a summary of hegels christian philosophy ryan haecker

31
Interview with a Right Hegelian: A Summary of Hegel's Christian Philosophy by Ryan Haecker [The following text is the compilation of an e-mail interview of Mr. Ryan Haecker conducted by Mr. Derick Varn between March and April of 2013.] Q: Why do you think Hegel's relevance as a specifically Christian thinker has been downplayed over time? A: There is a long-standing reticence to acknowledge Hegel as a Christian theologian. Controversy surrounding the Christian and orthodox content of the philosophy of Hegel has swelled since before Hegel passed from the world in 1831: Hegel had already in his lifetime been accused of denying a personal God, logizing the Holy Trinity, theologizing history, eleaticizing Spinozism, Pantheism, materialism, idealism, reactionary conservatism, radical republicanism, Prussian nationalism, liberal cosmopolitanism and Bonapartist imperialism. Some of these allegations may be more warranted than others, but even a cursory glance through the diversity of allegations and appropriations which have been made of the philosophy of Hegel during and after his life testifies to the bewilderment, excitement, and animosity stirred up by Hegel's philosophy. There are, to my mind, three primary reasons for this medley of bamboozlement and controversy: First, like no philosopher since Airstotle in the age of Alexander the Great, Hegel claimed, in the age of Napoleon, the imperial crown of sovereign philosophy by negating the conclusions of all hitherto existing philosophical systems, as well as asserting the superiority of his own doctrine - which simultaneously incorporated and appropriated the philosophies which he asserted himself to have superseded in thought. Second, Hegel announced the messianic and world-historical importance of his very own philosophy, which he held to have completed - as far as was possible in his own historical moment - the truth of religion and reason, that was only signified for imagination in the Christian Gospel. Ordinarily such claims would result in either confinement to a lunatic asylum or - as with Friederich Nietzsche - a struggle with immovable reality to the contrary that might well precipitate a mental collapse, but Hegel's extraordinary

Upload: siddharth-shankaran

Post on 17-Nov-2015

23 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Hegel's roots in christian philosophy

TRANSCRIPT

  • Interview with a Right Hegelian: A Summary of Hegel's Christian Philosophy

    by Ryan Haecker

    [The following text is the compilation of an e-mail interview of Mr. Ryan Haecker conducted by Mr. Derick

    Varn between March and April of 2013.]

    Q: Why do you think Hegel's relevance as a specifically Christian thinker has been

    downplayed over time?

    A: There is a long-standing reticence to acknowledge Hegel as a Christian theologian.

    Controversy surrounding the Christian and orthodox content of the philosophy of

    Hegel has swelled since before Hegel passed from the world in 1831: Hegel had already

    in his lifetime been accused of denying a personal God, logizing the Holy Trinity,

    theologizing history, eleaticizing Spinozism, Pantheism, materialism, idealism,

    reactionary conservatism, radical republicanism, Prussian nationalism, liberal

    cosmopolitanism and Bonapartist imperialism. Some of these allegations may be more

    warranted than others, but even a cursory glance through the diversity of allegations

    and appropriations which have been made of the philosophy of Hegel during and after

    his life testifies to the bewilderment, excitement, and animosity stirred up by Hegel's

    philosophy. There are, to my mind, three primary reasons for this medley of

    bamboozlement and controversy: First, like no philosopher since Airstotle in the age of

    Alexander the Great, Hegel claimed, in the age of Napoleon, the imperial crown of

    sovereign philosophy by negating the conclusions of all hitherto existing

    philosophical systems, as well as asserting the superiority of his own doctrine - which

    simultaneously incorporated and appropriated the philosophies which

    he asserted himself to have superseded in thought. Second, Hegel announced the

    messianic and world-historical importance of his very own philosophy, which he held

    to have completed - as far as was possible in his own historical moment - the truth

    of religion and reason, that was only signified for imagination in

    the Christian Gospel. Ordinarily such claims would result in either confinement to a

    lunatic asylum or - as with Friederich Nietzsche - a struggle with immovable reality to

    the contrary that might well precipitate a mental collapse, but Hegel's extraordinary

  • claims were plausibly, as with those of Jesus Christ's, fulfilled by extraordinary

    results. Third, there is the unmistakable circuitousness, complexity, and gothic intricacy

    of Hegel's writings, which belabor scholars for years just as they baffle and

    frustrate casual readers. The consequence is a general unwillingness of most - even

    scholarly readers - to devote the considerable labor of thought required to grasp the

    central ideas of Hegelian philosophy. The grandness of Hegel's self-estimation

    combined with the difficulty of his texts contributes to the suspicion and hostility

    towards the philosophy of Hegel among most thinkers, but especially among Christians

    for whom Hegel represents both the potential for the dialectical advancement, negation,

    and nullification of the central tenets of the Christian religion.

    Q: What do you think is the key theological truth of Hegel?

    A: There is nothing in Hegel's philosophy of Absolute Idealism which is not implicitly

    related to the Absolute, to theology, and to God. God is present from the first moment

    of sense-certainty, as the "richest and poorest truth," to the complete realization, in

    thought, of the Absolute Idea. In the introduction to the Encyclopedia of Philosophical

    Sciences Hegel wrote: "The objects of philosophy, it is true, are upon the whole the same

    as those of religion. In both the object is Truth, in that supreme sense in which God and

    God only is the Truth. Both in like manner go on to treat of the finite worlds

    of Nature and the human Mind, with their relation to each other and to their truth in

    God." All thought from the barest manifold of intuition to the most majestic

    apprehension of the entire cosmos is ideal participation in the divine life of God. For

    Hegel as with Paul of Tarsus, God is Hen Kai Pan - All in All -in whom we all "live, and

    move, and have our being" (Acts 17:28). In this regard, Hegel follows the ancient idealist

    tradition of Parmenides, Plato, Philo, Plotinus, Porphyry, and Proclus; as well as the

    medieval mystics from Augustine and John Scotus of Eriugena to Bonaventure, Meister

    Eckhart and Joseph Boehme; and finally the modern idealists of Spinoza, Kant and

    Schelling.

    Since the 13th century nominalists had overturned the great medieval synthesis of

    the Angelic Doctor Thomas Aquinas, theology had suffered from an ever-widening

  • chasm between saecula (the sacred) and seculorum (the profane), Deus (God)

    and mundi (the World), Caelo (Heaven) andTerra (Earth). This is Lessing's Chasm

    which characterizes the dualisms of modern philosophy. In the theology of Thomas

    Aquinas this chasm results from the transcendence of God's simple unity over the

    composite created world; in the theology of John Duns Scotus this chasm was the

    consequence of the division between God's necessary and accidental attributes, or

    between those things which are rationally necessary by divine reason and those things

    which are merely possible according to divine will; in the philosophy of Descartes this

    is the dualism of the perfect infinite incorporal God and the mechanistic corporal

    universe; in the philosophy of Leibniz this is the dualism of the Monad of Monads and

    the necessary cooperation of the infinite multiplicity of subordinate monads; in the

    philosophy of Spinoza, this is the dualism of thought and extension; and finally in the

    philosophy of Kant, this is the dualism of reason and intuition, concepts and percepts,

    and of the noumenal and the phenomenal realms. In every case, infinite Eleatic-Platonic

    simple transcendent One is opposed to finite multiple composite Milesian-Democritean

    atoms of material Nature. The ambition of the identity philosophy of Schelling and

    Hegel was conceived to be a purgative corrective to modernity's infinite repetition of

    the antitheses of the infinite non-Ego with the finite self-positing of the Ego. Schelling

    writes:

    "The genuinely speculative question remains: how may the absolutely One, the

    absolutely simple and eternal Will from which all things flow, expand into

    multiplicity and be reborn as a unity, i.e. into the moral world... The question

    would be an indispensable and unavoidable problem if this philosophy [of

    Fichte] actually made what is for it the Absolute into a principle as well - but it

    rather carefully guards against this and lets the whole of finitude be given to it,

    very conveniently along with the... common dogmatism that the Absolute is a

    result and something that needs a justification... What is the characteristic of this

    philosophy [of Fichte] is just that it has given new form to the age-old dichotomy

    between the infinite and the finite; but such forms may be legion - none lasts, and

    each carries impermanence within itself. It cannot found anything permanent.

    An enthusiasm that fancies itself to be great if it sets its own Ego up in its

    thoughts against the wild storms of elements, the thousand thousand suns and

    the ruins of the whole world, makes this philosophy popular; and also makes it

  • dumb and hollow otherwise - a fruit of the age whose spirit has for a time

    exalted this empty form, until the age sinks back as its own ebb sets in, and the

    fruit along with it. What abides is only what supersedes all dichotomy; for only

    that is in truth One and unchangeably the same... Only what proceeds from the

    absolute unity of the infinite and finite is immediately and essentially capable of

    symbolic presentation; capable of true philosophy; of becoming religion, or an

    objective and eternal source of new intuition; a universal model of everything in

    which human action endeavors to portray the harmony of the universe." - F. W. J.

    Schelling, On the Relationship of the Philosophy of Nature to the Philosophy in

    General, Kritisches Journal der Philosophie, I, no. 3, 1802

    The philosophy of Spirit of G.W.F. Hegel can be conceived of as a dialectical

    reconciliation of the finite world of our ordinary experience with the infinite ideal life of

    the Absolute, which is God's infinite being. The success of this reconciliation is meant to

    fulfill the promise, in thought, of the Christian religion and restore the august throne of

    speculative philosophy, or metaphysics, as the sovereign science: "The germ of

    Christianity was the feeling of separation of the world from God; its aim was the

    reconciliation with God -not through a raising of finitude to the infinite, but through the

    infinite's becoming finite, or through God's becoming man... All the symbols of

    Christianity exhibit the characteristic that they represent the identity of God with the

    world in images" (ibid.). The genuinely gnostic ambition of German Idealism is

    salvation, neither through faith or works alone, but through both together in the

    theoretical and fideistic praxis of philosophy, which is both devotion to God and love of

    holy wisdom - Hagia Sophia. Hegel considered himself a religious reformer. Yet unlike

    Luther, Hegel did not endeavor to widen but to reconcile the opposition of faith and

    reason; church and state; and man with God. He brought the sword of negativity down

    upon only those philosophies which maintained themselves in self-certain fixidity,

    refused to "tarry with the negative," and thereby "blasphemed against the Holy Ghost."

    Like Kant, Hegel's purpose was irenic: to pacify the endemic strife of thought that

    tossed into ceaseless tumult the Republic of Letters - "Blessed are the Peacemakers for

    they shall be called sons of God." (Mt. 5:9)

    The key contributions of Hegelian philosophy to Christian theology corresponds in a

    threefold way, to the persons of the Holy Trinity: First, the philosophy of Mind, in the

    https://www.facebook.com/pages/F-W-J-Schelling/108352565862615?group_id=0https://www.facebook.com/pages/F-W-J-Schelling/108352565862615?group_id=0

  • Phenomenology of Spirit, is Christocentric as it aims at nothing less than the approach of

    the subject consciousness with the eternal reason of God: this culminates in the death

    and resurrection of Jesus Christ in the final moment of religious consciousness; the dark

    night of the soul; the speculative Good Friday in which God is dead, that concludes the

    logical sequence of historical religions; dissolves all nature, objectivity, and natural

    religion into the subjective stages of consciousness; and reconstructs each and all

    according to the Spirit of Pentecost, the apostolic Church, and the Gospel of speculative

    philosophy. Second, the philosophy of logic, in the Science of Logic, is theocentric as it

    deduces the three persons of the Holy Trinity from logical generation of the heavenly

    Father into the three moments of Being, Essence and Concept; which come to be

    manifested in the encyclopedic divisions of Logic, Nature and Spirit; and which are

    altogether united in the ceaseless eternal self-loving - immanent and economic - logical

    procession of the Holy Trinity. Third, the philosophy of history, in the Lectures on the

    History of Philosophy and the Philosophy of History, is pnuematocentric as it illustrates the

    efflorescence and vital activity of the Holy Spirit as logic directs the sequence of events

    in history through the temporal realization of the eternal providence of God. The triadic

    division of Hegelian philosophy; into Father (Logic), Son (Mind) and Holy Spirit

    (History); is altogether integrally united in the Science of Logic, in which Hegel intends to

    demonstrate nothing less than the Trinitarian logic and essence of the Triune God. The

    result must, if correct, be at once the culmination and resolution of centuries of

    antitheses in theology, science and philosophy, and of no little interest to all speculative

    thinkers of some spiritual depth.

    Q: Do you think reading Hegel without this Christian background has led to a

    profound misunderstanding of his work? If so, what are the key misunderstandings?

    A: There is both an interpretation of the philosophy of Hegel in which his "Christian

    background" is denied, as well as an interpretation in which his "Christian

    background" is acknowledged and yet considered inessential to his philosophy. In

    every case, the genuine question must be, not whether Hegel is acknowledged to have

    believed in Christianity or to have lived in a largely Christian nation, but rather

    whether his philosophy is essentially Christian. Hegel did not understood philosophy

  • to be Christian because he himself was a Christian, any more than he held philosophy

    to be German because he was himself a German (although he once remarked that he

    would teach philosophy to speak German). Rather Hegel held religion to be essentially

    reasonable, and reason to be essentially religion, just as Christianity is essentially

    philosophical, and philosophy is essentially Christian. The opposite categories are

    altogether united in the speculative identity of the Absolute Idea. Hegel writes in the

    Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion:

    "The human spirit, in its innermost nature is not something so divided up that

    two contradictory elements might subsist together in it. If discord has arisen

    between intellectual insight and religion, and is not overcome in knowledge, it

    leads to despair. This despair is reconciliation carried out in a one-sided manner.

    The one side is cast away, and the other left alone held fast; but man cannot win

    true peace in this way. The one alternative is, for divided spirit to reject the

    demands of the intellect and try to return to simple religious feeling. To this,

    however, the spirit can only attain by doing violence to itself, for the

    independence of consciousness demands satisfaction and to renounce

    independent thought is not within the power of a healthy mind. Religious feeling

    becomes yearning hypocrisy, and retains the moment of non-satisfaction. The

    other alternative is a one-sided attitude of indifference toward religion, which is

    either left unquestioned, or ultimately attacked and opposed. That is the course

    followed by shallow spirits."

    Thus, it is a misunderstanding to suppose that Christianity is somehow capriciously

    attached to the philosophy of Hegel, as an afterthought brought in through the window.

    Schelling and Hegel wrote:

    "We do not even recognize as philosophy any view which is not already religion

    in its principle, [and] we reject any cognition of the Absolute which emerges

    merely as a result - we reject any view which thinks of God in himself in some

    empirical connection; precisely because the spirit of ethical life, and of

    philosophy, is for us one and the same; we reject any doctrine according to which

    the object of the intellect must, like nature, be just a means to the ethical life, and

  • must on that account be deprived, in itself stripped of the inner substance of that

    life." (Kritisches Journal der Philosophie, 1804)

    In his celebrated three critiques of reason, Immanuel Kant believed himself to disclose

    the essence, potential and limits of reason itself. Following the Late-Medieval

    nominalist opposition between faith and reason, Kant held faith (glauben) to consist in

    beliefs that were wholly unsupported by reason (wissen). Hence, the limits of reason

    fenced in rational understanding just as much as they fenced out irrational belief, so

    that true religion, like true philosophy, must remain within the secure battlements of

    self-critical reason - the limits of reason alone. Kant defined the limits of reason to be the

    antinomies, or paralogisms of reason, which he held to necessarily arise from the

    uncritical speculation of 'metaphysics' beyond the sure lighthouses of analytic

    deduction and the safe harbors of sensory intuition: inferences of synthetic apriori

    concepts that, qua synthetic, contain the content of sensory intuition and yet purport to

    describe objects which are properly supersensible (e.g. the soul, the cosmos and God)

    cannot be reliably trusted: for every dogmatic supersensible inference, any equally valid

    yet contradictory inference may be affirmed; and the possibility of affirming valid

    contradictions results in antinomies, or a contradictions in the valid exercise of the laws

    of logic; such that reasoning which trespasses beyond self-critical boundaries

    ineluctably obliterates itself in self-contradictory paralogisms. In this way, Kant

    anticipated the Verification Principle of A.J. Ayer and the Analytic Positivists in holding

    that consistent, i.e. non-contradictory, synthetic a priori truths of reason must be either

    analytically self-evident or empirically observable. This Kantian prohibition rendered

    knowledge of supersensible a priori concepts (e.g. the soul, the cosmos and God) totally

    inadmissible as theoretical knowledge, even while they were necessary for practical

    reason of ethics, politics and religion.

    The consequence of the Kantian prohibition on supersensible a priori concepts was a

    series of dualisms, between reason and intuition, concepts and percepts, theory and

    practice, a priori and a posteriori truths, and the noumenal and phenomenal realms.

    Kant struggled to reconcile these dualisms in the Critique of Judgment, in which the

    faculty of aesthetic judgment was intended to mediate between reason and intuition,

    yet only succeeded in producing many more speculative paradoxes. The task of Kant's

    immediate successors; e.g. Reinhold, Jacobi, Niebuhr, and Fichte; was to systematize the

  • prolific yet disconnected medley of concepts expounded in Kant's critical philosophy.

    This required a single axiom, or ur-form, to carry the weight as a cornerstone for the

    whole edifice of Kantian philosophy. Imagination, faith, practical reason, consciousness

    and the transcendental Ego were all proclaimed as sovereign axioms in a furious

    succession which culminated in the 1796 Wissenschaftslehre of J.G. Fichte. F.W.J.

    Schelling's decisive contribution was to oppose the self-positing Ego of Fichte with the

    Absolute non-Ego of Spinoza's Nature - Deus sive Natura - and unite both together in the

    speculative identity of the Absolute Ego, the idea of God. Thus did post-Kantian

    idealism return to St. Anselm of Canterbury's "highest idea... than which nothing

    greater can be conceived." (the Proslogion, 1078)

    After Schelling's departure from Jena in 1804, G.W.F. Hegel carried his erstwhile

    mentor's Identitie-Philosophie even further in his drafted speculative systems. This

    formative activity culminated in the 1807 publication of the Phenomenology of Spirit,

    which departed from Schelling in two important respects: the Absolute Idea was placed

    at the conclusion, rather than at the beginning, of the speculative system; and the

    deduction of the concepts was dialectical and paraconsistent rather than analytic and

    consistent. The Kantian antinomies of reason compelled post-Kantian philosophers to

    choose between reason that was limited to empiricism and analyticity, or somehow

    embrace the self-contradictoriness of the antinomies. Hegel departed from Fichte and

    Schelling; for whom the resolution of the antinomies was either simply self-posited or

    an ineffable aesthetic intuition; and boldly affirmed that all speculative reasoning must

    be self-contradictory, paraconsistent and dialectical. The operative principle of dialectic

    is contrary propositions (i.e. contra-diction). In the philosophy of Hegel, however,

    'contradiction' does not simply refer to the affirmation and denial of the same

    proposition; for there can be no 'fixed propositions' at all; but rather to the contrary

    opposition of the conflicting properties of concepts which results in their mutual

    negation; and this negativity imparts dynamic self-movement to concepts. Just as Plato

    conceived the cosmos as a world-soul in the likeness of an animal organism in the

    Timaeus, so does Hegel conceive of concepts as ideal organisms in the full negativity of

    dynamic self-motion. The Absolute Idea is consequently, like Plato's world-soul and

    Schelling's Weltgeist, the self-contradictory concept of concepts - Forma Formarum -

    which absolutely envelops and supercedes all possible concepts, all thought and being,

    as that Reason (nous) which rules the world.

  • Reading Hegel without consideration of his 'Christian context' results in a profound

    misunderstanding because such readings neglect, dismiss, or diminish the essential role

    of Christianity in Hegel's mature philosophical system. This essential role can be

    illustrated by describing how the Christian religion uniquely anticipated the particular

    philosophical contributions of Hegel in post-Kantian idealism and the history of

    philosophy in general. In the mature writings (1807-1831) of Hegel, Christianity is

    explicitly dealt with in three places: the final part of C.C. Religion in the Phenomenology

    of Spirit, the third part (3.3.2.3.) of the Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences, and the third

    part of the Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion: of these, the lectures on the philosophy

    of religion constitute a more detailed exposition of the Encyclopedia; the Phenomenology

    of Spirit presents Christianity in from the standpoint of the self-development of human

    consciousness in history as the culmination of a dialectical sequence of absolute picture-

    thinking, or religion; and the Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences presents religion as the

    concept which mediates between the concepts of art and the philosophy, and

    Christianity as the absolute religion which subsumes natural and finite religions within

    itself. The place of the concept of the Christian religion in the Phenomenology and

    Encyclopedia systems of Hegelian philosophy signifies its relations to other concepts,

    both as they are subordinated, superordinated, and sublated. In the Phenomenology of

    Spirit, the Hegelian christology of the hypostatic union lies at the very pinnacle of the

    system as the completion of the dialectic of religion; which guarantees, through

    revelation from the Absolute to itself in mankind, the completion of the preceding

    dialectical movements, and the ultimate possibility of knowledge of the Absolute. In the

    Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences, the Christian religion is the 'absolute religion'

    through which aesthetic imagination becomes philosophy of the truth. The differing

    places of Christianity in the Phenomenology and Encyclopedia systems can be

    explained according to the differing systematic roles of the two works: while the

    Phenomenology of Spirit presents the successive dialectical movements of naive

    consciousness in relation to the Absolute, the Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences

    outlines the relation of the Absolute to itself in the successive dialectical movements of

    its own self-development. Thus, Christianity makes knowledge of the Absolute (C.DD.

    Absolute Knowledge) possible for-consciousness in the Phenomenology of Spirit, while

    Christianity mediates between art and philosophy, intuitions and concepts, in the

    absolute self-becoming of concepts in the Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences.

  • Hegel distinguishes Christianity from all dialectically prior revealed religions (e.g.

    Zoroastrianism, Judaism, Islam etc.) according to the uniqueness of the incarnation and

    the 'death of God' on the cross. The incarnation of Christ is not merely an act of divine

    intervention but a world-historical event that, when believed to be true, radically

    transforms our collective self-understanding; for we then acknowledge our self-same

    absolute freedom, sacrality, and divinity through the image of the God-man. The

    deeper meaning of Ecce Homo, "behold the man", is precisely this; that man sees his own

    absoluteness in the person of Christ, in which the Absolute Idea of God is uniquely and

    substantially united with the essence of mankind. Through this revelation, the nature of

    man comes to be acknowledged as potentially absolute, and hence potentially sharing

    in the freedom, sacrality and divinity of God. For this reason, the gospels of Christ,

    through which the Absolute is imagistically revealed, is also an anthropology of man.

    Hegel held this Christian theological-anthropology to have world-historical importance

    for the development of reason itself, which is the spirit of the world - der Weltgeist. Faith

    in the hypostatic union of the dual natures of God and man in the person of Christ is the

    crucial presupposition that enables the reason to develop with complete confidence in

    knowing the objective world of the non-Ego and the Absolute. So long as subjective

    consciousness was opposed to an alien objective non-Ego, there could be no condition

    for the identity and synthesis of knowledge of things for-us and the things-in-

    themselves, and scientific knowledge of the cosmos could, with the ancient Skeptics, be

    assumed to be ultimately unknowable.

    This problem is represented by Plato in the sixth and greatest difficulty (133a134e) of

    the dialogue the Parmenides: Parmenides argues against Socrates that, according to the

    Platonic epistemology, forms may only be related to other forms just as sensible things

    may only be related to other sensible things; humans cannot know forms just as the

    gods cannot know human affairs; so that there can never be knowledge of forms or

    relations of the gods to men. The problem of the greatest difficulty is the problem of

    mediating the dualist cosmology - the divided line - of Plato's Middle-Period dialogues

    (e.g. Phaedo, Republic, Symposium) and resolving opposite ontic categories of form

    and matter into a consistent unity. This problem of dualism is represented in religious

    consciousness in the Messianism of the Jews after the Babylonian Exile (582-538 BC).

    Bereft of the anointed monarchy of the House of David and the Ark of the First Temple,

  • the Jews groaned in agony and expectation for their salvation from invasion,

    contamination and occupation by foreign peoples (e.g. the Greeks and Romans). The

    unnamable God - the tetragrammaton 'YHWH' - beyond the world was expected to

    directly intervene as a champion Messiah to shepherd Lord's people Israel to true

    freedom and everlasting majesty. The 71st Psalm petitions:

    "Give to the king thy judgment, O God, and to the king's son they justice... He

    shall judge the poor of the people, and he shall save the children of the poor, and

    he shall humble the oppressor, and he shall continue with the Sun and before the

    Moon, throughout all generations... In his day shall justice spring up, and

    abundance of peace, till the Moon be taken away. And he shall rule from sea to

    sea and from the river unto the ends of the Earth... And all kings of the Earth

    shall adore him; all nations shall serve him."

    Thus, both Jews and Gentiles - Jerusalem and Athens - awaited the absolute mediation

    of God with man at the conclusion of the political development of the antique world, in

    which the universal Roman Empire united all nations, and:

    "All the conditions for its production [were] present... These forms [of

    personality, legal right, of Stoicism and Skepticism] compose, the periphery of

    the forms, which attend round the birthplace of Spirit as it becomes self-

    consciousness. Their center is the yearning agony of the unhappy despairing self-

    consciousness, a pain which permeates all of them and is the common birth-pain

    of its production the simplicity of the pure notion, which contains those forms

    as its moments... The incarnation of the Divine Being, its having essentially and

    directly the shape of self-consciousness, is the simple content of Absolute

    Religion. Here the Divine Being is known as Spirit; this religion is the Divine

    Being's consciousness concerning itself that it is Spirit... Spirit is known as self-

    consciousness, and to this self-consciousness it is directly revealed, for it is this

    self-consciousness itself. The divine nature is the same as the human, and it is

    this unity which is intuitively apprehended." - Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,

    the Phenomenology of Spirit, C.CC. Religion C. Revealed Religion, par. 754-759

  • The Incarnation of Christ reveals the identity of consciousness and the Absolute

    through the hypostatic union of divine and human nature in the person of Jesus Christ:

    "I and my Father are one." (Jn. 10:30) This revealed identity speculatively reconciles and

    mediates, for religious consciousness, between the dualities of reason; e.g. Ego and non-

    Ego, subject and object, sensible and supersensible, Man and God. Through the

    incarnation, Christianity affirms an indissoluble identity between the reason of man and

    the reason of God so that we may potentially come to know all things just as God

    knows himself. Jesus told his disciples: "If you had known me, you would have known

    my Father also: and from henceforth you know him, and have seen him." (Jn. 14:7); "For

    nothing is secret, that shall not be made manifest; neither anything hid, that shall not be

    known and come to light." (Lk. 8:17); and "you shall know the truth, and the truth shall

    make you free." (Jn. 8:32). Hegel writes, in the Introduction to the Lectures on the Philosophy

    of History, "In the Christian Religion God has revealed God - that is, God has given us to

    understand what God is; so that God is no longer a concealed or secret existence. And

    this possibility of knowing God, thus afforded us, renders such knowledge a duty..."

    The speculative centrality of Christianity in the essential development of reason and the

    history of world-spirit is this speculative identity of God and Man in Christ; of all

    thought and being in the "Absolute Middle" that unites absolutely opposed categories

    of the subjective Ego and the objective non-Ego; and makes a philosophical science of

    absolute knowledge possible.

    It is sometimes objected that Christianity cannot be the 'absolute religion' for this reason

    because the incarnation of God is not an element that is unique to Christianity:

    incarnations are also present, for example, in the ten Dashavatara, or avatars of Vishnu,

    such as Krishna in the Bhagavad Gita. While other religious traditions affirm that God

    has been incarnated, only Christianity describes the passion, death and resurrection of

    the God-man Jesus Christ. Hegel describes the 'death of God' in both Faith and

    Knowledge and the Phenomenology of Spirit from the standpoint of religious

    consciousness. Religious consciousness views God the Father and Christ the Son as

    indivisibly united in Jesus of Nazareth. The death of Jesus is thus viewed as the 'death

    of God' for both are united in the self-same appearance known through the logical

    sequence of these appearances. Hegel writes at the conclusion of section C.CC.III.

    Revealed Religion in the Phenomenology of Spirit:

  • "This [religious] self-consciousness does not therefore really die, as the particular

    person [of Jesus] is pictorially imagined to have really died; its particularity

    expires in its universality, i.e. in its knowledge, which is essential Being reconciling

    itself with itself. That immediately preceding element of figurative thinking is

    thus here affirmed as transcended, has, in other words, returned into the self,

    into its notion. What was in the former merely an (objective) existent has come to

    assume the form of Subject... When the death of the mediator is grasped by the

    self, this means the sublation of his factuality, of his particular independent

    existence: this particular self-existence has become universal self-consciousness....

    The death of this pictorial idea implies at the same time the death of the

    abstraction of Divine Being, which is not yet affirmed as a self. 'That death is the

    bitterness of feeling of the unhappy consciousness, when it feels that God

    Himself is dead. This harsh utterance is the expression of inmost

    self knowledge which has simply self for its content; it is the return of

    consciousness into the depth of darkness where Ego is nothing but bare identity

    with Ego, a darkness distinguishing and knowing nothing more outside it. This

    feeling thus means, in point of fact, the loss of the Substance and of its objective

    existence over against consciousness... This knowledge is thus spiritualization,

    whereby Substance becomes Subject, by which its abstraction and lifelessness

    have expired, and Substance therefore has become real, simple, and universal

    self-consciousness." (PhG 785)

    With the death of the God-man for religious consciousness, the concept of the universal

    essence of the "objective existence over against consciousness" (PhG 162) is lost and

    shattered even as "bare identity" of the Fichtean self-positing Ego continues in lonesome

    cognition. Hegel suggests that the 'death of God' phenomenologically reveals, for

    religious consciousness, the immediate self-certainty, self-subsistence and infinite

    freedom of the Ego in a way that had formerly been obscured by "the objective

    existence", "abstraction and lifelessness" of the non-Ego "over against consciousness."

    The positive result of the 'death of God' is the absolute dynamism and spiritualization

    of all thought. Thus the concept of the absolute Spinozist substance is baptized as the

    divine subject. Hegel first describes this in the preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit:

  • "The living substance is that being which is truly subject, or, what is the same

    thing, is truly realized and actual (wirklich) solely in the process of positing itself,

    or in mediating with its own self its transitions from one state or position to the

    opposite. As subject it is pure and simple negativity... True reality is merely this

    process of reinstating self-identity, of reflecting into its own self in and from its

    other, and is not an original and primal unity as such, not an immediate unity as

    such. It is the process of its own becoming, the circle which presupposes its end

    as its purpose, and has its end for its beginning; it becomes concrete and actual

    only by being carried out, and by the end it involves." (PhG 18)

    For religious consciousness, revealed Christian theology is revealed anthropology. The

    new conception of the God-man Jesus Christ constitutes a new Christian conception of

    man: human nature is affirmed to participate in divine reason and divine grace. The

    final end and highest good of human life is, no longer as with Aristotle magnanimity

    within a merely human political community (Zoon Politikon), but rather participation in

    the divine life of the Absolute being through the superabundant grace and beatitude of

    the Kingdom of Heaven. This echoes St. Paul of Tarsus's description, in the Epistle to

    the Romans, of our participation in the death and resurrection of Jesus Christ: just as

    Hegel affirms that Ego becomes certain of itself through the 'death of God', so St. Paul

    affirms that we die, are buried, and are resurrected with Jesus Christ, to establish a

    hitherto unknown relationship between man and God:

    "we are buried with him by baptism into death: that like as Christ was raised up

    from the dead by the glory of the Father, even so we also should walk in

    newness of life. For if we have been planted together in the likeness of his death,

    we shall be also in the likeness of his resurrection: Knowing this, that our old

    man is crucified with him, that the body of sin might be destroyed, that

    henceforth we should not serve sin. For he that is dead is freed from sin. Now if

    we be dead with Christ, we believe that we shall also live with him: Knowing

    that Christ being raised from the dead dieth no more; death hath no more

    dominion over him. For in that he died, he died unto sin once: but in that he

    liveth, he liveth unto God. Likewise reckon ye also yourselves to be dead indeed

    unto sin, but alive unto God through Jesus Christ our Lord." (Rom 6:4-11)

  • The 'death of God' in Hegel, like the death of Christ in St. Paul, signifies the self-

    negation of the Absolute. For the Christian religious consciousness, the self-negating

    loss of "objective existence" is just as much the death of our objective bodily existence as

    "we are crucified with [Christ]" so that we might "liveth unto God." Christianity is thus

    distinguished from other incarnational religions by, not merely the absolute

    reconciliation of opposite categories through the incarnation, but also by the absolute

    self-negation of objective being through the passion, death and resurrection of Jesus

    Christ. Hegel's 'speculative Good Friday' is the self-negation of all concepts in the

    Absolute idea:

    "Infinity is the pure nullification of the antithesis or of finitude; but it is at the

    same time also the spring of eternal movement, the spring of that finitude which

    is infinite, because it eternally nullifies itself. Out of this nothing and pure night

    of infinity, as out of the secret abyss that is its birthplace, the truth lifts itself

    upward... the pure concept or infinity as the abyss of nothingness in which all

    being is engulfed, must signify the infinite grief [of the finite] purely as a

    moment of the supreme Idea, and no more than a moment... Thereby it must re-

    establish for philosophy the Idea of absolute freedom and along with it the

    absolute Passion, the speculative Good Friday in place of the historic Good

    Friday. Good Friday must be speculatively re-established in the whole truth and

    harshness of its God-forsakenness... the highest totality can and must achieve its

    resurrection solely from this harsh consciousness of loss, encompassing

    everything, and ascending in all its earnestness and out of its deepest ground to

    the most serene freedom of its shape." (Faith and Knowledge, 1802)

    The "absolute freedom" of the "pure concept" results from the absolute self-negation

    signified of the 'death of God' in religious consciousness. The drama of the Christian

    religion and the history of reason are united in the "absolute passion" of the 'speculative

    Good Friday', through which the totality of concepts are altogether negated in "infinite

    grief" and posited anew - resurrected from Hell and "ascending in all earnestness and

    out of its deepest ground" - of the Absolute Idea.

    Hegel's trinitarian theology confers the crown of absoluteness upon the Christian

    religion. Hegel describes at the conclusion of the Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences

  • (575 - 577), how the dialectical moments may be read in three different sequences, with

    three different subjects, and from three different beginnings: (i) Logic - Nature - Spirit;

    (ii) Nature - Spirit - Logic; and (iii) Spirit - Logic - Nature. The divine persons of the

    Holy Trinity within the triune God are mutually and recursively related, just as the

    conceptual moments of God are mutually and recursively related: Logic corresponds to

    God the Father, Nature to God the Son, and Spirit to the Holy Spirit. The major

    divisions and subdivisions of Hegel's work must correspond to the persons of the Holy

    Trinity because Hegel's dialectical logic is essentially trinitarian, and Hegel's conception

    of the Holy Trinity is essentially logical: the simplest seminal first moment (i.e. thesis) is

    the Father, the second self-alienated opposed moment (i.e. antithesis) is the Son, and the

    third reconciling dynamic moment (i.e. synthesis) is the Holy Spirit. The mystery of the

    Holy Trinity is an absolute self-contradiction: 'God is one' and 'God is three'. Hegel

    absolutizes contradiction in his Logic by affirming that the Holy Trinity is the absolute

    contradiction of three divine persons in one God and the eternal universal and living

    essence of all logic, consistency and contrareity: the contrariness of the Trinity is also

    Hegel's dialectical principle of identity in difference, through which he holds contrary

    opposite concepts to be resolved into the self-identical unity of a master concept [i.e. (A

    = A)&(A A)]. Subsumption (Aufhebung) is this process of resolution, which is

    simultaneous supercession, negation and preservation of differing and opposed

    concepts within a fuller and richer conceptual unity. The triadic relations of the

    concepts that pervade and dynamize the philosophy of Hegel instantiate these

    trinitarian logical relations. The conceptual moments of God may relate to one another,

    as that which is sublated and that which sublates, in as many ways as there are relations

    between the divine persons of the Holy Trinity. Thus, Hegel's Christian trinitarian

    conception of logic and contrareity informed his philosophical contributions to post-

    Kantian idealism. Hegel's elliptical axiom "Alles was vernnftig ist ist wirklich, und

    alles was wirklich ist ist vernnftig" ("All that is rational is real, and all that is real is

    rational"), can just as well be logicized as the axiom 'All logic is theological, and all

    theology is logical.' The revelation, intelligibility, and divination of universal reason in

    Christ the Logos was long ago acknowledged by Christian Neo-Platonists such as

    Clement and Origin of Alexandrian. The Thirteenth Century Dominican mystic Meister

    Ekhart describes this in the sermon on the Self Communication of God:

    "The Father is a revelation of the Godhead, the Son is an image and countenance

  • of the Father, and the Holy Ghost is an effulgence of that countenance, and a

    mutual love between Them, and these properties They have always possessed in

    Themselves."

    Dynamic movement is the result of the negative activity of potentiality in actuality, or

    of some recurring absence within the fullness of substance. Thus negation begets

    dynamic movement within a self-moving substance. For Hegel and Schelling, the

    substances of concepts are dynamic when self-negated by contrary opposite concepts:

    "The Concept is what is alive, is what mediates itself with itself. One of its

    determinations is also Being... This is the Concept as such, the Concept of God, the

    Absolute Concept; this is just what God is. As Spirit or as Love, God is this Self-

    particularizing." (G.W.F. Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion p. 436)

    Christianity is the most dynamic concept of religion because, for religious

    consciousness, the 'death of God' is the total negation the concept of the objectified

    Absolute. St. Paul writes: "Christ Jesus, who being in the form of God... emptied

    himself, taking the form of a servant, being made in the likeness of men... humbled

    himself, becoming obedient unto death, even to the death of the cross." (Phil. 2:5-8) The

    absolute self-negation of Christianity in the 'death of God' is also the most extreme self-

    alienation and opposition of concepts in the sacred history of God's children Israel. The

    dark night of the soul of Good Friday, in which Christ calls out "'Eli, Eli, lama

    sabachthani?' that is 'My God, my God, why hast thou forsaken me?'" (Mt. 27:46),

    historically recalls the grief of the 22nd Psalm over the ostensible abandonment of God's

    covenant with Israel during the sack of Jerusalem and the Babylonian Captivity; but

    also speculatively anticipates the apocalyptic opposition of all concepts, in the moment

    of our most heart-rending despair, when the essential coherency and self-identity of

    absolutely everything seems lost: when "things fall apart; the centre cannot hold/ mere

    anarchy is loosed upon the world" (William Butler Yeats, the Second Coming).

    The dynamism of Christianity propels Christian religious consciousness into an

    expectation of future reconciliation - the Second Coming of Christ - in which the

    covenantal promise of sacred history is expected to be fully realized. The absolute

    antithesis of the crucifixion demands an absolute resolution and finale. Any opposed

    pair of contrary concepts logically demands some third concept to mediate and

    reconcile each into a coherent self-identity. As (C.CC.) Religion completes (C.) Reason

    for-consciousness in the Phenomenology of Spirit, so does the teleological end of religion

  • superordain and determine the end of the (C.BB.) Spirit of history. The hopes of the City

    of Man are informed by the City of God, and the absolute expectations of Christian

    sacred history inform the expectations of secular philosophies of history, or theories of

    historicism. The future horizon of sacred history is the theological origin, in revealed

    religion, of all subsequent progressivist historicism. The ancient pagan Greeks and

    Roman acknowledged no absolute progress in history. The epics of Homer and the

    theogony of Hesiod depict a lengthy historical regress from the resplendent reign of the

    immortal gods to the pygmy age of mortal men. Likewise did the Jews count

    themselves to be lesser men than their fathers, Abraham, Isaac and Jacob. Christian's

    affirmed history to be progressive because Christians trust in the promised atonement

    of their savior, Jesus Christ, by whose death and resurrection God is believed to have

    conquered sin and death, and restored the pilgrim Church in the progress of faith

    towards the highest good of eternal beatitude: this hope for the restoration of the world

    in the eternal goodness of God is signified in the Lord's Prayer: "Thy kingdom come/

    thy will be done/ on Earth as it is in Heaven." In the Lectures on the Philosophy of History

    Hegel described the logical and theological origin of this eschatological orientation that

    is common to all progressivist historicism:

    "The truth, then, that a Providence of God presides over the events of the World -

    consorts with the proposition in question; for Divine Providence is Wisdom,

    endowed with an infinite Power which realizes its aim in the absolute rational-

    design of the World... the world is not abandoned to chance and external

    contingent causes, but that a Providence controls it... The insight to which

    Philosophy is to lead us is that the real world is at it ought to be; that the truly

    Good - the Universal Divine Reason - is not a mere abstraction, but a vital

    principle capable of realizing itself. This Good, this Reason, in its most concrete

    form, is God... The World Spirit corresponds to the Divine Spirit, which is the

    Absolute Spirit."

    History is providential simply because God is universal reason, all that is real is rational

    ("alles was wirklich ist ist vernnftig"), and reality is obedient to God. Hegel's

    progressivist historicism is the direct consequence of his trinitarian dialectical logic, in

    which thesis begets its opposite and opposites are reconciled into a richer unity, and the

    Absolute is placed at the end as the product rather than the axiom of philosophy. The

    Lectures on the Philosophy of History should be read as an illustration of historicism

  • determined by the eternal forms of reason described in the Science of Logic. As Karl

    Rahner would later elaborate, this picture of the self-development of Spirit in history is

    essentially the dynamic efflorescence of God's grace, a "universal pnuematology", and a

    "salvation history" (Geist in Welt,1939, and Hrer des Wortes, 1944). In the drama of

    sacred history, the proto-evangelium of the Old Testament is the first act, the Gospels of

    the New Testament are the second act, and the Acts of the Apostles begin the third and

    final act, which is prophesied to be completed by the Apocalypse of St. John. The order

    of the Mass re-presents this trinitarian drama of sacred history as well in the three parts;

    the Service of Prayer, Service of Instruction, and the Eucharistic Sacrifice; in which the

    priest assumes the sacramental role as the person of Christ to reenact the sacrifice of the

    Last Supper, the Passion and the Resurrection. The celebration of the Mass can thus be

    understood as a ritual re-presentation of the Hegelian themes of progressivist

    historicism, reason in history, and our eternal and eschatological salvation through our

    liturgical and sacramental participation in the self-giving Logos of Jesus Christ.

    Interpretations of Hegel vary widely, not merely because of the gothic-intricacy of

    Hegel's prose, but more especially because readers of Hegel's texts ineluctably interpret

    his speculative glosses as re-affirming their own preconceptions. One of literary master-

    strokes of Hegel was, like Plato, to favorably present opposed theses while neighter

    affirming nor denying any definite conclusions. By this artifice, Hegel retained for

    himself a veil of vagaries that elicited from his students a perpetual self-reciprocating

    dialectic of opposed questions and answers. Consequently, an interpretation of Hegel

    which purports to show that God is can with no less plausibility be opposed by an

    interpretation that God is not; just as the interpretation that the philosophy of Hegel is

    Christian can be opposed by the interpretation that Hegel is not a Christian, but

    perhaps a crypto-Feuerbachian. The opposed interpretations of the philosophy of

    Hegel; which were first publicly manifested in the conflict between the so-called old

    'Right Hegelians' and the young 'Left Hegelians'; has continued to this day in Christian

    transcendentist and Marxian immanentist interpretations. It is plausible that my own

    Christian and 'Right Hegelian' interpretation of Hegel has been pervasively conditioned

    by the preconceived categories of Christian religious consciousness, just as the

    interpretations of those who may disagree have been conditioned by some rejection of

    religious consciousness. The formal relation of the concepts in Hegel's system may

    frame, but not resolve, the dispute over the importance of the content of religion. The

  • key misunderstanding is then to simply entirely reject the importance of religion in

    philosophy. As philosophy, like religion, purports to describe the truth, a true reading

    of true philosophy may only be judged according to the self-legislated norms of reason

    itself. In this way, confessional conflicts of religious faith are reintroduced into

    philosophical hermeneutics. The genuine question of whether the philosophy of Hegel

    is essentially Christian must therefore remain disputed so long there remain doubts

    about Christianity.

    Q: What do you make of philosophers like Zizek trying to deal with Christianity of

    Hegel without just dismissing it as incidental while also trying to reconcile it with the

    materialism of Marx?

    A: The most Hegelian approach to the procession of ideas in history is the synthesis of

    all differentia and opposites within the Absolute Idea. There is, for this reason, nothing

    contrary to the spirit of Hegel in working to speculatively reconcile ostensibly opposed

    concepts such as Christianity with Marxism, or religion with historical materialism: this

    speculative enterprise can, perhaps, be understood more generally as the synthesis of

    transcendent supersensible forms revealed in religious consciousness with the natural

    operations of the material world observe through sensation; as a return to the Platonic

    project of reconciling the purely actual Being of Parmenides with the ever-changing

    conflux of Heraclitus; or as the return to the Kantian project of reconciling the

    immutable windowless monads of Leibniz with the extended and self-developing

    substance of Spinoza. In every case, speculative philosophy endeavors to unify the

    dualistic opposition of pure thought and intuition in an absolute concept that envelops

    and subsumes the true concepts of all reality. The project of reconciling Christian

    transcendence with socialist justice has in the past been undertaken from the standpoint

    of Christian theology; for example in the Franciscan Fraticelli, the Christian Socialism of

    Dorothy Day, and the Liberation Theology of Gustavo Gutirrez; and from the

    standpoint of Marxist theory; as in the writings of Ernst Bloch who wrote in The

    Principle of Hope "Where Lenin is, there is Jerusalem" and "the Bolshevist fulfillment of

    Communism is part of the age-old fight for God."

  • For either Christian theology or Marxist theory to be fully explanatory of the world, it

    would seem that each must offer some account of the pervasive appeal of the other:

    Christian theology must account for the Socialist contests against the social iniquities of

    modern capitalist economies, just as Marxist theory must account for the spiritual

    conditions of Christian religious consciousness: Marxists must explain the persisting

    desire for self-transcending faith and devotion, for which "religion is the sigh of the

    oppressed creature, the heart of a heartless world, and the soul of soulless conditions",

    just as Christians must explain how they are to bring justice to the present material

    conditions of society, for which they are commanded to "love thy neighbor as thyself."

    Hegel is the key to open each concept for the other. Hegel is not only a seminal thinker

    for Marxist theory, but also a great modern Christian theologian. In Hegelian terms,

    both Christian theology and Marxist theory must endeavor to speculatively sublate,

    negate, and preserve the other, so as to unlock, open, and take possession of all of the

    riches of Pharaoh from the land of Egypt.

    Although I have some suspicions about Prof. iek's interpretations of Hegel, it would

    be irresponsible for me to comment on an author's whose publications I am largely

    ignorant of. Some interpreters of Hegel are tempted by their preconceptions to deny

    Hegel's exuberant Christian confessions as little more than pious nods to the

    Restoration-era faith of the Kingdom of Prussia. For example, Prof. Robert Solomon

    interprets Hegel as "essentially an atheist" (In the Spirit of Hegel, 1983, p.582). Such

    esoteric interpretations, which maintain that Hegel was a writer who deliberately

    deceived his readers regarding his Christian faith, are (while not indubitably false)

    demanding of a much more conniving interpretation of Hegel than his fiercely

    independent and outspoken tone would seem to suggest. In his book review, Prof.

    Michael Rosen called Prof. Solomon's interpretation "extremely disappointing" and

    "bizarre" (The Philosophical Review, pp.115-117, 1986). Thus, leaving aside these

    interpretations, there appear to be three major ways in which Marxist theoreticians may

    seek to "deal with the Christianity of Hegel" by de-Christianizing the philosophy of

    Hegel to be more amenable to an ostensibly irreligious Marxist theory: by re-conceiving

    of (i) the formal relations of the system, (ii) the metaphysics, and (iii) the sociology of

    Hegel.

    (i) Christian interpreters of Hegel have earnestly and decisively emphasized the

    systematic place and function of the concept of Christian revealed religion in the system

  • of Hegel (e.g. James Sterling, Emil Fakenheim, William Wallace etc.). Christianity is not

    only acclaimed as the 'absolute religion' which subsumes all prior religions in religious

    consciousness, but furthermore as the concept that superordinately determines the

    essence of the subordinate concepts: in the Phenomenology of Spirit, for instance, the

    concept of (C.CC.III) Christian revealed religion is the apex of the concept of (C.CC)

    Religion which subordinates and subsumes, in (C) Reason, the concepts of (C.AA) Free

    Concrete Mind and (C.BB) Spirit; which in turn subsumes (A) Consciousness and (B)

    Self-Consciousness. Thus, the crowning concept of Christian subsumes all other

    concepts within itself. Although Christianity is enthroned at the zenith of the system of

    the Phenomenology of Spirit, it is not itself (C.DD) Absolute Knowing but merely the

    handmaid of the philosophical-theology of Absolute Idealism. The Phenomenology of

    Spirit is merely a prolegomena, for historically alienated consciousness, of the system of

    philosophy which Hegel begins in the Science of Logic and outlines in the Encyclopedia of

    Philosophical Sciences.

    As the Phenomenology of Spirit stands in the relation of the Absolute to consciousness as a

    mediating prelude to Hegel's mature philosophical science, it may be mystically

    envisaged to assume the filial role of Christ the Son in relation to the seminal role of

    God the Father in the Science of Logic, and the dynamic efflorescence of the Holy Spirit in

    the Berlin Lectures on the History of Philosophy and the Philosophy of History.

    Consequently, the sovereign concept of (C.CC.III) Christian Revealed Religion in the

    Phenomenology of Spirit must be understood, like Jesus Christ, to be the mediating

    concept between human consciousness and the Absolute Idea of God, just as (3.3.2)

    Religion appears again in the Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences as the mediating

    concept between (3.3.1) Art and (3.3.3) Philosophy (e.g. S-M-P or Father-Son-Holy

    Spirit). Religion mediates between art and philosophy in the Absolute Idea because

    Hegel, with Aristotle, Aquinas, and Kant, held all formal concepts to require the content

    of intuition: the universal philosophical concept is constructed from the content of

    aesthetic intuition related to the absolute truth of religion and yet formally purified of

    the content any particular intuition. The majestic tradition of Christian art, from the

    earliest hymns to the cantatas of Mozart, is for Hegel the spiritual flowering of the

    concerted imaginations of the children of God to manifest the Absolute Idea through

    the variegated forms aesthetic intuition. In the oldest systematic fragment on German

    Idealism describes the centrality of art to philosophy:

  • "the idea which unites all, the idea of beauty, the word taken in the higher

    platonic sense. I am convinced that the highest act of reason, which, in that it

    comprises all ideas, is an aesthetic act, and that truth and goodness are united

    like sisters only in beauty - the philosopher must possess just as much aesthetic

    power as the poet. The people without aesthetic sense are our philosophers of the

    letter. The philosophy of the spirit is an aesthetic philosophy. One cannot be

    clever in anything, one cannot even reason cleverly in history - without aesthetic

    sense."

    Interpreters who wish to de-Christianize Hegelian philosophy may allege that the

    subordinate and mediating role of religion in the system of Hegel means that the

    Christian religion is suppressed by the superior concept of (C.DD) Absolute Knowing

    and (3.3.3) Philosophy: just as the universal concept purifies philosophy of the

    particular content of intuition, so does it seem to exorcise philosophical reason of

    religion. However, this interpretation confuses the Hegelian principle of subsumption

    (Aufhebung), which preserves the subordinate concepts, with bad skepticism, which

    suppresses and rejects the subordinate concepts. Hegel describes the difference between

    subsumption and skepticism in the Introduction to the Phenomenology of Spirit:

    "For this view is skepticism, which always sees in the result only pure

    nothingness, and abstracts from the fact that this nothing is determinate, is the

    nothing of that out of which it comes as a result... The skepticism which ends

    with the abstraction nothing or emptiness can advance from this not a step

    farther, but must wait and see whether there is possibly anything new offered,

    and what that is in order to cast it into the same abysmal void. When once, on

    the other hand, the result is apprehended, as it truly is, as determinate negation,

    a new form has thereby immediately arisen; and in the negation the transition is

    made by which the progress through the complete succession of forms comes

    about of itself." (PhG 79)

    Lest we fall into the most abysmal skepticism which cannot advance a step further,

    thinking must incorporate the determinate negations of all concepts to "progress

    through the complete succession of forms": rather than being cast into the void, the

  • Christian religion is denied merely as absolute knowledge just as it is preserved as a

    concept that is essential to this knowledge, viz. the negation of negation or the

    determinate negation (determinatio est negatio): the concept of Christianity is negated as

    containing the fullness of purely conceptual truth even while it is affirmed, viz. this

    negation, to be altogether necessary for the emergence of philosophical truth. In the

    (3.3) Absolute Idea of the Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences, (3.3.2) Religion objectifies

    the varied aesthetic imaginings into a sacred drama of the self-revelation of the

    Absolute to consciousness.

    The Christian religion is essential as the most synthetic and dynamic form of religion

    which, through divine revelation, uniquely allows consciousness to imagine and know

    philosophical science. If religious consciousness were, on the contrary, consigned to the

    abysmal void of unthought, then there could be no warranted claim to scientific

    knowledge. This problem of the doxastic foundations of science in religious belief

    continues to resurface in anti-realist and anti-foundationalist critiques of natural science

    and scientific naturalism, such as Paul Feyerabend's Against Method (1975), Alvin

    Plantinga's evolutionary argument against naturalism (1993), and Thomas Nagel's

    recent book Mind and Cosmos (2012). The necessity of the mediating concept of Religion

    in the philosophy of Hegel thus inverts the common understanding of the relation of

    faith and reason: faith is not the ghostly shadow of reason the necessary precondition of

    reason itself. So Hegel may affirm, with St. Anselm, that we must have faith seeking

    understanding (Credo ut Intellegam), and with the proverbs that the "fear of the Lord is

    the beginning of wisdom, and the knowledge of the holy is understanding." (Pr. 9:10)

    (ii) Hegel's fundamental metaphysical commitments can perhaps be radically

    reconceived as materialist and anthropocentric rather than absolute idealist and

    theocentric. This approach was first pursued by the disenfranchised students of

    Hegelian philosophy who wished to weaponize the Hegelian dialectic against the

    alliance of altar and throne in the Kingdom of Prussia and the Holy Alliance (c.1815-

    1848).These radical critics of the established order of the world were called by David

    Strauss the 'Young Hegelians', in contrast to the doctrinaire former students of Hegel, or

    the 'Old Hegelians'. They counted among themselves such future luminaries as Ludwig

    Andreas Feuerbach, Max Stirner, Bruno Bauer, Friederich Engels and Karl Marx.

    Feuerbach interpreted Hegel's Absolute Idea to be no more Platonic and real than an

  • idea in the human mind. The idea of God and the Absolute should, on this account,

    become the absolute knowledge and power of mankind. Marx and Engels followed

    Feuerbach in juxtaposing critical, realist, and empirical dialectical materialism to

    Hegel's purportedly spiritualist, speculative and phantasmagoric absolute idealism. In

    each case, the Young Hegelians sought to unravel the unity of the systemic tapestry of

    the philosophy of Hegel, and then to re-conceive its formal relations and basic

    constituents in a way more suitable to the achievement of their social and political

    ambitions. Yet, as their aims differed as wildly as their re-conceptions, the Young

    Hegelians could produce no consistent school or system of philosophy. Each and all

    stand in relation to the speculative empire of Hegel as, what Marx once memorably

    described as, the successor generals (diadochi) of the spirit tearing and rending the

    corpse of their world-conquering great-king Alexander.

    Feuerbach denied the subjectivity of the Absolute to be anything other than the

    subjectivity of man, and consequently re-centered the Absolute Idea into the mind of

    man rather than the mind of God. Feuerbach's anthropocentrism rejected the

    Schellingian identity between the knowledge of the finite human Ego and the absolute

    divine Ego, the Berkeleyan subsistence of the universe in the perception of God, and the

    whole Platonic inheritance of preternatural transcendent forms. The consequence was

    not only the rejection of the priority of the pure forms of logic to the extended matter of

    nature but the implicit denial of the very possibility of a science of true philosophy:

    absolute knowledge requires an absolute knower as the subject which knows the object

    of truth, just as the truth of the particulars is the universal in which they are altogether

    united. The rejection of God, Platonic universals, and Logic from the metaphysics of

    Hegel, viz. the anthropocentric reduction, consequently makes true, universal and

    scientific knowledge impossible. The Absolute is the truth. To deny that there is truth is

    just as much to deny that this denial of truth is itself true, which is to affirm, viz. the

    Law of Excluded Middle, that this denial is false. Thus any denial of the truth self-

    contradictory. This is the problem of any anthropocentric reduction of absolute truth

    that relativizes truth to the human mind. Therefore, according to classical logic,

    Feuerbach cannot affirm an anthropocentrism or naturalism that excludes the Absolute,

    universals, and logic, without also contradicting himself.

    Marx and Engels re-conceived of Hegel's Absolute as the immanent dynamic self-

    development of nature which they called dialectical materialism, in opposition to the

  • transcendent spiritualist idealism which they attributed to Hegel. This materalists-

    idealist juxtaposition reiterates Aristotle's abstract opposition of form and matter in

    concrete substance, Spinoza's two attributes of thought and extension in divine nature

    (Deus sive Natura), Kant's division of concepts and intuition in the apperceptive unity of

    thought, and Schelling's realism and idealism in the self-identity of the Absolute; for in

    each case the materialist-idealist juxtaposition seeks to subordinate form to matter, the

    thought to extension, the concept to the intuition, and the ideal to the real, so as to

    affirm, against the purportedly mystical spiritualism of Hegel, that dialectical

    materialism stands upright on the firm metaphysical ground matter. The motivation is

    to ground an ontologically and epistemological foundation in sensible material reality.

    Kantian criticism quickly exposes the untenability of this one-sided opposition of

    foundational matter to epiphenomenal form. What is the essence of matter? How is the

    essence of matter deduced without dogmatic presuppositions? Where is matter to be

    sensibly intuited? How is matter without form dialectical? Can the ground of

    materialism be turtles all the way down? These embarrassing questions soon reveal that

    dialectical materialism simply subordinates one side of each conceptual dichotomy to

    the other, to suppress and banish the turtle from the shell, and affirm nature as the

    armored panoply of certain knowledge. Not only does the promised foundation of

    material nature prove to be no foundation at all, but materialism poisons philosophy

    with its essential finitude, closure, and finality. The essence of matter is simply the self-

    limited and self-subsisting atomic particles of Democritus. No whole can arise from the

    agglomeration of many merely self-related parts. Neither can any set of formal relations

    join together totally self-enclosed particles. The consequence of materialism is, then,

    either a tower of material bricks which reaches to the heavens but crumbles like the

    Tower of Babel under the weight of its own antinomies, or a spiritualized matter that is

    indistinguishable from Fichte's intellective being within Schelling's identity-philosophy.

    Fichte's ideal being for-consciousness that is identical to the reality of the Absolute in-

    itself is simply the phenomenological movement of what Hegel calls Spirit: where

    materialism affirms a pre-critical mechanistic relation of static material particles, the

    Hegelian spirit of properly critical dialectical materialism affirms a dynamic self-

    particularizing totality of all thought and being in Logic, Nature and Spirit. With the

    rejection of the mechanistic materialism, viz. the disjunctive inference, Hegelian Spirit is

    must be affirmed as the very substance becoming subject of the Absolute.

  • (iii) The (i) systematic and the (ii) metaphysical re-conceptions of the philosophy of

    Hegel are together united in the (iii) interpretation of Hegelianism as sociology. In this

    way, the negative re-conceptions of Hegel constitute a sort of negative dialectical triad,

    in which the dialectical reconciliation of opposites produces a more false and discordant

    rather than a more true and harmonious concept, in a way reminiscent of the negative

    dialectic of modern philosophy of subjectivity in Glauben und Wissen (Faith and

    Knowledge, 1802). The sociological re-conception affirms that the philosophy of Hegel

    can only be interpreted as the historical development of the self-understanding of

    society, and denies that any 'metaphysical', idealist, or platonizing interpretation is

    possible. Prof. Terry Pinkard summarizes this interpretative approach in the Successor to

    Metaphysics: Absolute Idea and Absolute Spirit (Monist, July 1991, Vol. 74, Issue 3). Prof.

    Pinkard conflates Kant's term 'metaphysics' with the term 'dogmatism' and

    simplistically presumes that all metaphysical reasoning is dogmatic and rejected by

    post-Kantian idealists. Thus, Pinkard's non-metaphysical interpretation simply purports

    to be critical philosophy without dogmatic assumptions about the reality or structure of

    being. The conflation of metaphysics with dogmatism leads Pinkard to reject all of the

    reality of all supra-physical and supersensible entities of theology and logic as the relics

    of a pre-critical metaphysics of substance. This is the occamist razor which shaves Logic

    from Pinkard's sociology of Spirit.

    With Feuerbach, Pinkard interprets the philosophy of Hegel from the anthropocentric

    perspective of a historical human community, and rejects the pure Platonic forms of

    preternatural and pre-human logic which are posited by God's seminal reason (rationes

    seminales, or logoi spermatikoi) rather than man. With Marx and Engels, Pinkard must

    assume a naturalistic cosmology reminiscent of dialectical materialism. This becomes

    even clearer when the presuppositions of sociology are investigated: sociology is the

    logic of human society, which is inter-subjectively constituted by social human actors,

    who are each themselves either the formal apperceptive unity of transcendental self-

    consciousness or the empirical composite of material nature; sociology thus

    methodologically assumes Kantian empiricism; rejects the self-subsistence of the

    transcendental self-conscious and affirms only empirical and material composition;

    therefore, sociology reduces to materialism which reduces to absurdity. In this way, the

    (iii) sociological interpretation inherits the errors of the (i) systematic and the (ii)

    metaphysical re-conceptions of the philosophy of Hegel: the sociological interpretation

  • dogmatically assumes that (i) society may subsist by itself or through the activity of

    social actors without any further mediation of society, and (ii) assumes the self-

    subsistence of society and persons to be supported by the real ground of material

    nature. However, the (i) unmediated self-subsistent society is merely assumed as a

    concept of (3) Spirit that floats alone as a postulate of thought wholly indifferent to any

    mediating conceptual relation to the (1) Logic and (2) Nature, which are the very

    necessary conditions of its conceptual possibility. Philosophy is for Hegel an absolute

    and all-encompassing science which cannot tolerate dogmatic postulates of wholly

    unmediated concepts, any more than the human body can tolerate gangrene infection.

    The (ii) materialist self-subsistence of society thus equally succumbs to materialist

    poison of finitude, closure, and finality, which threatens to collapse upon itself as soon

    as it is erected. The whole edifice is either unsupported and simply postulated, or

    closed in upon itself like a windowless castle of so many finite material bricks.

    In suppressing the pure forms of theology and logic, these interpretations (i, ii & iii)

    construct a locked and irreformable system. All of the concepts of nature and society are

    enclosed in finite vessels from which none can interact and none can escape. The castle

    that was intended to reach to the heavens becomes a god-forsaken dungeon in which,

    with the messianic yearning of the Jews in exile, mankind ceaselessly awaits an

    unforeseeable eschatological emancipation. No freedom of the spirit is possible for such

    an interpretation of the philosophy of Hegel according to the letter of the fixed

    proposition, in which propositions are understood simply by-themselves as the

    predicate of a subject and are (i) not mediated within and through the self-

    particularizing Absolute; (ii) exclude or suppress the pure forms of Logic; and assume

    an (i) unmediated and (ii) materially subsisting (iii) merely postulated society. Every

    de-Christianizing interpretation, that intends to unravel the system of Hegel, either

    returns safely to the harbor of the speculative Absolute Idea or crashes upon the rocks

    of its own dogmatic presuppositions. The stumbling-block for all of these impious

    interpretations is what Slavoj iek has called the monstrosity of Christ: it is putatively

    absurd to believe that God became man in the person of Jesus of Nazareth; was

    crucified; died; and was resurrected. Thus Tertulian confessed "Credo quia absurdum"

    ("I believe because it is absurd"). Christianity seems to be the most absurd religion of all

    because it absolutely negates itself through the self-negation of the Absolute. However

    this absolute self-negation is, in the philosophy of Hegel, the very unsurpassed

  • dynamism and spiritual vitality of Christianity. There could be no greater self-negation,

    and no greater dynamism, than the visible self-annihilation of the God-man in the

    'death of God' for "greater love has no man than this, that a man lay down his life for his

    friends." (Jn. 15:13)

    Selected Bibliography of Works on Hegel's Christian Philosophy:

    Altizer, T.J.J. (1991) Hegel and the Christian God, Journal of the American Academy of Religion 59(1)

    Altizer, T.J. J. (1993) The Genesis of God: A Theological Genealogy, ch. 2

    Butler, C. (1977) G.W.F. Hegel

    Butler, C. (1985) Hermeneutic Hegelianism, Idealistic Studies 15

    Calton, P.M. (2001) Hegels Metaphysics of God: The Ontological Proof as the Development of a Trinitarian Divine Ontology

    Christensen, D.E. (ed.) (1970) Hegel and the Philosophy of Religion

    Desmond W. (2003) Hegels God: A Counterfeit Double?

    Dickey, L. (1993) Hegel on religion and philosophy, in F.C. Beiser (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hegel

    Fackenheim, E.L. (1967) The Religious Dimension in Hegels Thought

    Flay, J. (1981) Religion and the absolute standpoint Thought 56, pp. 316-327

    Hallman, J. (1991) The Descent of God: Divine Suffering in History and Theology, last chapter

    Hodgson, P.C. (2005) Hegel and Christian Theology: A Reading of the Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion

    Hodgson, P.C. (2005) Hegel and Christian Theology: A Reading of the Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion

    Hodgson, P.C. (2005-06) Hegel: theologian of freedom, The Owl of Minerva 37(1)

    Houlgate, S. (1991) Freedom, Truth and History, ch. 5

    Houlgate, S. (1993) A reply to Joseph C. Flays Hegels metaphysics, The Owl of Minerva 24(2)

    Houlgate, S. (1994) Hegel and Fichte: recognition, otherness and absolute knowing, The Owl of Minerva 26(1)

  • Houlgate, S. (2005) An Introduction to Hegel: Freedom, Truth and History (2nd ed. of his Freedom, Truth and History, 1991), ch. 2 Thinking without presuppositionsHoulgate, S. (1991) Thought and being in Kant and Hegel, The Owl of Minerva 22(2)

    Hyppolite, J. [1946] Genesis and Structure of Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit, part 6 ch. 3

    Jaeschke, W. (1991) The history of religion and absolute religion, in J. Walker (ed.) Thought and Faith in the Philosophy of Hegel

    Jaeschke, W. (1992) Philosophical theology and the philosophy of religion in D. Kolb (ed.) New Perspectives on Hegels Philosophy of Religion

    Jaeschke, W. [1986] Reason in Religion: The Foundations of Hegels Philosophy of Religion

    Jamros, D.P. (1990) The appearing God in Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit, Clio 19

    Jamros, D.P. (1994) The Human Shape of God: Religion in Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit

    Jamros, D.P. (1995) Hegel on the incarnation: unique or universal? Theological Studies

    Kojve, A. (1970) Hegel, Marx and Christianity, Interpretation

    Kolb, D. (ed.) (1992) New Perspectives on Hegels Philosophy of Religion

    Kng, H. [1970] The Incarnation of God: An Introduction to Hegels Theological Thought as a Prolegomena to a Future Christology, tr. 1987

    Lauer, Q. (1970) Hegel on the identity of content in religion and philosophy in D.E. Christensen (ed.) Hegel and the Philosophy of Religion

    Lauer, Q. (1982) Hegels Concept of God, esp. introduction and ch.

    McCarthy, V.A. (1986) Quest for a Philosophical Jesus: Christianity and Philosophy in Rousseau, Kant, Hegel, and Schelling, ch. 3 Hegel and the Jesus of consummate religion

    McGrath, A.E. (1994) The Making of Modern German Christology, 1750-1990

    McTaggart, J.M.E. (1901) Studies in Hegelian Cosmology, ch. 7

    Merklinger, P.M. (1993) Philosophy, Theology and Hegels Berlin Philosophy of Religion 1821-1827

    Olson, A. (1992) Hegel and the Spirit: Philosophy as Pneumatology

    ORegan, C. (1994) The Heterodox Hegel

    ORegan, C. (1994) The Heterodox Hegel

    ORegan, C. (2006-06) Philosophy of religion in the context of Hegels philosophy, The Owl of Minerva 37(1)

    Pinkard, T. (1994) Hegels Phenomenology, ch. 6 sec. 1

    Plant, R. (1997) Hegel: On Religion and Philosophy, The Great Philosophers, esp. pp. 30-49

    Reardon, B.M. (1977) Hegels Philosophy of Religion

  • Rocker, S. (1995) Hegels Rational Religion: The Validity of Hegels Argument for the Identity in Content of Absolute Religion and Absolute Philosophy

    Rocker, S. (1995) Hegels Rational Religion: The Validity of Hegels Argument for the Identity in Content of Absolute Religion and Absolute Philosophy

    Schickler, J. (2005) Metaphysics as Christology: An Odyssey of the Self from Kant and Hegel to Steiner

    Schlitt, D.M. (1984) Hegels Trinitarian Claim: A Critical Reflection

    Shanks, A. (1991) Hegels Political Theology

    Solomon, R. (1983) In the Spirit of Hegel, ch. 10

    Taylor (1975) ch. 3 secs. 2,3,5 (reprinted as Taylors Hegel and Modern Society, ch. 1 secs. 2,3,5 ), esp. pp. 87-90, and ch. 18 secs. 1-2

    Taylor, C. (1975) Hegel, ch. 7

    Taylor, C. (1975) Hegel, ch. 18

    Walker, J. (ed.) (1991) Thought and Faith in the Philosophy of Hegel

    Westphal, M. (1979) History and Truth in Hegels Phenomenology, ch. 7

    Whittemore, R.C. (1960) Hegel as panentheist, Tulane Studies in Philosophy 9

    Williamson, R.K. (1984) Introduction to Hegels Philosophy of Religion

    Yerkes, J. (1978) The Christology of Hegel

    Yerkes, J. (1978) The Christology of Hegel