424 fpolitical theory volume 18 issue 2 1990 [doi 10.2307%2f191346] stephen macedo -- the politics...

Upload: emi-zarbar

Post on 02-Mar-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    1/26

    The Politics of JustificationAuthor(s): Stephen MacedoSource: Political Theory, Vol. 18, No. 2 (May, 1990), pp. 280-304Published by: Sage Publications, Inc.Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/191346.

    Accessed: 08/05/2014 22:19

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Sage Publications, Inc.is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Political Theory.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=sagehttp://www.jstor.org/stable/191346?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/191346?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=sage
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    2/26

    THE

    POLITICS

    OF

    JUSTIFICATION

    STEPHENMACEDO

    Harvard

    University

    THE

    PRACTICE OF

    POLITICALJUSTIFICATION

    s

    not

    just

    for

    philosophers,and t does not

    simply

    lie

    behind

    as

    we

    may

    hope)

    our

    political

    arrangements.Commitments o reasongiving andreasondemandingnform

    some

    of our most valuable

    political

    practices.

    Judicial

    review,

    most

    obvi-

    ously,

    helps

    ensure that

    legislative

    and executive acts are

    reasonable

    in

    constitutional

    erms:

    In

    court it is not the

    fact

    of

    power

    but the

    display

    of

    reasonsand evidence that

    counts. Not

    only

    the

    courts,

    but also

    Congress

    and

    the

    executive

    branch

    sometimes

    (and

    quite

    properly)

    onscientiously

    ustify

    their

    actions

    n

    constitutional erms.

    Constitution

    side,

    muchthat akes

    place

    in

    and

    around

    egislatures,

    elections,

    and

    other

    political

    fora can be under-

    stoodas effortstojustify particular olicies andprograms.1

    Liberals

    demand,

    as

    Jeremy

    Waldron

    puts it, that the

    social order

    should

    in

    principle

    be

    capable

    of

    explaining

    itself at the

    tribunal

    of

    each

    person's

    understanding. 2

    Liberal,

    democratic

    politics

    is not only

    about

    individual

    rightsand

    limited

    govemment,

    it is

    also about

    ustification,but

    not

    about

    any

    kind of

    justification

    at

    all. Liberal

    political

    ustification,

    even

    in

    its ideal

    form,

    shouldbe

    understood

    politically

    this

    article

    considers

    why

    and how.

    Liberalcontractualistsypicallyseekjustifications hatarewidelyaccept-

    able to

    reasonable

    people with

    a broad

    range of

    moral,

    philosophical,and

    religious

    commitments.3

    he aim is

    reasonable

    greement:

    o be

    both

    reason-

    able

    and

    agreeable

    n

    a

    widely

    pluralistic

    ociety.4The

    appropriate

    means is

    a

    processof

    reasoning hat

    s

    publicly

    accessible,

    but

    genuinely

    ustificatory.

    AUTHOR'S

    NOTE: Thanks

    to

    William

    Galston,

    Randy

    Krozsner,

    Charles

    Larmore,

    Percy

    Lehning,

    HarveyC.

    Mansfield,

    Jr.,John

    Rawls,

    Judith

    N. Shklar,

    Mark

    Tushnet, nd

    Leif

    Wenar,

    for comments on previous drafts. The article was improved by discussions in the Harvard

    Government

    DepartmentPolitical

    Theory

    Colloquium,and

    at a

    symposium t

    the

    Instituteor

    Humane

    Studies.

    A generous

    grant

    romthe

    Smith

    Richardson

    Foundation

    providedthe time

    to

    workon

    thispiece.

    POLITICAL

    HEORY,ol.18

    No. 2,

    May1990

    280-304

    ?

    1990

    Sage

    Publications, nc.

    280

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    3/26

    Macedo POLITICSOF

    JUSTIFICATION

    281

    The

    danger s

    that reasonswill

    be

    deployed that ease

    people

    into

    the

    liberal

    settlementby

    masking

    the

    true nature

    of

    liberalism

    as

    a

    regime.

    In

    the quest

    for consensus amidst

    diversity,

    iberals have

    a

    tendency

    to

    minimize the

    broad and

    deep implicationsof liberal

    politics.

    Reticence

    in

    spelling out

    the

    controversial implications

    of liberalism could

    lead

    to

    a

    conspiracyof

    silence and the

    embracement

    f a

    liberal

    false

    consciousness.

    Beginning

    from the desire

    to

    respectreasonable

    persons,publicjustification

    could

    become

    liberal

    hoodwinking,

    and

    political

    iberalismcould

    come

    to

    reston a

    noble

    fib.

    Liberal

    public

    ustification

    annot

    avoid

    controversy:

    t

    engages

    and

    seeks

    to shape

    our

    deepest and

    most

    personal values.

    Liberals,

    I

    argue,

    should

    acknowledge their

    partisanship

    and the practical

    impossibility of

    perfect

    convergence on

    common

    principles

    of

    justice.

    A

    workable

    conception

    of

    public

    justification

    must

    acknowledge

    the

    importance

    of a

    principled

    mod-

    eration

    as a

    core

    liberal

    virtue,

    one

    that allows

    us

    reasonably

    o

    aspire

    to

    public

    justificationwhile

    accepting

    the infirmitiesof

    the human

    condition.

    LIBERAL

    UBLIC

    JUSTIFICATION

    The

    commitment o

    public

    justification

    reflects a desire to

    regardcertain

    kinds of

    reasons

    as

    authoritativen

    politics:moral

    reasons

    hatcan be

    openly

    presented

    to others,

    critically

    defended, and

    widely

    shared by

    reasonable

    people. The

    reasonsmust be

    moral:

    good reasons

    for

    others as well

    as for

    oneself,

    not

    self- or

    narrowly

    nterested.

    They mustbe

    general reasons,

    ones

    we areprepared o extend to relevantlysimilarcases. The reasonsmust be

    public

    in

    the

    sense of

    being widely

    and

    openly

    accessible;

    appeals to inner

    conviction

    or

    faith, special

    insight,secret

    nformation, r

    very difficult

    forms

    of

    reasoningare

    ruledout.

    Public

    ustificationmust,

    finally,

    be critical in

    that

    objections

    have been

    soughtout

    and

    reasonable

    altematives

    confrontedor

    anticipated.5

    At its most

    basic

    level, public

    justification

    has dual

    aims:

    It seeks

    reflec-

    tive

    justification good

    reasons),but

    it also

    seeks

    reasonsthatcan

    be

    widely

    seen

    to be

    good

    by

    persons such as

    they

    are.

    These dual

    aims

    are pursued

    together o

    that,

    politically

    speaking

    at

    least, there s no

    independent

    tandard

    against

    which

    a

    political

    theorycan

    be

    judged.6

    Participants

    im

    at a system

    of

    principles hatall

    can see

    to be

    reasonable

    not one

    that

    some will

    regard

    as

    true).

    Public

    justification does

    not

    work down

    from

    a

    prior, purely

    philosophical

    standard:

    Political

    philosophy

    must

    be concerned,

    as

    moral

    philosophy

    neednot be,

    with

    practicalpolitical

    possibilities. 7

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    4/26

    282

    POLITICAL

    THEORY

    MAY

    1990

    The dual aims of

    justification

    are

    consonant

    with the

    principled

    commit-

    ments

    of

    a

    liberaldemocratic

    ociety: By

    pursuing

    both

    together,

    we

    respect

    not

    only the

    goodness

    of

    good

    reasons,

    but

    also the freedomand

    equality

    of

    citizens whose

    capacity

    for reason is limited and

    who

    espouse

    widely

    divergent

    comprehensive

    views.8

    Indeed,

    the

    goodness

    of

    good

    reasons,for

    a political

    heory,

    becomes

    entirely

    a function of

    their

    capacity

    to

    gain

    widespread

    agreement among

    reasonable

    people

    moved

    by

    a

    desire for

    reasonable

    agreement.9As

    ThomasNagel puts it,

    we should

    not impose

    arrangements,

    nstitutions,

    or

    requirements

    n

    other

    people on

    grounds hat

    hey

    could

    reasonably eject(where

    reasonableness

    s

    not

    simply

    a

    function

    of

    the

    independent

    ightness

    or

    wrongness

    of the

    arrangements

    n

    question,

    but

    genuinely

    dependson the

    point

    of view

    of the

    individual

    n

    question

    to

    some

    extent).'0

    Why public

    ustification?We

    acknowledge,

    irst

    of

    all,

    the

    permanent

    act

    of

    diversity:

    Reasonable

    people

    disagree

    not

    only

    about

    preferences

    and

    interests,

    but also widely

    and

    deeply about

    moral,

    philosophical,religious,

    and

    other

    views.

    Second,

    while

    acknowledging

    diversity,

    we

    respect

    as

    free

    andequalmoral

    beings

    all

    those

    who pass

    certain

    hreshold

    ests of reason-

    ableness:We

    respect hose

    whose

    disagreementwith us does not

    impugn

    heir

    reasonableness.

    We try to

    distinguish,

    finally,

    between

    intractable

    philo-

    sophical

    and

    religious issues and

    other

    problemsthat

    are

    both more

    urgent

    (at

    least from

    a liberal

    perspective)and

    easier

    to

    grapplewith.'2We

    urgently

    need

    agreementon

    certain

    practical

    problems:

    securing basic

    liberties

    and

    establishing

    air principles

    of

    distribution.'3

    here are,

    says

    Rawls, reason-

    able and

    generally

    acceptableanswers

    or only a

    few

    questionsof

    political

    justice; political

    wisdom

    consists

    in

    identifying hose

    few,

    and

    among

    them

    the

    most

    urgent.

    4

    Public

    justification

    embodies a

    complex form

    of

    respect for

    persons:It

    respects

    both our capacity

    for a

    shared

    reasonableness,

    ut also

    what Rawls

    calls the

    burdens

    of

    reason. '5

    eople

    disagreefor a

    variety of

    reasonsthat

    do not

    impugn their

    reasonablenessor

    undermine heir claim

    to

    respect.

    Public justification

    offers,

    therefore,a

    way of

    acceptingthe

    infirmities

    of

    reasonablecitizens and of respectingthem, blemishesand all. Moralargu-

    ments are,

    after all,

    complex and the

    relevant

    evidence is often

    difficult to

    assess

    and

    weigh

    appropriately.

    he conceptsof

    political

    moralityare

    inher-

    ently abstract

    and

    vague.

    Our judgments

    are

    inevitably

    somewhat

    subjec-

    tive-shaped, that

    s, by a

    totalityof

    personal

    experiencesthat are

    boundto

    differ

    from

    one person to

    another.

    Moral values

    are

    diverse,

    and different

    ones

    often

    weigh

    in

    on

    both

    sides of moral

    issues.

    Particular

    political

    institutions

    and

    policies cannot

    embody

    all

    values: We must

    make

    hard

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    5/26

    Macedo

    POLITICSOF JUSTIFICATION

    283

    choices and be

    selective.16

    Moral evaluation is a

    complex

    and

    difficult

    business,

    so

    convergence

    on common

    political

    principles

    is bound to

    be

    arduous;

    t is

    only

    reasonable o

    accept

    the fact

    of

    reasonable

    disagreement.

    Public

    justification

    plays

    a

    representative

    ole:

    mediating,

    n

    effect,

    be-

    tween

    philosophyand

    the

    citizenry

    (representing hilosophy

    to citizens and

    citizens to

    philosophy). 7

    he

    public conception

    avoids

    excessively subtle

    andcomplex

    forms

    of

    reasoning,preferring rguments

    hatnot

    only

    aresound

    but

    such

    that

    they

    can be

    publicly

    seen to be

    sound. '8

    Public

    justification

    respects the

    constraints

    of

    simplicity and availability

    of

    information,

    moderating he aims of

    philosophyso as to ensure

    the wide

    accessibility

    of

    the relevant forms of

    reasoning

    and evidence: These

    should be not

    too

    difficult

    and

    (if

    possible)

    not

    too deeply at odds

    with

    firmly

    held and not

    unreasonable iews. 9With its

    significantly public

    standard

    of

    reasonable-

    ness, the political conception

    fosters trustand

    promotescooperation.20

    nd

    it expressesthe

    need to perform

    ertainurgent asks

    without

    waiting

    to

    settle

    deep

    and

    intractable

    disputes.2'

    Public

    justification embodies the philosophical

    impetus toward

    critical

    reflection in a qualified form.These qualificationsmay strike us at first as

    odd,

    and

    indeed as inconsistent with

    certain

    liberal institutions.Judicial

    review

    elevates

    the political authority f courts,

    authority hat

    lows from

    the

    capacity

    to

    recognize good reasons and

    make

    good arguments.And so,

    Michael

    Walzer charges that

    Judicialreview is the

    crucial institutional

    device

    through

    which

    the

    philosophicalconquest

    of

    politics

    takes

    effect. 22

    Taking

    eriously he public

    natureof liberal ustification oftens

    the supposed

    antidemocratic endency of

    judicial review,

    and allows us to see that the

    authority fjudgesis notautomaticna liberaldemocratic ociety: They gain

    authorityby

    disceming

    interpretationsf the fundamentalaw

    whose reason-

    ableness

    can be

    widely

    seen.23

    This

    public

    conception of justification

    construesthe ends

    and means of

    justification

    n

    a

    way

    that

    accords

    with

    ourbroader ommitment

    o respecting

    the

    freedom and

    equality of

    persons. Having

    done so, it honestly acknowl-

    edges the

    substantive

    qualificationsbuilt into the idea of a

    public moral

    justification

    namely,

    hat t

    does not aim to identifywhat are

    simply the best

    reasons, where best is a function of only the quality of the reasons as

    reasons

    eaving

    aside the constraints f wide

    accessibility).24

    Given

    a

    polity

    with a

    widespread capacity

    for

    reasonableness

    and a

    general

    commitment to

    liberal

    principles, it seems

    to

    me

    right to say that

    the

    best

    political

    ustificationswill be public in

    the manner

    described.25 nd

    yet,

    the

    concessions that

    public

    justification

    makes to accessibility should

    not be

    confused

    with

    other,more political and

    problematic

    oncessions that

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    6/26

    284

    POLITICAL

    THEORY

    MAY

    1990

    some

    liberals

    might

    be

    disposed

    to

    make

    in

    the face

    of

    disagreement

    and

    controversy.

    POLITICIZING

    USTIFICATION?

    To

    smooth the

    way for

    a

    practical

    political settlement

    a

    convergence

    of

    reasonable

    people

    on

    common

    principles

    of

    justice

    liberals

    too often

    min-

    imize

    the

    broad

    and

    deep

    ramifications

    of

    liberalism. The

    question

    is,

    Rawlssays, what s theleast thatmustbe asserted;and f itmustbe asserted,

    what is its

    least

    controversial

    orm? 26

    his liberal

    reticence,

    I

    shall

    suggest,

    grows

    out of

    a

    desire

    for

    widespread

    agreement,but also

    flirts

    with

    a kind

    of

    liberal false

    consciousness.

    Liberals

    should,

    I

    shall

    argue,

    be

    candid about

    their

    partisanships,

    open

    in their

    arguments,

    and

    explicit

    on

    the need

    for

    principled

    moderation.

    By

    avoiding claims o

    universal

    ruth,

    r

    claims

    about he

    essential

    nature

    and

    identity of

    persons,

    Rawls

    asserts, the

    political

    conception

    of liberal

    justification

    extends the

    principleof

    toleration o

    the ultimate

    questions

    of

    philosophy

    itself.27

    Justice

    as

    fairness

    deliberately

    stays

    on

    the

    surface ;

    political

    justification

    seeks

    only to

    identify the kernel of

    overlapping

    consensus

    likely

    to be

    affirmed

    by

    each of

    the

    opposing

    comprehensive

    moral

    doctrines n

    a

    reasonably

    ust

    society.28

    The

    liberalismof

    overlapping

    consensus

    avoids close

    links with

    com-

    prehensive

    moral

    deals:

    dealsthat

    nclude

    conceptions f

    what is

    of

    value

    in

    human

    life,

    ideals

    of

    personal

    virtue

    and

    character,

    and

    the like,

    that

    are to inform

    much

    of

    our

    nonpolitical

    conduct

    (in the limit

    of

    our life as a

    whole). 29

    As

    Charles

    Larmoreputs

    it,

    we do

    better

    to

    recognize

    that lib-

    eralism s

    not a

    philosophyof

    man, but a

    philosophy

    of

    politics. 30

    nd

    so,

    we

    adopt

    a

    conception

    of the

    person

    framed as part

    of,

    and

    restricted

    o,

    an

    explicitly

    political

    conceptionof

    justice....

    [Plersons

    can

    accept

    this

    conception

    of

    themselvesas

    citizens

    and

    use it

    when

    discussing

    questions

    of

    political ustice

    withoutbeing

    committed

    in

    other

    parts

    of

    their ife to

    comprehensive

    moral

    dealsoften

    associatedwith

    liberalism,

    forexample,theidealsof autonomyandindividuality.31

    It is

    true

    enough

    that,

    given

    the

    differences

    amongthe

    religious

    and

    moral

    perspectives

    adopted

    n

    a

    liberal

    society,

    citizens

    will

    have

    different

    reasons

    for

    supporting he

    liberal

    settlement.

    And

    yet,

    while

    we

    seek

    reasons

    hat

    are

    widely

    accessible and

    acceptable,we

    must

    acknowledge he

    broad

    and

    deep

    implications

    of

    basic

    liberal

    principles

    and

    institutions.32

    iberal

    political

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    7/26

    Macedo

    POLITICSOF

    JUSTIFICATION

    285

    principles do not stay on

    the

    surface,

    and their

    consequences

    cannot

    be

    confined

    to a certain

    sphere

    of our lives.

    Let

    us examine how

    the

    various

    thrustsof theminimization trategy ail.

    TheBreadthand Weightof LiberalPolitical

    Principles

    The phrase overlapping

    consensus might be taken

    to underdescribe

    what iberalism tands

    or.Politics

    is

    the final recourse

    or

    people

    who cannot

    agree. People who

    disagree

    about

    religious

    beliefs

    or other

    commitments

    mustregard ommonpoliticalprinciplesasregulativeof all their nteractions

    with others. Liberalism

    requires,

    herefore,not merely

    an

    overlapping

    con-

    sensus but a consensus that

    practically

    overridesall

    competing

    values.33

    The idea of an overlapping

    onsensus does correctly

    suggest

    that

    specif-

    ically political

    values need not do all the work of

    supporting

    he liberal

    settlement or

    everyone

    or even

    most

    people.34

    he

    comprehensive

    moral

    and

    religious views of

    liberal citizens

    may provide a

    variety of values and

    interests

    hat

    support,without forming a partof, the

    sharedpolitical frame-

    work: religiousconvictionsthatprizefree and openargumentn a pluralistic

    environment,for

    example, or atheistic man-centered

    doctrines

    that

    prize

    human

    fulfillment

    n

    this life. Shared iberalvalues need

    not themselves be

    strongenough

    to overrideall

    competing

    ones so

    long

    as the

    weight,

    as

    it

    were,

    of liberal

    and

    supporting or proliberal)values

    is

    enough

    to

    outweigh

    all

    competing (or

    antiliberal)

    values and interests.

    The

    success and

    stability

    of

    liberal politics depends, therefore,on

    people's private

    beliefs and commit-

    ments

    becoming

    importantly iberalized becoming, that

    s, congruentwith

    andsupportiveof liberalpolitics.

    Liberalism

    provides

    wide bounds

    within which

    people are free to settle

    on

    their own

    religious beliefs,

    aesthetic values, and so

    on. And yet,

    basic

    liberal

    principles of

    respect or persons and theirrights,

    for example)

    wash

    across

    the whole

    of

    our

    lives,

    not

    determining

    all our

    choices

    but

    limiting,

    structuring,

    nd

    conditioning

    our

    lives as a whole.

    Illiberal orms of

    private

    associationare

    strictly

    ruled

    out, and manyother nterestsand

    commitments

    are

    bound to be

    discouragedby the

    free, open,

    pluralistic,progressive,and

    (arguably) ommercialisticnatureof a liberalsociety.

    Liberals

    do

    not,

    moreover, ust sit

    and hope that

    personal beliefs will

    become

    liberalized.

    In

    John Locke's

    Letter

    ConcerningToleration, or

    example,

    the liberal

    flag was planted

    deep within the bounds of

    people's

    comprehensive alues.

    Although

    Locke denies that he

    careof men's souls

    is committed o civil

    authority nd

    emphasizes he distinctionbetween

    public

    and

    privaterealms,

    he

    must appeal,nevertheless, o a

    certainkind of

    private

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    8/26

    286

    POLITICAL

    THEORY

    MAY

    1990

    character:

    o all Men thathave Souls

    largeenough

    to

    prefer

    he true

    Interest

    of the Publick

    before

    that

    of

    a

    Party.

    Considerthe repertoireof arguments or tolerationsupplied by Locke:

    Thatsalvation

    depends

    on

    an

    inner

    aiththatcannot

    be

    coerced,

    a

    distinction

    between

    the essential

    and he nonessential

    n

    Christian

    octrine,

    he

    suspicion

    that

    intolerance s a mere cloak for

    power,

    a

    social

    compact argument or

    political

    legitimacy,

    and the claim that

    oppression

    not

    liberty

    eads

    to

    vio-

    lence andrebellion.

    Significantly,

    Locke

    crosses the

    public/private

    oundary

    in

    arguing

    or

    toleration,

    nd

    n

    this

    way directly

    engages

    and

    shapes

    he

    most

    deeply personal

    concerns.

    Although

    such

    a

    strategy

    may

    seem

    dangerous,

    t

    is unavoidable.

    People's privatecommitments n a liberal

    society

    do

    not

    become

    liberal

    accidentally.

    A

    liberal

    polity

    takes

    care,

    in

    shaping

    educational

    nstitutions

    and

    in

    other ways

    (such

    as

    promotingcommerce),

    to

    encourage

    ts

    citizens

    to

    adopt

    a

    range

    of

    commitments hat

    support

    he

    liberal

    political

    settlement.

    What

    s distinctiveabouta liberal

    society

    is

    not that

    t

    wholly

    lacks a

    tutelary

    apparatus,

    ut that this

    apparatus

    peratesgently

    and

    often

    indirectly.35

    t

    is

    easy for us to take the

    success

    of

    liberalismfor

    granted,

    but

    only

    because

    liberal

    nstitutionshave been at work for so long.

    The

    Depth of

    Liberal

    Principles

    The

    notion of anoverlapping

    consensus might

    also suggest that

    political

    norms

    somehow

    stay on the surface,giving rise to

    no deep claims

    aboutthe

    kind of

    persons iberalism

    akes us to be. Consider

    Rawls's remark:

    We can, as it were, enter...[the

    original] position any

    time simply by

    reasoning for

    principlesof

    justice in accordancewith the enumerated

    estrictions.When in

    this way

    we simulate

    being in this position,our

    reasoningno morecommitsus to a

    metaphysical

    doctrineaboutthe nature

    of the self thanour playing a game

    like monopoly

    commits us

    to

    thinking hatwe are

    landlords

    ngaged in a desperate

    ivalry,winner take all.36

    Liberal

    ustice

    requiresus to be a certainsort of

    personall the time.37

    We do

    not

    play

    at

    being just now and

    then, as we occasionallyplay

    Monopoly.

    No

    doubt, we can often

    distinguishthe public

    and private

    identities of

    liberal

    citizens:Politically

    speaking,Saul of Tarsus

    ettingout for

    Damascus

    is the

    Paul who

    arrivesthere.38

    Likewise as

    citizens,

    we might support he

    difference

    principle (accepting

    only those

    inequalities that work

    to the

    advantage

    of the

    least

    well-off)

    while eschewing

    it in our private affairs.

    Nevertheless,

    liberalism

    presupposesthe widespreadexistence of

    certain

    deep character

    raits.39

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    9/26

    Macedo POLITICSOF

    JUSTIFICATION 287

    Liberalism

    elevates

    impartial tandards

    of respect

    for all

    persons

    and

    in

    doing so

    implies

    that

    people should be

    capable

    of

    reflectively

    distancing

    themselves

    from the

    whole range of their

    particular

    ommitments

    friend-

    ships,

    family ties,

    business

    associations-although

    not on all of them

    all

    at

    once)

    for the

    sake

    of

    interposing

    mpersonal

    tandards

    fjustice

    and

    honoring

    the

    equal

    rights

    of others.It

    cannotbe right o

    say,

    as

    Rawls

    does,

    that iberal

    citizens may, regard t is

    simply

    unthinkable o view themselves

    apart

    rom

    certain

    religious,

    philosophical,

    and moralconvictions.

    0

    Of

    course,

    critical

    self-reflection s not

    required

    f our

    personal

    commit-

    ments are

    already

    iberal

    but

    what guarantees hat?

    The

    reflective

    capaci-

    ties of

    liberal citizens, alertto

    possible conflicts between

    personalcommit-

    ments and

    liberal rights,

    should be a

    central

    mechanism or

    preserving

    and

    advancing

    he

    cause of

    justice

    in

    a well-ordered

    ociety.

    The

    Dynamics of

    LiberalPrinciples

    There s

    yet

    a

    thirdway

    in

    which

    it

    sometimes

    seems that iberalsminimize

    the reachof liberalvalues:byoveremphasizing heextent o whichliberalism

    settles

    basic

    moral issues once

    and for all. And so Rawls:

    a

    liberal

    conceptionmeets the

    urgentpolitical

    requirement

    o fix, once and for all,

    the

    contentof

    basic rightsand

    iberties,

    and to assignthem

    special priority.

    Doing this

    takes

    those

    guarantees

    off the

    political

    agenda....41

    The extent to which

    liberal

    values

    constituteus as persons

    becomes

    clearer

    when we considerthe dynamicqualitiesof liberalpublicjustification.

    Many

    basic

    liberal

    guaranteesnow

    seem pretty

    irmly

    settled

    in

    America

    (the evil

    of

    slavery,women's

    suffrage,

    he right o criticize the

    govemment),

    and these

    might

    be takenas

    a

    hardcore of rights

    whose

    fixity contributes o

    public

    trust

    and political

    stability.It

    cannot be claimed,

    however,

    that

    our

    Constitution

    or any

    other)

    managed

    o

    fix, once

    and

    for

    all,

    the

    content

    of

    basic

    rights and liberties.

    The

    contours of every one of

    our most basic

    liberties

    remains a

    matterof

    lively

    disagreement

    and whole

    categories of

    rights (of homosexuals,for example)remain argelyunacknowledged.The

    Constitution

    did

    not

    so much

    settle

    as frame an

    ongoing

    debate about

    the

    bounds

    between

    individual

    ibertyand government

    power.

    Public

    justification

    should be a

    never-ending

    commitment.It

    would be

    sheer

    hubris o think

    hatwe

    have, or ever

    will have,

    the whole political

    truth.

    We are

    always learningand

    confronting

    new circumstances;

    we will

    always

    have

    progress

    to make.

    Moreover, we

    could

    have no confidence

    in

    our

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    10/26

    288

    POLITICAL

    THEORY MAY

    1990

    reasonsfor

    committingourselves to what we

    understand

    ustice

    to

    be

    unless

    we keep

    debating

    t and remain

    open

    to new and better

    nterpretations

    f

    it.

    We

    cannothonorour statusas

    reasonable

    beings

    unless

    we remain

    open

    to

    a

    critical

    dialogue

    aboutthe

    justifiability

    of our

    deepest political

    conceptions,

    whatever

    they

    may be.

    Liberalism

    establishes,

    or

    good

    reason,

    a

    process

    of

    public

    debate

    about

    itself

    among other

    things. Liberalsneed dissenters rom liberalism

    because,

    as

    Mill

    observed,

    He

    who knows

    only

    his

    own side of the

    case,

    knows

    little

    of that. 42Not

    surprisingly,

    hen, closing public

    debate

    on basic

    political

    issues is

    incompatiblewith our

    deepest

    ideals

    and our

    practice

    of

    respecting

    even subversive

    speech (while

    drawing

    a

    sharp

    line between

    speech

    and

    action).43

    I

    do not mean to

    say

    that the

    question

    of

    slavery,

    for

    example,

    should

    be

    reopened.

    But

    the fact

    thatrace

    remainson our

    agenda

    meansthat he liberal

    understanding

    f this basic

    issue remainsvivid and has a chance

    to

    grow

    and

    deepen.

    And

    because

    public

    justification

    s

    dynamic

    and

    open,

    we can

    hope

    that iberal

    values

    will

    be

    tested,refined,andextendedever more

    pervasively

    throughoutsociety. All this means, as well, that while certain liberal

    guarantees

    may become

    stable, the overall

    patternof

    rights

    s

    likely

    to be

    in

    constant

    motion.

    Public

    justification

    s not a

    means

    only but also an

    end

    in

    itself:

    being

    a

    self-critical

    reasongiver s the best

    way of

    being

    a

    liberal and a

    good

    way

    (liberalsmust

    suppose)of

    livinga life.

    The

    reflective,

    self-critical

    capacities

    we

    associatewith public

    justificationmust,

    therefore,

    be

    regarded sperma-

    nent

    and

    ever-developing

    characteristics

    f

    liberal

    citizens at their

    best.

    The

    Method

    of

    Avoidance

    For the

    sake of

    facilitating

    he public

    acceptance

    of basic

    liberal princi-

    ples,

    liberals

    sometimes

    limit the reach

    and

    consequencesof

    liberal

    princi-

    ples in the

    ways

    we have seen.

    I

    have

    argued, in effect,

    that

    liberalism

    constitutes

    a

    regime:

    Liberalprinciples

    andgoals

    shapeour

    ives

    pervasively,

    deeply, and

    relentlessly.

    To

    a

    great

    extent, the modes

    of

    limitation hat we

    have

    examined

    so far

    are

    more

    apparent

    han

    real instances

    of

    reticencerather han

    a real

    refusal

    to

    acknowledge

    the full

    implicationsof

    liberalism.Rawls

    finally

    admits hat

    liberalism

    hapes

    the lives of

    liberal

    citizens broadly

    and

    deeply, nfluencing

    people'sdeepest

    aspirations. 45 e

    insists only

    that

    iberalism s not

    fully

    comprehensive

    meaning that

    the regime

    does not

    prescribe everything

    about

    the

    lives of its

    citizens)

    and says that

    its

    broadinfluences

    simply

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    11/26

    Macedo POLITICSOF JUSTIFICATION

    289

    cannotbe avoided

    on

    any

    view of political justice. 46Rawls defends the

    pervasiveand nonneutral onsequencesof liberal ustice by arguing hat its

    aim is to be fair to

    moral

    persons

    (as

    liberalism

    understands

    hem),

    not to

    all

    conceptions

    of the

    good

    or all

    ways

    of

    life.47

    But deep at the heart of Rawls's understanding

    f

    justification

    lies

    the

    methodof avoidance, a directstrategy

    o avoid

    assessing

    the truthor

    falsity

    of

    deeply

    held

    personalviews,

    such

    as

    religious

    beliefs or other

    aspects

    of

    people's comprehensive

    moralviews:

    nor need we say thatpoliticalvalues are intrinsicallymore importanthanother values

    and that's

    why

    the other

    values are overridden.

    ndeed,saying

    that

    is

    the kind

    of

    thing

    we hope to avoid, and achieving

    an

    overlapping

    onsensusenables us to avoid it.48

    Does it

    really? Can public justification

    avoid making

    ultimatejudgments

    aboutwhich

    religious beliefs,

    for

    example,

    are

    justified?

    What does

    a

    liberal

    say

    about

    a

    range

    of

    religious

    beliefs that

    include

    ecumenicalCatholicism,

    undamentalist rotestantism,

    nd

    sects that

    require

    holy war againstnonbelievers?There are, says Rawls, noresourceswithin

    the

    political view to judge those

    conflicting conceptions.They

    are equally

    permissible provided they respect

    the limits imposed by the principles of

    political justice. 49

    Underline

    provided :

    All

    religions compatible

    with

    liberalism will be respected;those not compatible

    will

    be opposed.50

    The

    liberal

    must

    in

    this way imply

    that religious convictions incompatible

    with

    liberalismare unsupportable.

    In

    making the personalchoice

    about whetherto support iberal politics,

    one wouldweigh liberalandproliberal alues against he strongestcompet-

    ing package,as one sees it. (Is the

    freedomto debate,choose, and live one's

    own

    way really

    more

    mportant

    hanstruggling o establisha commonculture

    that

    supports piety and other-worldlinessand punishes blasphemers?

    Is

    peaceful pluralismreally more important hanthe ideal of ChristianUnity?)

    To

    vindicate

    its overridingstatus,

    a liberal political moralitywill have to

    speak directlyto illiberalcomprehensivepersonal deals, arguing hat

    these

    are false or

    less important hancompeting iberalvalues, or that they

    can be

    mendedand made compatiblewith liberalism.

    The reticent liberal may still

    try to avoid issues of truth and ultimate

    importanceby excluding fromthe political space, as it were, the comparison

    between

    the

    political conception

    and conflicting comprehensiveviews:

    Of

    course,

    citizens

    must decide

    for

    themselves

    whether, n light of theircomprehensive

    views, and taking into account the

    great political values realized by the political

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    12/26

    290 POLITICALTHEORY MAY 1990

    conception, they can endorsethatconception

    with its

    idea

    of

    society

    as a fair

    system

    of

    social cooperation.5'

    But can political theory simply be silent

    at the crucial

    moment

    of

    deciding

    on

    the meritsof liberalism?52

    Rawls's conception of justification

    employs

    a

    remarkabledivision of

    labor.The citizen mustdecide for himself, n light of

    his own

    comprehen-

    sive scheme of values, whether

    o

    acceptthe political

    construction.

    The

    issue

    of

    acceptance

    s not

    within

    the

    verge

    of

    political

    ustification

    for

    Rawls,

    because acceptance

    raises

    questions

    of ultimate

    importance necessarily

    situatedwithin the

    Apace

    of comprehensiveviews, a space that remains

    personal

    and

    publicly opaque

    even after

    political

    theory

    has done its work.

    Liberalpolitical values must occupy, as

    I

    have

    argued,

    much of the same

    space

    as

    personal comprehensive deals, religious

    and otherwise.

    And

    so,

    unable to

    confine political values to

    an autonomous

    phere,

    Rawls

    attempts

    to restrict

    the scope

    of

    political justification by

    dividing

    the

    process

    of

    justification

    n

    two. First,

    here s

    the stage

    of

    construction,

    n

    which we leave

    aside the controversial lements of our

    comprehensive

    personalperspective

    because we

    recognize

    that

    reasonablepeople

    with

    whom we

    wish

    to form

    a

    political association reject them.53The stage of construction

    s a search for

    reasonable agreement. Only after construction s

    complete

    do we enter a

    second

    stage

    in which

    the

    question

    of

    acceptance

    comes

    to the fore. At this

    second

    stage, our controversial eligious and other

    personal

    convictions

    are

    reengaged:Can I, as a devout Catholic, really

    live with the kinds of ques-

    tioning

    attitudesandbeliefs

    likely to be promotedby

    a liberal

    framework?54

    The problem s thatsegmenting he processof

    justificationonly gives the

    appearance

    of

    avoiding

    a direct

    conflict between

    political and personal

    values. The conflict is not avoidedbut merely

    shiftedoff the political agenda

    (and, presumably, ut of political fora) by

    bracketing he question

    of

    theory

    acceptance,making t private,and leaving it aside

    until the public construc-

    tion is

    complete. The broaderand deeper

    mplicationsof liberalismremain,

    however, mattersof public concern that citizens

    are bound to raise. Public

    justification

    should have

    something o say abouthow

    the interface

    between

    political and personalvalues is negotiated.Managing hat interface s, in a

    sense, the crucialpolitical ssue: an issue we cannot

    help addressing n public

    fora,

    an

    issue that in some of its aspectsat least) we

    should address n public

    fora.

    A

    more realistic model of justificationwould

    allow, in effect, that par-

    ticipants' personal moral convictions are

    engaged as each feature of the

    political

    view is

    constructed.Theory constructionproperly nvolves not a

    rigid segmentationof public and private spaces

    of value, but a process of

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    13/26

    Macedo

    POLITICS

    OF JUSTIFICATION

    291

    negotiationbetween shared

    public

    values and each

    person's

    set of

    compre-

    hensive and personal

    values. None of us can

    entirely

    leave behind

    the

    baggage

    of

    our personalconvictions

    when

    thinking

    about

    political

    morality.

    At

    each stage of the

    argument,

    we

    would seek

    principles

    hatwe can live

    with

    in

    our public and broader

    personal

    capacities,

    as

    beings

    at

    once

    public

    and

    private.

    And here

    again, despite his

    attempt

    o

    limit the

    space

    of

    political values,

    Rawls

    reluctantlyadmitsthat a defenderof liberalismcannot avoid

    steering

    into

    the shoals of religious

    controversy

    and other matters

    of

    deep

    disagree-

    ment and

    cannot,crucially,avoid

    engaging

    and

    publicly relyingupon

    impor-

    tant

    featuresof a

    comprehensive

    et of

    moral

    values:

    in

    affirminga political

    conception of justice we

    may

    eventually

    have

    to

    assert

    at least

    certain

    aspects

    of our own

    comprehensive

    by

    no means

    necessarily

    fully comprehen-

    sive) religious

    or

    philosophical

    doctrine.This

    happens

    whenever someone

    insists,

    for

    example,

    that

    certain

    questions

    are

    so

    fundamental hat to

    ensure their

    being rightly

    settled

    ustifies

    civil strife . . .

    [T]hesalvation

    of

    a whole

    people, may

    be said to

    depend

    on

    it.

    At

    this

    point

    we have no

    alternative ut

    to

    deny

    this,

    and

    to

    assert

    he

    kind of

    thing

    we had hopedto avoid.55

    The

    participants

    n

    theory

    constructionhave

    recourse o their

    comprehensive

    views as they

    go along.

    And so, for example,

    liberals

    must deny

    that the

    concern for

    salvation

    requires

    anything

    ncompatible

    with

    equal

    liberty

    of

    conscience. 56

    Public

    justification s a

    process of constructive

    negotiation n which

    the

    moves are

    partly

    determined

    by what we tegard

    as reasonable

    assertionsand

    compromises rom within our comprehensiveview, and not only from a

    public perspective.

    We

    do

    not

    put

    off

    comparing he

    political construction

    with our

    personalview until

    the construction s

    complete.

    We do not

    really

    keep personal

    and public spaces of

    value

    separate.Each of us

    carries our

    comprehensivemoralviews with

    us

    in

    politics,drawingon

    the

    resources hey

    provide, and

    displaying

    these resourcesto

    others. Our

    deepest convictions

    and

    commitmentsare at risk in

    political

    controversies,and they are

    shaped

    by

    the

    confrontation

    with

    both

    political norms

    and the deep

    convictions of

    otherpeople. Enoughmustbe said to adjudicateat least the most serious

    conflicts between

    sharedpolitical

    principlesand

    widely held

    comprehensive

    views.

    The political

    construction

    nevitably

    occupies much of the same

    space as

    people's personal

    comprehensive

    values. Political

    theory

    cannot, hen, avoid

    advancing

    claims

    sufficient to tame

    or override

    the illiberal

    componentsof

    comprehensivepersonal

    value

    schemes. The success of

    liberal

    public justi-

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    14/26

    292

    POLITICALTHEORY

    MAY

    1990

    fication does not

    require

    he

    common

    embrace

    of one

    comprehensivemoral

    doctrine,butneitherdoes it allowtheseparation f publicandprivatespaces

    of

    value.

    JUSTIFICATION

    ERSUS

    LOYAL

    Y?

    There could be

    a

    substantiveand

    very political reason

    for

    wanting

    to

    segment

    the

    process

    of

    justification

    n

    the

    way

    that

    Rawls,

    at times at

    least,

    suggests.

    The

    stability

    of a liberal

    regime requires

    hat the

    personal

    moral

    and

    religious

    views

    of

    many people

    will

    (when

    illiberal)

    be mended

    to

    support

    the liberal settlement.

    Ideally,

    this transition

    will

    take

    place

    via

    candid, open

    public arguments.This

    is

    important

    n

    part

    because

    the

    transi-

    tional

    stage does not break

    sharply

    with normal

    practice:

    Public

    ustification

    is,

    as

    I

    have argued, he

    way liberalsshould live.

    Public

    justification s not

    the only means of

    getting

    people to be liberals.

    Some people will become liberalwithoutparticipatingn or being directly

    influenced

    by anythinglike a

    public

    argument.

    Indeed, one

    might

    even

    suppose

    that

    some

    people

    are

    more

    likely

    to be liberals

    f

    they

    are not

    pro-

    voked to

    reflection

    by

    a

    public moral

    argument.There

    might,

    n

    other

    words,

    be a

    trade-offbetween

    candid

    public

    argument nd liberalsocialization.

    Many

    people's

    comprehensive

    moral

    views are, Rawls

    asserts, rather

    loosely formulatedand

    only

    partially

    hought hrough.57

    ome who

    go along

    with

    liberalismonly as a

    modus

    vivendior

    who might oppose it

    altogether

    will often fail to be fully conscious of the relationbetween liberalpolitical

    principles

    and their

    broader personal

    values.

    As a

    consequence, liberal

    principles

    are

    more

    likely

    to win

    an

    initialallegiance

    that is

    independentof our

    comprehensive

    views

    and prior to conflict

    with them.

    Thus when conflicts do

    arise, the

    political

    conception has a better

    chance of

    sustaining tself and

    shapingthose views to

    accord

    with

    its

    requirements.We do not

    say, of

    course, thatthe stronger

    he initial

    allegiance

    the

    better;but it

    is

    desirable,

    politically speaking,that

    it be strong

    enough to make an

    overlapping onsensus

    stable.58

    People

    may go

    along without

    understanding

    nd

    eventuallydevelop liberal

    convictions

    out

    of

    habitrather han

    from

    anything ike a reasoned

    argument:

    many

    if

    not

    most

    citizens come to affirm

    their

    common politicalconception

    without

    seeing any

    particularonnection,

    one way or

    the other,

    between t and heirother

    views.59

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    15/26

    Macedo

    POLITICSOF JUSTIFICATION

    293

    Unconscious

    socialization,

    the

    result of living in an open,

    pluralistic

    environment,

    can contribute o

    a liberal settlement

    (admittedly,

    a

    nonideal

    settlement).' As a practicalmatter, ne mightpinone's hopesonunreflective

    acceptance,especially

    if

    one were disposed

    to see

    self-criticalreflectionand

    open justification as politically disruptive

    and largely beside the point

    of

    liberalpolitics. And

    Rawls, in his reticentmoments,

    sometimesseems to

    be

    deploying

    an

    exoteric

    ersion of liberalism,one

    thatsacrifices full

    disclo-

    sure to avoid confrontation nd contention

    and smooth

    the

    way

    to

    a

    liberal

    settlement.6'

    Widespread,unreflective heory acceptance

    might be jeopardizedby

    the

    open and candiddefense

    of liberalismas a regime.

    Sacrificingphilosophical

    candor and

    open argument

    o smooth the transition o

    liberal

    peace might

    well be justified if there

    really is a tensionbetween

    candorand allegiance,

    and the need

    for

    allegiance

    to liberalismreally is more urgent

    han the

    need

    for full

    disclosure

    and

    open publicjustification.

    Under

    some

    circumstances,

    in other words, public

    justificationmay be a luxury,and promoting iberal

    false

    consciousness

    a moral

    mperative.

    Mustliberals,to generateallegiance,exercise caution

    n

    spelling

    out

    and

    defending

    the full

    implications

    of liberalism?Should philosophical types

    keep theirbig mouths

    shut?

    LIBERAL

    USTIFICATION: UBLIC

    AND CANDID

    Compromising

    n the full

    disclosure

    of what liberalism tands

    or entails

    high costs. First of all, while public justificationis a form of respect for

    persons, failing

    to be

    candid is

    a

    form

    of

    disrespect.

    The

    search for widely

    accessible

    reasons is motivatedby a desire

    to

    respect

    the limits of reason-

    ableness of common citizens. The embraceof

    liberal false consciousness

    is

    moved not

    by respect

    but by fear of conflict and despairat the incapacity or

    reasonableness.

    Many practicalproblems

    cannot be settled without confronting

    he

    deep

    and

    divisive

    implications

    of

    a liberal public morality.

    Constitutional ases

    involvingthe FirstAmendment's ree exercise of religion clause is (depend-

    ing

    on

    how you

    look at it) a minefield or a gold mine of hard and deeply

    revealingquestionsat

    the tense interfaceof religion and politics.62Even so,

    one could

    try

    to

    paper

    over and avoid

    problemsby paying lip

    service to

    the

    public/private

    istinctionand a

    simplistic

    dea

    of liberal

    neutrality,deas that

    have

    a

    certainamount

    of

    currencyandthatdo, even

    when sincerelydeployed,

    obfuscatewhat

    is at stake

    in

    practicalpolitical

    issues.63

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    16/26

    294

    POLMCAL THEORY

    MAY

    1990

    Thereare otherbenefitsof

    public ustification

    hat

    a lack

    of

    candor

    would

    threaten:Althougha publicconceptionof justification,by avoidingoverly

    complex

    and esoteric

    arguments

    osters

    trust,any

    lack of

    candor,

    should

    it

    become

    publicly

    known,

    would undermine hat rust.And

    although

    avoiding

    problems

    might seem

    justified as a

    temporary

    measure,

    critical reflection

    might be hard

    o

    revive,

    especially

    under

    conditions

    of real

    popular

    consen-

    sus, and after

    philosophical

    and

    popular

    culture

    have

    diverged.

    Besides the

    costs

    of

    theoretical

    reticence,

    there are

    positive

    benefits

    of

    stirringup

    a little conflict.

    My

    sense is that

    Mill

    was

    right

    in

    thinking

    that

    someintemalopposition o a society'spoliticalmorality s a goodthing.(As

    Yogi

    Berra put

    it;

    If

    the world

    were

    perfect,

    it

    wouldn't

    be. )

    Liberals

    n

    particular re

    apt

    to

    forget

    what it

    is

    they

    stand

    for. Liberal heorists end

    to

    systematically

    minimizewhat

    liberalism

    ntails

    (as

    we have

    seen).

    One

    must

    be

    troubled

    by

    the

    slow and

    limp response

    of Western

    ntellectuals

    to the

    Ayatollah'scall for

    Salman

    Rushdie's

    death.

    Confronting

    anatics

    and

    grap-

    pling

    with divisiveness

    remindsus of

    what we

    stand

    for

    as

    liberals,

    and

    that

    we

    live

    in

    a

    world

    in

    which liberal

    values are

    neither

    uncontroversial

    nor

    foregoneconclusions.

    Timidity and

    a too

    ready

    willingness

    to

    compromise

    can be as

    danger-

    ous as

    intransigence

    and

    dogmatism.

    It is

    not

    obvious

    to me that

    divisive-

    ness is

    now a

    greater

    dangerthan

    timidity.

    Draining

    iberalism

    of its self-

    consciousnessand

    partisanship

    elps

    cultivatean

    allegiancethat s

    blind

    and

    bland.

    We

    should

    pick our

    fights

    carefully

    but

    preserve

    our

    ability to

    recognize

    and

    fight the

    good

    fight.

    As

    things

    stand,

    Americans

    are

    not

    especially

    reflective

    about

    what

    our

    regime

    stands or. A

    certain

    boldness in

    thedefense of liberalismmaynowbe a publicservice.

    Of

    course,

    domestic

    peace and

    tranquility

    nd the

    many

    political

    goods

    that

    have

    nothing o do with

    being

    self-critical,

    reason-giving

    iberal

    citizens

    all

    might counsel in

    favor

    of

    papering

    over divisive

    questions.

    And let

    me

    add

    one

    additional

    onsideration

    n

    favor

    of

    reticence:

    Liberalism s an

    export

    commodity

    andnot

    only

    a

    good for

    domestic

    consumption.64

    hereare

    places

    in

    the

    world

    where liberal

    values are

    decidedly

    on

    the

    defensive. To

    encour-

    age

    the

    exportof

    liberalism,

    we

    mightwant

    to

    keep

    the price

    downby

    playing

    along withthosewho wouldminimizewhat it standsfor.

    My

    own

    disposition

    would

    be to adopt

    the

    public

    conceptionof

    justifica-

    tion

    and to

    deploy

    it

    candidly.

    We should

    seek,

    in other

    words,

    justifications

    that

    are

    not

    only

    reasonable

    but

    that

    can be

    widely

    seen to

    be

    reasonable.

    Once

    justification

    has

    gone

    public,

    a

    good

    deal has

    been

    conceded

    to

    pluralism

    and

    the

    burdens

    of

    reason.

    We should

    be

    extremely

    reluctant o

    go

    further

    and

    avoid

    articulating

    what

    appearto be

    inescapablebut

    possibly

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    17/26

    Macedo POLITICSOF JUSTIFICATION

    295

    divisive implications

    of

    liberalism.65

    o do so would

    be to strikeat the

    heart

    of

    the

    liberal

    aspiration

    o

    public

    justificationby driving

    a

    wedge

    between

    critical reflectionand political practice.

    FOR

    A

    PRINCIPLEDLIBERALMODERATION

    Lest my defense

    of

    open ustifications

    openly arrived

    at

    should

    appear

    naive, let me introduce

    a

    final

    consideration.Public justification

    accepts,

    even

    invites, open

    moral

    disagreement

    on a wide

    range

    of

    political

    contro-

    versies. And yet we know thatbecause

    even the most conscientiousarguers

    often start

    from

    markedlydifferent

    positions, consensus

    can

    be

    difficult

    to

    achieve.

    On

    certain

    especially

    difficult ssues,

    liberal

    public ustification

    has

    room for a kind of moderation.

    The aim of liberalpublic ustification

    s to

    respectdiversity

    while

    forging

    a

    framework

    f common moral

    principles

    hatall

    can

    understand,

    ccept,

    and

    openly

    affirmbeforeone another.The aim is

    a

    transparent, emystified

    ocial

    order,one capable,as Waldronputs it, ofexplaining tself atthe tribunalof

    each

    person'sunderstanding.

    nd so, Rawls'spoliticalconception

    of

    justice

    aims at a

    publicly recognized

    point of

    view

    from which all citizens

    can

    examine before

    one

    anotherwhether

    or not

    their

    political

    and social

    institu-

    tions

    are ust. 66 chieving

    a

    commonmoral ramework

    llows us to express

    our common reasonableness

    publicly;

    it allows

    us,

    in

    effect,

    to

    mutually

    recognize

    one another

    as equally

    reasonablemoralbeings.

    The only way that we can achieve a public moral framework

    while

    accepting the deep and permanent act of diversityis by puttingaside not

    only the personal nterestsandreligiousbeliefs, but also the manyphilosoph-

    ical andmoral

    convictions that

    reasonable ellow citizens

    will

    disagree

    with.

    Participantsmust share

    an

    overriding

    desire to affirmprinciples hat

    are not

    simplyjustified (or true)

    n

    any sense,

    but ratherare capableof being

    widely

    seen to

    be justified (or reasonable).The goal of a public moralframework

    s

    a noble

    one,

    but

    just

    how

    adamantly

    hould we pursue t?

    We

    do not, Rawls insists, strike

    balancesamongthe differentcomprehen-

    sive moraldoctrines religiousand philosophical) hatexist in society:To do

    so would be to abandon he

    hope

    of appearing efore one anotheras free and

    equal,

    or

    fully

    autonomous,

    itizens.67

    We

    must abstract

    away

    from

    or

    leave

    behind

    grounds

    hatwe

    cannotshare

    with reasonable ellow citizens.

    We seek

    a common

    ground

    of

    publicly

    reasonable consensus; we do not accept,

    moderate,

    and

    balance enduringand ineliminabledifferences of belief

    and

    perspective.

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    18/26

    296

    POLITICAL

    THEORY MAY

    1990

    It is

    unrealistic to

    hope

    for

    perfect

    convergence

    on

    a

    common

    moral

    standpoint:

    Thatwould

    require

    a

    very

    strong

    and

    sustaineddesire

    for

    public

    moral

    agreement.

    Given the

    range

    of

    nonpolitical

    nterests hat

    people

    quite

    properly

    have

    in

    a

    liberal

    society,

    it

    would be hard o

    imagine

    thatthe

    desire

    for

    public

    moralconsensus

    could

    be

    sufficiently

    strong

    or

    sustained

    o

    make

    convergence a

    realistic

    possibility.

    The

    kind of common moral

    standpoint

    represented

    y the veil of

    ignorance

    and the

    original

    position

    may

    be

    ideals

    to

    be

    aspired

    or,

    but,

    practically

    peaking,

    we cannot

    hope

    really

    to

    converge

    on

    a

    common

    understanding

    f

    basic

    political

    principles.68

    eople

    will

    be

    moved to

    peek, as it

    were, out

    frombehind theveil of ignorancenotonly by

    self-interest

    or

    impatience,

    but

    also

    by

    the

    variety

    of moral

    beliefs

    excluded

    by the drive for

    principles

    hat

    all

    reasonable

    people

    can

    accept.

    Moderation

    s

    a virtue that

    comes to the

    fore when

    we

    acknowledge

    that

    afterpublic

    reasonableness

    as done

    its work

    (or

    as muchwork as

    reasonable

    people

    are

    prepared

    o

    allow it

    to

    do), our

    perspectives

    will

    inevitably

    remain

    plural

    and

    divergent.

    Moderation

    llows us to

    accept

    the

    fact thata

    large

    and

    diverse

    group

    of

    reasonable

    people can never

    really

    stand within

    the

    same

    moral framework.69Even the best possible liberal settlement will have

    something

    of

    the

    character f

    a

    composite of

    irreduciblydissimilar

    parts.

    It

    would

    be

    nice

    to think

    that all of

    us

    -rich and

    poor;

    libertarian

    nd

    socialist;

    Catholic,

    Jew,

    Amish,

    and

    Jehovah's

    Witness

    could

    stand

    before

    one

    another

    imply

    in

    our

    moral

    capacity.

    And,

    indeed,

    we

    should

    aspire

    to

    do

    so.

    But

    at the end

    of

    the

    political

    day

    we

    must

    simply

    accept

    the

    fact

    of

    reasonable

    disagreement

    nda

    reasonable

    divergenceof

    moral

    perspective.70

    At

    that

    point,

    the most

    reasonable

    hing

    may well

    be to

    moderate

    our

    claims

    mutually n the face of thereasonableclaims of others,to balance,andsplit

    at

    least

    some of

    our

    differences.

    Respect

    s

    called

    for

    in

    the

    face of

    persons

    whom

    we

    regard

    as

    reasonable.

    Even when

    we

    cannot

    really

    respect

    a

    particular

    iew

    (antisemitism,

    acism,

    and other

    views

    based on

    sheer

    prejudice),

    we

    may still

    tolerate its

    expres-

    sion,

    partly

    because

    it

    is

    being

    expressed

    by a

    person:We

    wish

    to

    respect

    hat

    person

    as a

    being

    capable

    of

    reasonand

    we

    wish to

    respect

    peech

    (the

    vehicle

    of

    reason)

    as

    such.

    And

    so we

    tolerate

    the

    antisemiteby

    allowing him

    to

    expresshisviews, but we concede no ground o him,we do notcompromise

    with

    him,

    we do

    not

    approach

    him

    with

    moderation.

    Moderation

    oes

    beyond

    toleration.

    Thereare,

    or

    example,

    many

    reason-

    able

    arguments

    on

    both

    sides

    of the

    abortion

    debate.

    The

    abortion

    question

    is

    so

    vexing,

    in a

    sense,

    precisely

    because there

    are

    weighty

    reasonson

    both

    sides, and it

    is

    easy to

    see

    how

    reasonable

    people

    can

    come

    down

    on

    either

    side.

    On

    policy

    issues

    such as

    abortion,

    which

    seems, as

    things

    stand, o

    come

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    19/26

    Macedo POLITICSOF JUSTIFICATION

    297

    down to a fairly close

    call between two

    well-reasonedsets of

    arguments,

    he

    best

    thing

    for reasonable

    people

    to do

    might

    be to

    acknowledge

    he

    difficulty

    of the argumentand the burdensof reason,to respecttheiropponentsandto

    compromise

    with

    them,

    to find some

    middle

    ground

    hat

    gives

    something

    to

    each side while the argument

    oes forward.7'

    he

    right

    kindof middle

    ground

    on

    abortionwould

    acknowledge

    both the

    great weight

    due to the

    judgment

    of the motherandthe

    fact that his choice concerns

    he

    continuance f another

    life. It would, perhaps,honor a

    woman's choice

    up

    to

    a

    certain

    point

    in

    the

    pregnancy and also countenancea variety of

    measures that would

    not

    be

    permittedwere abortion

    imply

    a

    matter

    of an individual's

    right

    to choose:

    measures o ensure at least that the choice is reflectiveand informed.72

    Moderation s a liberal virtuejustified by the difficulty

    of

    occupying

    a

    common

    moralstandpoint,

    r of exercising

    ourcommon

    capacity

    or reason-

    ableness

    in

    the

    same

    way. Taking

    moderation

    seriously

    would lead

    us to

    qualify

    Dworkin's nsistence hat he party

    with the

    strongest

    ase on balance

    (no matter how close a call)

    has a right to win. The best solution may

    sometimes

    be

    to give

    something

    o

    each side. Moderation

    n

    the face of

    very

    strongcompeting

    cases

    offers a

    way

    of

    honoring

    not

    simply

    the best case but

    also the case that is

    very strong.

    There

    is an

    argument

    o be

    developed

    here

    for

    judicial prudence

    and statesmanship,not (I hope) for pragmatismor a

    blanket

    deferenceto legislatures.73

    To acceptmoderation s to admit hata mutually ransparent

    oliticalorder

    is unrealistic.Explicitly embracing

    he value of moderation

    means that we

    representcitizens

    in

    public justification

    with some measureof

    their differ-

    ences and

    disagreements some measureof partialityof perspective)

    ntact.

    It is a way of coming directly to gripswith the residual and realistically

    ineliminablemoraldiversity hat

    on my analysis) eads to Rawls's reticence.

    I

    am not, I should emphasize, arguing that we should

    celebrate our

    inability o abstract way from

    some of our differences;we should

    acknowl-

    edge

    but

    not idealize our incapacity o achieve a common moral

    perspective.

    We should, rather, accept this

    limitation as an infirmity of

    the human

    condition and adoptan attitude hat allows us to deal with it constructively.

    CONCLUSION

    Even

    where citizens share a desire to establish and support

    political

    institutions that can be commonly

    affirmed as reasonable, fully public

    justificationson controversial

    ssues (ones that all reasonablepeople really

    do

    accept)

    will

    often be

    impossible

    o come by

    -

    we mustreconcileourselves

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    20/26

    298

    POLITICAL

    THEORY MAY

    1990

    to that.

    Although it

    may

    fail

    to

    achieve a

    construction

    hat

    all

    reasonable

    people can

    agree

    upon, public

    reflection can

    help

    us narrowthe

    gaps and

    negotiate

    thetensions

    among

    public and personal

    values.74

    Because it

    respects

    reasonable

    persons

    and

    the limits of

    reason

    as

    located

    in

    persons,

    public

    justification s

    distinctly

    liberal

    and

    democratic,

    ubstan-

    tive

    and

    partisan.Where

    iberals

    see

    respect

    or free and

    equal

    persons,

    some

    religious

    people

    aregoing

    to see

    secularhumanism

    nd the

    hegemony

    of

    a

    way of

    thinking hat

    owes a lot to

    science and

    the

    enlightenment

    but

    that

    is

    deeply at

    odds with

    some

    forms of

    religion.75This cannot be

    avoided.

    Liberalsoffer

    true

    believers, like

    everyone else,

    a

    sphere

    of

    privacy

    and

    the

    opportunity

    o

    continue

    arguing.The liberal

    must,

    in

    the

    end,

    defend

    his

    partisanship

    nd

    not

    evade it.

    If

    liberalism s

    justified,

    that must

    be,

    in

    part

    at

    least,

    because of the

    superiorityof

    justificationsbased on

    widely accept-

    able

    reasons

    and

    public

    arguments, ndbecause reasonable

    people

    really

    are

    worthy of liberal

    respect.

    The

    public conception

    of

    justification

    may seem to embrace he

    concerns

    of

    those

    postmodernist

    hilosophers

    who

    deny

    the

    availability

    of

    objective

    standards f truth, tandardswhose justificationdoes notdependon thesocial

    practices of

    particular

    ocieties.76But

    while

    acknowledging the practical

    limits

    of

    reason,

    public

    justification does

    not

    embrace

    conventionalismor

    localism. Reason

    establishes he

    contoursand

    substanceof

    moderation: t is

    reasonable o

    want to

    live

    in

    accordancenot only

    with

    reasonableprinciples

    but also

    with

    principles that all

    can

    see to be

    reasonable.

    We have

    good

    reasons for

    tempering

    our

    expectations

    about the

    public

    efficacy of

    reason,

    not for

    abandoning ur

    aspiration

    o

    govern

    ourselves

    reasonably.

    Public justification is a core liberal goal, one that informs practical

    aspirations nd

    political

    nstitutions like

    judicial

    review) that

    iberalscan

    be

    proud

    of.

    But public

    justification

    s not our

    only

    political

    goal. We

    want the

    freedom

    to live

    our own

    lives,

    and so a

    release

    from

    political

    argument.

    We

    want

    peace, and

    more

    thanthat,

    we

    want

    comity or

    concord.

    Comity

    is a

    political good

    that

    is not

    quite the same as

    moral

    consensus,

    as

    Richard

    Hofstadter

    describes:

    Comityexists in societyto thedegreethatthoseenlisted n its contendingnterestshave

    a

    basic

    minimal

    regard

    for

    each

    other....

    The basic

    humanityof

    the opposition

    is not

    forgotten;

    ivility is not

    abandoned;he

    sense thata

    community ife must

    be

    carriedon

    after

    the

    acerbic ssues of

    the

    moment

    havebeen

    fought

    over andwon is

    seldom

    far out

    77

    of

    mind....

    And

    in the

    first

    Federalist,

    Publius

    urged

    moderation

    as a

    means to

    comity

    even

    more

    forcefully:

    This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 22:19:01 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/26/2019 424 fPolitical Theory Volume 18 Issue 2 1990 [Doi 10.2307%2F191346] Stephen Macedo -- The Politics of Justificat

    21/26

    Macedo POLITICSOF

    JUSTIFICATION 299

    So numerous ndeed andso powerful

    are

    the

    causes which serve

    to

    give

    a

    false bias to

    judgment,thatwe, upon manyoccasions, see wise and good men on the

    wrong

    as well

    as on therightside of questionsof the firstmagnitude o society.Thiscircumstance, f

    duly

    attended o, would furnisha lesson of moderation o those who

    are ever so much

    persuaded

    f their

    being

    in

    the right

    n

    any controversy.

    Comity,

    or

    concord, requires

    a

    gift

    for conciliation and a

    willingness to

    compromise.

    There

    may, of course, be

    grounds or various forms of moderation for a

    prudentmoderation, or example,

    in the face of rancorous

    disagreement nd

    imminentviolence). We do well, however, to makeroom for a principled

    moderationat the most basic

    level, in our understanding f publicjustifica-

    tion. To

    do so

    allows us to define

    and defend a form of moderationwhose

    justificationgrows out

    of

    the commitment

    o reasonableness

    tself, and so to

    extend

    moderationon

    grounds

    hat hold out the promise

    of drawingpeople

    into the

    process of public reason.

    Principledmoderationdrawssupport, hen,

    from the

    hope of an ever-more-reasonable olitical order.

    NOTES

    1. I will

    refer to the

    United

    States as an

    exampleof

    a liberalsociety

    because it is familiar

    and in

    manyways

    liberal.

    I

    do not

    mean

    to identify iberalismwith

    American

    politics,

    although

    certain

    nstitutions

    specially

    suited to

    liberalreason

    giving

    are

    well

    developed

    n

    America.

    For

    a more extended

    treatmentof liberalism n

    general

    and as

    manifested

    n

    American

    national

    institutions, ee my

    Liberal

    VirtuesOxford:

    Oxford

    University

    Press,1990).

    2. JeremyWaldron, Theoretical oundations f Liberalism, hilosophical

    Quarterly,

    7

    (1987