9 empiricism

Upload: marran

Post on 05-Jul-2018

246 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    1/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm

    CHAPTER 8: BRITISH EMPIRICISM 

    From The History of Philosophy: A Short Survey by James Fieser Home: www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/110

    Copyright 2008, updated: 1/7/2012 

    Contents 

    A. Locke No Innate IdeasSimple and Complex IdeasPrimary and Secondary Qualities

     Natural Rights and RevolutionB. Berkeley

    Idealism: No Materials ObjectsArguments against Material ObjectsGod and Evil

    C. HumeOrigin and Association of IdeasPersonal Identity and CausalityBelief in MiraclesMorality: Reason vs. EmotionRadical Skepticism and Natural Belief 

     Questions for Reflection1. Our five senses clearly give us a lot of information. Is there any knowledge that we obtain without our 

    five senses?2. Consider the qualities of an apple, and explain which of these belong to the apple itself, and which

    exist only in our minds.3. When you look at an object, such as a chair, you typically assume that there really exists a “chair-

    shaped thing” that is the source of your perceptions of it. What is your evidence that a physical“chair-shaped thing” actually exists?

    4. You typically assume that your personal identity remains unified and intact as time passes from onemoment to the next. Do you really have a unified conscious experience of yourself from onemoment to the next? If so, try to describe it.

    5. Some philosophers think that morality involves a rational judgment about objective moral truths, andothers think that moral judgments are emotional reactions that we have when we observe peopleact in certain ways. Does one of these views seem more correct than the other?

     During the 17th and 18th centuries, Britain certainly had its fair share of rationalist philosophers,

     particularly of the Platonist variety. However, Britain’s philosophy was soon dominated by an alternativeand more scientific view that knowledge is gained primarily or mainly through the five senses. We seethis presumption in Francis Bacon’s statement that in our efforts to understand nature we can “can actand understand no further than [we have] . . . observed in either the operation or the contemplation of themethod and order of nature” ( New Organon, 1.1). Direct experience is foundational for obtaining

    knowledge, and this position is known as empiricism. During the first half of the 18th century, three great philosophers—Locke, Berkeley and Hume—argued for this approach, thus forming a philosophical

    movement known as British empiricism. Contrary to the 17th century rationalist philosophers in

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    2/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 2

    Continental Europe, these British empiricists largely denied the role of innate ideas and deduction in thequest for knowledge. Instead, they argued, knowledge comes from sensory experience and inductivereasoning. A. LOCKEThe originator of British empiricism was John Locke (1632–1704), who was born into a Puritan familynear Bristol, England, his father being an attorney and government official. He studied at OxfordUniversity and later worked there in various positions, where he took particular interest in the writings of

    Descartes and other modern thinkers. The direction of Locke’s life shifted dramatically when he acceptedemployment as the household physician of a prominent British politician who founded the radical Whig

     party, which opposed the absolute rule of the British monarchy. As public opposition to the King was onthe increase during this period, Locke’s association with the Whigs forced him to flee to the Netherlandsfor his safety. He returned home after the King was overthrown in the Glorious Revolution of 1688, andsubsequently published a steady stream of books that he had been working on for some time. The bookswere instant sensations, and his reputation skyrocketed, rivaling that of Newton. He died at age 72, neverhaving married or produced children. Locke wrote on a range of subjects, including politics, religion,economics and education. His fame as a philosopher, though, rests on his work in two distinct areas.First, as a metaphysical philosopher he expounded the empiricist position that there are no innate ideasand all knowledge comes from experience. He sets this out in his Essay Concerning Human

    Understanding (1689). Second, as a political philosopher he developed the notion of natural rights in hisTwo Treatises of Government (1690). We will look at each of these. No Innate Ideas

    Throughout the history of philosophy it was common to hold that human beings are born with a specialset of ideas—innate ideas—that guide us in our quest for truth and certainty. In ancient times Plato heldthat we have an inborn knowledge of the perfect Forms of justice, piety, goodness, and countless others.In the Renaissance John Calvin held that we are all born with a sense of God. Descartes, the leadingContinental rationalist, held that we have an innate idea of ourselves and of infinite perfection. Whenlooking at this long history of belief in innate ideas, Locke said that enough was enough, and he launched

    a powerful attack on the very concept. For Locke, we simply have no innate ideas, and all notions that wehave come to us through experience. It’s important to recognize that Locke was not critical of other typesof innate human characteristics, such as coughing or blinking, which are inborn muscle reflexes. Hisattack focuses exclusively on the ideas that we are born with. The movie “Close Encounters of a ThirdKind” illustrates the features of an innate idea. The lead character has an idea of a mountain embedded inhis mind by some aliens from outer space. The idea obsesses him to the point that one evening at thesupper table he scoops a pile of mashed potatoes onto his plate and then shapes it into the image he has othe mountain.  While Locke’s attack on innate ideas certainly applies to the views of Descartes and other Continental rationalists, they were not his immediate target. Instead, according to Locke, there are twotypes of innate ideas that philosophers commonly allege: speculative ones and practical ones. Good

    examples of speculative innate ideas, he argues, are the foundational logical concepts that are sometimesdubbed “laws of thought” and associated with Aristotle. Chief among these is the law of identity whichsimply states that an object is the same as itself, or, in more formal terms, A=A. The chair in front of meis identical to the chair in front of me. The tree in the yard is identical to the tree in the yard. While thisseems to be a painfully obvious truth, it does play an important role in logical systems. Next, there is thelaw of non-contradiction, which Aristotle himself states as follows: “It is impossible for the same thing to

     belong and not to belong at the same time to the same thing and in the same respect” ( Metaphysics, 4.3).The point can be stated more formally as “not (P and not P)”, that is, it is not the case that P and itsopposite not-P obtain at the same time. It is impossible for the chair in front of me to exist and not existat the same time. It is impossible for the apple on the table to be completely red and not completely red at

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    3/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 3

    the same time.  The second type of alleged innate idea involves practical  ones, that is, ideas that regulate moral

     behavioral practices. Examples of these, according to Locke, are the famous “five common notions” of religion and morality proposed by British philosopher Edward Herbert (1583-1648). They are (1) Thereexists a supreme God, (2) We should worship God, (3) The best form of worship is proper moral

     behavior, (4) We should repent for our immoral conduct, (5) We will be rewarded or punished in theafterlife for our conduct on earth. Herbert argued that all humans have an inborn knowledge of thesetruths and we find these truths exhibited in virtually all religions around the world.

      Locke has two main arguments against the innateness of ideas, both speculative and practical.First, he argues, people in fact do not universally hold to these ideas, contrary to what defenders of innateideas typically claim. This is particularly obvious with the laws of thought, which children and mentallychallenged people have no conception of whatsoever: 

    If therefore children and idiots have souls, have minds, with those impressions upon them, theymust unavoidably perceive them, and necessarily know and assent to these truths. Which sincethey do not, it is evident that there are no such impressions. For if they are not notions naturallyimprinted, how can they be innate? and if they are notions imprinted, how can they be unknown?To say a notion is imprinted on the mind, and yet at the same time to say, that the mind is ignorantof it, and never yet took notice of it, is to make this impression nothing. [ Essay, 1.2.12]

     Locke’s second argument is that it makes no sense to hold that such ideas lie dormant within us, and then

     blossom when we reach the right age, contrary to what defenders of innate ideas commonly claim. Again particularly with the laws of thought, children reason perfectly well regarding identity and non-contradiction, yet at the same time are completely incapable of articulating those specific ideas. If theseideas really were innate, then children should be able to verbally express them. As Locke states it, “Howmany instances of the use of reason may we observe in children, a long time before they have anyknowledge of this maxim, ‘That it is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be?’” (ibid). Also, itis obvious that may adults have reached the so-called age of reason, such as the illiterate and those from

     primitive societies, and yet lack these ideas. These people “pass many years, even of their rational age,

    without ever thinking on this and the like general propositions.” Simple and Complex Ideas

    According to Locke, then, we should completely reject the theory of innate ideas and instead look for thetrue source of our ideas within human experience. His basic position, which encapsulates the entireempiricist approach, is that the mind is from birth a blank slate (or sheet of “white paper” in his words),which gets filled with information through experience. However, the process by which we form our ideasthrough experience has two main steps. We first acquire simple ideas through experience, and thenrecombine those simple ideas in different ways to create more complex ideas.  Simple ideas are the building blocks from which all other ideas are formed, and, for Locke, thereare two main sources of simple ideas. The first and most obvious source is that they come from

     sensation, specifically our five senses which give us perceptions of colors, tastes, smells, tactile solidity.The color of blue, the taste of sweetness, the tactile sensation of smoothness, the sound of a high-pitchedsqueak are all basic sensory experiences that are building bocks for our ideas about the external world.Second, there are simple ideas that come to us through reflecting on our mental processes; these are ideasof reflection, or “introspection” as we now call them. I can shut my eyes and think about how my mindoperates: how I perceive things through my senses, how I think about problems, how I doubtquestionable ideas, how I believe reasonable ideas, how I will to perform actions. According to Locke,“This source of ideas every man has wholly in himself; and though it be not sense, as having nothing todo with external objects, yet it is very like it, and might properly enough be called internal sense” (ibid,2.1.3).

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    4/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 4

      According to Locke, some of our simple ideas come solely through sensation without anyintrospective reflection, such as our perceptions of colors, sounds and smells. Others come solely throughintrospective reflection, such as our notions of perceptions of the mental acts of thinking and willing.

     Nothing that we perceive through our five senses will give us ideas of these. Then there is an especiallyinteresting group of simple ideas that we can get either through sensation or introspective reflection.Pleasure and pain is a good example. I can feel physical pain through my senses as when a candle flame

     burns me; but I can also experience emotional pain in my mind when a loved one dies. Another example

    is the notion of causal force, or “power” as 18th century philosophers called it. Through my senses, I see

    a volcano spew out lava with great causal force. But through introspective reflection I can alsoexperience causal force when I reflect on my own willful decisions, such as when I will to conjure up inmy mind the idea of a rock, a tree or a unicorn. My will itself is a causal power. Other ideas that we getthrough both sensation and reflection are existence, unity, and succession.  For Locke, there are countless simple perceptions that flood into our minds through sensation andreflection, in fact so many that we don’t even have names for most of them. But as we store these rawsimple notions in our memories, our minds mechanically shuffle them around and create new ones whichhe calls complex ideas. There are three specific mental processes that form complex ideas. First, some arethe result of simply combining together more simple ideas. For example, I can get a complex idea of anapple by assembling the simple ideas of roundness, redness, sweetness, and moistness. Second, somecomplex ideas involve relations that we get from comparing two things, such as the notions of “larger”and “smaller” that I get when comparing two apples of different sizes. Third, there are complex ideas thatresult from the mental process of abstraction, such as when I arrive at the abstract notion of “roundness”

     by looking at an apple and stripping away all of its attributes except for its being round. As the mind thenchurns out complex ideas from simple ones, the complex ideas will be of two types: ideas of substancesand ideas of modes. Ideas of substances are those of individual objects such as such as rocks, trees,houses, animals, people and God. Ideas of modes are attributes of those objects that cannot existindependently of them, such as an apple’s attributes of being round, crunchy and moist. Primary and Secondary QualitiesOne of Locke’s philosophical claims to fame is his development of the distinction between primary and

    secondary qualities of objects. The issue involves a distinction between qualities of objects that actually belong to the object itself, and qualities of objects that we impose on them. Suppose, for example, that Imade a list of the qualities that I perceive in an apple. It has a round shape, red surface, smooth texture,and a sweet taste. It also has a particular size and weight. Some of these qualities are part of the objectitself, and others are qualities that I am imposing on the apple. For Locke, a primary quality is anattribute of that is inseparable for a physical body, and includes solidity, shape, motion, number. Theseare components that an object retains, regardless of how we might modify the object, such as by cutting iinto pieces. He illustrates this by considering changes that we might impose on a grain of wheat: 

    Take a grain of wheat, divide it into two parts; each part has still solidity, extension, figure, andmobility: divide it again, and it retains still the same qualities; and so divide it on, till the parts

     become insensible; they must retain still each of them all those qualities. For division (which is althat a mill, or pestle, or any other body, does upon another, in reducing it to insensible parts) cannever take away either solidity, extension, figure, or mobility from any body, but only makes twoor more distinct separate masses of matter, of that which was but one before; all which distinctmasses, reckoned as so many distinct bodies, after division, make a certain number. [Ibid, 2.8.9]

      No matter how much we grind down the grain of wheat, the parts still retain the qualities of solidity andshape which were inherent in the original grain.  In contrast with primary qualities, there are also secondary qualities that are spectator-dependent:we impose the attributes onto objects, and these include colors, sounds, and tastes. For example, there is

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    5/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 5

    something in the apple that makes it appear red to me, but the redness itself does not reside within theapple but instead is a function of my sense organs and biology. The phenomenon of colorblindness isample proof of this: while the structure of the apple itself might trigger the perception of redness in mymind, I need to have the appropriately designed eyes to have that perception. So too with other qualitiesof the apple like taste and smell: the specific sensations of taste and smell directly depend upon theconstruction of my tongue and nose.  Locke adds there is a third type of quality of objects— tertiary qualities —which involves the

     power that an object has to produce new ideas or sensations in us. For example, the mere sight of an

    apple may produce a feeling of hunger within me. Being near a fire may produce a feeling of warmthwithin me. Perhaps the main difference between secondary and tertiary qualities is that with secondaryones we often improperly mistake them for primary attributes of the objects themselves. For example, Imight just assume that an apple’s redness is actually part of the apple when, upon reflection, I would seethat it clearly isn’t. With tertiary qualities, though, we are less apt to make this mistake; for example, Iwould never presume that my feeling of hunger resides in the apple itself. Aesthetic feelings, such as thesense of beauty I get when viewing a landscape, might also be included among tertiary qualities. Natural Rights and RevolutionLocke’s empiricist views immediately impacted the direction of philosophy for generations to come,

     particularly in Great Britain. As influential as Locke was in this regard, however, his impact was even

    greater with his political philosophy. Even today, people around the world are familiar with the idea thatthe function of governments is to protect our freedoms, and citizens are morally entitled to overthrowgovernments when they fail to perform that task. This was Locke’s great political contribution to thecivilized world. Prior to Locke, the standard view of political authority was a position called the “divineright of kings.” That is, political rulers are put in power by God, and, as God’s representatives on earth,we can never challenge their authority over us. Locke was strongly opposed to this notion, in part

     because of his personal experience in England where the people recently overthrew their despotic king.Locke supported the overthrow and composed his Two Treatises of Government (1690) to justifyrebellion against bad rulers.  The starting point for Locke’s theory is the state of nature, that is, the condition that humans were

    in prior to the creation of societies and governments. Thomas Hobbes, we’ve seen, believed that the stateof nature is a place of moral chaos, where might makes right, and everyone is perpetually at war witheveryone else to gain the upper hand. Locke, though, is a little more optimistic than Hobbes. Yes, thestate of nature sometimes can be brutal, but there still are moral rules that everyone must follow. For Locke, everyone is born with fundamental God-given rights and, even without governments, we have amoral obligation to respect each other’s rights. The four main natural rights are those of life, health,liberty and possessions: 

    The state of nature has a law of nature to govern it, which obliges every one: and reason, which isthat law, teaches all mankind, who will but consult it, that being all equal and independent, no oneought to harm another in his life, health, liberty, or possessions. [Two Treatises, 2.6]

     What if someone does violate my rights by mugging me and taking my wallet, for example? Locke’sanswer is that I am entitled to punish the mugger: “every one has a right to punish the transgressors of that law to such a degree, as may hinder its violation” (ibid, 2.7). By violating my rights, the mugger hasthereby forfeited all of his own rights, including his right to life, and at that point I am fully entitled tohunt him down, punish him, and even kill him as I see fit. The reason for such a harsh reprisal is that,when the mugger attacks me he puts me in a position where I’m fully under his control, and, even if hedoesn’t kill me, I have every reason to assume that he might. The mugger has thus declared war on meand, at that point, I have the right to punish him by any means whatsoever.  While in the state of nature, vigilante justice is the only recourse we have to retaliate against

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    6/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 6

    attackers. Once we create a civil society with a government, however, all that changes. FollowingHobbes, Locke argues that we create societies by forming a social contract with each other: we agree tomutually set aside our hostilities in the name of preserving peace. And, to assure that we all follow therules, we set up a government that has the authority to punish anyone who breaks the rules and therebyviolates our basic rights. The whole point of establishing societies and governments to begin with is to

     preserve our natural rights, particularly, Locke argues, our right to possessions: 

    The reason why men enter into society, is the preservation of their property. And the end why

    they choose and authorize a legislative, is, that there may be laws made, and rules set, as guardsand fences to the properties of all the members of the society, to limit the power, and moderate thedominion, of every part and member of the society. [ibid, 222] What happens, though, when governments fail at their assigned task, and, rather than protecting

    our rights they undermine them? Locke specifically has in mind a situation in which the governmentunjustly takes people’s property and reduces them to “slavery under arbitrary power” (ibid, 222). Hisanswer is that we are thrown back into a state of war, this time a war with our government. By violatingour rights, the government has forfeited its authority over us, and we are fully entitled to remove theoffending government and set up a better one: 

     by this breach of trust they forfeit the power the people had put into their hands for quite contraryends, and it devolves to the people, who have a right to resume their original liberty, and, by theestablishment of a new legislative, (such as they shall think fit) provide for their own safety andsecurity, which is the end for which they are in society. [Ibid, 222]

     As necessary as governments are for assuring that individual citizens respect each others’ rights, thegovernment itself has a responsibility to uphold its part of the social contract; if it fails in that regard,society is entitled to do what’s necessary to remove it—even start a full-fledged revolution. If it comes tothat, according to Locke, the blame lies with the government, not with the revolutionaries.  Locke’s justification for revolution was quite radical in his time, especially when other 

     philosophers were arguing that governments have absolute authority over citizens through a divine rightof kings, and can never be overthrown. Within a matter of decades, Locke’s rationale was adopted byrevolutionary movements in both America and France, as we see specifically in this famous opening tothe U.S. Declaration of Independence, penned by Thomas Jefferson: 

    We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed bytheir creator with certain unalienable rights, that among these are life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness.—That to secure these rights, governments are instituted among men, deriving their 

     just powers from the consent of the governed,—that whenever any form of government becomesdestructive of these ends, it is the right of the people to alter or to abolish it, and to institute newgovernment, laying its foundation on such principles and organizing its powers in such form, as to

    them shall seem most likely to effect their safety and happiness. Locke, we’ve seen, stressed that revolution is justified particularly when governments violate our 

     property rights. Jefferson, though, deemphasizes our property rights and implies that the governmentalviolation of any of our fundamental natural rights may justify revolution. B. BERKELEYThe second major figure in British Empiricism was George Berkeley (1685-1753). Born into amoderately wealthy family near Kilkenny, Ireland, his father was a customs officer who migrated therefrom England. Berkeley received his B.A. and M.A. degrees from Trinity College, Dublin, and taught

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    7/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 7

    there for some years. Still in his twenties he, he wrote his two main philosophical works, upon which hisfame today rests: A Treatise concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge  (1710) and Three Dialoguesbetween Hylas and Philonous (1713). In his thirties he was ordained into the Anglican Church of Irelandand received is Doctor of Divinity degree. Shortly after, he devised a plan to establish a college in theBermuda Islands to train ministers and missionaries for the colonies. He traveled to Rhode Island to

     prepare for the project, but after three years abandoned it when governmental funding for it never camethrough. He then donated land and books to the newly founded Yale College and returned to Ireland.Back home he was appointed Bishop of Cloyne in south Ireland, a position that he retained for most of 

    the remainder of his life. Berkeley’s fame grew with his many publications, one of the most unusual of which was a work called Siris (1744), which details the medical benefits of tar-water, which he learnedfrom Native Americans years earlier. He died of a stroke at age 67. Idealism: No Material ObjectsThe heart of Berkeley’s philosophy is his theory of idealism: material things do not exist, and all realityexists as perceptions within the minds of spirits. The term “idealism” comes from the word “idea” insofaras the only things that exist are ideas in one’s mind. In that sense, a term like “idea-ism” might have

     better conveyed its meaning. A good way of understanding Berkeley’s position is to see it as takingDescartes’ evil genius hypothesis seriously. Consider again what Descartes suggested. For all I know,there is no material world whatsoever, and all of my experiences are hallucinations that are imposed into

    my mind by an evil genius. It might appear that I have a body and am sitting on a chair, but it could bethat there is no three-dimensional world at all, and an evil genius is just making those things appear inmy mind, while my mind itself floats around without any body. Descartes, we noted, did not actually

     believe this hypothesis, but only proposed it as a strategy for arriving at certainty about the world aroundus. Berkeley, however, does take this scenario seriously, although he rejects that there is anything sinisteror deceptive about it. This is simply the way that God constructed the world: it is a virtual reality thatconsists of God continually feeding our spirit-minds sensory information in a very consistent way.  Key here for Berkeley is the regularity and consistency with which God feeds our minds sensorydata. God stores all sensible perceptions in his mind – in something like a master database – and he feedsthem to us at the appropriate time. Imagine that I perceive myself to be in a room conversing with five

    friends. For Berkeley, the reality is that I and five other spirit-minds are being consistently fed similar sense data by God. Drawing from his master database of perceptions, God feeds us all sense data of walls, tables and chairs within the room. I decide to speak to my friends and say “Did you hear thePresident’s speech list night?” Drawing again from his master database of perceptions, God theninterjects sensory data into all of our minds that portray the image of my mouth moving with audiblewords coming out. One of my friends decides to respond and say “The President’s speech was an insultto the intelligence of everyone in this country!” Another friend decides to say “I disagree, and think thePresident properly addressed the concerns of the nation.” In each case, God reads the thoughts of myfriends and interjects sensory data into all of our minds, thus portraying them speaking. When we’re doneconversing, we decide to get up and leave the room. We might then ask what happens to the empty roomsince God is no longer feeding us sense perceptions of it. Does the room go out of existence? According

    to Berkeley, no it does not: God himself is still perceiving the sensory information about the room and itcontinues to exist in his mind. Indeed, God continually monitors his master database of perceptions, andthus keeps the perceptions active. Berkeley expresses this point with the idealist motto that to be is to be

     perceived . That is, external things exist only in our minds or in God’s mind.  On face value, the idealist position of denying material objects seems ridiculous. The vastmajority of us believe that we live in a world of material objects that includes physical things like rocks,houses, chairs, and our own bodies. Berkeley, though, takes the opposite view: it is belief in the existenceof material objects that is ridiculous. He writes, 

    It is indeed an opinion strangely prevailing amongst men, that houses, mountains, rivers, and in a

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    8/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 8

    word all sensible objects, have an existence, natural or real, distinct from their being perceived bythe understanding. But, with how great an assurance and acquiescence soever this principle may

     be entertained in the world, yet whoever shall find in his heart to call it in question may, if Imistake not, perceive it to involve a manifest contradiction. For, what are the fore-mentionedobjects but the things we perceive by sense? and what do we perceive besides our own ideas or sensations? and is it not plainly repugnant that any one of these, or any combination of them,should exist unperceived? [ Principles, 4]

     

    His point is that when I perceive something like a table, I’m not really experiencing any physical thing, but instead I’m only receiving sensations. This sensory data is all that I really know, and it is a colossalfabrication to assume that some physical thing is the source of my perceptions of the table. Berkeleyrecognizes that there is indeed some external source of my perception of the table, but that source is God,not some mysterious physical stuff. So natural is this position, he argues, that it is backed by commonsense: 

    I am content . . . to appeal to the common sense of the world for the truth of my notion. Ask thegardener why he thinks yonder cherry-tree exists in the garden, and he shall tell you, because hesees and feels it; in a word, because he perceives it by his senses. Ask him why he thinks anorange-tree not to be there, and he shall tell you, because he does not perceive it. What he

     perceives by sense, that he terms a real, being, and says it is or exists; but, that which is not perceivable, the same, he says, has no being. . . . The question between the materialists and me isnot, whether things have a real existence out of the mind of this or that person, but whether theyhave an absolute existence, distinct from being perceived by God, and exterior to all minds.[ Dialogues, 3]

     Berkeley is classified as an “empiricist” philosopher along with Locke. How, though, can Berkeley be anempiricist if he doesn’t believe in material objects? The answer is that the central point of empiricisminvolves gaining knowledge through the senses, rather than through innate ideas. And Berkeleywholeheartedly believes that we do acquire all of our knowledge through sense perception. The only

    issue involves what the source is of those sense perceptions. Whereas Locke believed that materialobjects feed us sensory information, Berkeley believed that God performs that role, not material things. Arguments against Material Objects

    As always with philosophy, it’s one thing to simply propose a theory, but quite another to prove it.Berkeley rises to the occasion, though, offering an abundance of arguments for his position. We’ll look atthe two most compelling of these. The first is his argument from primary and secondary qualities.According to Locke, the fundamental difference between the two types of qualities is whether they arespectator dependent. Primary ones, such as shape, motion and solidity, are part of the external thingsthemselves and not spectator dependent, where as secondary ones such as colors, sounds and tastes arenot part of external things and are spectator dependent. On Locke’s view, primary qualities involve the

    fundamental nature of external things: they are three-dimensional, have solidity, and move around in athree dimensional area. To believe in external material objects, then, requires a commitment to the realityof primary qualities that exist in things, independently of what a spectator might perceive. Berkeleydenies that there are any primary qualities of objects in this sense, and he argues instead that all so-called

     primary qualities are just as spectator dependent as secondary ones. In other words, all qualities of objects are really secondary and thus spectator dependent. His main argument is here: 

    They who assert that figure, motion, and the rest of the primary or original qualities do existwithout the mind in unthinking substances, do at the same time acknowledge that colors, sounds,heat cold, and suchlike secondary qualities, do not- which they tell us are sensations existing in

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    9/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 9

    the mind alone, that depend on and are occasioned by the different size, texture, and motion of theminute particles of matter. This they take for an undoubted truth, which they can demonstrate

     beyond all exception. Now, if it be certain that those original [primary] qualities are inseparablyunited with the other sensible [secondary] qualities, and not, even in thought, capable of beingabstracted from them, it plainly follows that they exist only in the mind. But I desire any one toreflect and try whether he can, by any abstraction of thought, conceive the extension and motionof a body without all other sensible qualities. For my own part, I see evidently that it is not in my

     power to frame an idea of a body extended and moving, but I must withal give it some color or 

    other sensible quality which is acknowledged to exist only in the mind. [ Principles, 10] His main point is that so-called primary qualities are nothing beyond the secondary qualities that we

     perceive in things. Visual perceptions of shape, for example, are just patches of color, which aresecondary.  To make his case, Berkeley examines several so-called primary qualities and explains with eachone how it is spectator dependent. Take, for example, the quality of extension, that is, three-dimensionalshape. Our conceptions of an object’s shape hinge directly on the perspective of the spectator. The leg of a bug, for example, appears exceedingly small to us; to the bug itself it would appear to be a mediumsized thing, yet to an even tinier microscopic organism it would appear to be huge. The texture of anobject similarly hinges on the perspective from which we examine it. From a distance bug’s leg might

    appear to be smooth; through a microscope it might appear to be quite coarse. The point is thateverything that we know about shape depends upon where we stand in relation to the things that we are

     perceiving; thus, all notions of shape are spectator dependent. The so-called primary quality of motion isalso relative to the perceiver. Imagine, for example, that a leaf is falling from a tree directly in front of ahumming bird, a human, and a sloth. How would each of these creatures perceive the leaf’s motion? Tothe humming bird the leaf’s motion might appear to be so slow as to be almost frozen in time. To thehuman it would appear to be moving at a normal pace. To the sloth it might appear exceedingly rapid.According to Berkeley, speed and time are measured by the succession of ideas in our minds, whichvaries in different perceivers.  Berkeley’s second argument against material objects is based on the principle of simplicity: there

    is no real need for the material objects, hence would be a useless creation. Everything we need to perceive sensible qualities is accounted for more efficiently through idealism: God directly feeds ussensory information without creating the material world as a useless middleman. He writes, 

    If therefore it were possible for bodies to exist without the mind, yet to hold they do so, mustneeds be a very precarious opinion; since it is to suppose, without any reason at all, that God hascreated innumerable beings that are entirely useless, and serve to no manner of purpose.[ Principles, 19]

     In theory, we might think that God could have created the material world as a middleman if he wanted tosort of as an instrument to accomplish the task. But even that, according to Berkeley, is inconsistent with

    God’s nature. Instruments are used only when there is a need. A hammer is a useful instrument since Ican’t effectively pound in a nail with my bare hands. My glasses are a useful instrument since I can’t seevery well without them. However, God, who has infinite powers, has no needs and thus has no use of anyinstrument that might help him accomplish some task. Berkeley writes: 

    We indeed, who are beings of finite powers, are forced to make use of instruments. And the use ofan instrument shows the agent to be limited by rules of another’s prescription, and that he cannotobtain his end but in such a way, and by such conditions. Whence it seems a clear consequence,that the supreme unlimited agent uses no tool or instrument at all. [ Dialogues, 2]

     

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    10/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 10

    Thus, God is perfectly capable of feeding us sensory information directly without the need for him tocreate the material world as a crutch. God and evilReconciling God’s existence with the presence of evil in the world has been a central concern among

     philosophers since at least the time of Augustine. Why would an all good God permit the enormousamount of suffering that we see in the world around us? The problem is especially acute for Berkeley’stheory since God not only permits suffering, but he also seems to be the originator of suffering as he

    injects all external sensory information into our minds. Imagine again that I perceive myself to be in aroom conversing with five friends about the President’s speech. All of my perceptions of the room itself are implanted directly into my mind by God; the dialogue that I’m having with my friends also dependsupon God feeding each of us sensations of our voices and bodily images. Suppose that our politicalconversation becomes heated, a fight erupts and in a fit of anger my friend throws me out the window;my spine is broken and I’m paralyzed for life from my neck down. Let’s now see what God’s role was inthis tragedy. First, he enabled the controversy by mediating the sensory information of the dialogue.When things became heated, he could have just cut off the flow of perceptions. Second, since, accordingto Berkeley’s theory, I have no physical body, God alone is the source of whatever physical pain Iexperience from my so-called “physical injury”. Third, God is directly responsible for whatever continued incapacity I have as a quadriplegic. God decides to shut off all perceptions I might have of 

     bodily movement and sensation in my arms and legs, and I’m stuck with that for life. While I and myfriends are certainly morally responsible for our respective roles, God is nevertheless an active

     participant and conspirator in how I am affected.  Berkeley has two responses to this criticism. First, he argues that the problem with God and evilis no more severe with his idealist theory than it is for those who believe in the existence of matter. In

     both cases, God is actively involved in sustaining a world that includes immorality and suffering. If amaterial world does exist, then it would just be an instrument in God’s hands, and a person is just asmorally responsible whether or not he used an instrument. He writes, 

    the imputation of guilt is the same, whether a person commits an action with or without an

    instrument. In case therefore you suppose God to act by the mediation of an instrument or occasion, called matter, you as truly make Him the author of sin as I, who think Him theimmediate agent in all those operations vulgarly ascribed to Nature. [ Dialogues, 3]

     Technically, this response does not attempt to solve the problem of God and evil, but only maintains thatthere is no extra problem added to the situation by endorsing Berkeley’s idealism.  Berkeley’s second response, though, does attempt to solve the problem in a more positive way.According to Berkeley, evil does not consist of outward actions, but inward attitudes: 

    I farther observe that sin or moral turpitude does not consist in the outward physical action or motion, but in the internal deviation of the will from the laws of reason and religion. This is plain,

    in that the killing an enemy in a battle, or putting a criminal legally to death, is not thought sinful;though the outward act be the very same with that in the case of murder. Since, therefore, sin doesnot consist in the physical action, the making God an immediate cause of all such actions is notmaking Him the Author of sin. [ Dialogues, ibid]

     Thus, when God feeds us sensory information that involves immorality or is painful, his motives are

     pure. It is as though he is performing the role of a messenger or delivery service; sometimes theinformation is good, sometimes not so good. But we shouldn’t blame the messenger when we don’t likewhat he delivers. Ultimately the fault rests with the person who initially sent the message, not deliveredit. With the present example, the fault rests solely with me and my friends.

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    11/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 1

     C. HUME

    The last of the great British empiricists was David Hume (1711-1776), who pushed empiricism to itsskeptical conclusions. Hume was born near Edinburgh, Scotland into a moderately wealthy family, butthe bulk of the family fortune went to Hume’s older brother after their father died, thus forcing Hume to

     be frugal for some decades. Educated in law at his family’s direction, he quickly abandoned that career and devoted himself to the study of philosophy. In his teens wrestled with the question of God’sexistence, balancing the arguments on both sides, and soon rejected the notion of an all powerful divine

     being. In his early twenties he wrote the manuscript of his most important work, A Treatise of Human Nature (1739-1740). To Hume’s disappointment, it received little attention, and the discussion that it didgenerate was highly critical. Blaming its failure on the work’s technical style, he rewrote and published

     portions of it in a more reader-friendly format. Hume hoped to work as a philosophy teacher at one of Edinburgh’s universities, but the skeptical and anti-religious nature of his writings poisoned his efforts,and instead he took on temporary jobs in government and as a librarian. With a steady flow of 

     publications, branching out into history as well as philosophy, by his mid forties he became one of themost famous—and controversial—authors in Europe. His wealth grew with his fame. In spite of theskeptical tone of his writings, Hume was a cheerful person and enjoyed socializing with people at alllevels of society. Though he never married, he was well received by “modest women” as he words it inhis autobiography. One of his friends was the controversial French author Jean Jacque Rousseau, who

    took political refuge in Hume’s home for a short time. Rousseau had mental problems, though, and,turning on his generous host, he publicly accused Hume of trying to sabotage his reputation. The eventturned into an international scandal, and the two never reconciled. Hume died at age 65 from a digestivedisorder that lingered for a year and left him emaciated. On his deathbed, crowds of people gatheredaround his Edinburgh home, curious to know whether he would repent of his irreligion. He held firm inhis disbelief, and, in fact, one of his final acts was to plan for the posthumous publication of his mostanti-religious writing, which he felt was too controversial to appear in print while he was alive. Origin of and Association of Ideas

    In his own day, as now, Hume had a notorious reputation as a skeptical philosopher, and in many ways he

    carried on the skeptical tradition forged in ancient Greece. Much of Hume’s skepticism, though, resultsfrom pushing the empiricist agenda to its logical conclusion. There are two main building blocks uponwhich his empiricist philosophy is founded. The first of these concerns the origin of ideas. Thoughts andideas flow through our minds endlessly – ideas of people, houses, music concerts, scientific discoveries,God, on and on. Where do they all come from? Hume’s answer is that all of our ideas come from twotypes of experiences, or impressions as he calls them: (1) outward impressions through our five sensesand (2) inward impressions through reflection on our mental operations. For example, the idea I have of the color red ultimately came from some outward sensory experience that I had of the color red that wasstored in my memory. The idea I have of fear similarly came from an inward feeling of fear that Iexperienced in the past. He writes, 

    though our thought seems to possess this unbounded liberty, we shall find, upon a nearer examination, that it is really confined within very narrow limits. . . . When we think of a goldenmountain, we only join two consistent ideas, gold , and mountain, with which we were formerlyacquainted. . . . In short, all the materials of thinking are derived either from our outward or inward sentiment: The mixture and composition of these belongs alone to the mind and will. Or,to express myself in philosophical language, all our ideas or more feeble perceptions are copies ofour impressions or more lively ones. [ Enquiry, 2]

     Hume offers two proofs for his position that all ideas are copied from impressions. First, he says that if you take any idea you have and examine its components, you’ll find that it traces back to outward or 

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    12/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 12

    inward one or more sensory experience or inward feeling. Second, he says that, if you go your entire lifewithout having a particular type of sensation, then you would lack the corresponding idea of thatsensation. For example, “a blind man can form no notion of colors.”  On face value, Hume’s view is innocent enough, and he seems to just be reiterating Locke’s

     position that experience is the source of all our mental contents. What Hume does with this, though, isquite radical insofar as he transforms it into a theory of meaning. For my ideas to have any meaning, theymust be grounded in some impression that I’ve had. An idea is meaningless, then, if I cannot trace it backto any impression. He writes,

     When we entertain, therefore, any suspicion that a philosophical term is employed without anymeaning or idea (as is but too frequent), we need but enquire, from what impression is that 

     supposed idea derived ? And if it be impossible to assign any, this will serve to confirm our suspicion. By bringing ideas into so clear a light we may reasonably hope to remove all dispute,which may arise, concerning their nature and reality. [Ibid]

     For example, if I have an idea of an all-powerful divine being, but I’ve never had any impression of something that is all powerful or divine, then my idea is without meaning. Whatever I idea I do have of God – regardless of whether God even exists – it must be grounded in impressions that I’ve had. It is thistheory of meaning that leads Hume down the path of skepticism as he explores one philosophical theory

    after another. In fact, he believes that much of traditional philosophy and religion can be dismissed asmeaningless since it fails this test.  The second building block of Hume’s empiricism is his theory of the association of ideas.Suppose that I sit down on a couch and let my mind wander where it will. I think about the President,then Japan, then my car, then a telephone pole, then a railroad track, then an old apartment I lived in. It istempting to think that I am conjuring up these ideas spontaneously without any organization behind them

     Not so, Hume argues. Our flow of ideas is connected together by three principles of association. First isresemblance, where one thought leads to another because of resembling features that they have. For example, if I look at a photograph of a friend, I’ll start thinking about that friend. Second is contiguity,that is, one thing being in close proximity to another. For example, if someone says something about a

    store in a shopping mall, I might then think about the store located next to it. Third is cause and effect .For example, if I look at a scar on my arm, I immediately start thinking about the accident I had thatcaused me to get the scar. These three principles alone, according to Hume, are responsible for all mentalassociation that our minds make in the normal flow of ideas. With the above example, my thought aboutthe President leads me to think about Japan since he recently visited there (contiguity); Japan is wheremy car was built (causality); my car is parked next to a telephone pole (contiguity); the telephone pole iscovered with the same kind of black tar that’s on railroad ties (resemblance); my old apartment was alongside a railroad track (contiguity). Hume says that “The more instances we examine, and the more care weemploy, the more assurance shall we acquire, that the enumeration, which we form from the whole, iscomplete and entire” ( Enquiry, 3). 

    Personal Identity and CausalityHume’s skepticism emerges quite clearly with his treatment of two philosophical notions, namely

     personal identity and causality. In both of these cases his skeptical conclusions arise from applying thetheory of meaning described above. If the traditional ideas of causality and personal identity are to bemeaningful, then we must be able to trace those ideas back to some impression. In each case, though,there are problems locating an impression that is suitable for forming these ideas.  Let’s start with the idea of personal identity. The traditional notion of personal identity held byDescartes and other philosophers is that it is a single, unified substance that continues through time. Onthis view, I am a single conscious entity, and, even though my specific thoughts change, my identityremains intact throughout time, and perhaps even into the afterlife. The critical question for Hume, then,

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    13/18

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    14/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 14

    notion of necessary connection as an objective force or invisible explosion. He suggests an alternative,though. There is a more moderate notion of necessary connection that comes from an inward feeling of expectation that occurs when we repeatedly see A followed by B. Consider again the example of billiard

     balls: it is only after repeatedly seeing ball A move B that our minds feel a transition from the cause tothe effect. He writes, 

    The first time a man saw the communication of motion by impulse, as by the shock of two billiard balls, he could not pronounce that the one event was connected : But only that it was conjoined 

    with the other. After he has observed several instances of this nature, he then pronounces them to be connected . What alteration has happened to give rise to this new idea of connection? Nothing but that he now feels these events to be connected  in his imagination, and can readily foretell theexistence of one from the appearance of the other. [Ibid]

     In the end, Hume does not completely reject the idea of necessary connection and causality. But he doesreject the traditional idea of it being something like a primary quality within objects themselves. Instead,he suggests that necessary connection is like a secondary quality that we spectators impose onto A-Bsequences when we repeatedly see A and B conjoined. It’s just a habit of our minds, not a reality in theobjects themselves. 

    Belief in MiraclesOne of Hume’s lifelong goals was to help rid the world of religious superstition and fanaticism, andnowhere is this better seen than with his attack on the belief in miracles. To properly understand exactlywhat Hume is criticizing, three things need to be clarified. First, Hume as in mind a very precise notionof the term “miracle”, which is that it is a violation of a law of nature. It is not simply an unusual eventthat occurs at just the right moment, such as if I’m saved from drowning by grabbing onto a vine that justhappens to be hanging from a tree within my reach. Rather, it must break some law of nature, such as if my arm gets chopped off and a new one instantly appears. Second, Hume focuses specifically on reportsof miracles—stories about miracles that we hear about from other people or read about in books such asthe Bible. He does not consider miracles that we might directly witness ourselves. Third, Hume focuses

    on whether it is reasonable for us to believe reports of miracles, not whether the miraculous eventactually took place. It is impossible for us to go back in time and prove with absolute certainty whether any reported miracle was genuine. The best we can do is consider whether the evidence in support of amiracle report is compelling enough for us to believe the report. Hume’s precise position, then, is that itis never reasonable to believe reports of violations of laws of nature.  Hume offers a series of arguments against belief in miracles, but his main one is this: it is never reasonable to believe in reports of miracles since those reports will always be outweighed by stronger evidence for consistent laws of nature. Suppose, for example, that the Mayor and all the city officials saythat they witnessed a genuine miracle. As they report, a car rammed into city hall, causing the wall tocollapse, but seconds later all the smashed pieces of the wall floated into the air, and reassembledthemselves just as they were before. Should we believe their report?

      According to Hume, our first step is to weigh the evidence for and against this miracle, sort of like we were placing the evidence in the pans of a balance scale. On the one side, the evidence that wehave in favor of the miracle is the credibility of the witnesses. They are reporting what they’ve seen withtheir eyes, and we know from past experience that they are people of their word. On the other side, theevidence against the miracle consists of the accumulated experience that we have in favor of uniformlaws of nature. The natural world behaves in an orderly way based to natural laws. We count on thisevery moment of the day as when, for example, I open a door and expect it to swing on a hinge, rather than do something like transform into a bird and fly away. According to Hume, the evidence that we havein favor of consistent laws of nature is overwhelming, and will always outweigh even the best evidencein favor of a reported miraculous violation of a law of nature. He writes,

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    15/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 15

     A miracle is a violation of the laws of nature; and as a firm and unalterable experience hasestablished these laws, the proof against a miracle, from the very nature of the fact, is as entire asany argument from experience can possibly be imagined. . . . There must, therefore, be a uniformexperience against every miraculous event, otherwise the event would not merit that appellation[i.e., that title]. And as a uniform experience amounts to a proof, there is here a direct and full

     proof from the nature of the fact against the existence of any miracle. . . . [ Enquiry, 10] 

    For Hume, since miracles are defined as violations of laws of nature, any alleged miracle report isinstantly outweighed by overwhelming evidence that we have of consistent laws of nature. The wisething to do, Hume says, is to proportion our belief to the evidence. With the above City Hall example, weshould thus disbelieve the report that the wall miraculously reassembled itself since the evidence isoverwhelmingly in favor of consistent laws of nature.  In addition to this main argument against belief in miracles, Hume offers four additionalcriticisms. First, he says, the witnesses who report miracles typically lack credibility. Sometimes theylack sufficient education and good sense, which makes them gullible. Other times they are consciouslydeceptive. Even in the above example of the City Hall miracle, our first reaction would be to suspect thatthe Mayor and the city officials concocted the story to hide something politically sensitive. Second,Hume argues that human beings are predisposed to enjoy hearing sensational stories, and this creates an

    instant audience for accounts of miraculous events. In recent times, we see this in the success of tabloid publications such as the National Enquirer  that specialize in stories about alien abductions, monsterssuch as Bigfoot, and every possible type of miracle. This vulnerability within human nature itself castsdoubt on the truth of such sensational claims. Third, Hume states that reports of miracles typically comefrom pre-scientific and primitive countries whose cultures are obsessed with the supernatural. The mostordinary natural events are ascribed to supernatural causes, and reliance on omens and oracles is thenorm. The very location of such miracle reports counts against their credibility. Fourth, Hume argues thatreports of miracles support rival religious systems, and thus nullify each other. There are reports of miracles within virtually every religious tradition around the world. Christian miracles support theChristian plan of salvation. Muslim miracles support the Muslim plan of salvation, and so on. The

     problem is that these religions are rivals to each other and typically discredit the others’ legitimacy.Taken as a whole, then, rival miracle reports are mutually undermining.  Hume recognizes that the Christian religious tradition not only contains reports of miracles, but isin fact founded on miraculous circumstances in the lives of the Biblical characters. Nevertheless, Humeargues, the reasonable thing to do even here is to disbelieve these reports. In fact, belief in such miraclestories is so irrational that it would take an act of God to make an otherwise reasonable person suspend“all the principles of his understanding” and make him believe a miracle story that “is most contrary tocustom and experience” (ibid). Morality: Reason vs. SentimentThroughout the history of philosophy, the traditional conception of morality was that it consists of 

    objective universal truths that can be discovered through human reason. Plato’s view of the forms is theclearest example of this. For Plato, moral standards such as justice and goodness exist independently of human society in the higher spirit-realm of the forms. And, for Plato, it takes a mental act of reason tograsp moral truths, in much the way it takes an act of reason to grasp mathematical truths which alsoreside in the realm of the forms. This is largely the view of morality that moral philosophers in Hume’sday held: we discover objective universal moral principles through reason. Hume rejects this view:morality is not grounded in an objective feature of the external world, but rather on internal mentalfeelings of pleasure and pain.  Hume’s main argument for his position is that, as hard as we may try, we can never discover anyspecial fact about an action that makes it either moral or immoral – either within the physical act itself or 

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    16/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 16

    in any alleged higher realm of moral truths. All that we will find is a feeling of pleasure or pain inreaction to the action. He writes, 

    Take any action allowed to be vicious; willful murder, for instance. Examine it in all lights, andsee if you can find that matter of fact, or real existence, which you call vice. In whichever wayyou take it, you find only certain passions, motives, volitions, and thoughts. There is no other matter of fact in the case. The vice entirely escapes you, as long as you consider the object. Younever can find it, till you turn your reflection into your own breast, and find a sentiment of 

    disapprobation, which arises in you, towards this action. Here is a matter of fact; but it is theobject of feeling, not of reason. It lies in yourself, not in the object. So that when you pronounceany action or character to be vicious, you mean nothing, but that from the constitution of your nature you have a feeling or sentiment of blame from the contemplation of it. [Treatise, 3.1.1]

     Thus, morality does not involve making a rational judgment about some objective moral facts. Instead,moral assessments are just emotional reactions. If I see someone robbing a bank and determine thataction to be morally wrong, I am not making a rational judgment about some objective moral truth or fact; rather, I am experiencing a feeling of emotional pain, and that feeling constitutes my negativeassessment of the robber. Using the terminology of primary and secondary qualities, Hume’s point is thamorality is not a primary quality that’s part of external things, but is instead like a secondary quality that

    spectators impose onto actions. He writes, “Vice and virtue, therefore, may be compared to sounds,colors, heat, and cold, which, according to modern philosophy, are not [primary] qualities in objects, but

     perceptions in the mind” (ibid).  As obvious as this all seems to Hume, he notes that most moral theories insist on linking moralassessments with some factual judgment of reason. They begin by listing some kind of fact, such as a facabout moral Forms, moral truths, divine commands; from these facts, then, they immediately jump tosome moral statement, such as “Stealing is wrong”. He makes this point here: 

    In every system of morality which I have hitherto met with, I have always remarked, that theauthor proceeds for some time in the ordinary way of reasoning, and establishes the being of a

    God, or makes observations concerning human affairs; when of a sudden I am surprised to find,that instead of the usual copulations of propositions, is, and is not, I meet with no proposition thatis not connected with an ought, or an ought not.

     The problem, for Hume, is that you just can’t rationally deduce a statement of moral obligation from astatement of fact—stated more succinctly, you cannot derive ought  from is. Rather, the obligation comesfrom feeling, not from deduction of facts. When I see a bank robber and state that “The robber’s act of stealing is wrong”, I am expressing the painful feelings that I am experiencing. Thus, statements of moralobligation are introduced through an emotional reaction, not through a rational deduction. Radical Skepticism and Natural Belief 

    Hume was a chronically skeptical philosopher, and we’ve already seen several expressions of this. He began with a theory of meaning that ruthlessly dismembers any concept that is not grounded in anoutward or inward impression, and the first victims were traditional notions of personal identity andcausality. He questioned the legitimacy of belief in miracles and, in essence, called into doubt anythingsupernatural. Finally, he attacked the traditional notion of rationally perceived moral truths, and reducedmoral assessments to emotional reactions. But there is an even more radical skepticism within Hume’s

     philosophy that goes beyond these particular issues. According to Hume, the underlying structure of human reason itself is inherently flawed, and thus completely untrustworthy. Specifically, the humanreasoning process, even at its very best, is on a collision course with itself and regularly contradicts itselfIf we follow one rational train of thought we reach conclusion A; if we follow a different rational train of

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    17/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

    https://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/8-empiricism.htm 17

    thought we reach a conflicting conclusion “not A”. It’s like a computer that is running two incompatible programs that eventually cause the computer to crash. Hume describes this collision course here: 

    The intense view of these manifold contradictions and imperfections in human reason has sowrought upon me, and heated my brain, that I am ready to reject all belief and reasoning, and canlook upon no opinion even as more probable or likely than another. Where am I, or what? Fromwhat causes do I derive my existence, and to what condition shall I return? Whose favor shall Icourt, and whose anger must I dread? What beings surround me? and on whom have I any

    influence, or who have any influence on me? I am confounded with all these questions, and beginto fancy myself in the most deplorable condition imaginable, environed with the deepestdarkness, and utterly deprived of the use of every member and faculty. [ Treatise, 1.4.7]

     For Hume, then, the most central questions about human existence are incapable of being adequatelyanswered because of the inherent flaws in the human reasoning process. Whatever reason tells us aboutthese matters can never be fully trusted, and thus we slide down the slope of philosophical despair.  Amidst all this skepticism and despair, though, Hume has a strangely optimistic solution. Humannature has embedded within us some very concrete natural beliefs which enable us to get through the day.

     Nature forces us to believe in external objects, causal relationships, personal identity, moral responsibilityand a host of other notions that are crucial for our normal routines. These are not innate ideas per se, but

    are normal beliefs about the world that emerge through natural inclinations. For example, when I look ata chair and I’m naturally inclined to think that it exists in the external world exactly as I perceive it. Thefact that we have these natural beliefs doesn’t mean that they are entirely true, and Hume warns thatmany are not. However, they are functionally important for our lives. Also, they serve as a naturalantidote to philosophical despair. When radical skepticism causes us to mentally crash, all that we needto do is back off from our philosophical inquiries and let our natural beliefs take over: “Nature herself suffices to that purpose, and cures me of this philosophical melancholy and delirium” (ibid). Hume warnsthat natural beliefs are no replacement for philosophical inquiry, which, even with all its skepticism, isstill important to keep us from giving in to gullibility and superstition. As flawed as human reason is, it isstill preferable to “superstition of every kind or denomination” (ibid).

     Questions for Review Please answer all of the following questions for review. 1. What are Locke’s main arguments against innate ideas?2. Explain Locke’s distinction between ideas of sensation and ideas of reflection.3. What are the three mental processes involved in forming complex ideas?4. What is Locke’s distinction between primary and secondary qualities?5. Explain Locke’s view of natural rights and the justification of revolution.6. Explain Berkeley’s idealism and God’s role as the source of perceptions.7. What are Berkeley’s arguments for idealism from primary/secondary qualities and simplicity.

    8. What are Berkeley’s two solutions to the problem of God and evil?9. What is Hume’s view of the origin of ideas and the association of ideas?10. Explain Hume’s view of personal identity.11. Explain Hume’s view of necessary connection.12. What is Hume’s main argument against miracles?13. Explain Hume’s view about emotion and moral judgment.14. Explain Hume’s view of radical skepticism and natural belief. Questions for Analysis

     Please select only one question for analysis from those below and answer it.

  • 8/16/2019 9 Empiricism

    18/18

    23/5/2016 9: Empiricism

     1. Locke argued that if ideas such as Aristotle’s laws of thought were truly innate, then children and

    retarded people would have some knowledge of them. Explain his argument and try to refute it.2. Berkeley argued that, just as secondary qualities don't exist outside of the mind, primary qualities don't

    either. Explain his argument and try to refute it.3. Hume argued that all ideas are copies of some kind of impression. Explain his argument and try to

    refute it.4. Hume argued that we have no idea of a continuous and unified self. Explain his argument and try to

    refute it.5. Hume argued that the idea of necessary connection derives from a feeling of expectation which

    habitually results from observing two constantly conjoined events. Explain his argument and tryto refute it.

    6. Write a dialogue between Plato and Hume, where Plato defends the view that moral assessments arerational judgments about moral Forms, and Hume holds the view that moral assessments are justemotional reactions.