art as communicable knowledge

Upload: lenwor

Post on 02-Jun-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    1/14

    Art as Communicable KnowledgeAuthor(s): Henry P. RaleighSource: Journal of Aesthetic Education, Vol. 5, No. 1 (Jan., 1971), pp. 115-127Published by: University of Illinois PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3331580.

    Accessed: 26/09/2014 00:11

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    University of Illinois Pressis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access toJournal of

    Aesthetic Education.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 134.76.63.66 on Fri, 26 Sep 2014 00:11:10 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=illinoishttp://www.jstor.org/stable/3331580?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/3331580?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=illinois
  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    2/14

    Art

    as

    Communicable

    Knowledge

    HENRY

    P. RALEIGH

    The

    following

    remarks are

    addressed to the

    notion that fine

    art

    is

    a

    special

    mode

    of

    thought

    and

    knowledge.

    This

    speciality

    is

    most

    interest-

    ing,

    for we

    suppose

    the

    value of that

    knowledge

    shares

    in

    the

    value

    we

    place

    on

    knowledge

    in

    general,

    and,

    additionally,

    in

    the

    special

    value

    we

    place

    on

    art

    for both aesthetic and nonaesthetic

    reasons.

    The

    impli-

    cations this holds for a theory of art education are obvious. Insofar as

    aesthetic

    speculation

    may

    regard

    the

    experience

    of fine arts

    as

    essentially

    an

    exchange

    of

    knowledge,

    this would

    certainly

    be

    considered

    as con-

    tributing

    to a

    theory

    of

    fine

    arts

    as

    communicable

    knowledge.

    As

    a

    kind

    of

    knowledge,

    even

    special

    or

    unique,

    it must be

    supposed

    as

    well that

    it

    can

    be

    learned

    and

    promoted by

    educational

    means.

    Art

    as

    knowledge

    in

    the above

    sense is

    especially, perhaps

    peculiarly,

    a

    modem

    innovation.

    In the traditional

    view,

    from

    the

    Latin ars and

    the Greek

    techne,

    art was

    any

    knowledge

    that

    served

    as

    a skill in trans-

    forming

    material. Art was

    craftsmanship

    and learned as such. That the

    experience

    of

    art was a

    form

    of

    divine

    or

    inspirational

    madness was never

    entirely

    absent

    from classical

    aesthetics.

    Inspired

    madness was more a

    disease

    of

    poets

    than

    artists

    and

    was

    not

    believed

    by

    the ancients to be

    a

    functioning,

    valuable

    knowledge.

    The fine

    arts stood

    in

    sometimes

    subservient,

    sometimes

    purely

    mystical

    relation to

    philosophy,

    the

    para-

    gon

    of

    true

    knowledge.

    St.

    Thomas did

    speak

    of

    art as

    intellectual,

    its

    apprehension

    the

    response

    of the

    maxime

    cognoscitivi

    -

    sight

    and

    hearing.

    But

    art

    was still

    essentially making,

    a

    job,

    in the

    classic

    sense,

    HENRY P.

    RALEIGH

    is

    Chairman

    of

    the

    Division

    of

    Art at the State

    University

    College

    at New

    Paltz,

    New

    York.

    He has contributed

    to several

    scholarly

    journals

    including

    the

    Journal

    of Aesthetics

    and

    Art Criticism.

    His

    article The Problem

    of

    'Expression'

    in

    Art

    and Art

    Education was

    published

    in the

    April

    1968

    issue

    of

    this

    Journal.

    He

    is also

    a

    Journal

    consultant.

    This content downloaded from 134.76.63.66 on Fri, 26 Sep 2014 00:11:10 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    3/14

    116

    HENRY

    RALEIGH

    to be well done and one only loosely identified with the absolute source

    of

    knowledge

    -

    Beauty.

    There is little

    change

    in

    the

    predominant

    Greek

    attitude until

    very

    much later

    when,

    in aesthetic

    thought,

    the fine

    arts

    begin

    to assume

    the

    position

    of

    a

    different kind of

    mental

    operation,

    vague

    to

    be

    sure,

    but

    somehow

    representing

    a

    mysterious,

    universal

    truth.

    Baumgarten,

    following

    Leibnitz,

    had

    attempted

    to frame

    a

    logic

    of

    the

    imagination

    and

    separated

    the mind

    into two

    levels. One

    of

    these,

    a

    region

    of confused

    imagery,

    was the seat

    of artistic

    knowledge.

    Kant,

    in

    summarizing

    and

    structuring

    these

    newer

    views,

    was

    among

    the

    first

    to see art as autonomous and not

    necessarily

    reduced to an alien prin-

    ciple

    or

    jurisdiction.

    He

    made

    of art a kind

    of

    judgment,

    a

    union

    between

    the

    imagination

    and the

    understanding.

    Art

    is not

    merely

    ex-

    periential

    but

    the

    bridge

    joining

    theoretical

    and

    practical

    knowledge.

    This

    judgment,

    for

    Kant,

    was

    formal and

    subjective,

    not mediated

    by

    cognition

    of

    an end or

    any

    reflective

    idea.

    In

    itself,

    the

    experience

    of

    art

    may

    serve

    in

    judgment,

    yet

    it

    was

    not

    knowledge.

    To

    Kant,

    as

    to those

    who had

    preceded

    him,

    art

    was

    really

    the

    matter

    of a

    metaphysical

    idea,

    and

    the

    artist,

    unknowingly,

    exercised

    a distinct

    and

    largely

    detached

    quality

    of mind called

    Imagination.

    With

    Schopenhauer

    the real

    oppo-

    nents,

    at least

    in

    modem

    terms,

    are

    given

    their

    first,

    characteristic

    orm:

    art versus science.

    Schopenhauer

    divorced

    the

    objects

    of

    cognition

    from

    the

    blind,

    irrational

    apprehension

    of

    an

    underlying

    reality.

    The route

    to this felt

    knowledge

    was aesthetic

    vision. Art

    alone tore

    the

    objects

    of

    the

    mind

    out of the

    fleeting, momentary qualities

    of

    rational,

    pragmatic

    scientific

    thought.

    Unhappily,

    art

    was

    more an

    escape

    from

    knowledge

    than

    a form of

    knowledge

    in itself

    and

    Schopenhauer,

    as

    Plato,

    Vico,

    and

    Baumgarten,

    concluded that

    art was but

    an

    opiate

    and

    the

    genius

    ultimately

    a madman.

    This

    conclusion,

    Romantic

    and

    traditional as

    it

    is,

    has

    not satisfied

    modern rationalists who

    have come to

    prefer

    the

    thesis

    that art and

    science

    seek the same truths but

    in

    different

    ways.

    That

    art and

    science

    are

    the

    same but different is

    important

    to

    the

    theory

    that the

    fine arts

    represent

    communicable

    knowledge.

    During

    the fif-

    teenth and sixteenth

    centuries the artist had

    enjoyed

    a

    brief

    peership

    with the

    scientist and

    in

    some instances he was

    the

    only experimental,

    methodological

    worker

    deserving

    of

    the

    term.

    The reasons

    for

    this

    were

    partly due to a quest

    for

    technical solutions to difficult and advanced

    pictorial

    and

    three-dimensional

    problems

    and

    partly

    a desire to elevate

    the

    social

    status of

    the artist.

    Frequently

    the artist of

    that time

    was

    a

    geometer, engineer,

    and

    alchemist as well as

    a

    superb

    craftsman. But

    science and mathematics

    soon

    outstripped

    the

    comparatively

    humble

    This content downloaded from 134.76.63.66 on Fri, 26 Sep 2014 00:11:10 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    4/14

    ART AS

    COMMUNICABLEKNOWLEDGE

    117

    level of technology that occupied the artist, and the artist as scientist

    died

    ignobly.

    The alternative is

    to

    hypothesize

    artistic

    activity

    as

    another,

    equivalently

    valid,

    hopefully

    verifiable

    way

    of

    truth-seeking

    and thus

    avoid the

    unequal comparison

    between

    the

    technological

    funds of knowl-

    edge

    of

    artist

    and

    scientist.

    This

    has

    apparently

    found

    favor

    in

    the

    present

    time.

    Out of

    Romantic

    aesthetic

    conjecture

    has

    grown

    a

    belief that art

    is

    an

    activity

    that reveals the

    unity

    and

    harmony

    of the universal structure.

    Art is the assembler of

    wholes;

    science is the

    disassembler,

    he

    analyzer

    of parts. From a meager and rather negative Platonic view that art

    informs,

    that

    is,

    communicates

    knowledge

    by

    imitation,

    through

    Schiller

    and

    Schelling

    and the

    regard

    for art as an

    objective

    philosophy,

    there

    has

    developed

    a

    consistent theme of art as

    knowledge.

    The usual modes

    of

    thought

    and

    perception arrange

    and

    classify

    objects

    as

    parts

    of enti-

    ties,

    selecting

    and

    reordering

    these as

    parts

    of

    greater

    entities--all

    against

    some

    ultimate

    purpose.

    Art

    suffers

    no restrictions

    of

    utility

    of

    ends;

    it deals

    with whole

    appearances.

    Science is concerned with

    the

    coherent

    relations

    between

    things,

    art

    with the

    thing

    in

    itself. The

    ques-

    tions must

    obviously

    be

    asked,

    What is the exact nature of this

    special

    knowledge?

    and,

    What

    is it

    knowledge

    of?

    An

    examination

    of

    but

    a

    few of the moder

    speculative

    ventures into

    this

    problem

    of

    aesthetic

    knowledge

    will indicate the

    general

    directions to

    which

    such

    questions

    have

    led.

    One

    of the

    first

    of these

    examinations,

    much influenced

    by

    the

    psy-

    chologism

    of

    the

    period,

    was

    Conrad Fiedler's.

    Writing

    in

    the late

    1800s,

    Fiedler inherited

    Goethe's

    and

    Herder's interest in

    visual,

    Gestalt

    wholes.

    A

    work of

    art

    cannot

    be known or

    judged

    in

    the

    same

    way

    as

    a

    product

    of

    nature. In the

    Kantian

    tradition,

    artistic

    judgment

    is not

    rational

    nor

    is it

    conceptual

    knowing.

    Conceptual

    abilities start with

    appearance

    forming

    concepts

    of what

    is

    given:

    In abstract

    cognition

    we

    possess

    the means

    of

    submitting

    appearances

    to

    certain demands of

    our

    thinking

    faculties,

    and

    thus

    appropriating

    them for

    ourselves

    by

    transforming

    hem into

    conceptual

    Gestalt-formation. '

    There

    is another

    form

    of

    cognition,

    and

    for Fiedler

    the true

    and final

    level

    is

    that of artistic

    perception.

    Scientific

    abstraction

    rushes

    through

    and beyond the world of appearances.

    Art

    reveals what

    is there:

    It

    should be

    understood

    that man

    can

    attain

    the mental

    mastery

    of the

    Conrad

    Fiedler,

    On

    Judging

    Works

    of

    Visual

    Art,

    trans.

    Henry

    Schaefer-

    Simmern

    and Fulmer

    Mood

    (Berkeley:

    University

    of

    California

    Press, 1957),

    p.

    31.

    This content downloaded from 134.76.63.66 on Fri, 26 Sep 2014 00:11:10 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    5/14

    118 HENRY RALEIGH

    world not only by the creation of concepts but also by the creation of

    visual

    conceptions. 2

    Unlike

    the

    Romantic

    theorists

    before and the

    Expressionists

    after

    him,

    Fiedler's

    artist

    is

    neither an

    emotional

    escapist

    nor an

    objectifier

    of his

    feelings.

    As

    does

    abstraction,

    feeling (sensation)

    obstructs

    and

    inhibits

    the

    artist's

    perceptions:

    ..

    .

    we must

    be able to

    forget

    every

    sensation

    in

    order

    to

    further our

    perceptual

    grasp

    of the

    object

    for its own sake. 3

    His artist is a

    strange

    creature of

    science who

    neither thinks

    nor

    feels,

    only

    perceives

    dispassionately.

    Detachment and

    disinterest

    have been

    borrowed from the Kantian aesthetic

    contemplation

    and made a virtue

    of

    the

    personality.

    Just

    how visual

    conceptions

    will

    help

    give

    a

    mental

    mastery

    is not

    explained.

    That is to

    say,

    Fiedler does not tell us what

    or

    how artistic

    perception

    cognizes.

    However,

    we

    are

    told

    something

    of

    what it

    is

    supposed

    to

    be.

    Very

    similar in his

    regard

    for

    the

    perceptual

    function

    and

    the

    con-

    comitant distinctions of mental

    processes

    s

    Hugo

    Miinsterberg:

    science

    is

    connection,

    art

    is

    isolation:

    To isolate

    the

    object

    for the mind means

    to

    make

    it

    beautiful,

    for

    it fills the

    mind

    without an

    idea of

    anything

    else. 4

    The

    value of

    art is

    to

    separate

    the

    single experience

    from

    a network of

    multiple

    experiences.

    Drawing

    from

    the

    argument,

    advanced

    by

    William

    James

    for

    one,

    that all

    mental

    processes

    result in an

    isolation

    of

    singulars,

    Miinsterberg

    continues the

    opposition

    to

    scientific

    thought by noting

    that other

    perceptual

    activities lead to some action

    or

    to further

    visual

    relationships.

    The art

    object

    holds us

    in

    arrestment.

    Why

    should

    we

    be

    held

    in

    this

    suspension?

    Disappointingly,

    it is not

    to

    gain

    something

    from

    contemplation

    freed

    of all

    practicality

    and

    purpose

    but

    only

    to

    effect

    a

    physiological

    release of

    tensions and

    strains.

    The

    synaesthesis

    of

    Ogden

    and

    Richards is of

    the same

    order,

    although purportedly

    being

    an

    advance over earlier

    theories of

    the

    reciprocal

    relation of

    aesthetic

    pleasure

    and

    physiological

    functions.

    Synaesthesis,

    according

    to

    Ogden

    and

    Richards,

    is

    mental

    harmony, impersonal

    and

    disinterested.5

    From semantic

    and

    psychoanalytic

    studies

    has

    come

    a

    distinct

    attempt

    to

    explain

    art as an

    interpersonal knowledge.

    These

    arguments

    require

    the

    casting

    of art

    in

    a

    special

    role

    as the

    symbolic

    reconstructor

    of

    the human

    psyche.

    As

    a theory

    of

    aesthetic knowledge such interpreta-

    2Ibid.,

    p.

    40.

    3

    Ibid.,

    p.

    29.

    4Hugo

    Miinsterberg,

    The

    Principles of

    Art

    Education

    (New

    York:

    Prang,

    1905), p.

    20.

    5

    Cf.,

    C. K.

    Ogden,

    I. A.

    Richards, J. Wood,

    The

    Foundation

    of

    Aesthetics

    (London:

    Allen and

    Unwin,

    1925).

    This content downloaded from 134.76.63.66 on Fri, 26 Sep 2014 00:11:10 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    6/14

    ARTAS

    COMMUNICABLE

    NOWLEDGE

    119

    tions have interesting implicationsas well as seriousdeficiencies. It may

    be

    probably

    agreed

    that

    any

    activity

    which

    resulted

    in

    information

    about

    one's

    self,

    if more than

    intuitional

    guessing,

    could

    be

    considered

    knowledge,

    especially

    if

    this information could

    be

    acted

    upon

    in the

    performing

    of a

    descriptive

    service.

    A

    theory

    of

    knowledge

    is

    expected

    to

    hold,

    directly

    or

    indirectly,

    that

    knowledge

    qua

    knowledge

    must be

    useful in

    some

    way,

    usually

    in some

    operable

    sense.

    Any

    psychoanalytic

    assumption

    about

    the

    human

    constitution

    supposes

    some

    pathology

    of

    that constitution that

    may

    be

    treated

    educationally.

    In

    the

    simplest

    sense,unconscious and unorganizedknowledge is reorganized n the con-

    scious

    to

    improve

    the

    efficiency

    of

    the

    organism,

    to restore

    proper

    emotional

    functions.

    Significantly,

    psychoanalytic

    treatment

    of emotional

    pathologies

    is

    educational and

    not

    medical

    or

    surgical.

    Could

    art,

    there-

    fore,

    be considered

    educational and

    involving

    useful

    knowledge?

    This

    is

    unlikely

    in

    current

    psychoanalytic nterpretations

    of

    art.

    Anton

    Ehrenzweig

    divides

    form

    or

    form

    language

    into articulate

    perceptions.6

    These have

    obvious

    correspondence

    o

    the assumed

    psychic

    structure

    of

    the

    conscious

    and the unconscious.

    The

    production

    of

    art

    entails

    the

    articulation

    of inarticulate form

    language,

    the latter essen-

    tially

    pangenital,

    driven into

    the

    unconscious because

    of the

    prohibitions

    of civilized conventions.

    Aesthetic

    articulation,

    the

    form

    quality

    which

    structurally

    determines

    that a

    form is an

    art

    form,

    is

    like

    any

    convention,

    the

    acceptable

    facade

    behind

    which

    inarticulate,

    secret

    form

    language

    lurks

    (in

    Ehrenzweig's

    words,

    Gestalt-free ).

    While

    in

    a

    pure therapy

    transaction

    the

    raw

    material

    of the unconscious

    may

    be revealed

    as

    operable

    information,

    the

    stylistic

    articulations

    that

    characterize art

    for-

    ever

    prevent

    the

    Gestalt-free

    imagery

    from

    being

    acted

    upon

    and

    thus

    resolved.

    The

    tug-of-war

    between articulation of

    the inarticulate

    always

    wins

    in

    favor

    of

    conventionalized,

    safe,

    articulate

    structure

    and the artist

    is

    eternally

    driven

    to

    go

    on

    to

    yet

    another

    creation,

    and

    his

    audience

    to

    yet

    more

    secret

    communications without

    ever

    knowing

    why.

    Art

    cannot

    hold

    out

    the

    relief

    of

    knowledge

    but

    only

    the

    frustration

    of

    almost

    knowledge.

    Art

    is

    self-perpetuating,

    blind,

    hardly

    satisfactory

    knowledge.

    Other

    psychoanalytic

    references,

    such

    as H.

    Westman's

    return

    to

    a near

    Neo-Platonism,

    deny

    that aesthetic

    experience

    can

    be

    regarded as a superiorknowledge.7

    After

    Jung,

    Westman

    views

    art

    as

    the

    symbolic

    carrier

    of

    archetypical

    forms whose

    meaning

    is

    beyond

    objective grasp

    and

    sensed

    only existentially.

    The

    ontological

    implica-

    6

    Cf.,

    The

    Psycho-Analysis

    of

    Artistic

    Vision and

    Hearing

    (London:

    Routledge

    and

    Kegan

    Paul, 1953).

    7

    Cf.,

    The

    Springs

    of

    Creativity

    (New

    York:

    Atheneum,

    1961).

    This content downloaded from 134.76.63.66 on Fri, 26 Sep 2014 00:11:10 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    7/14

    120 HENRY RALEIGH

    tions very often approached in psychoanalyticaesthetic speculationsare

    invariably

    cut short

    by

    the

    overbearing

    tendency

    to

    consider

    the artist

    and his

    audience as unconscious and

    ignorant

    victims of their

    psychic

    drives. Since such

    psychic

    drives are

    fundamentally

    the

    same,

    analytic

    knowledge,

    whether

    pangenital

    or

    mythical,

    is

    repetitively

    the same.

    Inversely,

    if men

    were

    more

    knowledgeable,

    they

    would

    have

    no

    need

    of art either

    to

    produce

    it or to see

    it.

    Symbolic investigations

    of art

    have

    come,

    perhaps,

    the

    closest,

    method-

    ologically,

    to a

    theory

    of

    art

    as

    knowledge. They

    have

    done

    so,

    un-

    doubtedly

    because it was

    just

    such an aesthetic

    theory

    that

    symbolic

    investigators

    sought

    to

    find,

    basing

    their research

    on

    the fact that

    other,

    more familiar modes

    of

    knowledge

    may

    be

    understood as

    systems

    of

    signs

    and referents.8

    More

    interesting

    as

    a

    synthesis

    of

    the

    stronger

    features

    of

    both

    semantically

    derived

    and

    psychoanalytic

    theories

    of

    art have been

    Sir

    Herbert

    Read's

    studies.

    Read,

    like other

    theorists,

    believes

    there is

    a

    special,

    investigatory

    distinction in

    artistic

    processes

    that is akin to

    sci-

    ence

    although

    not similar in method. In The Forms

    of Things

    Unknown,

    Read

    adopts

    from Charles Morris

    the

    term

    appraisive-valuative

    o

    indicate

    the

    type

    of

    discoursewhich is

    represented by

    art. This is distin-

    guished

    from scientific

    discourse which is

    designative-informative.

    To

    demonstrate

    that

    art

    obeys

    internal,

    structural

    relationships

    similar

    to

    linguistic, grammatical

    structures,

    even

    to

    note

    functional,

    material

    limitations which

    correspond

    to

    the

    orthogonal

    restrictionsof

    language,

    is to

    prepare

    the

    ground

    for the claim

    that

    art

    is

    engaged

    in

    the

    trans-

    mission

    of

    some kind of information.

    The nature

    of that transmission

    s,

    of

    course,

    appraisive-valuative.

    But what is

    appraised

    and valuated

    by

    the fine

    arts?

    Not

    the

    objects

    of

    reality,

    for a

    painted representation

    is

    only

    a

    designative sign

    for

    the

    thing

    it

    represents.

    The

    alternative,

    pur-

    suing

    the

    theory

    of

    art

    as

    knowledge,

    is to arrive

    at the

    impasse

    of the

    symbolists:

    the

    art

    object appraises

    and valuates

    itself;

    or

    passes

    on

    to a

    metaphysical

    impasse

    of unknowable

    knowledge

    that

    lies

    beyond

    the

    mind and

    beyond

    the level of

    descriptive-informative nowledge.

    For

    Read,

    the

    cognitive

    quality

    of art

    is

    found

    in

    its treatment

    of

    singularity:

    The

    apprehension

    of

    singulars,

    in

    any complete

    sense,

    is the

    artistic

    process

    itself. 9

    The notion of art as involved with this special attribute of the world

    8

    For

    a criticism of

    such semantic

    based

    theories see

    Max Reiser's

    The Se-

    mantic

    Theory

    of

    Art in

    America, Journal

    of

    Aesthetics and

    Art

    Criticism,

    Vol.

    15,

    No.

    1

    (September

    1956).

    9

    Herbert

    Read,

    The

    Forms

    of

    Things

    Unknown

    (New

    York:

    Horizon

    Press,

    1960), p.

    44.

    This content downloaded from 134.76.63.66 on Fri, 26 Sep 2014 00:11:10 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    8/14

    ART AS COMMUNICABLE

    KNOWLEDGE

    121

    seems to be a consequence of the phenomenal, singular quality of art

    objects

    themselves as well as

    the

    desire to

    distinguish

    a

    mode of

    appre-

    hension

    by

    contrast

    to

    apparently

    pluralistic

    and relational

    apprehension.

    It

    is

    not

    plausible

    to conceive of the art

    object

    as relational

    in sensate

    experience.

    The

    assumption

    here is

    always

    that art

    knowledge

    is like

    scientific

    knowledge

    in

    that it

    informs,

    interpretively,

    of

    a

    cause

    and

    effect

    world but

    in

    its

    own

    way

    of

    expressing

    the

    singular.

    The

    mis-

    leading

    and

    probably

    self-defeating

    result

    of

    this

    assumption

    is

    that

    scien-

    tific

    discourse

    does,

    by

    the

    very

    nature

    of

    the

    symbolic

    devices

    employed,

    impart an equivalentstructural

    sequence

    in the events or series it chooses

    to

    describe. The

    process

    of

    artistic

    activity

    may

    well be

    similar

    but

    the

    product,

    since a

    physical

    object,

    is

    not

    symbolic

    of

    a

    serial

    activity.

    It is

    always

    a

    singular

    and cannot

    be

    viewed

    any

    other

    way.10

    The

    singular

    symbol

    of

    a

    propositional

    formulation is

    arbitrary

    and like a

    painted

    representation,

    or,

    more

    abstractly,

    a

    painted

    geometric

    shape,

    may

    or

    may

    not

    refer

    to

    something

    in

    reality

    but does

    not evaluate

    or

    appraise,

    or

    in

    any

    manner

    provide

    information about

    its referent. The

    significance

    of the

    singular

    symbol,

    the fact of

    its

    being

    apprehended

    as

    knowledge

    about

    something,

    is relative to the

    possibility

    of verification of the

    pro-

    position

    in

    reality.

    The

    art

    object,

    as a

    singular

    symbol,

    cannot

    at

    all be

    verified in

    reality

    in order to

    gain

    reifiable

    knowledge.

    This

    is

    no

    more

    possible

    than

    to

    do

    the

    same

    for the

    symbol

    one

    or x.

    The

    way

    out

    of the

    dilemma

    for

    the

    symbolic

    theorist,

    if he

    wishes

    to

    avoid

    an ate-

    ological

    absolute,

    is

    to

    internalize

    knowledge,

    referring

    it back to

    some-

    thing

    within

    the

    participant

    in

    the

    aesthetic

    experience.

    The

    referral

    activates

    or

    reconstructssome

    knowledge

    already present.

    Read

    accepts

    the

    Jungian theory

    of

    psychologically

    continuous

    mythic

    materials.

    In

    this

    respect

    artistic

    knowledge

    is

    merely

    an

    endless

    reminiscing

    of the

    primordial

    past

    in

    psychic

    symbols

    which alter

    their

    forms

    but

    never

    their

    content.

    Read, however,

    would

    have

    the

    best

    of

    two

    possibilities.

    He finds a

    vital difference

    between the

    repetitive

    psychic

    symbol

    and

    the

    pure

    aesthetic

    symbol

    which is

    concerned

    only

    with the

    sensations

    pro-

    duced

    by

    the

    art

    object.

    It

    (the

    aesthetic

    object)

    is a

    perceptual

    mode

    that excludes all

    details

    of

    accident

    and environment

    not

    intrinsic to

    the

    thing

    itself. '

    As

    knowledge,

    the

    aesthetic

    symbol

    is

    caught again in its own trap

    of

    informing

    the

    observer

    that it is there

    and

    no more

    -

    a

    symbol

    of

    10

    The

    cinema,

    on the other

    hand,

    suffers no such

    disadvantage

    and

    the

    nature

    of

    its

    communicability

    is

    much

    closer to

    that

    of

    literature.

    1

    Read,

    op.

    cit.,

    p.

    80.

    This content downloaded from 134.76.63.66 on Fri, 26 Sep 2014 00:11:10 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    9/14

    122

    HENRY

    RALEIGH

    itself. Both Cassirerand Whitehead have argued for art symbols as a

    type

    of

    intuitive

    knowledge, claiming

    that such

    special

    information is

    one of the

    ways

    of

    achieving

    an

    objective

    view

    of

    reality.

    Cassirerwished

    to

    give

    an

    autonomy

    to art

    by separating

    the

    symbolic

    functions of

    art,

    language,

    and

    science.

    He

    considered

    art as

    a

    language

    of

    forms of

    feelings,

    not

    of

    concepts.

    Science

    gives

    us

    order in

    thoughts; morality

    gives

    us

    order

    in

    actions;

    art

    gives

    us order

    in the

    apprehensions

    of

    visible,

    tangible,

    and

    audible

    appearances.1'l2

    We would

    assume

    that

    such

    apprehension

    is

    special

    insofar as it

    reveals something of objective reality, but in Cassirer'sview this is not

    exactly

    so: .

    ..

    art

    gives

    us a

    new

    kind of truth-

    a

    truth

    not

    of em-

    pirical things

    but

    of

    pure

    forms. 13We

    are led back

    to

    classical theories

    which

    sought

    the

    sources

    of

    knowledge

    in

    categories

    of

    absolute

    beauty

    or absolute forms

    that

    lay

    behind,

    as

    logical

    necessity,

    and

    beyond

    the

    knowledge

    of

    objective

    reality.

    The

    presence

    of

    a

    visual

    art

    object

    as

    totally

    given

    to

    immediate

    apprehension

    of the senses

    is troublesome

    to

    account

    for in

    any specu-

    lation

    concerning

    the

    knowledge,

    truth,

    or

    meaning

    of the arts. The

    forms of literature

    may very

    well,

    as

    John

    Hospers

    has

    remarked,

    con-

    tain

    statements about

    the

    world

    which,

    as

    information,

    may

    or

    may

    not

    be

    relevant to

    it as

    art. From

    a

    novel,

    for

    example,

    Hospers

    believes

    we

    may

    learn

    truths about

    human nature

    not as

    directly presented

    but in-

    directly,

    simply

    by

    virtue

    of

    its

    being

    true

    to

    human

    experience:

    Appre-

    ciation

    of

    art

    gives

    us

    new

    'ways

    of

    seeing'

    but no

    knowledge,

    no

    facts,

    no

    propositions;

    so also with

    music and much

    literature,

    especially

    poetry. 14

    Not

    all would exclude

    poetry

    from the

    realm of

    cognitive meaning.

    Bertram

    Jessup15

    requires

    as

    a

    test

    of

    cognitive

    meaning

    only repeat-

    ability

    of the described

    experience,

    whether of a

    scientific

    report

    or of a

    poetic

    statement.

    This

    cannot

    be

    claimed for

    the

    visual

    object,

    for there

    is

    nothing

    to which

    it

    may

    be

    compared

    and thus

    tested for

    repeatability

    unless

    it be

    a

    matter of

    further visual

    cognitions.

    Obviously

    a

    painting

    does

    not

    teach

    us to see

    in

    new

    ways.

    We

    may

    see

    something

    else or

    something

    different.

    There

    is no evidence

    that

    art teaches us to

    see

    differently,

    although

    Heinrich

    Wolfflin

    had

    suggested

    an

    evolution

    in

    12

    Ernst Cassirer, An Essay on Man (New Haven: Yale University Press,

    1944), p.

    168.

    Ibid.,

    p.

    164.

    14John

    Hospers,

    Meaning

    and

    Truth

    in the Arts

    (Chapel

    Hill:

    University

    of

    North

    Carolina

    Press,

    1946), p.

    206.

    15

    Bertram

    Jessup,

    On Fictional

    Expressions

    of

    Cognitive Meaning,

    Journal

    of

    Aesthetics and

    Art

    Criticism,

    Vol.

    23,

    No.

    4

    (Summer 1965).

    This content downloaded from 134.76.63.66 on Fri, 26 Sep 2014 00:11:10 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    10/14

    ART

    AS COMMUNICABLEKNOWLEDGE

    123

    visual perception. We suppose, both practically and for purposes of

    critical

    operations,

    that all viewers of the art

    object

    see

    it

    in

    exactly

    the

    same

    way.

    If art could

    promote

    changes

    in

    the

    perception

    of

    reality

    this

    would indeed

    be

    considered a contribution

    to

    knowledge.

    Still,

    we

    know

    that an

    Impressionist

    painting

    of

    a

    bowl

    of flowers

    is different

    from an

    Expressionist

    treatment

    of the same

    subject

    and both in turn

    are

    quite

    different

    from

    the

    real

    bowl

    of

    flowers

    that

    may

    have served

    as

    inspira-

    tion for

    the

    paintings.

    We

    know,

    as

    well,

    that

    the

    painters

    saw

    the

    original

    bowl

    of

    flowers

    just

    as

    we

    did

    -

    only

    their

    presented

    forms are

    different. It is the

    stability

    of

    perception

    that

    handily

    allows us to dis-

    tinguish

    the

    paintings

    from

    one another

    and from the

    object

    of

    reality.

    There is

    yet

    another

    approach

    to

    the view

    that

    visual

    art communi-

    cates

    knowledge.

    This

    view

    requires

    a

    very

    rudimentary

    definition

    of

    knowledge:

    knowledge

    is

    literally

    any

    resultant of the action

    to

    know

    and

    is

    often

    equivalently

    identified

    to

    it.

    Such theories

    of art as

    com-

    municable

    knowledge

    sustain

    themselves

    on

    tenuous

    grounds

    since

    they

    would tend

    to include all

    effectory

    situations

    or

    stand as almost

    purely

    tautological.

    These

    views

    might

    be

    subsumed

    under

    general expressionist

    theoriesof art but are differentin the

    respect

    that

    they attempt

    to frame

    expression

    or

    feeling

    as a

    type

    of

    knowledge

    or

    some form

    of com-

    municable

    meaning. John

    Hospers,

    for

    example,

    accepts

    a most inclusive

    definition of

    meaning

    n art: .. . a work

    of

    art

    means to

    us

    whatever

    effects

    (not

    necessarily

    emotions)

    it

    evokes

    in

    us;

    a

    work which

    has

    no

    effect on

    us means

    nothing

    to

    us,

    and

    whatever effect it

    does

    evoke

    con-

    stitutes its

    meaning

    for us. '6

    This

    would not

    be

    helpful

    as a

    suggestion

    of

    an aesthetic

    theory

    of

    knowledge

    for we must ask

    if

    no

    effect is not as

    significant

    a

    meaning

    as a

    positive

    effect.

    It would

    be

    true,

    too,

    that

    to

    recognize

    an

    object

    as an

    object

    intended

    to

    produce

    an

    effect,

    although

    no further

    addi-

    tional

    effect

    may

    be

    reported,

    is,

    nevertheless,

    an

    effect deducible

    as

    meaning.

    However,

    Hospers

    is not concerned

    with

    formulating

    a

    theory

    of aesthetic

    knowledge

    for he notes

    that

    even the

    statements

    made

    of

    the

    world

    by

    literature are irrelevant as information.

    The alternative

    to

    this

    is

    to

    claim

    for

    art,

    not informational

    communication,

    but a

    special

    and

    exclusive function of emotional

    communication.

    Under certain

    assumed

    conditions objectified-feelings might be construed as knowledge, em-

    ploying

    a

    definition

    of

    knowledge

    in

    common

    usage:

    information

    of

    a

    kind

    that

    can

    lead

    to

    further,

    unspecified

    action;

    that

    is

    susceptible

    to

    methodological

    treatment;

    that is

    communicable as

    understanding.

    6

    Hospers, op.

    cit.,

    p.

    95.

    This content downloaded from 134.76.63.66 on Fri, 26 Sep 2014 00:11:10 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    11/14

    124

    HENRY

    RALEIGH

    Argumentsof this nature draw in part from Kant's theoryof knowledge,

    assigning

    to the mind

    some active

    principle

    which

    exercises

    a

    power

    held to be

    a

    necessary

    condition

    for

    the

    knowledge

    of

    objects

    or

    the

    self.

    In Art

    and

    Scientific

    Thought,

    Martin

    Johnson

    compares

    both

    art and

    science relative

    to

    their roles

    of

    communicating

    agreed

    to

    patterns

    or

    structures: ... each

    attempting

    to communicate

    mental

    images

    through

    patterns

    and

    structures and

    forms,

    in

    the

    qualitative

    domain of

    mea-

    surement

    respectively. 17

    In

    the

    face

    of

    a

    persistent

    belief that art

    objects

    are

    independent

    and

    unique

    entities it is difficult to

    speak

    of

    agreed

    to

    patterns

    and struc-

    tures

    in

    the same

    way

    that one

    may speak

    of

    them in science.

    While

    it

    cannot

    be denied

    that art

    objects

    do have

    patterns

    and structures

    as

    do

    all

    entities,

    their existence

    as art

    objects

    depends

    not

    on

    any

    relational

    dependence

    on other

    structural

    systems

    (other

    objects),

    but on a

    total

    distinction from

    all

    other structures

    and

    patterns.

    The criterion

    of

    reasonable

    agreement

    for

    scientific entities

    is

    well

    known and this alone

    is sufficientto

    diminish the

    value of

    such

    a

    comparison

    to

    the arts.

    Straddling

    the

    positions

    of

    art

    as

    a different

    mode

    of

    perceptual

    reality

    and

    as

    objectified

    emotion

    is the

    recent

    suggestion

    advanced

    by

    Harry

    S.

    Broudy.

    Underscoring

    the

    importance

    of

    the

    problem

    of

    art

    as

    knowledge

    and

    recognizing

    the

    inherent

    difficulties

    in

    this

    stance,

    Broudy

    does not

    entirely

    abandon

    the

    belief that art must serve

    some

    sort

    of

    cognitive

    function:

    . . .

    it

    is

    exceedingly

    hard to

    construe

    works

    of art

    as statements

    of

    meaning.

    But as

    objects

    of

    perception

    they

    can

    and

    often do

    express

    a

    meaning by making

    an

    image

    of some

    feeling

    or

    ideas

    or

    some

    combination

    of

    them. '8

    Broudy argues that while such expressed meanings are not assertions,

    they

    are clues

    from

    which

    assertive inferences

    may

    be

    made.

    The

    difficulty

    here

    is

    only

    delayed.

    A search for inferred assertions

    s

    no more

    clear

    or accessible

    than

    a

    search for assertions of

    meaning immediately

    given.

    Yet more

    difficult

    is

    the

    possibility,

    since inferences

    are

    by

    clues,

    of

    gross

    misinterpretation

    and an

    inference

    of

    no-meaning

    s as

    defen-

    sible

    as of

    some-feeling

    or

    some-idea.

    Most

    thorough

    in its search for

    adequate grounds

    on

    which

    to base

    an

    aesthetic

    theory

    of

    objectified

    feeling

    is the thesis

    of

    Milton

    C. Nahm.

    Nahm recasts the Kantian theory in moder behavioral terms: The

    17

    Martin

    Johnson,

    Art

    and

    Scientific

    Thought (New

    York:

    Columbia Univer-

    sity

    Press,

    1949),

    p.

    24.

    18 The

    Structure

    of

    Knowledge

    in

    the

    Arts,

    in R. A.

    Smith

    (ed.),

    Aesthetics

    and

    Criticism

    n Art

    Education

    (Chicago:

    Rand

    McNally,

    1966).

    This content downloaded from 134.76.63.66 on Fri, 26 Sep 2014 00:11:10 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    12/14

    ART AS COMMUNICABLE

    KNOWLEDGE

    125

    behavior called 'feeling' is knowledge of the nature of the stimulus. '9

    Space permits

    only

    an

    outline of certain salient features

    of

    Nahm's

    theory.

    The artist

    reproduces

    his

    feelings

    in

    the

    object,

    although

    he

    need

    not refer

    directly

    to

    the

    specific

    stimulus and

    he

    is

    most

    likely

    uncon-

    scious of

    the referent. The

    generic

    source of these

    feeling-symbols

    s

    the

    artist's

    biological

    and cultural

    past.

    In

    its

    biological, primitive

    origins

    the

    human

    mind

    held a

    structural

    potential,

    an

    emotional

    predisposition

    to

    react to its

    environment

    in a

    way

    most

    probably

    suited

    to

    insure its

    survival.

    This assumed

    nervous

    mechanism is not learned

    nor

    is

    it

    con-

    trolled

    by

    the individual. Before a stimulus, it servesto

    produce,

    rather

    to

    reproduce,

    the

    best

    biologically

    appropriate

    feeling

    response

    out

    of all

    other

    possibilities

    of

    response. Imagination

    is thus the

    organism's

    effec-

    tive

    presentation

    to

    itself

    of a

    stimulus. 20

    Moreover,

    all

    man-made

    symbols

    are

    recognitive

    and In all

    men,

    'reproductive

    imagination'

    operates

    to

    permit recognition

    of

    the

    presented

    stimuli for

    feeling. 21

    Such

    symbols

    are

    the

    perceptual recognition

    of

    an

    earlier

    knowledge

    of

    morality,

    science,

    ethics

    -

    all of the differentiated

    feeling

    responses,

    externalized as

    concrete

    expressions

    of

    man:

    By

    means

    of

    art,

    the

    maker

    actualizes

    the

    symbols

    in

    sensuous

    media.

    Those

    who

    experience

    the

    art

    actualize

    in

    their own

    experience

    the

    predisposition

    to

    action

    which,

    in its

    primitive

    form,

    is the mechanical

    reaction

    of

    organisms

    behaving

    with

    some

    appropriateness

    to

    particular

    features

    of

    their

    en-

    vironment.22

    This

    position

    removes

    the difficulties

    encountered

    in

    other

    symbolist

    theories;

    the art

    object

    appraises

    itself.

    For

    Nahm,

    the art

    object

    reappraises

    and revaluates

    man

    himself and leads him

    to

    unspecified

    ends of

    action.

    Nahm's

    psychoanalytic

    implications

    are

    evident and

    therein

    lies

    a

    familiar weakness.

    The aesthetic

    experience

    is less a

    form

    of

    self-knowledge

    than

    quite

    literally

    a neurotic

    response.

    Despite

    Nahm's claim

    that

    aesthetic

    experience

    is

    characterized

    by

    a sense of

    exaltation and

    courage

    that

    furthers

    action,

    his

    description

    of

    the

    sensation bears

    the

    qualities

    of a

    pure

    neurosis,

    uncontrolled

    and

    trig-

    gered

    by

    stimulus

    cues of

    varying strengths.

    The

    argument

    would

    not

    lose

    in

    plausibility

    by

    considering

    the

    aesthetic effect as

    a

    neurotic

    reaction to

    situations

    designed

    for

    such an

    end.

    However,

    neurotic be-

    havior cannot

    be

    ranked as

    a

    kind

    of

    knowledge,

    that

    is,

    as

    rational

    19

    Milton

    C.

    Nahm,

    Aesthetic

    Experience

    and

    Its

    Presuppositions

    (New

    York:

    Harper, 1946), p.

    355.

    20

    Ibid.,

    p.

    357.

    21

    Ibid.,

    p.

    366.

    2

    Ibid.,

    p.

    368.

    This content downloaded from 134.76.63.66 on Fri, 26 Sep 2014 00:11:10 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    13/14

  • 8/11/2019 Art as Communicable Knowledge

    14/14

    ART

    AS COMMUNICABLENOWLEDGE

    127

    conditions of the outside world. All such attempts lead ultimately to the

    conclusion

    that

    references

    which

    the

    usual

    symbols

    of

    knowledge

    must

    have are

    unknown.

    It

    may

    therefore

    be

    conjectured

    if the

    question

    of the

    nature of the

    knowledge

    represented

    by

    the fine

    arts

    may

    be

    meaning-

    fully

    asked.

    Further,

    it

    seems reasonable

    to

    query

    the

    relationship

    of the

    development

    of

    theories of

    aesthetic

    knowledge

    to the

    stylistic

    develop-

    ment

    of

    the fine

    arts.

    It

    is,

    perhaps,

    not

    accidental

    that theories of

    aesthetic

    knowledge

    become

    more

    pointed

    in

    their

    premise

    that art is

    a kind of communicable

    knowledge

    as

    the

    styles

    of

    the

    fine

    arts reach

    higher levels of abstractionaway from

    reality.

    That is, abstractand non-

    objective

    forms

    take on

    more

    the

    appearance

    of all

    symbol

    systems

    whose

    forms

    are

    arbitrarily assigned.

    In

    the

    latter case the

    meaning,

    that

    is,

    the referents of

    the

    symbols,

    are

    agreed

    to.

    In

    fine

    art,

    such forms

    are

    called

    creatively-unique

    nd

    there

    is

    no

    agreement

    as

    to their

    referents.