awylie paper

Upload: gustavo-sandoval

Post on 06-Apr-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    1/13

    1

    PHILOSOPHY FROM THE GROUND UP:

    EVIDENTIAL REASONING IN ARCHAEOLOGY

    Alison Wylie

    Barnard College, Columbia University

    Making Society, Knowing Society

    University of California, San Diego

    DRAFT: DO NOT QUOTE OR CIRCULATE

    We know a great deal about the human cultural past: about its time depth, about the trajectories by which

    humans dispersed across the globe, about the processes by which they responded to and transformed the

    environments in which they found themselves, and about the dynamics of interaction and internal

    evolution by which social and cultural forms have proliferated. And for the vast majority of human life on

    earth this body of knowledge is based entirely on archaeological data. This is something of a paradox

    when you consider how tenuous the archaeological database is, and how epistemically fraught the

    enterprise of archaeological inquiry. As one philosophically minded practitioner recently put it:

    archaeology is at once the hardest as well as the most important study of all (a modest advocate for his

    field), not just because of the inherent complexity of the human systems it studies, but because it uses

    evidence that is remote from and uncertainly coupled to the systems it seeks to study (Chippindale 2002:

    606).

    The questions I address here and elsewhere arise directly from this conundrum: how do we come to know

    (anything) about the cultural past?; what confidence should we have in our best available methods for

    producing and adjudicating archaeological knowledge claims? I begin with some background on how

    these questions have been addressed, by philosophers and by archaeologists, and then outline my answer

    to them in the form of a model of evidential reasoning. What I present here is an overview of the analysis

    developed in a series of case and issue-specific essays that appear together in Thinking from Things:

    Essays in the Philosophy of Archaeology (2002): the historical analysis that follows is elaborated in

    Section II, How New is the New Archaeology; the analysis of the interpretive dilemma is developed in

    Section III, Interpretive Dilemmas: Crisis Arguments in the New Archaeology; and details of the model

    of evidential reasoning are to be found in chapters 13, 14, and 15, in Section III (Bootstrapping in the

    Un-Natural Sciences; The Constitution of Archaeological Evidence; Rethinking Unity as a Working

    Hypothesis for Philosophy of Science: How Archaeologists Exploit the Disunities of Science).

    Philosophical Questions in and about Archaeology

    Periodically epistemic questions raised by and about archaeology have attracted the attention of

    philosophers. Hempel considers the tacit dependence of archaeological inference on laws in dating

    archaeological materials at the end of The Function of General Laws in History (1942: 48) and

    philosophers of the life and earth sciencesspecially those concerned with evolutionary

    theorizingperiodically consider the structure and limitations of historical inference based on the

    archaeological record: e.g., Toulmin and Goodfield on the formation of contemporary horizons of

    geological and historical time inDiscovery of Time (1965); Wimsatts recent work on models of

    generative systems; Tuckers consideration of biological and historical patterns of inference in Our

    Knowledge of the Past(2004). Examples of more systematic analysis of archaeological inquiry include, in

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    2/13

    2

    the 19th century, Whewells treatment of the strategies of inference typical of comparative archaeology,

    which he took to be an example of the palaetiological sciences: the sciences which deal with objects

    that are descended from a more ancient condition, from which the present is derived by intelligible

    causes (Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences 1967 [1840]: 637). And in the interwar period, mid-20th

    century, Collingwood frequently relied on examples of archaeological inference in analysis of the logic of

    historical (question-and-answer) reasoning in The Idea of History (1946: Epilogomena), and he makes

    explicit a number of philosophical lessons that he attributes to archaeological field experience inAnAutobiography (1939). Most dramatically, since the 1970s, analytic philosophy of archaeology (M.

    Salmon) or meta-archaeology (Embree) has become something of a cottage industry, spurred by the

    philosophical provocations of the New Archaeology. More of this shortly.

    For archaeologists, anxiety about the proxy status of material evidencequestions about how

    archaeological data can (best) be used as evidence of a cultural pasthas been a matter of intense and

    perennial concern from the time the field began to professionalize and take root in museums and

    universities in the late 19th century. The underlying issues here are manifestly philosophical and, indeed,

    archaeologists have periodically turned to philosophy for epistemic insight and reassuranceespecially

    when engaged in crisis debates that have erupted, by my estimation, every 20 to 30 years since the early

    20th century. At the core of these recurrent debates is a worry that the fragmentary, enigmatic nature of the

    material record generates an interpretive dilemma that imposes absolute limits on archaeologicalinquiry. This dilemma arises from the pessimistic appraisal that interesting claims about the cultural past

    inevitably extend beyond what can be securely established on the basis of the archaeological record. If

    this premise is accepted, so the argument goes, archaeologists have just two options. If they are

    committed to ideals of epistemic responsibility, they must confine themselves to the pursuit of narrowly

    descriptive goals, documenting the contents of the archaeological record: this is the narrow empiricist

    horn of the dilemma. But if they are committed to anthropological, historical goals, they must be prepared

    to embrace the speculative horn of the dilemma; archaeological narratives may be captivating and richly

    grounded in archaeological data but they are, at best, forms of aesthetic appreciation and, at worst,

    projections of our own expectations and preoccupations in the form of just-so stories. Those who treat

    these options as mutually exclusive and exhaustiveas genuinely dilemmictypically rely on two further

    presuppositions: that the connections between surviving material evidence and antecedent events or

    conditions are (all equally / extremely) tenuous; and that the bar for epistemic responsibility in a field likearchaeology should be set extremely high.

    The locus classicus for such an argument is a widely cited discussion note published in the British

    Archaeological Newsletter in 1955 by a field archaeologist, M.A. Smith. She insisted that there is no

    logical relation between the social, cultural past and its surviving record, by which she seems to mean no

    relation of deductive entailment; archaeological interpretation incorporates an irreducible element of

    conjecture which cannot be tested (e.g., Smith 1955: 4-5). Consequently, the Diogenes problem, as she

    describes it, is inescapable: archaeologists may find the tub but altogether miss Diogenes (1955: 1-2),

    and may have no way of ever knowing what theyre missing. What begins as a problem of contingent

    underdetermination is thus generalized; the potential for pervasive and undetectable error is inferred from

    specific instances of error fortuitously detected or counterfactually projected. A domain-wide (if not

    wholesale) skepticism is thus inescapable; the only alternative to irresponsible speculation is anarchaeology defined by severely curtailed ambitions.

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    3/13

    3

    Archaeological Responses to the Interpretive Dilemma

    This interpretive dilemma has generated three recurrent strategies of response, three methodological

    stances that have taken shape in response to crisis debate within archaeology: sequent stage,

    constructivist, and integrationist approaches to inquiry.

    Sequent stage approaches. These were embraced by optimistic conservatives who insist that epistemicallyresponsible archaeologists must eschew any form of (premature) theoretical speculation about the cultural

    past. Their first priority should be to explore the archaeological record, to collect and systematize

    archaeological data which they see, not as an end in itself, but as a necessary first stepa matter of

    establishing a secure empirical foundation before venturing historical or anthropological hypotheses. As

    one sardonic pair of commentators observed, theorizing is thus deferred until a future Darwin of

    Anthropology appears on the scene who can interpret the great historical scheme that will have been

    erected(Steward and Setlzer 1938: 3)

    Initially, in the WWI era, advocates of this epistemic stance argued that that archaeologists should just get

    on with the discovery and documentation of the archaeological record. Systematic empirical research and

    theorizing are starkly opposed. Indeed, a preoccupation with the latter (which includes interpretive

    inference about the cultural past as well as reflexive debate about archaeological practice), threatens toinduce a methodological paralysis: a Hamletic state of mind not wholesome in pushing on active

    research work as Dixon put it in 1913 (p. 577). The epistemic rationale for this deferral of theory was

    articulated a decade later, when Taylor (from whom I get the term sequent stage) argued that

    archaeology is no more than a method or set of specialized techniques for the gathering of cultural

    information; its purpose is to establish the foundation for a roughly...sequential series of stages,

    beginning with data collection, analysis and chronological synthesis, then moving on to chronological

    and ethnographic reconstruction, finally culminating in the anthropological study of culture as such (its

    dynamics and statics, nature and workings; Taylor 1948).

    Constructivism. From the early 20th century (1908-1917) critics of sequent stage approaches have

    objected that no interpretively or theoretically innocent investigation of the record is possible, either as a

    necessary preliminary or as an end in itself. Inevitably, the identification of material as archaeological,much less the construction of chronological sequences and regional/cultural typological schemes, requires

    substantial interpretive inference beyond description of the material contents of the record. And even if

    interpretively neutral description of the contents of the archaeological record was possible, it could not be

    counted on to yield the kinds of data base that archaeologists will require when they turn to

    anthropological and historical questions about the cultural past.

    One response to such arguments was to circumscribe this threat of insecurity. British contemporaries of

    Smiths argued that the intractable ambiguities she notes chiefly afflict inferences concerning belief

    systems, religious convictions, abstract social norms. In fact, archaeologists can quite reliably reconstruct

    technology and physical environment, some aspects of subsistence practice, perhaps some limited

    dimensions of social organization (as necessary conditions for technology/subsistence); they should focus

    on these dimensions of the cultural past and eschew speculation about the rest. The result was a schematicladder of inference advocated in the 1950s by Hawkes and Piggott (1954).

    A quite different, explicitly pragmatist and in some cases subjectivist response took the form of

    arguments that archaeologists should give up the quest for interest and problem-neutral empirical

    foundations, acknowledge the inherent limitations of archaeological inquiry and make explicit its

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    4/13

    4

    presuppositions. In this spirit archaeologists working the U.S. American southeast argued (initially with

    reference to ceramic typologies) that classificatory systems are merely tools, tools of analysis,

    manufactured and employed by students (Brew 1946); they do not capture culturally meaningful reality

    but rather serve specific purposes, e.g., establishing chronological control (Ford 1954). In a more

    explicitly subjectivist version of this argument, an archaeologist working in the U.S. southwest (evidently

    influenced by Dewey) argued that ascriptions of function to archaeological material depend on analogical

    comparisons that incorporate an irreducibly subjective element. Ultimately, assessments of theepistemic credibility of interpretive inference depends on judgements of professional competence;

    archaeologists have no alternative but to invoke a convergence of trained and expert intuition (e.g.,

    Thompson 1956).

    Integrationist approaches. A third strategy of response is evident in recurrent demands for a new

    departure, for a New Archaeology, motivated by concern that sequent stage and constructivist options

    typically revert to one or the other horn of the original interpetive dilemma. By mid-century (1930s-

    1950s) anthropological archaeologists had accumulated enormous stores of data and were constructing an

    elaborate edifice of chronological sequences and typological schemes but, impatient critics objected, this

    increasingly rich and finely systematized empirical foundation showed little promise of delivering any

    significant historical or anthropological understanding of the cultural past. The constructivist and

    pragmatist responses of the 1950s offer little more than capitulation to the speculative horn of thedilemma; all that constrains speculation is a reliance on convention, on now made explicit in procedures

    that critics vilified as a matter of pooling practitioners.

    Although the underlying epistemological argument is almost never explicit, the conviction that there must

    be a third way, an alternative that escapes the dilemma, derives from an intuition that it should be possible

    to integrate in archaeological inquiry the theorizing necessary to identify and interpret archaeological

    data as evidence, and to make it empirically and conceptually accountable. The earliest call for a New

    Archaeology, in 1907-1918, was intended to displace the woefully haphazard and uncoordinated

    practices of antequarianism (Dixon 1913). For these advocates of a newly professional archaeology, the

    chief characteristic of self-consciously anthropological and scientific practice is an interest not in

    specimens but rather in the relations of things, with the whens and the whys and the hows (Dixon

    1913: 565). Most important, they insisted that these ambitious goals could not be deferred if they wereever to be realized: the mere collecting of curious and expensive objects once used by man is impotent

    to answer the...questions we are all interested in, viz., anthropological, historical questions proper to the

    science of man (Wissler 1917: 100). What is required, Wissler declared in 1917, is a real, new

    archaeology: an archaeology informed by a reasoned formulation of definite problems and predicated

    on commitment to saner more truly scientific methods (1913: 563). These Dixon described in quite

    generic terms, invoking Chamberlins (1890) discussion of the method of multiple working hypotheses:

    If there are gaps in the evidence, why not make a systematic attempt to fill them? On the basis of

    evidence at hand a working hypothesis or several alternative hypotheses may be framed, and

    material sought which shall either prove or disprove them. (Dixon 1913: 564)

    By the 1930s-1940s the target of criticism was not so much non-archaeological (antequarian) forms ofpractice, but an established tradition of professional archaeology characterized by commitment to a

    sequent stage approach. In the era of the WPA, anthropological archaeologists were chiefly concerned

    with bringing some order to the immense body of data generated by large scale, multi-year excavation

    projects on some of the richest sites in North America. At this point a philosophical rationale was

    articulated for insisting that historical and anthropological theorizing could not be deferred, as a series of

    epistemic arguments for problem-oriented research, as it was later described. In an article that appeared in

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    5/13

    5

    Philosophy of Science in 1939, Kluckhohn objected to the influence in archaeology of what he identifies

    as a narrow empiricism: a simpliste mechanistic-positivistic philosophy (1940: 46) according to

    which some form of empirical datum is presumed to be the source and foundation of all legitimate

    knowledge, to exhaust its cognitive content. This, he argues, makes a mockery of physics and other

    theoretically sophisticated forms of natural science, and cannot be a reasonable guide to archaeological

    practice. Anticipating Kuhn and Hanson by two decades, Kluckhohn argues that archaeologists do not

    have the option of establishing the archaeological facts first, before they venture interpretive/explanatoryhypotheses: no fact has meaning except in the context of a conceptual scheme (1940: 47), a theme

    elaborated a few years later by Bennett in the context of an archaeological debate about typological

    schemes. No sense can be made of the notion of 'fact' [as] a phenomenological datum, Bennett argued

    (1946: 198); what constitutes a fact or a classification is a relative affair determined entirely by the

    problem at hand (1946: 200). Consequently, attempts at systematization that purport to be empirically

    driven and interpretively neutral should be viewed with suspicion. They are abstractions...really bundles

    of testable hypotheses about the nature of correspondence of cultural objects to the dynamic

    culture-historical pattern which bore them (Bennett 1946: 200); as such, they depend on rich, problem-

    specific presuppositions that are simply unacknowledged. As Kluckhohn put this point,

    The alternative is not...between theory and no theory or a minimum of theory, but between adequate

    and inadequate theories, and, even more important, between theories, the postulates and propositions

    of which are conscious and hence lend themselves to systematic criticism, and theories the premisesof which have not been examined even by their formulators. (1939: 330)

    In the same period, in the context of British archaeology/philosophy of history, Collingwood made

    parallel case for problem-oriented, theoretically informed research:

    Long practice in excavation had taught me that one conditionindeed the most important

    conditionof success was that the person responsible for any piece of digging, however small

    and however large, should know exactly what he wants to find out, and then decide what kind

    of digging will show it to him. This was the central principle of my logic of question and

    answer as applied to archaeology. (1978 [1946]: 121-122)

    The most strident and ambitious of these New Archaeologies burst on the scene in 1960s and 1970s, its

    advocates arguing strenuously against the bankruptcy, not just of an antequarian preoccupation with

    collecting archaeological material, or a typological preoccupation with systematizing archaeological data,but of culture history: a preoccupation with reconstructive goals in the form of covert systematization,

    or cautious interpretive reconstruction of the material aspects of the cultural past (in the spirit of the

    Hawkes/Piggott ladder of inference). They argued that the limitations of traditional archaeology lie, not

    in the archaeological record, but in what archaeologists bring to inquiry by way of interpretive resources,

    and they rejected the presupposition, underlying both sequent stage and constructivist approaches, that

    archaeologists can only proceed inductively, generating interpretive hypotheses after the fact, as

    (speculative) conclusions. The alternative they proposed was that archaeologists should make the most

    ambitious anthropological problems the primary and immediate focus of their research, and the problems

    to which they gave prioritythe problems appropriate to a properly scientific archaeologywere broadly

    processual: cultural systems should be understood in adaptationist, eco-materialist terms, with the aim

    of establishing universal (nomological) laws of cultural process (the interdependence of system

    components; patterns of response to environmental conditions; dynamics of internal evolution).

    To realize these processual goals, the New Archaeologists argued for a rigorously problem-oriented

    form of practice: theorizing about culture process should be the point of departure for inquiry, rather than

    a deferred later stage, and all aspects of archaeological inquiry should be designed as a matter of testing

    explanatory, interpretive hypotheses against the archaeological record. They invoked Hempels

    hypothetico-deductive (H-D) of confirmation and insisted that the insecurity of venturing claims about the

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    6/13

    6

    cultural past could be eliminated only if their credibility was assessed, not in terms of inductive support

    generated in the process of their formulation (in a context of discovery) but, rather, in terms of their

    success surviving rigorous archaeological testing (in a context of verification). They particularly objected

    to reliance on analogical reasoning and were confident, more generally, that a systematic process of

    deductive testing could supplant reliance on all forms of inductive speculation. When they considered the

    vagaries of establishing what Fritz refers to as observations of the past (1972)the empirical basis for

    testing presumptive laws and hypothesesthey turn again to Hempel for inspiration. The significance ofarchaeological data as material traces of specific past conditions was to be established by law-governed

    retrodiction, on the model of covering-law (D-N) explanation.

    The reaction against this self-consciously positivist rhetoric and research program was swift and deeply

    factionalizing. Both internal archaeological critics and external philosophical commentators invoked

    arguments from postpositivist philosophy of scienceunderdetermination, holism and, most prominently,

    the theory-ladenness of evidenceto make the case that the insecurities of inference that gave rise to

    worries about post-hoc reconstructive inference equally afflict the use of archaeological data as test

    evidence; deductive certainty is almost never realized in drawing test implications, let alone in the

    confirming or disconfirming inferences by which archaeological data are brought to bear on a test

    hypothesis. Biconditional laws establish secure linkages in a vanishingly few cases: although Peircean

    references never figure in these debates, the point here is that archaeological inference is a matter ofabduction (not induction in the narrow sense, and certainly not deduction)

    The most outspoken post- or anti-processual critics of the New Archaeology advocated a stance of ironic

    dissociation from the enterprise as a whole. Some insisted that an uncrompomising constructivism is

    inescapable, now reframed in explicitly social (and political) terms. In this spirit, Hodder argues that the

    ascription of significance to archaeological data depends on interpretive principles that are nothing but

    disciplinary conventions. Archaeologists must therefore be understood to "create facts" (1983b: 6; see

    also 1984a); there is "literally nothing independent of theory or propositions to test against" (Shanks and

    Tilley 1987: 111). By extension of such arguments, some post-processual archaeologists have been

    prepared to embrace what they idenitify as a radical pluralism according to which "any interpretation of

    the past is multiple and constantly open to change, to re-evaluation, as stance described by one

    sympathetic critic as a self-defeating hyperrelativism (Trigger 1989). In elaborating these arguments,post-processuals have turned to philosophical hermeneutics, phenomenology, the frank ethnocentrism of

    Rorty-style pragmatism, and the deconstructive, postmodern descendants of these traditions for

    inspiration in articulating a resolutely humanistic, anti-scientific counter-tradition of interpretive

    archaeology (Hodder 1991, 1999).

    This broadly pluralist, constructivist epistemic stance was reinforced by challenges to the explanatory

    commitments of the new Archaeology. Post-processual critics rallied compelling ethnohistoric and

    archaeological evidence that the most inscrutable dimensions of the pastthe cultural lifeworld and all

    the beliefs and intentions, power dynamics and exercises of agency that make it upcannot be set aside as

    causally, explanatorily irrelevant, in preference for analysis of eco-system dynamics. Hodder was

    particularly influential in arguing that it is imperative for archaeologists to attend to the insides of

    action (invoking Collingwood; Hodder 1982a,b; 1983a); these less tangible dimensions of cultural lifecan be consequential in shaping the large-scale structure of cultural systems and the long-term processes

    by which they adapt to or transform their material environments. Post-processuals also add to these joint

    epistemic and ontological considerations a further normative, political argument: that, in a world riven by

    increasingly stark inequalities and structured by deeply entrenched systems of oppression, in a world in

    which strategic manipulation of the past frequently serves the purpose of legitimating the claims of the

    elites that benefit from these conditions, archaeologists should tell the stories (about the past) that need to

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    7/13

    7

    be told (e.g., Hodder 1983b). With the formulation of this antithesis to the positivism of the New

    Archaeologya position which struck even sympathetic their critics as a reductio of post-

    processualismthe dynamic of the interpretive dilemma reasserted itself in particularly stark terms.

    Frustrated by seemingly intractable and increasingly polarized debate, and fed up with philosophy-heavy

    programmatic arguments that had little bearing on the actual doing of archaeology, a great many

    practitioners backed away from both extremes, declaring a plague on both houses and sometimes a plagueon philosophy. In the early to mid-1980s, when the lines of debate were most sharply drawn, a number of

    ironic, sharply critical commentaries appeared with titles like Is a Little Philosophy (Science?) a

    Dangerous Thing? (Plog 1982) and Plumbing, Philosophy, and Poetry (Fitting 1973). One especially

    influential example of the genre, Flannerys Golden Marshalltown (1982), offered a sharply satirical

    caricature in which the philosophizing classes in archaeology are vilified as a species of self-satisfied

    sports commentator who has long since lost touch with the gritty realities of the play.

    In the last ten to fifteen years, however, most archaeological practitioners have been quietly exploring

    hybrid modes of inquiry that embody the most promising, practicable aspects of processual testing

    procedures, now applied to the range of interpretive problems endorsed by postprocessuals; Hegmon

    describes them as a loose-knit cluster of research programs that she characterizes as processual+

    archaeology (2003). Although disengaged from theoretical, philosophical debate, these archaeologists aremindful of the uncertainties of the forms of inference on which they rely but are unconvinced that this

    entails anything like the scope or degree of disabling circularity required to establish that the speculative

    horn of the dilemma is inescapable. This stance seems informed by a practical appreciation that the

    archaeological record routinely demonstrates a capacity to subvert expectations, to impose empirical

    constraints on archaeological theorizing, despite being thoroughly a construct. And, in fact, archaeologists

    of all philosophical stripesprocessual and postprocessual alikevery effectively deploy these constraints,

    relying on localized strategies for building and adjudicating evidential claims that warrant epistemic

    confidence even if they rarely deliver the kinds of certainty for which archaeological skeptics and

    reformers have periodically hankered. In this, I would argue, archaeologists often escape the horns of the

    interpretive dilemma even if epistemic insights embodied in the know-how that makes this possible are

    rarely explicit.

    Evidential Reasoning in Archaeology

    My aim has been to develop a model of evidential reasoning that captures the principles implicit in the

    hybrid strategies of inference that taken shape in archaeological practice below the threshold of

    philosophical debate. That is to say, I am concerned to articulate the epistemic rationale for a discerning

    confidence in judgements of evidential significance that reduce neither to an untenable narrow

    empiricism nor to mere speculation. The central intuition embodied in this practice is that evidential

    reasoning in archaeology is differentially insecure. More specifically, the types and degrees of insecurity

    with which archaeologists grapple are a function of characteristics of the inferences linking surviving

    traces to antecedent conditions; they are not determined by characteristics of the target domain; they do

    not necessarily track the domain-specific categories of epistemic risk set out in inference schemes like theHawkes/Piggott ladder.

    The key to understanding nuanced judgements of differential security/insecurity in archaeological

    inference is, first, to disambiguate what counts as the theory (or theorizing) that is said to laden,

    overreach, or render insecure any use of archaeological data as evidence. Virtually any belief or

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    8/13

    8

    knowledge claim can mediate archaeological inference, from the most narrowly specified empirical fact

    through to the most expansive explanatory schema, from the convictions of common sense to esoteric

    insights of nuclear physics, from claims established within archaeology to those supplied not only by its

    closest neighbor disciplines but also by an expansive range of social, life, and natural sciences. Whether a

    given claim is theory in the sense of theorizing about the cultural past, or theory in the mediating

    sense of middle range theory (which is to say, linking principles, auxiliary hypotheses, gap-crossers), is

    determined not by its content or its target but by the role it plays in the specific inference at hand.

    Second, the threat of vicious circularity arises only if an implausibly seamless holism is assumed. In

    practice, the many different kinds of theory that play functionally different roles in archaeological

    inference are often disjoint in epistemically consequential ways.

    Third is a point I will not develop here but that informs my analysis of evidential reasoning; I recommend

    a shift in the focus of philosophical analysis from theorizing to modeling, along lines of that proposed

    more generally by Morgan and Morrison (1999). What archaeologists build and test are typically models,

    not isolated factual claims or systems of logically interdependent laws/law-like propositions. In some

    cases these are models of particular past activities or events that could have produced, or likely did

    produce, specific elements of the archaeological record; in other cases they are models of large-scale and

    long-term socio-cultural dynamics. Archaeologists use models at one scale, or models of one dimensionof a cultural system, to test models pitched at other scales/other dimensions. Claims about evidential

    significance are typically claims about the credibility of a model component, itself a narrowly specified

    model of some aspect of the past cultural context or process or system under study.

    Focusing on the first two points, here are three sets of principles that underpin the ways in which

    archaeologists exploit disjunctions between the various kinds of theory they deploy, to good epistemic

    effect.

    Vertical independence. The worry informing constructivist challenges, from Thompsons subjectivism to

    the hyperrelativism associated with post-processual critics of the New Archaeology, is that the middle

    range theory on which archaeologists rely to interpret their data as evidence simply mediates an

    imposition on these data of the expectations of their test hypotheses. Under what conditions is such athreat of circularity realized? The classic case, considered in some detail by Glymour in connection with

    his bootstrapping account of confirmation, is one in which the target hyptheses and the mediating

    auxiliary hypotheses are integrated into a single coherent theoretical framework. But even in this case, he

    argues, vicious circularity is not inevitable. Evidence can bootstrap-confirm a theory if, using the theory,

    we can deduce from the evidence an instance of hypothesis...and the deduction is such that it does not

    guarantee that we would have gotten an instance of the hypothesis regardless of what the evidence might

    have been (1980:127). What distinguishes virtuous from vicious circularity is the structure of relations

    that hold between the components of the encompassing theory, not the fact that they are both components

    of this theory. If the internal structure of the theory is such that the mediating hypothesis provides an

    algorithm for interpreting experimental results but does not determine that they will confirm to the

    expectations of the test hypothesisit may well be possible to use one component of an overarching

    theory to interpret data as evidence that provides a genuine test of another component of the theory.

    In practice, however, archaeologists rarely have available to them a theory so comprehensive that it

    provides all the resources they need both to generate and to test hypotheses about the cultural past.

    Typically they draw interpretive resources from widely disparate fields, many of which have little to do

    with the sources that inform their thinking about the social structures and cultural dynamics of the past

    cultures they investigate. In short, the theory that ladens their data is very often unconnected to the

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    9/13

    9

    theory that informs the reconstructive/explanatory hypotheses they are intent on testing. Consider a

    hypothetical example that figured in the debate between New Archaeologists and their imagined

    adversaries, traditional archaeologists: a case in which an archaeologist posits an hypothesis about trade

    between two distant and otherwise distinct cultural groups, separated by a wide geographical margin in

    which no evidence of a common record has been found (Binfords Allchin hypothesis; 1968: 18-19).

    Perhaps this hypothesis is inspired by structuralist analysis of the grammar of design traditions evident in

    the burial goods and elite ceramics characteristic of these two prehistoric communities. An archaeologistmight rely on radiocarbon dating and various types of materials analysis to determine whether it is

    possible that the artifacts thought to have been traded into one context could have originated in the other:

    whether it is contemporaneous and whether it is made of materials or by means of technologies possessed

    by the source culture. Although each of these lines of evidence is liable to error of various kinds, these are

    not likely to be a function of nepotism; there is no obvious (or likely) interdependence between the

    chemistry and the physics required to establish the source and the dates of the archaeological material, on

    one hand, and the linguistics and socio-cultural anthropology presupposed by the test hypothesis, on the

    other.

    Security. These lines of evidence vary greatly in degree of security and are each individually subject to

    empirical and conceptual constraint. Contra Hodders most extreme constructivist claims (or, indeed,

    Thompsons subjectivism), the linking principles on which archaeologists typically rely are by no meansstrictly conventional (subjective) heuristics. In fact, archaeologists put a great deal of emphasis on

    adjudicating the credibility and the relevance of the linking principles on which they rely, and they do this

    on several dimensions: the credibility of these principles in their source contexts; the degree to which they

    establish deterministic linkages between surviving archaeological traces and the past conditions or events

    of which they are taken to be evidence; and the overall length and complexity of the inferential chains in

    which specific inferential links are embedded (Kosso 2001). Because external sources do not offer the

    requisite linking principles in many key areas, archaeologists have developed research programs designed

    to identify the kinds of archaeological signature associated with specific human activities or social

    arrangements (ethnoarchaeology), to establish the forms of practice, technical knowledge, and resources

    required to produce specific kinds of archaeological material (experimental archaeology), and to

    characterize the patterns of differential survival and/or disturbance that can be expected under specific

    kinds of geological and other conditions of preservation.

    The New Archaeologists have been especially strong advocates of systematic, empirical source-side

    research along these lines, but with the aim of establishing a body of middle range theory that

    approximates the Hempelian ideal of covering laws, capable of supporting deductive retrodictions from

    the surviving record to past events and conditions. This requires not only nomological but biconditional

    laws (absolute security in the first and second sense), applicable without recourse to any other auxiliary

    assumptions (minimizing the length and complexity of inferential chains)a standard that is almost never

    met in practice. The most promising examples are methods of absolute dating (e.g., radiocarbon dating),

    geological sourcing, the use of non-radioactive isotope analysis to determine lifetime dietary profile. But

    even in these best cases, of which radiocarbon dating was expected to be the paradigm, the vagaries of

    confounding factors are legendary. The linking principles drawn from the physics may be unimpeachable

    and may meet the requirement of determinism, establishing a unique causal event that must have obtainedfor the trace to have been produced. But the causal chains are long and complex, as reflected in the risks

    of contamination in the preservation and recovery of samples, the complications introduced by carbon

    sinks and differential rates of carbon fixing that establish proportion of radioactive C14 to stable C12 and

    C13 in the original production of the trace, and the impact of fossil fuel and bomb effects on the baseline

    ratios of C14 to C12 and C13 in the atmosphere. Moreover, even with significant refinements in the

    background knowledge of these physical processes, the difficulty remains that the auxiliaries drawn from

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    10/13

    10

    physics and biochemistry typically establish archaeologically relevant facts about the cultural past only

    given inferences and assumptions about a number of other aspects of the archaeological context. They

    may allow archaeologists to determine the cutting date of a piece of building timber but determining a

    construction sequence from a dated sample depends on collateral evidence that rules our (or indicates)

    practices of curation or reuse; it may be possible to determine the chemical composition of bone

    recovered from a burial, but reconstructing diet from these isotope values requires paleobotanical

    information about the resources actually available, and evidence of subsistence practices that specifieswhich resources were exploited by an archaeological population.

    Typically assessments of security do not and, indeed, cannot proceed on a trace-by-trace, auxiliary-by-

    auxiliary basis. Rather, they depend on a complex process of evaluating multiply connected (relational)

    analogical arguments in which insights from diverse sources are integrated into a model (or multiple

    models) of the archaeological context. I have argued that the strength of analogical inference can be

    assessed on two dimensions (1985; Chapter 9, 2002): in terms of the completeness of fit between source

    and subject, or by appeal to the persistence of association between a limited subset of attributes across

    sources that differ in other respects. In both cases empirical investigation of the sources of a proposed

    analog is required; supporting evidenceof comprehensive similarity or of robust correlationsuggests

    that the association between observed and inferred attributes is non-accidental, the consequence of a

    determining structure that may be causal, functional, intentional, symbolic (to use terminology fromWeitzenfeld 1984). And in both cases the strength of the analogy requires, as well, subject-side

    investigation to determine whether the interdependence between analogically linked attributes could have

    obtained, or the mechanism of production posited for a specific trace could have been instantiated, in a

    particular archaeological subject.

    Ironically, although the New Archaeologists staunchly opposed reliance on analogical inference in any

    capacity other than as a creative source of hypotheses, their own practice illustrates with particular clarity

    how this process of adjudicating security proceeds with respect to analogical inference, on both the source

    and the subject side of the inferential equation. Hills and Longacres research at Carter Ranch and

    Broken K pueblos in the 1970s was designed to test hypotheses about the dynamics of population

    decrease and aggregation that led to widespread abandonment of pueblos after AD 1300 (Hill 1966, 1970;

    Longacre 1964, 1970). They hypothesized that, in the pre-abandonment period, the population offormerly distinct pueblos that aggregated in the few viable pueblos (near reliable water sources) would

    have retained their social distinctness, and they suggested that this should be evident in stylistically

    distinct ceramic traditions associated with enclaves of affiliated households. They drew on ethnohistoric

    accounts of post-contact pueblo social organization for a model of the functions served by four distinct

    types of pueblo room they found clustered in what they hypothesized were distinct households, and for a

    model of ceramic production by women in generationally stable, matrilocal kin groups that they thought

    might be associated with socially distinct groups occupying these spatially segregated clusters of rooms.

    The first of thesethe model of room functionsdepends on an argument from completeness of mapping,

    and the second on appeal to a binding mechanism of social interaction that, if it obtained, would account

    for a persistent association of distinctive design elements. They tested the room function hypothesis by

    checking for evidence (not initially considered in distinguishing the room types) that should be present if

    the formally distinct rooms were, in fact, used differentially for storage, food processing and generalliving activities, and ritual practice. And they tested the implication that spatially distinct clusters of these

    rooms were associated with distinct social groups by analyzing the spatial distribution and correlation of

    design elements.

    Their tests of the room function hypothesis generated not just corroboration of the posited functions, but

    also intriguing points of divergence from the ethnographic model of, for example, storage uses and food

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    11/13

    11

    preparation activities. They found a much greater preponderance of wild plant material relative to

    cultigens than had been documented for ethnohistoric pueblos, suggesting a partial reversion to foraging

    subsistence practices among still sedentary pueblo communities early in the volatile process of pueblo

    aggregation and abandonment. Although the analysis of ceramic design seemed initially to establish the

    existence of several socially distinct residential units, subsequent ethnohistoric research on the dynamics

    of apprenticeship and diffusion of design in face-to-face communities of producers who use the ceramics

    they produce (in the U.S., southwest and in the Philippines) called these results into question. Evidentlythe aspects of ceramic design that diffuse most rapidly and widely are isolated design elements; it is the

    integrity of the larger structure, the grammar of the design that is conserved in local working groups. In

    this case the posit of a binding mechanism was challenged not archaeologically, but on the basis of

    ethnographic and social-psychological (source-side) research designed to evaluate the background

    assumptions by which archaeological data was interpreted as evidence.

    Cases of this kind make it clear that there is much to be gained from systematic empirical evaluation of

    the credibility and scope of linking principles imported from diverse and sometimes distant sources. But

    typically security is assessed through a process of building, refining, and testing the credibility of the

    analogical inferences by playing constraints elicited from source contexts off against constraints elicited

    from the subject. And in this case the source-side considerations that play a role in developing models of

    the cultural pastconventionally, the context of discoverydo bear significantly on judgements about theinferential security of the resulting models; evidential support (security) does not arise exclusively (in the

    context of verification) from archaeological testing.

    Horizontal independence. These examples also draw attention to ways in which the fragmentary,

    incomplete nature of the material record can be a crucial epistemic resource, although it is typically seen

    as a crippling liability for archaeology. Even though no one line of evidence is absolutely secure, when

    archaeologists rely on multiple lines of evidence, in combination they can provide more than simply

    additive increments in empirical credibility when they converge in support of a particular model or set of

    claims about the cultural past. Archaeologists typically deal in cables rather than chains of inference

    (1989; Chapter 11, 2002).

    The central principles here have been articulated in a number of philosophical contexts: by Wimsatt onvarieties of evidence (1987); by Shapere in reflection on what it means to say we observe events at the

    center of the sun (1982, 1985); by Hacking in analysis of why it is that we believe what we see through

    microscopes (1983). Take Hackings account as a point of departure. The credibility of indirect systems

    for observing entities or events that are otherwise inaccessible depends not only our ability to calibrate

    these systems internally (by refining background knowledge about the nature and complexity of the

    signal itself, how it is generated, transmitted, and detected), but also on the possibility of exploiting

    different causal systemsdifferent processes of signal production, transmission, detectionto produce an

    image of the target. The great value of the proliferation of microscopes that Hacking considerse.g.,

    acoustic as opposed to optical microscopesis that they allow for a triangulation of signals, correcting and

    enhancing the information any one microscope could provide about the entities they allow us to observe.

    We believe what we see because it is implausible that images produced by such different means should

    converge as a consequence of confounding influences that generate compensating error in each distinctline of evidence. And when multiple lines of evidence fail to converge, they have a capacity to expose

    error that might not be detected in assessment of the security of each taken on its own (see Shapere 1982

    on error detection).

    The closest counterpart in archaeology is, perhaps, the use of multiple dating techniques. Consider the

    juxtaposition of tree ring counts and measures of radio-carbon decay, magnetic orientation, and the

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    12/13

  • 8/3/2019 AWylie Paper

    13/13

    13

    fundamentally different impact on the historians, as opposed to the archaeologists, who study the

    operations of various colonial powers in the Americas. Nor is it plausible that historians would have

    escaped the influence of the racialist assumptions that Trigger finds deeply influential in archaeological

    thinking about contact period interactions between Europeans and First Nations. Trigger is as sharply

    critical of the romanticism that renders indigenous people non-strategic agents, bound by static

    convention, as he is of explicitly racist assumptions of manifest destiny essentialism that this

    romanticism was meant to displace (1980, 1991). Feminist critics draw attention to myriad ways in whichpractitioners across the social and historical sciences reproduce a common stock of gender-normative

    assumptions, despite using very different kinds of data bases and research tools; they consistently

    overlook or misinterpret aspects of their subject that are incongruous (unpalatable or unrecognizable)

    given a conviction that familiar binaries and role conventions capture a natural, universal fact about

    human society.

    In short, appearances of disciplinary and conceptual independence may be deceiving. Disciplinary

    boundaries may not cut the world at its joints where the causal production of apparently distinct traces are

    concerned, and may not insulate neighboring disciplines from the influence of assumptions that are

    capable of inducing compensatory errors even when causal independence can be assumed. This should

    not be taken as a counsel of (epistemic) despair, however. The vagaries of establishing epistemic

    independence make it clear that archaeological inference is unavoidably insecure but this does not, initself, return us to the speculative horn of the interpretive dilemma.

    Conclusions

    My thesis is that strategies for assessing epistemic independence are crucial in making effective use of

    limited evidence to establish credible claims about the cultural past that escape the narrow confines of the

    interpretive dilemma. And the analysis developed here suggests that two lines of inquiry are necessary

    determine whether epistemic independence is realized in any given case. One is a matter of first order

    empirical research designed to establish the extent to which the processes that generate different kinds of

    trace or, more broadly, lines of evidence are, in fact, causally independentof one another; this is one key

    component of appraisals of the security of individual lines of evidence. A second quite different line ofinquiry is required to determine whether the background of technical expertise, empirical and theoretical

    knowledge that makes it possible to detect and interpret these traces as evidence are, in fact, conceptually

    independent. This is a program of second order, meta-scientific investigation, philosophical and

    social/historical, designed to trace confounding interactions between disciplinary traditions,

    systematically appraising the proxies for epistemic independence on which practitioners typically rely.

    This suggests that the philosophical study of science must be socially and historically naturalized. Even

    such a core epistemic concept as that of evidence and how it functions as a contingent platform for

    mediating controversy, cannot succeed without attention to the histories of disciplinary practice, their

    institutional settings, their patterns of interaction and communication. It also suggests that a jointly

    philosophical and historical/social program of science studies has an important on-going role to play

    within the sciences; it provides the resources to establish what Harding describes as strong objectivity. Itsvalue is not just that it promises more sophisticated, probative philosophical understanding of the sciences

    but that, in the best tradition of American pragmatism, it has the potential to address forward-looking

    questions about how to improve our best going practices of empirical inquiry, a task for which the stakes

    are much larger than the purely philosophical.