tractatus was complete and Wittgenstein's interests

     turned to matters far removed from philosophy. It is clear that in the

     years immediately following he continued to remain convinced that

     the ideas of the Tractatus contained in essence the definitive solutions

     to the problems of philosophy, and all that remained to be done was to

     work out the details, although this was a task for which Wittgenstein

     himself obviously had little enthusiasm. As a result Wittgenstein's

     degree of interest in philosophical matters sank to a very low level and

     remained there for some time. That this was so is shown very clearly

     by the testimony of Frank Ramsey. In 1923 Ramsey visited Witt

     genstein in the remote Austrian villages where he was working as a

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    5/27

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    6/27

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM 269

     a clue as to the source of the radical transformation in his views which

     was soon to take place.

     3. WITTGENSTEIN'S ENCOUNTER WITH THE VIENNA CIRCLE

     The first new ideas which Wittgenstein encountered during this period

     were none other than those of Moritz Schlick and the group of his

     colleagues and students who were to become known as the Vienna

     Circle. Wittgenstein first met Schlick towards the end of 1927 and

     attended discussions with Schlick and some members of his group for

     several years.8 Once we know this much it might seem that we need

     look no further for the explanation of the radical transformation which

     Wittgenstein's ideas had undergone by the time he resumed intensive

     philosophical research in January 1929. Schlick and his circle were, of

     course, all committed radical empiricists for whom verificationism was

     an absolutely central doctrine. The fact that only a very short time

     after being exposed to their ideas for the first time Wittgenstein

     himself began to put forward almost identical ideas about the relation

     of meaning and verification can, surely, only be explained in one way.

     It was through the sustained and persuasive advocacy of the Vienna

     Circle that Wittgenstein was made to realise the immense im

     plausibility of the total exclusion of epistemological considerations

     from his earlier account of meaning, and how much more plausible a

     verificationist approach was. In short, Wittgenstein owed his con

     version to verificationism to the Vienna Circle.

     This explanation is attractively simple, and, it might seem, must

     obviously be correct. For surely it is too implausible to suggest that

     despite his discussions with the Vienna Circle just prior to his explicit

     acceptance of verificationism Wittgenstein in fact arrived at these

     views by some other quite different route and that this change in his

     views had nothing to do with the Vienna Circle. For one thing, what

     other possible explanation is there for the source of Wittgenstein's

     verificationism, and for another, if it was not their advocacy of

     verificationism which held Wittgenstein's interest in what the Vienna

     Circle had to say what was it? It seems obvious that something they

     had to say must have interested him or he would not have kept on

     going to their discussions. And if it was not their advocacy of

     verificationism what was it?

     However, if we look a little more closely at Wittgenstein's inter

     action with the Vienna Circle, the picture that emerges is one that

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    7/27

     270

     MICH EL WRIGLEY

     does strongly suggest that this apparently implausible possibility was in

     fact exactly what did happen, and that the Vienna Circle had nothing

     to do with Wittgenstein's conversion to verificationism. Although little

     is known about what was said in these discussions during the crucial

     period between 1927 and 1929, enough is known to decisively rule out

     this attempted explanation of the origins of Wittgenstein's

     verificationism. For if the Vienna Circle really had the kind of effect

     on Wittgenstein that it is being suggested, then they did nothing less

     than bring about a fundamental transformation in Wittgenstein's

     views. And if that were the case we would expect to find that

     Wittgenstein participated in these discussions eagerly and enthusias

     tically as he began to explore the full implications of the new and very

     different philosophical perspective whose merits he now appreciated

     for the first time. And in that case the other participants in these

     discussions could hardly have been unaware of the fact. Yet in fact it

     is abundantly clear from the reports that have been given by other

     participants in these discussions that nothing of the kind took place.

     Herbert Feigl attended many of these discussions and this is how he

     described them:9

     Wittgenstein ... emphatically told the few of us ... with whom he occasionally met

     [between 1927 and 1929]... that he was no longer interested in philosophy. He felt that

     he had said all he could in the Tractatus. Moreover, only on relatively rare occasions

     could we get him to clarify one or another of the puzzling or obscure passages in his

     work. He seemed himself rather unclear on the ideas he had developed during the First

     World War.

     This is very clearly not the picture of a man in the throes of a radical

     transformation involving some of his most fundamental ideas. But this

     is very much the picture given by other participants in these dis

     cussions. Far from taking a keen interest in the proceedings it was

     more often than not difficult to get Wittgenstein to discuss philoso

     phical questions at all. Sometimes all he would do was to read poetry

     aloud.10 When he could be prevailed upon to consider philosophical

     questions his contributions seem to have been limited to giving

     explanations of the Tractatus. There is certainly no sign of his having

     radically changed his views nor of his having rejected any fundamen

     tal aspect of the ideas he had expounded ten years earlier. So, far from

     a radical transformation having taken place as a result of Witt

     genstein's encounter with the Vienna Circle, things seem to have

     changed very little from the state of affairs a few years earlier when he

     wrote to Keynes. If pressed Wittgenstein could sometime be prevailed

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    8/27

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM 271

     upon to explain bits of the Tractatus, as he had to Ramsey, but that

     was about all. Certainly the one thing Wittgenstein seems not to have

     done was to seize on the ideas of the Vienna Circle as a basis for

     making far-reaching modifications in his earlier views. So, surprising

     though it may seem, I think this attempt to explain the source of

     Wittgenstein's verificationism does have to be rejected.

     This conclusion means that we are going to have to find answers to

     those two questions mentioned earlier. Firstly, and most obviously, if it

     was not by this route that Wittgenstein arrived at his own

     verificationism, where did it originate? Secondly, if it was not because

     they had won him over to verificationism what was it that interested

     Wittgenstein sufficiently for him to keep coming to these discussions?

     A reply to this second question is needed, and we will come back to it

     later. But for the moment I want to concentrate on the first and most

     fundamental question of the source of Wittgenstein's verificationism.

     By answering this question we will also be able to answer the second.

     It seems that in order to find out what motivated Wittgenstein's

     adoption of verificationism we need to locate some powerful influence

     which affected Wittgenstein during the crucial period just before his

     return to Cambridge, and which was capable of leading him in the

     direction of verificationism. In fact there is an obvious candidate

     which, in one respect, seems to be just what we are looking for. This is

     the impact made on Wittgenstein by the ideas of Brouwer.

     4. THE IMPACT OF BROUWER

     In March 1928 Wittgenstein attended a lecture given by Brouwer in

     Vienna. Brouwer's ideas evidently made a considerable impression on

     him. Once again Feigl provides an eyewitness account:11

     When the Dutch mathematician Luitzen Jan Egbertus Brouwer was scheduled to lecture

     on intuitionist mathematics in Vienna, Waismann and I managed to coax Wittgenstein,

     after much resistance, to join us in attending the lecture. When, afterwards, Witt

     genstein went to a caf? with us, a great event took place. Suddenly and very volubly

     Wittgenstein began talking philosophy - at great length.

     Quite clearly something Wittgenstein heard struck a chord which had

     not happened during his discussions with the Vienna Circle. What is

     more Wittgenstein's excitement was not something that quickly

     faded away. He was sufficiently interested to go back and hear

     Brouwer's second lecture a few days later,12 and the story circulates (it

     seems to have originated with Waismann) that he even travelled to

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    9/27

     272

     MICH EL WRIGLEY

     Holland to have discussions with Brouwer. Less than a year later

     Wittgenstein was back in Cambridge at work on philosophy as in

     tensively as ever. So the purely circumstantial evidence, that it was

     here in the ideas of Brouwer that Wittgenstein found the crucial new

     inspiration for the views he began to expound in 1929, looks quite

     persuasive.

     However when we try to explain in more detail just how the ideas of

     Brouwer could have had this effect on Wittgenstein we encounter an

     obvious problem. In fact there are two distinct but related problems.

     Firstly, it is not at all obvious how anyone could have been led to

     adopt radical verificationism by exposure to the ideas of Brouwer.

     Secondly, it is particularly difficult to see how Wittgenstein could have

     got verificationism, or indeed anything else, out of Brouwer. These

     problems arise because, although Brouwer was primarily a philosopher

     of mathematics, his account of mathematics was part of a general

     metaphysical view which amounted to a solipsistic form of transcen

     dental idealism strongly influenced by Schopenhauer. Such an outlook

     is obviously far removed from the radical empiricism which forms the

     basis for verificationism. It is for this reason that there is a problem in

     seeing how anyone could have been led to adopt verificationism by

     exposure to the ideas of Brouwer. Furthermore, Brouwer's ideas also

     provide an almost perfect example of the psychologism which had

     been attacked by Frege as one of the worst errors any philosophical

     account of mathematics could commit, and it is this feature of

     Brouwer in particular which makes it so difficult to understand how

     Wittgenstein could have responded in such a positive way to

     Brouwer's ideas. For on the question of psychologism Wittgenstein

     was a loyal follower of Frege,13 and so we would expect him to have

     found views like Brouwer's as much of an anathema as Frege himself

     would have. Certainly the last thing we would expect to find is

     Wittgenstein reacting enthusiastically to such ideas. Yet, despite this

     apparent obstacle, it seems quite clear that something in Brouwer's

     ideas nevertheless did strike a deep chord in Wittgenstein.

     In order to discover what it might have been we must obviously

     take a closer look at both Brouwer's ideas and Wittgenstein's response

     to them. Despite the many differences there is one obvious point of

     contact between Brouwer and Wittgenstein, which has already been

     mentioned, and this is the influence of Schopenhauer. The strongly

     Schopenhauerian tone of Brouwer's general metaphysical outlook can

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    10/27

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM 273

     hardly have failed to find a sympathetic response in Wittgenstein. But

     while this is likely enough, there is an obvious reason why it cannot

     have been this aspect of Brouwer which was responsible for bringing

     about a change in Wittgenstein's attitude towards verificationism. For,

     quite apart from the difficulty in seeing how Schopenhauer could have

     been the source of radical verificationism, we need only remember

     that this was not Wittgenstein's first encounter with the ideas of

     Schopenhauer. On the contrary, Schopenhauer was one of the very

     earliest influences on Wittgenstein's philosophical development.14 So

     by the time he encountered Brouwer Wittgenstein had long ago

     absorbed all those aspects of Schopenhauer's ideas which he thought

     were of value. By 1928 there was nothing new which he had to learn

     from Schopenhauer, and so it cannot have been this aspect of

     Brouwer's thought which struck Wittgenstein and which, apparently,

     led him to modify his views in such a radical way.

     In order to try and locate what it might have been in Brouwer which

     Wittgenstein responded to, we need only notice one very striking fact

     about the ideas which he began putting forward immediately after his

     return to philosophy in 1929. Although one very conspicuous feature

     of his thought during this period is his new-found radical veri

     ficationism, there is another equally conspicuous new feature - his

     intense interest in the philosophy of mathematics. This area was, of

     course, precisely the one which was at the centre of Brouwer's

     interests and, for good measure, it was the subject to which he

     devoted the bulk of his Vienna lectures. The fact that within only a

     few months of encountering Brouwer's ideas for the first time Witt

     genstein himself developed an intense interest in this very area can

     hardly be a mere coincidence. What this suggests is that something in

     what Brouwer said struck Wittgenstein as containing a major new

     insight into the nature of mathematics which revealed the fundament

     ally mistaken nature of his own earlier views.

     When we look at the details of the new ideas about mathematics

     which Wittgenstein began to develop in 1929 we find that many of his

     ideas bear a striking resemblance to key ideas of Brouwer. A rejection

     of the completed infinite, criticism of the Law of the Excluded Middle,

     and an insistence that the content of a mathematical sentence is

     determined by its proof, all these are central features of an intuitionist

     account of mathematics which Wittgenstein appears to echo. Witt

     genstein's discussions of mathematics even contain explicit references

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    11/27

     274  MICH EL WRIGLEY

     to Brouwer. In view of all this we might seem both to have well nigh

     conclusive evidence that it was here in Brouwer's account of mathe

     matics that the crucial inspiration for Wittgenstein's return to

     philosophy is to be found, and also to have pinpointed the precise

     aspect of Brouwer which Wittgenstein was so struck by.

     If this is right then the answer to our central question must be that

     Wittgenstein was led to adopt a radically verificationist account of

     meaning not in the very direct way that the previous attempted

     explanation suggested, but by a much more roundabout route which

     began with certain new ideas about mathematics. However it is one

     thing to conclude that this must provide the explanation of Witt

     genstein's conversion to verificationism, quite another to show how he

     found himself led to verificationism by adopting an account of

     mathematics modelled on Brouwer's intuitionism. In fact not only do

     we need to explain the nature of the connection which it appears must

     exist between Wittgenstein's new account of mathematics and his

     equally new verificationism, but we also need to explain how he even

     arrived at this account of mathematics in the first place.

     We need to do this because, while there is little room for doubt that

     Wittgenstein's new view of mathematics was in some way directly

     inspired by Brouwer, there is still an obvious problem of explaining

     how Wittgenstein could have responded so positively to Brouwer's

     ideas about mathematics. The thoroughly psychologistic nature of

     Brouwer's ideas about mathematics has already been pointed out. It

     has also been pointed out that Wittgenstein would have been un

     sympathetic in the extreme to this aspect of Brouwer. And in case

     there is any doubt about this, we do indeed find him emphatically

     rejecting such psychologism in his discussions of mathematics after

     1929, and, what is more, singling out Brouwer for criticism on this

     score.15 But this creates an acute problem for the following reason. All

     the striking theses about mathematics which intuitionism is notorious

     for, its rejection of the completed infinite, and other characteristically

     constructivist claims, are, in Brouwer's view, justified only on the basis

     of his underlying metaphysical view. What Wittgenstein vehemently

     rejects as psychologism constitutes for Brouwer not some optional

     extra but the very essence of his whole account of mathematics. But if

     this is right then by taking his uncompromisingly anti-psychologistic

     stance Wittgenstein is depriving all the other aspects of intuitionism of

     their sole justification. Yet in fact he seems to be quite happy to

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    12/27

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM 275

     accept those other aspects. Such a position seems on the face of it to

     be blatantly inconsistent. So if this attempt to explain the origins of

     Wittgenstein's verificationism is going to get anywhere it has got to

     find some way of showing that this inconsistency is only apparent and

     that Wittgenstein's selective attitude to Brouwer is a tenable position.

     I now want to consider a way that has been suggested of solving both

     these problems at a single stroke.

     5. A POSSIBLE ROUTE FROM INTUITIONISM

     TO VERIFIC TIONISM

     The starting-point of this suggested solution is a proposal that has

     been made by Michael Dummett concerning the interpretation of

     Brouwer's account of mathematics. What Dummett claims is that

     despite the prominence given to it by Brouwer himself, the psy

     chologistic dimension of intuitionism is actually completely irrelevant

     to, and indeed, actually in conflict with, the genuine insight at the

     heart of intuitionism. According to Dummett what is really at the core

     of the intuitionist approach to mathematics, and what provides the real

     motivation for all the familiar intuitionist claims about mathematics, is

     not some murky idealist metaphysical picture, but something quite

     different, namely a radically innovatory theory of meaning for

     mathematical sentences.16

     What intuitionism is implicitly claiming, Dummett suggests, is that

     instead of regarding the meaning of a mathematical sentence as

     determined by its truth-conditions, we should recognise that it is

     determined by something quite different, namely its proof-conditions.

     The principal argument in favour of this interpretation of Brouwer is

     that when the implications of such an account of meaning for mathe

     matical sentences are worked out in detail, they match exactly those

     that Brouwer was led to advocate on the basis of his more metaphysi

     cal formulation of intuitionism. I shall not pursue the question of

     whether or not Dummett's interpretation really does justice to

     Brouwer's account of mathematics,17 but if so it is clear that Dum

     mett's proposal is of immediate relevance to our problem of under

     standing how Wittgenstein could have consistently reacted to Brouwer

     in the selective way he did.18 For all we need to do is to suppose that,

     like Dummett, Wittgenstein also recognised the possibility of separat

     ing the semantic core of intuitionism from the purely psychologistic

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    13/27

     276

     MICH EL WRIGLEY

     setting in which Brouwer had embedded it. In that case we would

     expect to find Wittgenstein endorsing all the substantial claims about

     mathematical practice which are characteristic of intuitionism, while

     at the same time rejecting its psychologism. And this, apparently, is

     exactly what we do find. So the mystery of how Wittgenstein could

     have responded so enthusiastically to Brouwer's ideas is dispelled.

     If this is right then we have disposed of one of the problems raised

     by the suggestion that Brouwer provided the crucial inspiration behind

     Wittgenstein's revival of interest in philosophy after 1929. They key

     inspiration was in the philosophy of mathematics and Wittgenstein's

     revival of interest in other areas is to be seen as in some way the result

     of this. But the obvious question is how? In particular, what about the

     problem of explaining how Wittgenstein's verificationism could also

     have originated in his encounter with Brouwer? It is one of the great

     attractions of this interpretation of Brouwer that it offers an equally

     neat and elegant solution to this problem too. Again the crucial point

     has been clarified by Dummett. For, he has argued, if a case can be

     made at all for replacing an account of meaning for mathematical

     sentences in terms of truth-conditions by one in terms of proof

     conditions, then it has potentially global application and is not restric

     ted only to the domain of mathematics. When such a generalisation of

     the intuitionists' implicit account of meaning is carried out the ap

     propriate analogue of proof-conditions turns out, Dummett argues, to

     be none other than the concept of ueri/icaiiott-conditions.19 Hence, to

     explain how Wittgenstein's conversion to verificationism was the out

     come of his encounter with Brouwer, we need only suppose that he

     too grasped the implicitly global implications of the new conception of

     meaning which provided the underlying motivation for the intuitionist

     account of mathematics.

     Making use of Dummett's work in this way we are able to demon

     strate the existence of a very natural route which leads from Witt

     genstein's encounter with the ideas of Brouwer to his apparently

     totally unconnected conversion to verificationism. Granted that this is

     a possible route from intuitionism to verificationism the question we

     must now ask is whether this was a route which Wittgenstein travelled.

     In fact, despite its great ingenuity and considerable initial plausibility,

     I think that this attempted explanation of the origins of Wittgenstein's

     verificationism is open to decisive objections and is in the end no more

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    14/27

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM 277

     successful than the attempt to trace these ideas back to Wittgenstein's

     contact with the Vienna Circle.

     6. DUMMETT'S INTERPRETATION REJECTED

     Although I shall argue that it cannot adequately explain the origin of

     Wittgenstein's verificationism this perspective does nonetheless have a

     number of things to recommend it and there are some important

     things to be learned from it. Quite apart from the intrinsic interest of

     this new approach to questions in the theory of meaning, this inter

     pretation quite rightly draws attention to the fact that any adequate

     account of Wittgenstein's ideas in the early Thirties has got to take

     account of the central place which the philosophy of mathematics

     occupied in his thought at that time, and why it was that it was this

     particular area he became so preoccupied with at this time. It also

     highlights the need to give an account of the connections which must

     surely exist between Wittgenstein's ideas on mathematics and the rest

     of his thought. Finally it also draws attention to the need to give some

     explanation of why Wittgenstein responded with such enthusiasm to

     Brouwer's ideas. I think this interpretation is absolutely right to raise

     all these points, and that all these questions are of great importance.

     What is more, I think that the answers which this interpretation

     proposes to these questions do contain at least an important grain of

     truth. For I think that it is quite right to suggest that there are

     important connections between Wittgenstein's new ideas about

     mathematics and his other new ideas. I think it is right again to

     suggest that Brouwer did play a role in shaping these new ideas, both

     in the philosophy of mathematics and elsewhere. However it is when it

     comes to the proposed explanation of precisely how Brouwer

     influenced Wittgenstein that his interpretation goes astray, and as a

     result its attempted explanation of the origins of Wittgenstein's

     verificationism is wholly mistaken.

     Let us now see why it is mistaken. The core of this interpretation

     consists in the claim that Brouwer's intuitionism provided Wittgen

     stein with a model for a new account of meaning for mathematical

     sentences. It was then suggested that his verificationism is to be

     explained as the result of generalising this new account of meaning

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    15/27

     278

     MICH EL WRIGLEY

     outside mathematics. Clearly if the first claim about the nature of

     Brouwer's influence on Wittgenstein's account of mathematics is in

     correct then the proposed explanation of Wittgenstein's conversion to

     verificationism must also be incorrect. Yet I think that it can be

     conclusively established that this first claim is indeed incorrect. The

     key to showing this is to look a little more closely at Wittgenstein's

     philosophy of mathematics.

     The starting-point of this whole interpretation was the discovery

     that the new account of mathematics which Wittgenstein began to

     expound after 1929 exhibited a number of very striking points of

     resemblance to Brouwer's intuitionism. However, while there un

     doubtedly do appear to be some very striking resemblances between

     what Wittgenstein says and what Brouwer says, by no means every

     thing Wittgenstein says about mathematics fits so smoothly with this

     interpretation. In fact it is not difficult to find aspects of his account of

     mathematics which are not merely very different from any account of

     mathematics modelled on intuitionism but are clearly inconsistent with

     it. Nor is this a matter of a few minor discrepancies which might

     perhaps be brushed under the carpet. On the contrary, Wittgenstein's

     points of disagreement with intuitionism concern absolutely central

     issues and go to the very heart of his account of mathematics.

     The crucial issue is what view Wittgenstein took of the role of

     mathematical sentences. Intuitionism in common with most other

     philosophical accounts of mathematics assumes that the function of

     mathematical sentences is to describe, truly or falsely, a certain

     domain of facts. To say that a mathematical sentence has a meaning

     really amounts to nothing more than the claim that it has descriptive

     content. Now if the explanation we are considering of the origins of

     Wittgenstein's verificationism is correct then Wittgenstein too must

     have accepted this assumption. Yet it- is clear from many quite

     unequivocal remarks that Wittgenstein did not accept it. Not only did

     he reject the idea that mathematical sentences have a descriptive

     meaning, but his rejection is fundamental to his whole vision of

     mathematics. In complete contrast with intuitionism (in either its

     original psychologistic form or the refurbished semantic form pro

     posed by Dummett) Wittgenstein emphatically rejects the whole idea

     that mathematical sentences are properly construed as having de

     scriptive content or being 'about' anything. 'When we talk about the

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    16/27

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM 279

     sense of mathematical sentences, or what they are about ', Witt

     genstein insists, 'we are using a false picture'.20 Just how fundamental

     this idea is to Wittgenstein's view of the nature of mathematics is

     illustrated very clearly by his warning that 'nothing is more fatal to

     philosophical understanding [of mathematics] than the notion of proof

     and experience as two different but comparable methods of

     verification',21 since this implies nothing less than that almost all errors

     in philosophy of mathematics stem from failing to grasp this fun

     damental fact about the distinctive role of mathematical sentences.

     Such errors can be avoided, in Wittgenstein's view, only if we con

     stantly bear in mind that in mathematics, in sharp contrast with the rest

     of language, 'nothing [is] meaning... even when it doesn't look like

     that because we seem to be using words to talk about mathematics'.22

     It emerges, then, that where intuitionism sees an identity of function

     between mathematics and the rest of language Wittgenstein wishes to

     make the sharpest possible distinction. This point is clearly fatal to the

     whole idea that Wittgenstein reacted to Brouwer in the way that has

     been suggested, that is by taking intuitionism as the starting-point for

     a new theory of meaning for mathematical sentences. Wittgenstein

     cannot have reacted in this way because he had no account of

     meaning for mathematical sentences since he did not think that

     mathematical sentences had a meaning of which some account needed

     to be given. But in that case Wittgenstein's verificationism cannot

     have been arrived at by a process of generalisation from his new

     account of meaning for mathematical sentences because there is no

     such account to generalise from. So whatever it was that Wittgenstein

     got from his contact with the ideas of Brouwer his radical

     verificationism was not it, and while there may be a possible route

     from an account of mathematics modelled on intuitionism of the kind

     Dummett has described to a general verificationism it was not a route

     which Wittgenstein followed.

     Before we consider what alternative explanation might be available

     of the source of Wittgenstein's verificationism, however, there are a

     number of other obvious questions which the conclusion we have just

     reached raises and which call for at least brief comment. And in fact

     this will turn out not to be a complete digression from our central

     question, since in answering these questions some unexpected light

     will be thrown on the way to answer our central question.

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    17/27

     280

     MICH EL WRIGLEY

     7. EXPLAINING AWAY APPARENT RESEMBLANCES

     TO INTUITIONISM

     Perhaps the most obvious question raised by the argument of the

     previous section is that of what alternative account Wittgenstein had

     of the role of mathematical sentences if he rejected the usual view that

     they have a descriptive function. Does this denial of descriptive

     meaning to mathematical sentences leave him with no option but to

     say that mathematics consists only of empty marks on paper? If this

     were his position then it would no more deserve to be taken seriously

     than the naive nineteenth century formalist accounts of mathematics

     which Frege criticised so devastatingly. So if Wittgenstein's philoso

     phy of mathematics is to be taken at all seriously then it needs to be

     shown that his position was clearly quite distinct from anything so

     crude and implausible. The only account of mathematics which shares

     with Wittgenstein a rejection of the descriptive meaningfulness of

     mathematical sentences is the more recent and much more sophisti

     cated version of formalism of which Hubert was the most committed

     advocate.23

     However it is important to realise that Wittgenstein's reasons for

     taking this position are quite different from Hubert's. Wittgenstein's

     account in fact offers a radically new picture of mathematics which is

     quite different from any of the familiar positions. The key idea in

     Wittgenstein's approach is that mathematical sentences instead of

     having a descriptive role have a prescriptive or normative role. Rather

     than describing anything themselves they constitute a framework with

     in which any description must take place. The importance and interest

     of Wittgenstein's account of mathematics stems from the question of

     whether or not he succeeded in giving cogent reasons for thinking that

     this is the correct way to regard mathematics and in meeting the

     obvious objections to which this position appears to be open. Whether

     or not he did succeed should still, I think, be regarded as an open

     question. This question is obviously a large and complex one and

     further discussion of it would take us too far afield from our central

     question. However I have mentioned this facet of Wittgenstein's

     account of mathematics not merely because it is so central. I do so

     also because it throws light in an unexpected way on the central

     question of this paper, namely the origin of Wittgenstein's

     verificationism. To see how it does this we need to consider one of the

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    18/27

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM 281

     other questions raised by the rejection of Dummett's interpretation.

     Now we can appreciate how different the basis of Wittgenstein's

     account of mathematics is from intuitionism we need to say something

     about those aspects of it which appeared to provide such convincing

     evidence of Wittgenstein's debt to intuitionism. What alternative

     explanation are we now to give of these now that it is clear that they

     cannot be the manifestations of intuitionist influence which they

     appeared to be? There are two outstanding features of Wittgenstein's

     views which need fresh explanations. These are his insistence that the

     significance of a mathematical sentence is determined by its proof, and

     his emphatic rejection of the completed infinite. To explain the first of

     these I think we need only grasp one of the lessons of Wittgenstein's

     rejection of the idea that mathematical sentences have a descriptive

     meaning. Although this idea is one with few parallels in other accounts

     of mathematics there is one context from which it ought to be very

     familiar, and this is Wittgenstein's own earlier work. It is one of the

     most fundamental and innovatory ideas of the Tractatus that the

     sentences of mathematics (and logic) had an entirely different status

     from sentences of other kinds. Unlike ordinary sentences which had

     Sinn, or sense, the sentences of mathematics were sinnlos, or sense

     less, although that was not at all to say that they were nonsensical like

     empty marks on paper. Rather it was to say that they were normative

     in function. So it turns out that one of the central ideas of the account

     of mathematics which Wittgenstein was putting forward in the early

     Thirties was in fact not anything new at all, but stems directly from the

     Tractatus. And I think exactly the same turns out to be true of

     Wittgenstein's statements about the connection between a mathema

     tical sentence and its proof. This idea too is present, if in an extremely

     compressed form, in the Tractatus and has nothing to do with in

     tuitionism.24

     When we turn to the other apparent point of agreement between

     Wittgenstein and intuitionism, his rejection of the completed infinite, I

     think that here we do have to admit that the agreement is genuine and

     not merely apparent. What is more in this case we must also admit that

     this does mark a genuine change in Wittgenstein's views and is not

     something that can be traced back to the Tractatus.25 However this

     does not mean that we are at a loss to explain how Wittgenstein came

     to adopt this view, nor even that we are compelled to deny that it had

     anything to do with Brouwer. All that was ruled out by the argument

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    19/27

     282

     MICH EL WRIGLEY

     of Section 6 was the idea that Wittgenstein came to reject the

     completed infinite through his acceptance of a theory of meaning

     which was based on intuitionism. But this does not rule out the

     possibility that he was influenced by Brouwer's ideas in some quite

     different way. Indeed it is a good thing that this is not ruled out,

     otherwise we would be in danger of being unable to find any way of

     explaining how Brouwer influenced Wittgenstein. But on the strength

     of Wittgenstein's reaction to Brouwer's lecture alone, and more im

     portantly, in the light of the many explicit references to Brouwer's

     ideas in Wittgenstein's writings this is one of the few things we can be

     sure of.

     Very briefly I think the true picture of what happened was, in

     outline, as follows.26 What so struck Wittgenstein was not so much any

     particular thesis which Brouwer advanced as the fact that he raised in

     a very vivid form the whole problem of the nature of the infinite. This

     was something which Wittgenstein had previously regarded as com

     pletely unproblematic (there is nothing in the Tractatus to suggest the

     opposite). But the form in which the problem of the nature of the

     infinite crystallised for Wittgenstein was quite different from the way in

     which Brouwer presented it. The crucial question for Brouwer con

     cerned the incompletability of infinite mental processes of construc

     tion. But for Wittgenstein the question was, rather, one of how can

     any rule, which must be finite, determine its infinitely many possible

     applications. The concept of a rule had a pervasive role in the

     Tractatus, but until he encountered Brouwer its immensely prob

     lematic nature had simply never struck Wittgenstein. How Witt

     genstein pursued this question need not concern us here. But it is

     obvious enough from the subsequent course of Wittgenstein's thought

     that this is a problem whose ramifications are perfectly general and are

     not confined to the philosophy of mathematics. It is also obvious that

     there is nothing inconsistent in Wittgenstein's adopting this new

     perspective on the nature of rules while at the same time retaining the

     basic framework of his Tractatus account of mathematics.

     So it is here, I think, that the explanation is to be found of what it

     was that excited Wittgenstein so much in Brouwer. This also explains

     how this crucial new inspiration led Wittgenstein to begin exploring

     new and very different ideas both in philosophy of mathematics and in

     other areas too. This is the grain of truth which I suggested earlier was

     to be found in Dummett's interpretation and the attempt to explain

     Wittgenstein's verificationism as the outcome of his encounter with

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    20/27

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM 283

     the ideas of Brouwer. Although it was in a quite different way from

     that suggested by the interpretation based on Dummett's inter

     pretation of Brouwer, it turns out that Brouwer was the crucial

     stimulus behind many of the new ideas which Wittgenstein began

     expounding in 1929. However, to return to our main concern, his

     verificationism is a very conspicuous exception. Whatever may be true

     of the other ideas which are prominent in what Wittgenstein was

     saying immediately after 1929, his verificationism is certainly not

     something that can be traced back to Brouwer.

     But if this is right then what are we to say about the origin of

     Wittgenstein's verificationism? We seem to have reached an impasse

     since none of the available candidates for the source of these new

     ideas has turned out to be capable of providing a convincing explana

     tion. I think the key to discovering its real source lies in taking to

     heart the general lesson of the failure to establish a connection

     between Brouwer and Wittgenstein's verificationism and calling into

     question a fundamental assumption that has, thus far, gone unques

     tioned. As we saw, the crucial mistake in that attempted explanation

     lay in the assumption that Wittgenstein's conception of mathematics

     underwent a complete transformation in 1929. Although there cer

     tainly are important changes in Wittgenstein's view of mathematics, at

     the most fundamental level the picture is not one of change, but of

     complete continuity. The more general lesson of this discovery is that

     we ought to be open to the possibility that even where there appears

     to be dramatic change in Wittgenstein's views, beneath the apparent

     change there may be deep continuity, and that what seems to be new

     may not really be new at all. By now it is probably not too difficult to

     guess what I am going to suggest is the correct explanation of the

     source of Wittgenstein's verificationism. My claim will be that far from

     representing the radical change they appear to, Wittgenstein's

     verificationist ideas in fact stem directly from the Tractatus. My

     method of trying to establish this will be to focus on the importance of

     some key facts about Wittgenstein's interaction with the Vienna Circle

     which were overlooked in our earlier discussion.

     8. A SECOND LOOK AT THE VIENNA CIRCLE

     Our earlier discussion of Wittgenstein's meetings with the Vienna

     Circle left one important question unanswered. This was simply if

     Wittgenstein did not, as I argued he cannot, learn his verificationism

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    21/27

     284

     MICH EL WRIGLEY

     from the Vienna Circle, what was it that was of sufficient interest in

     these discussions that provided him with the motivation to keep on

     attending them? We can approach this question by asking another

     obvious question. Why did these discussions ever start in the first

     place? The initiative came from the Vienna Circle not from Witt

     genstein. So what was it that they were so interested by in his ideas? I

     think the answer to this question is that they thought that they had

     found in the Tractatus an extraordinarily powerful and penetrating

     crystallisation of the central tenets of views which they had arrived at

     independently. They were eager to have discussions with Wittgenstein

     because they felt certain that he had grasped far more clearly than

     they yet had the full implications of these views. But what were these

     views? It is hardly necessary to be reminded that Schlick and his circle

     were all committed radical empiricists. And it was this philosophical

     perspective of radical empiricism which they thought found expression

     in Wittgenstein's Tractatus. But, as was pointed out earlier, one very

     noticeable feature of the Tractatus is the absence of any explicit

     reference to verificationism or any other sign of radical empiricism.

     What is more, it has been apparently convincingly argued on the basis

     of things that the Tractatus does say that we can rule out the

     possibility that verificationism is implicit in the Tractatus at any level.

     It was precisely for this reason that it was so important to discover

     how Wittgenstein came to adopt verificationism since this appeared to

     mark a radical change in his views at the most fundamental level.

     But now remember what was argued in Section 2. We concluded

     there that all the evidence is that between finishing the Tractatus in

     1918 and his first encounter with the Vienna Circle in 1927 Witt

     genstein's views did not change in any way. But this means that he

     came to those discussions still holding exactly the views he had put

     forward in the Tractatus. In other words when Wittgenstein first

     encountered the Vienna Circle there must have been a direct con

     frontation between the Tractatus as Wittgenstein himself understood it

     and the Tractatus as the Vienna Circle understood it. And this clearly

     provides us with an absolutely clearcut and decisive test of the

     correctness or otherwise of the Vienna Circle's interpretation. It does

     so because even where far less significant issues were concerned

     Wittgenstein was most definitely not someone to take misrepresen

     tations of his views lightly.27 So if the Vienna Circle's interpretation

     had been half as far from the real intentions of the Tractatus as is

     usually supposed, Wittgenstein's reaction would still have been one of

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    22/27

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM 285

     outrage. And we can be certain that in that case he would not have

     had the slightest interest in maintaining contact with these people who

     had so badly misunderstood his ideas.

     But of course Wittgenstein did nothing of the sort. Even if he was

     not always the most forthcoming of participants in these discussions he

     did come back and kept doing so. Far from being outraged he was

     quite content to sit placidly by while the air was thick with talk of

     verification, protocol sentences, sense-data, and so on, as the Vienna

     Circle attempted to work out the details of the Tractatus. Evidently all

     this was perfectly congenial to Wittgenstein. This can, I think, mean

     only one thing. That far from being the travesty of the Tractatus it is

     commonly taken to be, the Vienna Circle's interpretation contains a

     very important element of truth. This must be so because by his mere

     presence at their meetings Wittgenstein was clearly giving his tacit

     approval to the general way in which the Vienna Circle wished to

     interpret the Tractatus. And if this is right then we have finally found

     the answer to our central question, although in the most unexpected of

     places. The source of the radical verificationism which Wittgen

     stein espoused so enthusiastically in the early Thirties lies in the

     Tractatus.

     Even if this does answer our central question, however, we still have

     to answer the question with which this section began. What was it that

     held Wittgenstein's attention in the Vienna Circle discussions? And in

     answering this we can also deal with a further question which is raised

     by our central conclusion. Even if the source of Wittgenstein's

     verificationism is in the Tractatus there is still one very obvious

     difference between the verificationism of the Tractatus and the

     verificationism of the early Thirties. It is simply that in the Tractatus it

     was only implicit, whereas after 1929 it became very explicit. Why was

     this? Although this change is a great deal less dramatic than the one

     which was initially supposed to have occurred between 1918 and

     1929, it is still a genuine change and some explanation is required of

     why it happened. I think that the way to explain this change is to

     realise that although the Tractatus is tacitly committed to some form

     of verificationism, it is not committed to any particular detailed

     formulation of verificationism. As so often in the Tractatus Witt

     genstein is operating at a very high level of generality. It seems likely

     that he may have had a number of different possible candidates in

     mind for the specific way his general commitment to verificationism

     might be worked out, but he had not come to any decision between

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    23/27

     286

     MICH EL WRIGLEY

     them since it was not crucial for him to do so because he knew (or

     thought he knew) on a priori grounds that some candidate must fit the

     bill. Finding out which it was was simply a matter of detail that Witt

     genstein was not particularly interested in. This is surely the reason

     why we do not find any detailed explicit verificationist pronounce

     ments in the Tractatus itself. However once he had been confronted

     with the Vienna Circle's determined efforts to work out a fully explicit

     answer to the question of what precise form verificationism should

     take Wittgenstein did gradually become more concerned with these

     questions of detail himself. And in doing so he now did commit

     himself to a specific formulation of verificationism. It was his parti

     cipation in this gradual process of trying to arrive at a satisfactory

     detailed and explicit formulation of verificationism which was what

     held Wittgenstein's attention in the Vienna Circle discussions, and it

     was for the same reason that by 1929 he formulated his verificationism

     absolutely explicitly. Yet because much of this was already relatively

     familiar to Wittgenstein and because this was also a relatively gradual

     process this claim is not inconsistent with his relatively low level

     of interest in the proceedings.

     Let me now conclude by making clear what I think has been

     established and what not, and indicate some further questions raised

     by my conclusions.

     9. RECONSIDERING THE TRACTATUS'

     First of all let me emphasize what I am not claiming. I am not

     proposing simply to revive the Vienna Circle interpretation of the

     Tractatus in its entirety. Undoubtedly the Vienna Circle's inter

     pretation did badly misrepresent the Tractatus on many issues, the

     nature of philosophy, the nature of mathematics and logic, ethics, to

     give only a few examples. It has undoubtedly been one of the major

     achievements of recent work on the Tractatus to make this very clear

     and to show how much there is in the Tractatus that stems from Frege,

     Hertz, Schopenhauer and elsewhere, and has nothing to do with the

     Vienna Circle or radical empiricism. It was precisely all these aspects

     of the Tractatus which the Vienna Circle were completely blind to.

     However now that this lesson has been thoroughly learned, and also

     now that some of the texts from Wittgenstein's crucial middle period

     are available, we can perhaps take a second look at the Vienna

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    24/27

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM 287

     Circle's interpretation and realise that while this interpretation is

     certainly not the whole truth about the Tractatus, it is not wholly

     mistaken either, and on one point of some importance it does contain

     a genuine insight. So although the Vienna Circle's interpretation is not

     without its shortcomings it is certainly an exaggeration to claim that

     this interpretation fails 'not from any minor defect but because it

     comes from entirely the wrong philosophical tradition'.28 The reply

     to this must surely be that this interpretation is far from being the

     complete failure suggested since there is every sign that Wittgenstein

     felt perfectly at home in this supposedly alien philosophical tradition.

     In one sense this conclusion about the source of Wittgenstein's

     verificationism raises many more questions than it answers. For those

     who reject the Vienna Circle's reading do so on the basis of what look

     like very persuasive arguments which are based on what Wittgenstein

     says in the Tractatus. Whereas my claim that we must trace the source

     of Wittgenstein's verificationism back to the Tractatus is not based on

     what he actually says in the Tractatus. While I do not think that this

     makes my argument any less conclusive, clearly if I am right then it

     must be possible to demonstrate the existence of Wittgenstein's tacit

     verificationism directly on the basis of what he says in the Tractatus.

     In addition it needs to be shown precisely where the arguments which

     appear to show that there is no place within the framework of the

     Tractatus for verificationism go wrong. It seems like no easy task to

     do either of these things, and I shall not attempt to do either here. But

     I do not think it will prove any easier to find a convincing alternative

     explanation of the source of Wittgenstein's verificationism or to show

     where my own argument goes wrong.

     I suggested earlier that finding an answer to the question of the

     origins of Wittgenstein's verification might well have far-reaching

     consequences and involve radical revisions of widely accepted views

     about Wittgenstein's ideas beyond the brief period of his explicit

     verificationism. This much seems certain, that if my argument is

     correct then this suggestion has very definitely been borne out.

     NOTES

     1 These remarks come, respectively, from Philosophical Remarks, Basil Blackwell,

     Oxford, 1975, pp. 174, 200; and from Ludwig Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle, Basil

     Blackwell, Oxford, 1979, pp. 47, 53, 79.

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    25/27

     288 MICHAEL WRIGLEY

     2 Desmond Lee (ed.): 1980, Wittgenstein's Lectures: Cambridge, 1930-1932, Basil

     Blackwell, Oxford, p. 66.

     3 He once said, 'I used at one time to say that, in order to get clear how a certain

     sentence is used, it was a good idea to ask oneself: How would one try to verify such an

     assertion? _But some people have turned this suggestion about asking for the

     verification into a dogma - as if I'd been advancing a theory about meaning', Gasking

     and Jackson: 1978, 'Wittgenstein as a Teacher', in K. T. Fann (ed.), Ludwig Witt

     genstein: The Man and His Philosophy, Harvester, Brighton, p. 54. Notice that even

     here what Wittgenstein was objecting to was not so much the idea that meaning was in

     some way connected with verification as the idea that this provided the basis for a theory

     of meaning. Of course it is not clear that he was even justified in complaining about this.

     Certainly it's hard on reading the texts of the early Thirties to escape the impression

     that, in one sense at least of 'theory', that was exactly what Wittgenstein was doing.

     4 Cf. Ramsey's description of these meetings in the letter to his mother written while he

     was still in Austria, in Wittgenstein, Letters to C. K. Ogden, Basil Blackwell and

     Routledge and Kegan Paul, Oxford and London, 1973, p. 78.

     5 So G. E. Moore reports, 'Wittgenstein's Lectures, 1930-1933', Philosophical Papers,

     Allen and Unwin, London, 1959, pp. 248-49.

     6 Letter to Keynes, 4th July 1924, in Wittgenstein's Letters to Russell, Keynes and

     Moore, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1974, p. 116.

     7 As he remarked later, 'When I was building the house for my sister in Vienna I was so

     completely exhausted at the end of each day that all I could do was go to a flick every

     night', Drury: 1984, 'Conversations with Wittgenstein', in Rhees (ed.), Recollections of

     Wittgenstein, Oxford University Press, London, p. 106.

     8 Wittgenstein never attended the official meetings of the Vienna Circle, but met some

     members of the Circle separately. Cf. McGuinness' introduction to Wittgenstein and the

     Vienna Circle.

     9 Feigl: 1980, 'The Wiener Kreis in America', in R. S. Cohen (ed.), Inquiries and

     Provocations: Selected Writings, 1929-1974, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, p. 63.

     10 Cf. McGuinness' introduction to Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle, p. 15, and Feigl

     op. cit.

     11 Feigl op. cit., p. 64.

     12 Cf. Hallett: 1977, A Companion to Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations',

     Cornell University Press, Ithaca, p. 762.

     13 Indeed Wittgenstein seems to go even further and takes Frege himself to task for

     lapsing into psychologism, commenting, 'it is remarkable that a thinker as rigorous as

     Frege appealed to self-evidence as a criterion of a logical proposition', Tractatus

     6.1271.

     14 As we know from von Wright's report in 'Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Biographical

     Sketch' Wittgenstein, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1982, p. 18. Although von Wright goes

     on to say that Wittgenstein abandoned some of his earliest Schopenhauerian views as a

     result of the influence of Frege, it has been argued very convincingly that the ideas of

     the Tractatus still incorporate substantial Schopenhauerian elements. Cf. Hacker: 1972,

     Insight and Illusion, Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp. 58fF.

     15 For example, 'when the intuitionists speak of the basic intuition - is this a

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    26/27

     THE ORIGINS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S VERIFICATIONISM 289

     psychological process? If so, how does it come into mathematics?', Philosophical

     Grammar, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1974, p. 322.

     16 Cf. Dummett: 1977, Elements of Intuitionism, Clarendon Press, Oxford; and, espe

     cially, 'The Philosophical Basis of Intuitionist Logic', Truth and Other Enigmas,

     Duckworth, London, 1978.

     17 Although two points are worth making briefly. One obvious question, whose im

     portance was stressed to me by Peter Eggenberger, is whether Dummett's interpretation

     can do justice to the evident transcendental dimension of Brouwer's thought. At a

     different level questions can be raised whether the kind of picture of mathematics which

     follows from the theory of meaning which Dummett claims is implicit in Brouwer

     actually tallies with the views which Brouwer put forward. In particular, it can be

     questioned whether Dummett's theory of meaning really has the revisionary con

     sequences with respect to mathematics which are such a notorious part of Brouwer's

     ideas. Cf. Crispin Wright: 1981, 'Dummett and Revisionism' in Philosophical Quarterly,

     where it is forcefully argued that Dummett's account of meaning does not have any such

     revisionary consequences. If this is right then Dummett's claim to have extracted the

     true core of Brouwer's intuitionism is clearly called into question.

     18 Although the key idea behind this perspective on Wittgenstein is due to Dummett, he

     has not been much concerned with working out any detailed interpretation of Witt

     genstein himself. The most detailed presentation of such an interpretation is to be found

     in the early work of Baker and Hacker, e.g., Hacker Insight and Illusion, and Baker and

     Hacker 'Critical Notice of Wittgenstein's Philosophical Grammar', Mind, April 1976.

     (Although I should stress that Baker and Hacker have long since vigorously rejected

     such a reading of Wittgenstein. Cf. Scepticism, Rules and Language, Basil Blackwell,

     Oxford, 1984, pp. 46-47.) Similar ideas have been put forward in John Richardson:

     1976, The Grammar of Justification, Sussex University Press, London, and in Crispin

     Wright: 1980, Wittgenstein on the Foundations of Mathematics, Duckworth, London.

     19 Dummett has discussed this aspect of his ideas most fully in 'What is a Theory of

     Meaning? (II)', in Evans and McDowell (eds.), Truth and Meaning, Clarendon Press,

     Oxford, 1976. Cf. also Crispin Wright 'Truth-Conditions and Criteria', Proceedings of

     the Aristotelian Society, Suppl. Vol. 1976.

     20 Philosophical Grammar, p. 290.

     21 Philosophical Grammar, p. 361.

     22 Philosophical Grammar, p. 468.

     23 In fact it is an oversimplification to say that Hubert completely rejected the idea that

     mathematical sentences had a meaning. For a certain very restricted class of sentences

     he did allow that they had descriptive content.

     24 In 'Mathematics in the Tractatus' (to appear) I have tried to show that it is possible to

     piece together enough of the extremely compressed account of mathematics given in

     the Tractatus to see that this claim about the relation between a mathematical sentence

     and its proof is implicit in that account.

     25 Cf. 'Mathematics in the Tractatus' for arguments that, contrary to what is often

     claimed, Wittgenstein did not reject the completed infinite in the Tractatus.

     26 I have discussed how exactly Brouwer did influence Wittgenstein in more detail in

     'Wittgenstein and Brouwer' (to appear).

     27 As both Russell and Waismann, among others, found. Cf. Kenneth Blackwell: 1981,

    This content downloaded from 155.223.64.100 on Sat, 21 May 2016 19:37:40 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/16/2019 20116622

    27/27

     290 MICHAEL WRIGLEY

     'The Early Wittgenstein and the Middle Russell', in I. Block (ed.), Perspectives on the

     Philosophy of Wittgenstein, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, p. 27n, and Gordon Baker: 1979,

     'Verehrung und Verkehrung: Wittgenstein and Waismann', in Luckhardt (ed.), Wit

     genstein: Sources and Perspectives, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, New York, pp.

     267 68.

     28 James Griffin: 1964, Wittgenstein's Logical Atomism, Clarendon Press, Oxford, p.

     150.

     Departamento de Filosof?a (IFCH)

     Universidade Estadual de Campinas

     CP? 117

    13100 Campinas, S.P.

     Brazil