a logician's fairy tale. h. l. a. hart

16
A Logician's Fairy Tale 1IIiiiiil .. 1IiiiII@ H. L. A. Hart The Philosophical Review, Vol. 60, No.2. (Apr., 1951), pp. 198-212. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8108%28195104%2960%3A2%3CI98%3AALFT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-7 The Philosophical Review is currently published by Cornell University. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR' s Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/sageschool.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to creating and preserving a digital archive of scholarly journals. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.j stor.org/ Thu Jun 22 00:14:152006

Upload: lcj0509

Post on 18-May-2017

227 views

Category:

Documents


3 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

A Logician's Fairy Tale1IIiiiiil..1IiiiII@

H. L. A. Hart

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 60, No.2. (Apr., 1951), pp. 198-212.

Stable URL:http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8108%28195104%2960%3A2%3CI98%3AALFT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-7

The Philosophical Review is currently published by Cornell University.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR' s Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless youhave obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, andyou may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.jstor.org/journals/sageschool.html.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen orprinted page of such transmission.

JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to creating and preserving a digital archive ofscholarly journals. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

http://www.j stor.org/Thu Jun 22 00:14:152006

Page 2: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

A LOGICIAN'S FAIRY TALE

I

"ONCE upon a time.... " How shall we characterize the use oflanguage which this familiar formula introduces? When fairy

tales were told to us as children we understood them perfectly,and as adults we still understand them though perhaps less well, but themodern logician, in spite of the arsenal of weapons at his disposal,involves himself in paradox and absurdity in trying to say what it isthat the storyteller does with words. What accounts for his failureis, I think, just the supply of modern weapons, because they tempt thelogician who wields them into the incautious assumption that themethods of logical analysis, the principles of logical classification, andthe symbolic notation which have been so fruitful and so clarifying inthe treatment of mathematical or other systems of necessary truth cansafely be used, merely mutatis mutandis, in the elucidation of the non­necessary propositions of ordinary discourse. And since in modern!manuals of logic this assumption determines the whole presentation ofthe subject, it is worth examining a single case where, as it seems to me,it calamitously breaks down, especially as a moral may be drawn forother cases where also the obviously valuable apparatus of modernlogic seems not to clarify but to distort.

II

I shall take as my example of the modern treatment of this topic thediscussion by Ambrose and Lazerowitz2 in their FunrJamentals ofSymbolic Logic (pp. 178-190) of general propositions and the fourAristotelian forms A, E, I, and O. This discussion reaches the noworthodox conclusion that the classical interpretation of statements of theform "All S is P," "No S is P," "Some S is P," and "Some S is not P"as shown in the Square of Opposition traditionally used for the ex-

1 lowe the substance of this criticism of modern logical doctrine to Mr. P. F.Strawson. See his article, "On Referring," Mind (July, 1950), esp. pp. 343-344.

• Hereafter referred to as "the authors."

19B

Page 3: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

A LOGICIAN'S FAIRY TALE

hibition of the logical relations between these fonns was both mistakenand inconsistent; and the counterrecommendation (also now ortho­dox) is made that while the I and 0 forms are affinnative existentialsentences [( 3 x).f x . g x and ( 3 x). f x . ,..., g xl, which entail thatthere exist members of the class designated by their subject tenns, theA and E fonns should be interpreted as negative existential sentencesso as to leave open, as I and 0 do not, the possibility that there are nomembers of the subject class. Thus, for the modern logician, ,..., (3 x).f x . ,..., g x (called "the minimum interpretation") is the sole assertiveforce of A and correspondingly,..., ( 3 x). fx' gx of E; whereas on theclassical interpretation the A and E forms have "existential import"and according to the authors their force on that interpretation is re­spectively"'" ( 3 x). f x . ,..., g x: ( 3 x). f x and ,..., ( 3 x). f x . g x:(3 x). f x (called "the existential interpretation"). Of course the au­thors recognize that in ordinary English usage expressions of thefonn "All S is P" would be understood existentially, i.e., "so as toimply that there are S's" and to allow this they treat such ordinaryEnglish expressions as in fact elliptic and as asserting not merelya statement of the A form but also the further existential statement(:I x) . f x ; and they recommend that what is thus "implicit" in ordinarydiscourse be made explicit in an accurate logical analysis by transcrib­ing such ordinary but elliptic English expressions by the conjunctivefonn ,..., ( 3 x). f x . ,..., g x: ( :I x). f x.

On this familiar basis three criticisms of the classical analysis aremade:

First, there is no single interpretation of the A and E forms forwhich all the relations depicted in the classical Square of Oppositionhold. For according to the modern doctrine A can only be construedeither (I) as ,..., (3 x). f x . ,..., g x (the minimum interpretation) or(2) as,..., ( :I x). f x . ,..., g x:(:1 x). f x (the existential interpreta­tion). If the minimum interpretation is chosen all the relations repre­sented by the sides of the Square fail leaving only the relationship ofcontradiction between A and 0, E and I represented by the diagonals;whereas if the existential interpretation is chosen the relation of con­tradiction represented by the diagonals fails, for on this interpretationA and 0, and E and I are contraries since both of each pair would befalse if ,..., ( :I x). f x is true, and the relation of subcontrariety betweenI and 0 also fails.

199

Page 4: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW

Secondly, since according to the classical view "All S is P" isinterpreted existentially, which for the authors' view means as u say_ing)}3,...., (3 x). f x . ,...., g x:( 3 x). f x, it is impossible on this inter­pretation to express an important class of general proposition of whichthe authors c'ite "No uranium deposits in Ohio are easy to mine" and"All Greek gods have human frailities" and others as examples. Foraccording to the authors "all these statements are held to be true,"yet they would not be true if they were interpreted as asserting thatthere were uranium deposits in Ohio or Greek gods as, in the authors'view, the classical analysis would interpret them. So if we adopt theclassical interpretation, this important. class of general propositionwould have to be treated as exceptions to it; whereas, if we adoptthe minimum interpretation recommended, these propositions can berepresented by it, and the existentially understood propositions ofordinary discourse represented by the conjuncton of the minimuminterpretation together with the further form (3 x). f x.

Thirdly, the classical interpretation leads to the supreme absurditythat the existence of at least one thing of e~ery kind whatever couldbe logically demonstrated.. For, given any set of four propositions ofthe A, E, I, and 0 forms such as the following (cited by the authors)

All ogres are wicked,No ogres are wicked,Some ogres are wicked,Some ogres are not wicked,

it will follow on the classical interpretation that ogres exist and "notonly ogres but something of every mentionable kind would have toexist by logical necessity" (p. 187). And the authors remark that"theologians and metaphysicians" anxious to construct a proof of theexistence of God oddly failed to see that the Square of Opposition"which all or nearly all of them accepted" (p. 187) provided themwith all that they needed for the proof of the existence of an AbsolutelyPerfect Being.

The novelty in this presentation of the indictment is the use by theauthors of a fairy-tale generalization to render glaring the absurdity ofthe Aristotelian interpretation and to bring out the clarificatory powerof the modem analysis. Perhaps also novel is the curious mixture ofappeals to modem English usage ("there is a further justification of

~ My italics.200

Page 5: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

A LOGICIAN'S FAIRY TALE

the modern analysis in the fact that the classical interpretation resultsin upsetting the relations holding in English usage between A and 0,E and I" [po 185]) with the acceptance of a consequence of the mod­ern analysis described as "at first sight paradoxical" (p. 190), namely,that A and E are not contraries but can be true together as in theauthors' fairy-tale example "All leprechauns are bearded" and "Noleprechauns are bearded," which are to be "counted" true given thecircumstance that there are no leprechauns. But novel or not, the ac­count which results from the analysis advocated by the authors of the

general propositions of a fairy tale, whose subject is an ogre, aleprechaun, or any other creature of fancy, is a curious one; indeed itis hardly less curious than the old pre-Russellian notion that, since the

propositions of fiction have a meaning, there must be a subsistent butnonexistent "universe of discourse" which these propositions if true

describe and if false misdescribe. For according to the authors' analysis,

all such universal propositions of a fairy tale ("All ogres are wicked,""No ogres are wicked") are true though "vacuously" true, and all the

particular propositions ("Some ogres are wicked," "Some ogres arenot wicked") are false. This is, indeed, "at first sight paradoxical" and

the air of paradox is not dissipated by a second glance. Surely to make

believe that there are ogres, to speak as if there were ogres, and to sayof them that they are all wicked is not really the same as to assert the

"vacuous" truth that nothing is an ogre and not wicked. For the truthaccorded in this analysis to "All ogres are wicked," though calledvacuous, is not truth in some harmless special sense ("true in fiction"),meaning no more than that the proposition forms part of the story or

myth, in which sense "No ogres are wicked" would be false; but both

these fairy-tale generalizations are true in the same factual sense that

"There are no ogres" is true and for the same reason, namely, they

accurately describe the world. Perhaps rather than this, most peoplewould prefer to swallow what in the view of these authors is the con­

sequence of the classical existential interpretation, that all the general

propositions of a fairy-tale describing its fictitious beings, universal andparticular alike, are false. But if fiction and vacuous truth seem differentthings, so do fiction and falsity. Can we resist the identification of

fiction with either?

201

Page 6: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW

III

That we can and indeed should resist, is apparent from an examina­tion of the argument used to convict Aristotle of having provided inthe Square of Opposition a proof "of the existence of at least one thingof every kind whatsoever." This argument involves two steps, each ofwhich rests I think on a misunderstanding of important features ofempirical discourse and is as follows:

(I) "Given any set of four propositions answering to the forms,A, E, I, 0, it is plain that at least one of them must be true" (p. 186)and "the underlying assumption is such that one of the two particularsI and 0 must be true" (page 187).

(II) "Both I and 0 (where the A, E, 1. 0, propositions are takento be 'All ogres are wicked,' etc.) imply that there are ogres" (p. 187).

From which the authors draw their conclusion:

(III) "Hence given that one of the four propositions about ogresmust be true and that everyone of them implies that there must beogres then there are no conceivable circumstances under which, 'Thereare ogres' will be false. This is to say that 'There are ogres' is necessar­

ily true ... " (p. 187).

Of these statements (I) surely is profoundly misleading, and thereseems no reason to believe that any of the "theologians or meta­physicians" who accepted the traditional Square of Opposition werecommitted to it. For the Square is simply concerned to exhibit thelogical interrelation of these four forms of statement, i.e., to showhow the truth value of statements of one form is determined by thetruth value of the others, and what its sides and diagonals representare statements of entailment or statements of logical necessity or im­possibility. Thus the line for superimplication drawn between A andI represents" 'A' entails'!, " or " , A :::> l' is logically necessary" andthe line for subcontrariety between I and 0 represents "-'1' entails'0' " and" '-0' entails'!' " or " '-1.-0' is logically impossible" or, asthe authors themselves so clearly put it, " 'I v 0' is a disjunction whichholds necessarily." But it is quite clear that the only information whichsuch statements of entailment or logical necessity or impossibility canyield as to the truth or falsity of values of anyone of the A,E,I,O formsmust be hypothetical: they tell us only if 0 is false then I must be true,if A is true then I must be true, etc. Of course we might say, e.g., of

202

Page 7: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

A LOGICIAN'S FAIRY TALE

the contradictory forms A and 0, E and I, "One of them must be true,"but this would be a loose idiom for "If either is true then the other mustbe false, and if either is false the other must be true." Accordingly in­stead of (1) the authors are entitled only to assert:

(IA) "Given any set of propositions of the forms A, E, I, 0, it isplain that if one or more are false one of them at least must be true" and"the underlying assumption is such that if one of two particulars I ando is false the other must be true."

Now if this simple and vital correction of (I) to (IA) is made thenthe authors' conclusion (III) does not follow and Aristotle is notguilty of having provided a proof of the "existence of not only ogresbut something of every mentionable kind" and the "theologians andmetaphysicians" are not guilty of having neglected this proof.

But of course the correction may be challenged on the ground thatin order to sustain the authors' indictment of Aristotle we merely haveto add to (I) and (II) the principle "every meaningful proposition iseither true or false" and that this has not been stated only becauseit is too obvious to be stated even in an elementary book on logic.But here I think lies a serious misunderstanding of the nature of com­mon discourse, for in the sense required for the authors' argument thisprinciple is not only not obvious but false. Of course we could concedethat if an empirical descriptive sentence has meaning it must be possible(however vaguely or imperfectly) to describe circumstances in whichif the sentence were used the statement thereby made would be trueand not also false, and other circumstances in which it would be falseand not also true. And no doubt "Some ogres are wicked" has a mean­ing for us just because we could specify such circumstances, but thisdoes not in the least mean that on every occasion (including the courseof a fairy tale) when the sentences "All ogres are wicked," "Some ogresare wicked," are used a statement is made which must be graded aseither true or false. And yet it is this that the authors must maintainif their indictment of Aristotle is to succeed; for, only if it is the casethat on every occasion of the meaningful use of a sentence of the A, E,I, 0 form the statement thereby made must be true or false, does itfollow from the description given by the Square of the logical relationsbetween these forms that one of them must be true; only if this is thecase, has Aristotle proved into existence "not only ogres but somethingof every mentionable kind."

203

Page 8: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW

In making this criticism I am not contending for a third truth value,a "multi-valued" logic, or the introduction of any sophisticated formalprinciple. I am on the contrary defending a feature of ordinary speechagainst a formal logician's prejudice which has blinded authors as ac­curate as these to the difference between (I) and (IA), or at least hasmade them disregard it. The prejudice is that all descriptive sentencesshare at least this characteristic, that whenever they are meaningfullyuttered this results in a statement which must be either true or false(factually true or false, not "true or false in fiction") and must applyto something, though not necessarily the entities designated by theirgrammatical subjects, for those may not exist. No doubt this closeidentification of the notion of meaning with the notion of being true orfalse is a fundamental principle of the "extensional" logic which hasresulted from the transfer to empirical discourse of principles appro­priate enough in the logical analysis of mathematics, but it leads hereto the obliteration of a vital feature in the use (and in some contextsthe abuse) we make of words. To make serious factually true or falsestatements is no doubt the most important use of intelligible descriptivesentences, but it is not the only use. For we can and do often say when asentence has been used in our presence that the question of its truthor falsity does not arise on this occasion though of course we can under­stand it and consequently may recognize its logical relation to otherpropositions. One such situation is the occasion when fairy tales aretold to us; ogres, we know, do not exist, but the storyteller is for ourentertainment making the peculiar use of words which we can callspeaking as if they do, and saying things which, if ogres existed, couldbe true or false, but since they do not exist are neither. The context ofthis occasion, verbal, factual (no ogres), and histrionic, make it clearthat it would be absurd to press seriously the question; "Is it true(not just part of the story) that all ogres are wicked?" Indeed so faris it from being the case that every statement we understand mustbe either true or false that if we did press this question seriously thatwould be a sign that we had not understood the speaker's use of thesentence. An important variant of this type of situation when "true"or "false" is out of place has been recognized by lawyers as well aslogicians in the Fallacy of Many Questions. If Smith has no wife werefuse to say that "Smith has left off beating his wife" is true or false.Of course the sentence has a meaning which we understand: we could

204

Page 9: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

A LOGICIAN'S FAIRY TALE

describe the circumstances in which it would be true or false and wecould say what it entails or what is entailed by it. All that is "wrong"where the Fallacy of Many Questions is committed is that on theparticular occasion of its usage we cannot characterize it as true or falsebecause this is possible only when the prior questions "Has he a wifeand has he beaten her?" have been settled affirmatively. If the speakerpresses for an answer to the question: "Is it true or is it false?" wesay "It does not arise; you must be under the mistaken impressionthat Smith has a wife:' Nothing but the logician's prejudice that onevery occasion of use a meaningful sentence must be true or false debarsus from making this natural comment: only this prejudice forces us to"translate" the sentence into an existential statement in order to havethe dubious satisfaction of calling it false. And the same prejudiceforces us to "translate" All ogres are wicked" into a negative existentialstatement, ,.., ( 3 x). f x . ,.., g x, in order to have the still more dubi­ous satisfaction of calling it (vacuously) true. To steer clear of theseparadoxes, it is necessary to keep sharply separate the question whichconcerns the meaning or meaningful character of a sentence, namely, inwhat circumstances would it be true or false, from the question whetheron any particular occasion of use the statement made is true or false or,as in the case of fiction, cannot be seriously characterized as either.

IV

The foregoing is enough to clear Aristotle of the authors' thirdcharge. But it is important to see that the first charge of the incon­sistency of the Square is for similar reasons also ill-founded, not be­cause it matters much that Aristotle was not guilty but because thecharge rests on a misunderstanding of the precise character of the"existential import" of the A, E, I, 0 forms which we need to under­stand if we are to characterize adequately their use in fiction.

Consider the authors' statement:(II) "Both I and 0 imply that there are ogres."Here "imply" has, as the authors make dear, the sense of "entail:'

But is (II) true? Of course the modern transcription of I and 0as ( 3 x). f x . g x and ( 3 x). f x . ,.., g x assumes that it is true, andconsistently with this the authors (P. 178), in advocating this tran­scription, write "Some cab drivers are well-read says4 that some in-

• My italics.205

Page 10: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW

dividuals are both cab drivers and well-read" and add the remark that"Some cab drivers are well-read" would be made false if no individualwere either a cab driver or well-read. But unless the propriety of themodern transcription of the I and 0 forms is already assumed thereseems no reas~)ll for saying that the statement is false if made underthese circumstances. For again the proper comment in these circum­stances is that the statement is not to be characterized as either true orfalse, just as "Smith has left off beating his wife" is neither true or falseif Smith has no wife or has never beaten her. And so in fairy tales. Ofcourse the story-teller who says "Some ogres are wicked" speaks on thisoccasion as if there were ogres; perhaps he pretends to believe that thereare ogres or might even believe that in fact there are. But whichever (ifany) of these is the correct description of the use made on this occasionof the sentence "Some ogres are wicked," the fact that there are noogres does not render what he says false; and, if this is so, "Some ogresare wicked" does not entail that there are ogres. Moreover the sameholds true of the relation between "There are no ogres" and the A andE forms, "All ogres are wicked" and "No ogres are wicked." Thesedo not entail "There are ogres" and are not rendered false by"There are no ogres" as they would be on the existential interpretation,..., (3 x). f x . - g x : (3 x). f x ; nor are they rendered true by it asthey would be on the minimum interpretation - ( 3 x). f x . - g x.

N one the less there is a close connection, though not entailment, be­tween the A, E, I, 0 forms as used in ordinary nonmathematical andnonscientific discourse and sentences asserting the existence of mem­bers of their subject class: they have "existential import"; but it isnot that of the existential interpretation of the A and E forms or of themodern transcription of the I and 0 forms. It consists in the followingfeatures of their use:

(I) The existential interpretation - ( 3 x). f x . - g x: ( 3 x). f xmisrepresents the force of "All S is P" because what may falsify theformer, viz.: - ( 3 x). f x does not falsify the latter. On the other handa sentence of this existential form does entail, though it is not entailedby a sentence of the A form; for if "There are cab drivers and there areno cab drivers that are not well-read" is true, it follows that "All cabdrivers are well-read" is true. Accordingly the truth of the existentialsentence is a sufficient condition of the truth of the A sentence.

Page 11: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

A LOGICIAN'S FAIRY TALE

Further, it is also a necessary condition, but not in the same way thatthe truth of a sentence Q is a necessary condition of the truth of an­other sentence P which entails Q. For if "P" entails "Q" then if Q isfalse P is false; but though the truth of the existential sentence is anecessary condition of the truth of the A sentence ("All ogres arewicked" could not be true unless "There are ogres and there are nonethat are not wicked" is true) the falsity of the existential sentence doesnot necessarily render the A sentence false, but as in this instance maywith other circumstances show the statement made to be neither truenor false, but, e.g., fiction.

(2) Since the truth of the existential sentence is both a necessary andsufficient condition of the truth of the A sentence, anyone who in nor­mal discourse asserts such a sentence as, e.g., "All taxi drivers arewell-read," and appears to be making on this occasion a serious asse"r­tion will be properly taken to believe the corresponding existentialsentence to be true. For otherwise he could have no reasons for assert­ing it and the assumption that people do not use descriptive sentenceswithout good reason for believing them to be true (which of coursestrongly influences the whole character of empirical discourse) con­stitutes here a nonformal connection between the existential statementand the A form. If we want a word we can say that the A form in theabsence of a special indication "presupposes" or "strongly suggests"the truth of the existential form. But these psychological terms ill con­vey the conventional character of the connection.

(3) The above shows the connection between the whole complexexistential sentence ,-.J ( 3 x). f x . ,-.J g x :( 3 x). f x and the A form.But the truth of the sentence (3 x). f x, asserting merely the existenceof members of the subject class, though it does not entail the A form,is a necessary condition of its truth in the special sense explainedabove. For the normal use of the A, E, I, 0 forms outside science andmathematics is in a context where (I) members of their subject classexist and (2) the speaker believes this. This existential condition is somuch part of the conventional context for the use of these forms thatif a speaker after saying, e.g., "All Smith's children are girls," added"But he has none," the addition, though not a contradiction (as onthe existential interpretation it would be), and though certainly nota verification (as on the minimum interpretation), would cancel theoriginal remark, not as something which the speaker has no reason

207

Page 12: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW

to believe, but as applying to nothing, not to be graded true or false, and(since it was not part of a story) pointless. But that this existentialcondition, conventionally required for the normal use of these forms, issatisfied, is not anything which they either state or entail; for they canbe used without contradiction or loss of meaning where it is not satis­fied, as in fiction. On the other hand, for a vast range of empiricalsentences the logical force of "All" and "Some" as part of the subjectterm is determined by this convention, though its effect cannot be con­veyed in the notation of quantifiers and propositional functions, for thatfails either by explicitly stating that the existential condition is satisfiedor by ignoring it altogether.

(4) The use of the A, E, I, 0 forms in fiction is a play upon thesefeatures of their normal usage. The storyteller's use of sentences doesnot in fact satisfy the conventional requirement for normal use, but hespeaks as if they did, and thus obtains his effects. Perhaps nothingshows more clearly the connection between sentences of these formsand the existential statements which are wrongly said to be entailed bythem, or by part of their meaning, than an examination of how "Thereare no ogres" might bear upon "Some ogres are wicked." We mightsay "There are no ogres" comfortingly to the crying child who hasheard the storyteller say "Some ogres are wicked", or we might sayit admonishingly to the storyteller. And in either case we are doingsomething more radical than saying "That is false" but less radicalthan saying "That has no sense" ; we are saying "That applies to noth­ing." We could contradict "Some ogres are wicked" by saying "Thatis false: no ogres are wicked," but contradiction is a colder comfortthan what we provide with "There are no ogres," for it leaves the childto face ogres with qualities other than wickedness. "There are no ogres"cuts deeper at the roots of fear: it points out that the existential con­ditions for a serious statement which can be graded as either true orfalse are not on this occasion satisfied and so "Some ogres are wicked"is neither. And of course the storyteller might himself say after thestory is over "But there are no ogres" without contradicting himself,just to show that he had been telling a story, though it would defeathis purpose as a storyteller to say this while telling it. In short "Thereare no ogres" shows that the conventionally required context for theserious use of these forms does not hold: and showing this is an im­portant piece of evidence that the speaker was Just telling a story. Of

208

Page 13: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

A LOGICIAN'S FAIRY TALE

course, though important, it is only evidence, not proof, because alter­native explanations are possible, dependent on the speaker's intentionor state of mind: he may have been guilty of a deliberate· attempt tomislead or a sheer misunderstanding. Moreover, if the speaker wasbent on telling a story, what he said would still be fiction, even if ogresdid exist.

These characteristics of the normal use of the A, E, I, 0 forms out­side science and mathematics constitute their "existential import" andshow that, while neither the minimum interpretation nor the existentialinterpretation conveys their meaning or special function, these twoalternatives do not, as is often assumed when the Square of Oppositionis attacked as inconsistent, exhaust the possibilities of interpretation.The alleged inconsistencies in the Square materialize only if, acceptingthese two interpretations as exhaustive, we mistakenly concede thatthe A, E, I, 0 forms are existential sentences to whose truth or falsitythe existence of members of the subject classes is directly relevant. Infact they are not forms of existential statements (though they have closeconnections with such statements) and the existence or nonexistenceof members of the subject class determines not the truth or falsity ofstatements of these forms but only the prior question whether the ques­tion of their truth or falsity can arise. And this being so, there is nothingto prevent all the relations represented by the Square from holdinggood. For in considering these relations, e.g., whether A and 0 arecontradictories, and whether A is superimplicant to I (two relationswhich, on the authors' view, cannot hold for anyone interpretation ofthese forms), we have only to ask the hypothetical question whether, ifA were true, would 0 be false and I true, and the answer to this ques­tion (which is "yes") is not affected by the fact that on some occasionsof use, e.g., in the event of their being no members of the subject class,statements of these forms would not be graded as either true or false.Questions of existence lie outside the scope of the Square and thosewho constructed it along these lines accurately interpreted the ordinaryusage of these forms. Of course the Square tells us nothing about thedifference between seriously true and false statements and fiction;but it depicts the logical relations between sentences which hold goodindependently of whether or not on any particular occasion the usemade of these forms is serious statement and so true or false, or fictionand so neither.

Page 14: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW

What I have said is open to a misinterpretation which I can bestpreclude by dealing with the authors' remaining charge, namely, thatthe classical existential interpretation fails to express and the modernminimum interpretation does express an important class of universalproposition (of which they cite four) all "held to be true" .(p. 180).

(1) No uranium deposits in Ohio are easy to mine.(2) All human beings free from bacteria are free from disease.(3) All bodies free from impressed force persevere in their state of rest or in

uniform motion in a straight line.(4) All Greek gods have human frailties.

The authors draw no distinction between these four: all, in theirview, are negative existential statements and they so "translate" thefirst two; and all are true (together of course with their apparentcontraries "All uranium deposits .., .," etc., "No human beings ... ,"etc.) in the same factual though vacuous sense of true, because theycorrectly describe a world in which there are no Ohio uranium de­posits, bacteria-free human beings, bodies free from impressed forcesor Greek gods. But clearly it is necessary to distinguish between thesefour statements. If asked to say whether (I) was true, there being noOhio uranium deposits, only those debarred by logical prejudices fromsaying it was neither true nor false would say it was true; this at leastis an obvious case where we would say the question of truth does notarise and would correct the mistaken assumption which has led to theremark. (4) is a different case, for, if by "true" we mean the proposi­tion is part of Greek mythology or of the religious beliefs of the ancientGreeks, then in this sense it is true though not vacuously, and "NoGreek gods have human frailties" is in the corresponding sense falseand not (as it too would be on the authors' interpretation) vacuouslytrue; but we might also equally well say that since Greek gods did notexist the serious question of the truth or falsity of this statement cannotarise. Cases (2) and (3) are different again: they are propositions ofscience which might well be called true: certainly we would not saythe question of their truth or falsity does not arise. But of course tosee what is done by calling (3) "true," we must examine its role inthe physical theory of which it is part and the way in which the theoryrelates to fact. This is a complex matter and involves a discussion ofthe sense in which contrary-to-the-fact conditionals can be called trueor false. But it is clear that the truth of (2) and (3) is not vacuous

210

Page 15: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

A LOGICIAN'S FAIRY TALE

truth: they are not true because they accurately describe the worldas empty of bacteria-free human beings not also free from disease, andas empty of bodies at once free from impressed forces and failing topersevere in their state of motion or rest, etc. This is simply not theirrole, and if it were we should have to say, in spite of the evidence ofscience, that their apparent contraries are also true. And this seemsmore than "at first sight paradoxicaL" But though the authors havegiven us no examples of statements of the form "All S is P" which wewould say are true merely because there are no S's, it is also quite clearthat it is not always the case that where there are no S's we shouldsay the question of the truth or falsity does not arise. We would saythis where the speaker in ordinary discourse is under the mistakenimpression that there are S's and S's might conceivably have existed(uranium deposits in Ohio; Smith's children) but merely in fact donot: we would not say it where S stands for a theoretical concept ofphysics, and the ground for asserting it is its role as a law of atheoretical system and not its success in describing the world, thoughthe theory as a whole may be verified in various complex ways by ob­servation. Such general propositions of law, though they are notlogically necessary, resemble in some respects necessary propositionsin that they are not themselves verifiable or falsifiable by a simple ap­appeal to the facts as general propositions of fact such as "All Smith'schildren are girls" are. Hence the nonexistence of S's in cases such as(3) is not a ground for calling (3) true, but it is also not a ground forsaying that the statement is neither true nor false.

vAccordingly, in order to characterise a fairy tale and no doubt other

important uses of words, we must do a number of things which theformal logician is not accustomed to do. First, we must recognize that,because a sentence has a meaning which we understand and statementsmade by its use have logical relations with other statements, it doesnot follow that on every occasion of the intelligible use of the sentencea statement is made which must be either true or false, for fiction isneither. Secondly, we must recognize that, as a result of the obviousfact that certain types of empirical sentence such as the A, E, I, 0 formsare primarily designed for use (and so to be true and false) whereobjects mentioned by their subject terms exist, there is a conventional

2II

Page 16: A Logician's Fairy Tale. H. L. a. Hart

THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW

connection between these sentences and existential sentences by WhIChwe affirm that the conditions for normal use are satisfied. This con­ventional connection is not entailment; and one of the major devices offiction is the intentional infringement of the convention. Thirdly, wemust shift our logical attention from the general to the particular, andwe must concentrate not on the meaning, or the truth conditions, orthe logical relations of statements, but on the circumstances of particu­lar occasions of use, and on what may be called the mode of assertionof the sentence on the particular occasion. That is,. we must enquire( I) whether the existential condition required for the normal use of asentence is satisfied, and (2) why the speaker spoke as if this conditionwere satisfied. For the differentia of fiction does not lie in the generalmatters first mentioned, but in the use (which is in a sense a calculatedabuse) of a general form of words on a particular occasion.

H. L. A. HARTNew College, Oxford

212