aristóteles. frags. gigon, o. (ed., berlín - n. y., 1987) - gottschalk, h. b. (1991)
Embed Size (px)
TRANSCRIPT
-
8/10/2019 Aristteles. Frags. Gigon, O. (Ed., Berln - N. Y., 1987) - GOTTSCHALK, H. B. (1991)
1/5
The Fragments of Aristotle
Aristotelis Opera III: Librorum Deperditorum Fragmenta by Olof GigonReview by: H. B. GottschalkThe Classical Review, New Series, Vol. 41, No. 1 (1991), pp. 31-34Published by: Cambridge University Presson behalf of The Classical AssociationStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/712566.
Accessed: 02/09/2014 05:07
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
.
Cambridge University Pressand The Classical Associationare collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve
and extend access to The Classical Review.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 212.128.182.231 on Tue, 2 Sep 2014 05:07:23 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cuphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=classicalhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/712566?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/712566?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=classicalhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup -
8/10/2019 Aristteles. Frags. Gigon, O. (Ed., Berln - N. Y., 1987) - GOTTSCHALK, H. B. (1991)
2/5
311
HE
CLASSICAL
REVIEWHE
CLASSICAL
REVIEW
leads
her
to
accept
hat certain
groupspass
fromone section o another
of
Aristotle's
fundamental ivision.
She
appears
o think thatAristotledoesthis
deliberately.
t is
easierto
accept
Kirwan's
approach.
N. follows more familiar
paths,entering
nto the standard
arguments
bout the
interpretation
f this book and its
place
nAristotle's
hought.
He relates t
especially
to
Plato,
and
in
particular
o
the
Theaetetus nd the
Sophist.
The
danger
of the
approach
of both
C.
and
N. is
to
think
of Aristotle
as
primarily
oncernedwith the
Presocratics,
he
Sophists
and
Plato,
and less with the
subject
about which he is
arguing,
and
with his
students o whom
he
is
trying
o
make
his
points
clear.It
is
true
that since he believed hat hecouldlearn romhis
predecessors
e did
bring
hem
n,
but
philosophy
n his time had reachedthe
point
where it was
possible
to see a
problem
as a
problem,
and the
ustification
f the
principles
f
non-contradictionnd
of the excludedmiddlewould be
questions
n theirown
right
whoeverhad
dealt with
them before.Further, heyarenaturallyinkedwith the problemsabout the nature
of
reality
alsoconsidered n both Platoand
Aristotle,
and
especially
onnectedwith
the name of
Protagoras.
C.
claims
originality
or the idea that all Aristotlewants n order o
refute
sceptics
is
significance
nd not affirmation r denial from his
supposed
nterlocutor,
who
could,
for
instance,
ust
say
'Good
morning',
and that would be
enough
to
get
Aristotle
started.She
is
interesting
n
the
word
semainein,
istinguishing
etweena
man as
signifier
and a word as
signifier.
Men
use words to
signify
things:
words
signify
a
meaning
or
a
definition,
and
significance
ere
s
a
relationbetweenwords.
She
brings
in the treatmentof
goatstag
in
Post. Anal.
2.7,
denying
that
we must
divorcethe two treatments f meaning,and rangeswidelyover Aristotle'sremarks
about
semantics.
University
of
Liverpool
P
A M E L
A M. H U
B
Y
THE
FRAGMENTS OF ARISTOTLE
OLOF
GIGON
(ed.):
Aristotelis
Opera
(ex
recensione I.
Bekkeri,
ed.
2),
III: Librorum
Deperditorum
Fragmenta. Pp.
viii
+
875. Berlin and
New York: De
Gruyter,
1987. DM 780.
Gigon's long-awaited eplacement
or
Rose's collection
of
Ar(istotle)'s
ragments
s
a
massive
quarto
volume,
nearly
ourtimesas
long
as its
predecessor; llowing
or the
inclusion of a
good
deal of
explanatory
matterin the form
of introductions nd
headnotes o various
groups
of
fragmentsbut
no
commentary;
his is
promised
or
later),
it
must
contain
more than three times the amount of text. Even
so G. has
excluded ome texts
printedby
Rose. Rose believed hat all the
writings
ttributed o
Ar in
antiquity, xcept
for
the extant
pragmateiai,
were
apocryphal,
nd when he
set
out
to
collect their
remains,
ncludedsome
fragments
which no-one
ever
seriously
regardedas Ar's work, some of them not even ascribed o Ar in our sources.G.
howeverwould claim that
all
the texts in
his
collection are
connected,
directly
or
indirectly,
with
genuine
ost
writings
of
Ar,
even if
few
give
Ar's own
words,
andhe
has omitted hose which
fail to
satisfy
this
criterion.Most of
these are
unimportant
remarksabout
non-philosophical
ubjects
not
attributedto
Ar in
the
sources,
including
some
ascribed
o
-Theophrastusfrom
the
Hepi
iLErdAAcov
nd even the
Hist.
Plant.);
also omittedare Ar's
apophthegms
nd
the
fragments
f his
speeches
0009-840X/91
3.00
?
Oxford
University
Press 1991
leads
her
to
accept
hat certain
groupspass
fromone section o another
of
Aristotle's
fundamental ivision.
She
appears
o think thatAristotledoesthis
deliberately.
t is
easierto
accept
Kirwan's
approach.
N. follows more familiar
paths,entering
nto the standard
arguments
bout the
interpretation
f this book and its
place
nAristotle's
hought.
He relates t
especially
to
Plato,
and
in
particular
o
the
Theaetetus nd the
Sophist.
The
danger
of the
approach
of both
C.
and
N. is
to
think
of Aristotle
as
primarily
oncernedwith the
Presocratics,
he
Sophists
and
Plato,
and less with the
subject
about which he is
arguing,
and
with his
students o whom
he
is
trying
o
make
his
points
clear.It
is
true
that since he believed hat hecouldlearn romhis
predecessors
e did
bring
hem
n,
but
philosophy
n his time had reachedthe
point
where it was
possible
to see a
problem
as a
problem,
and the
ustification
f the
principles
f
non-contradictionnd
of the excludedmiddlewould be
questions
n theirown
right
whoeverhad
dealt with
them before.Further, heyarenaturallyinkedwith the problemsabout the nature
of
reality
alsoconsidered n both Platoand
Aristotle,
and
especially
onnectedwith
the name of
Protagoras.
C.
claims
originality
or the idea that all Aristotlewants n order o
refute
sceptics
is
significance
nd not affirmation r denial from his
supposed
nterlocutor,
who
could,
for
instance,
ust
say
'Good
morning',
and that would be
enough
to
get
Aristotle
started.She
is
interesting
n
the
word
semainein,
istinguishing
etweena
man as
signifier
and a word as
signifier.
Men
use words to
signify
things:
words
signify
a
meaning
or
a
definition,
and
significance
ere
s
a
relationbetweenwords.
She
brings
in the treatmentof
goatstag
in
Post. Anal.
2.7,
denying
that
we must
divorcethe two treatments f meaning,and rangeswidelyover Aristotle'sremarks
about
semantics.
University
of
Liverpool
P
A M E L
A M. H U
B
Y
THE
FRAGMENTS OF ARISTOTLE
OLOF
GIGON
(ed.):
Aristotelis
Opera
(ex
recensione I.
Bekkeri,
ed.
2),
III: Librorum
Deperditorum
Fragmenta. Pp.
viii
+
875. Berlin and
New York: De
Gruyter,
1987. DM 780.
Gigon's long-awaited eplacement
or
Rose's collection
of
Ar(istotle)'s
ragments
s
a
massive
quarto
volume,
nearly
ourtimesas
long
as its
predecessor; llowing
or the
inclusion of a
good
deal of
explanatory
matterin the form
of introductions nd
headnotes o various
groups
of
fragmentsbut
no
commentary;
his is
promised
or
later),
it
must
contain
more than three times the amount of text. Even
so G. has
excluded ome texts
printedby
Rose. Rose believed hat all the
writings
ttributed o
Ar in
antiquity, xcept
for
the extant
pragmateiai,
were
apocryphal,
nd when he
set
out
to
collect their
remains,
ncludedsome
fragments
which no-one
ever
seriously
regardedas Ar's work, some of them not even ascribed o Ar in our sources.G.
howeverwould claim that
all
the texts in
his
collection are
connected,
directly
or
indirectly,
with
genuine
ost
writings
of
Ar,
even if
few
give
Ar's own
words,
andhe
has omitted hose which
fail to
satisfy
this
criterion.Most of
these are
unimportant
remarksabout
non-philosophical
ubjects
not
attributedto
Ar in
the
sources,
including
some
ascribed
o
-Theophrastusfrom
the
Hepi
iLErdAAcov
nd even the
Hist.
Plant.);
also omittedare Ar's
apophthegms
nd
the
fragments
f his
speeches
0009-840X/91
3.00
?
Oxford
University
Press 1991
This content downloaded from 212.128.182.231 on Tue, 2 Sep 2014 05:07:23 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp -
8/10/2019 Aristteles. Frags. Gigon, O. (Ed., Berln - N. Y., 1987) - GOTTSCHALK, H. B. (1991)
3/5
32
THE CLASSICAL REVIEW
and
letters,
except
for those included
in
his Lives
(which
are
reprinted
entire),
and the
Peplos.
On the
other hand G. has admitted some
passages
not attributed to Ar
by
name where there are
grounds
for
believing
that
they
referto his lost
writings, e.g.
fr.
712;
the
most numerous of these are from Ar's own extant works
(together
with the
relevant ancient
commentaries), referring
to the
IlEpi
T-j
loEas
(as
G.
prefers
to call
it),
I7ep[
TOV
yaOov,
Anatomai,
Problemata
Physica,
Iep[
ckv-Tbv
etc. Other
major
additions
come from
papyrus
texts discovered since Rose's last edition was
published,
including
the whole of the
Ath. Pol.
(fr.
474),
a
large part
of the
Anonymus
Londinensis
(fr. 355)
and a section of Philodemus' Rhetorica
(fr. 130-2).
A
welcome
feature
of the
edition
is that G. has
generally printed
more of the context than
previous
editors.
Nearly
one third of the work
(pp.
1-254)
is
devoted to
testimonia: the ancient Lives
and other
biographical passages; Dionysius'
Letter to
Ammonius;
the Arabo-Latin
dialogue De pomo; various reportsconcerning the fate of Ar's works after his death;
the
Neoplatonic
prolegomena
to Ar's
pragmateiai;
the Aristotelian
doxographies
of
Areius
Didymus
and Aetius and three
passages
of
Cicero
dealing
with Aristotelian
philosophy
(Acad.
1.1343,
Fin.
4.2-13,
5.6-96);
the
fragments
of Atticus'
Against
Ar;
finally
those
passages
in
Ar's
pragmateiai
containing
references to his exoterikoi
logoi,
with the extant Greek
commentaries thereon and a selection of other relevant
texts. Here we have most of the available
material for a
Rezeptionsgeschichte
of Ar's
philosophy
in the Hellenistic and
early
Roman
period.
The
prolegomena
to this
section
(pp.
3-17)
gives
an indication of the
way
in which
G. would have
these texts
understood;
his views on the main issues are
judicious
and
balanced,
although
there
is room for disagreement on details.
Unlike
Rose,
G. tries to
assign
the extant
fragments
to known titles as far as
possible,
and has succeeded
in
grouping
788
texts in this
way;
a further 232 are
printed
at the
end of the collection
as
Fragmente
ohne
Buchangabe (789-982)
and
Nachtrage (983-1020).
Each known
title is treated as
belonging
to a
separate
work;
G. is
chary
of
identifying any
of
the titles in the ancient
catalogues
with others
from
the same lists or
with
extant
works
or
parts
of extant works
(p.
213).
With each
title,
including
those
for which there
are no
surviving
texts,
G. has furnished
a headnote
listing
works
by
other authors with the same
or related titles
and
discussing
the
meaning
of
the terms which occur
in
them,
and an end-note
listing passages
in Ar's
extant writings dealing with the same or related subject-matterand suggesting what
topics
may
have been raised
in
the lost
work. These hints are
valuable,
although
their
scope
is limited. G.
does not claim
to
give
anything
like a 'reconstruction'
of
Ar's lost
works,
but
only
to set the
limits which such a reconstruction
must observe.
This
warning
is
particularly
necessary
in the case of
Ar's
dialogues.
As G.
explains
in
his
Prolegomena (pp.
236ff.),
he believes that
many
of the fundamental
doctrines of
the
pragmateiai
were also
discussed,
often
in
greater
detail and
in
a
more
systematic
way,
in the
dialogues
and that
the
pragmateiai
presuppose
a
knowledge
of these
discussions. The
danger
of
falling
into
a circular
argument
is obvious and
I do not
find G.'s view
entirely
convincing:
if the
dialogues
were so
important
for
understanding the pragmateiai, why did later Aristotelians not refer to them more
often and more
explicitly
in
their
commentaries?
It is
in
assigning
fragments
to the extant
titles that a
degree
of arbitrariness
creeps
in. G.
rightly
insists that the
starting-point
for such decisions
must be the
ascription
of
fragments
in
our
sources,
but
since these are
comparatively
rare,
he uses the context
in which
unassigned
fragments
are
quoted
as an additional
criterion
(see
pp.
216f.).
This sounds
reasonable
enough,
but
the result can
be
disconcerting.
For
example,
of
This content downloaded from 212.128.182.231 on Tue, 2 Sep 2014 05:07:23 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp -
8/10/2019 Aristteles. Frags. Gigon, O. (Ed., Berln - N. Y., 1987) - GOTTSCHALK, H. B. (1991)
4/5
THE CLASSICAL REVIEW
33
the four references
to
Sardanapallus
traditionally
assigned
to the
Protreptikos(fr.
16
Ross)
one,
from
Athenaios,
is
placed
with the
fragments
of
the
/epl
8LKamoav71S
by
G.
(fr. 5),
enlarged by
a
long quotation
from
Archestratos whose
immediate
source
is given as Chrysippus, not Ar; two from Cicero are printed among the unplaced
fragments
and
the
last,
from
Strabo,
is
dropped
(rightly);
but a scholion on
Juvenal,
which
says only
that Cicero made a
derogatory
remark about
Sardanapallus
in
the
De
republica
which
echoes,
but
does not
reproduce exactly,
the one attributed
to
Ar
by
Athenaios,
is
accepted
as
/7.
tK. fr. 4. The link between the
passages assigned
to the /7. 8iK.
is
that Athenaios
quotes Chrysippus
on
Sardanapallus immediately
after
Ar,
and Plutarch
reports
that
Chrysippus
wrote
against
Ar
~repi
3tKatoo6vvrs;
but
it is not certain that these
words
refer
to
the title of a
book,
and G.'s
assumption
that
Ar
must have referred
to
Sardanapallus
in
several different
works,
but all the
non-Platonic material
in
Cicero's
De
republica
was taken from his
/7.
&IK.,
s
unproved and unprovable. The 'fragments' of this work are further bulked out by
four columns of miscellaneous information about the
burglar
and/or
traitor
Eurybatos
and
other
rogues
associated with him in the
tradition;
of all this
only
one
anecdote
is attributed
to Ar
by
our sources and
deserves to be
included in a collection
of his
fragments
(fr.
2
Ross,
84
Rose3).
Similarly,
G. includes all the
words and
phrases
from
Ar,
except
those from his
letters,
quoted
by
Demetrius to illustrate
stylistic
points, although they
are scattered
over
many
pages
and
only
the first
(28
=
fr. 8
G)
is
said to have
come from the
/7.
&K. In both cases
G.'s
'principle
of
economy',
that our authorities are
unlikely
to have
used more than one source for
each
work,
makes too little allowance
for
the
magpie
habits of ancient
grammarians.
By way of contrast, only the first two of the fragments traditionally assigned to the
Protreptikos
have survived as
such,
the others
being relegated
to the
'unplaced'
fragments
or a
special appendix
of
Tortot
rrporperTmKol
(fr. 73-83).
This
category
is
stretched to include the so-called Aristotelian Divisiones
(fr. 82-3);
in his headnote G.
argues
that these consist of extracts from the
dialogues,
but he
gives
no cross-
references to them in his
end-notes,
not
even in what
would be obvious cases such as
the
/7epl
evyevefa~
and
Div.
10.
Among
the other
fragmentary
writings
G.'s
treatment of
the
/ep[
~cov
is most
striking
and
a
good
example
of his
approach. Diogenes
lists this work as
having
nine
books and
has
generally
been
thought
to
refer to a work
consisting
of books 1-9 of
the extant HA. On G.'s reckoning there are 115 'fragments' (180-294) occupying,
with
their
contexts,
72
quarto pages,
derived from this
work;
some of
these are so
close to
passages
of Ar's
extant
zoological
works that
they
have
usually
been
regarded
as
quotations
of
them,
while others
do not
correspond
to
anything
in them
(the
situation is
similar
in
the
case of
Theophrastus'
botanical
writings).
Our
only
authority
to attach
any
titles to his
quotations
is
Athenaios and
he
gives many
variants which
may
or
may
not
belong
to the
same work.
G.
despairs
of
finding any
order
in
this confusion and
reprints
the
fragments
in
the order
in
which
they
occur
in
Athenaios and the
other
sources;
but true
to his
'principle
of
economy'
he takes
the view
that all the
fragments
are derived
from the same
original,
a Hellenistic
recension of Ar's zoological works much of which coincided closely with the text of
the
pragmateiai
as
edited
by
Andronicus,
but
which also
contained
matter not
included in
the later
recension,
and that the
title
77?pi
co3wv
efers to the
older
recension,
not the
extant one.
In
his choice of
text
G.
generally
follows
the standard modern
editions,
with
some
modifications;
he is
especially
prone
to
postulate
short
lacunas or to insert odd
words
which
certainly
make the
text read
more
smoothly,
but are
often not
really
necessary.
This content downloaded from 212.128.182.231 on Tue, 2 Sep 2014 05:07:23 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp -
8/10/2019 Aristteles. Frags. Gigon, O. (Ed., Berln - N. Y., 1987) - GOTTSCHALK, H. B. (1991)
5/5