bubbio - met a philosophical reflections on theism and atheism in the current debate

Upload: diego-bubbio

Post on 06-Apr-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    1/28

    12Metaphilosophical reflections on theism

    and atheism in the current debatePaolo Diego Bubbio

    I. New atheism and new theismIn the last few years, philosophy of religion has increasingly become a

    subject of dispute. Two positions seem to be the most popular. On the

    one hand, outspoken atheists reject religion in the name of reason and

    science. On the other hand, we witness an increase of scholarship

    sympathetic with evangelical movements, especially in the United

    States. For the purpose of this paper, I will use the term new atheists

    for referring to the former approach, and the term new theists for

    referring to the latter approach.1

    New atheists is a label that has become usual for identifying some

    thinkers such as Richard Dawkins, Sam Harris and Quentin Smith.

    1 A previous version of this paper has been presented as a response to Graham

    Oppys paper New atheism and Christian evangelicalism, notes in progress at the

    Philosophy of Religion Research Seminar (University of Sydney). I wish to thankGraham for having shared with me his comments on my response: in the current

    version of the paper I try to answer some of his objections. An improved version

    of the paper has been presented at the Australian Catholic University School of

    Philosophy Seminar and I am grateful to the seminar participants for helpful

    discussions. I wish also to thank Paul Crittenden, Paul Redding and Luca Moretti

    for their close reading of this paper and for their insightful comments. Thanks are

    also due to Philip Quadrio, who also commented on some of my ideas on phi-

    losophy of religion, for his amicable assistance by joining in the proof-readings.

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    2/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 355

    Atheism being a general term, a more detailed specification is neces-

    sary. The distinguishing feature of the new atheism seems to be a

    kind of scientific atheism. To borrow the philosopher ThomasDixons definition (2002: 33759), scientific atheism involves belief in

    three central doctrines. The first is anti-theism. The second is scien-

    tism, conceived as the belief that science, especially natural science, is

    much the most valuable part of human learning because it is much

    the most authoritative, or serious, or beneficial (Sorrell 1991: 1,

    quoted in Dixon 2002: 342). Thirdly, scientific atheists recognise the

    need to develop an alternative worldview to replace supernaturalism

    and theism, in which to ground their interpretation of the results of

    natural science, their understanding of the origins and meaning of

    human life, and their ethical discourse (Dixon 2002: 342).2 Main-

    stream scientific atheism is different from evolutionary humanism.

    The term, coined by Julian Huxley, is used by Dixon to identify a sub-

    species of scientific atheism, such as that of John C. Avise (1998),

    which is characterised, in comparison with mainstream scientific

    atheism, by its more sympathetic attitude to traditional religious be-lievers, religious language and theology (Dixon 2002: 349).

    Providing a precise account of the new theism is much more diffi-

    cult. If it is true that some scholars explicitly profess evangelicalism, or

    at least some of its characteristics as identified by David Bebbington

    (1989)including: conversionism, biblicism, activism, cruicentrism

    and hence are often referred to as Evangelic Christians, the term is

    only partly accurate, both because not all of them profess all thesebeliefs, and because the movement embraces a wider range of phi-

    losophical expressions. Sometimes they are referred to as Christian

    2 As Dixon stresses, This corresponds roughly to the fifth of Stenmarks five sorts

    of scientism, which he calls redemptive scientism, that is, the view that science

    alone is sufficient for dealing with our existential questions or for creating a world

    view by which he could live cf. (Stenmark 1997: 31).

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    3/28

    356 Politics and religion in the new century

    nationalists, but this label is even less accurate, because it implies an

    emphasis on the political dimension of their philosophical activity

    which, even assuming this as their ultimate goal, does not representthe philosophical justification of their reasoning. Rather, the distin-

    guishing feature of what I call new theism seems to be a revived

    natural philosophy that welcomes rational proofs for the existence of a

    personal God and supernatural/religious explanations for scientific

    phenomena. This philosophical attitude is exemplified by (but not

    limited to) the theory of intelligent design. Intelligent design is the

    claim that certain features of the universe and of living things are best

    explained by an intelligent cause, not an undirected process such as

    natural selection (Discovery Institute 2007: Top Questions section).

    Thinkers such as William Lane Craig and Robert Koons seem to be

    committed to this notion.3

    II. Should they be considered as philosophies of religion?

    The works of the new atheists and of the new theists are usually con-

    sidered as belonging to (the discipline of) philosophy of religion for

    they express a (positive or negative) relation between religion and

    philosophy. However, from a normative point of view, this belonging

    seems to me disputable. In other words, what I am wondering is

    whether they should normatively be considered as philosophies of

    religion.4

    Moreover it has to be noted that a descriptive criterion implies a nor-

    mative criterion, for it is thanks to a generally shared normative

    3 The Center for Science and Culture 2007: Top Questions section (retrieved on

    September 23, 2007). The website includes both William Lane Craig and Robert

    Koons as Fellows.

    4 Questioning the disciplinary belonging of various theses and publications could

    seem just a problem of linguistic idiosyncrasy, but when we focus on philosophy

    of religion it is not. I hope it will be made clear before the end of this paper.

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    4/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 357

    criterion that, for instance, we describe the book we are reading as a

    book of philosophy of religion, of religious philosophy or of theol-

    ogyor, simply, of literature. What is a normative criterion groundedon? Possible answers are: a) reason; b) a typical standard or model.

    The latter answer is obviously weaker than the former, as it entails a

    higher degree of arbitrariness. Let the former option be considered.

    Unless a notion of objective reason is adopted (which is difficult when

    focusing on normative criteria), the formulation of the former option

    should be modified as follows: reasonat least byordinary standards

    of reasonableness. In both cases,5 it is implied that a normative crite-

    rion depends on a tradition, conceiving this term in the (general)

    sense of a set of beliefs, customs or practices taught by one generation

    to the next.

    The thoughts, theories and publications of the new theists are descrip-

    tively considered as belonging to (the discipline of) philosophy of

    religion. So are the thoughts, theories and publications of the new

    atheists, insofar as they are considered, as Quentin Smith critically

    stresses, as a subfield of the philosophy of religion.6 If the descriptive

    criterion according to which all these thoughts, theories and publica-

    tions are considered as belonging to (the discipline of) philosophy of

    religion implies a normative criterion, and if a normative criterion

    always depends (partially at least) on a tradition, it follows that this

    5 Most of the times these two options do not exclude each other, but they partially

    overlapfor instance, a normative criterion often (but not always) is grounded on

    a typical standard or model that has been adopted also because of a reasonat

    least by ordinary standards of reasonableness.

    6 As a subfield of the philosophy of religion, atheism is usually classified as a

    body of counter-arguments against the cosmological, teleological and ontological

    arguments, and counter-arguments against the arguments from religious experi-

    ence and (alleged) miracles (Smith 2001: 195215).

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    5/28

    358 Politics and religion in the new century

    normative criterion has to be found in the broad philosophical tradi-

    tion these thoughts, theories and publications belong to.

    The emergence of a normative criterion within a specific traditionthus derives from both a degree of arbitrariness and a reasonat least

    by ordinary standards of reasonableness (cf. Hobsbawm & Ranger

    1992). It seems to me that the reason why the thoughts, theories and

    publications of the new theists and of the new atheists are considered

    as belonging to the (discipline of) philosophy of religion lies on the

    following argument: any philosophical questions that arise in connec-

    tion with religion properly belong to philosophy of religion. One ofthe philosophical questions thrown up by reflection on religion is the

    question whether God exists. Therefore, arguments defining or deny-

    ing religious explanations for scientific phenomena, and arguments

    advancing or rejecting rational proofs for the existence of God belong

    to the (discipline of) philosophy of religion.

    This normative criterion (which I will refer to as the inclusive crite-

    rion) seems to have a high degree of reasonableness. This view can be

    challenged only by another normative criterion with a higher degree

    of reasonableness. What I am going to do is to examine a different

    normative criterion usually adopted in the so-called continental phi-

    losophical tradition in order to question whether that criterion is

    more reasonable than the inclusive criterion. The brief historical ac-

    count I am going to present is thus motivated not by an attempt to

    historically circumscribe what could be studied under the label phi-

    losophy of religion, but by the aim of showing the motives for theadoption of this criterion, including both a degree of arbitrariness and

    (what counts more for the purpose of this essay) a degree of reason-

    ableness (at least by ordinary standards of reasonableness).

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    6/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 359

    III. Philosophy, theology and religious philosophy

    Philosophy of religion, as a specific discipline, was born relatively late,

    not before the 18th century, when modern philosophy stopped focus-

    ing on the whole, and started focusing on the human being and on

    her relationship to the world and to God. Only with the Enlighten-

    ment is a philosophy of religion developed that is distinct from the

    ways that medieval philosophy (and also early modern philosophy)

    had dealt with religion. The universal questions about the being of

    God are not set aside with this anthropocentric conversion. But the

    question is not anymore to know the essence of God. Rather, the ques-tion is to know how the human being can relate herself to

    transcendence.

    A fundamental step in this process is Kants Copernican turn plac-

    ing the human cognitive activities at the centre of philosophy. With

    the transcendental move, rational arguments on religion become

    objects of self-critical reason. Hence, Kant concludes that it is mis-

    taken to take the ideas of the soul, the world, and God asconstitutivethey are not cognitive objects, but regulative principles

    which serve to guide the understanding through reason in respect of

    experience by using to their greatest perfection the rules of reason

    (Kant 1998: A320/B376). Kants Religion within the boundaries of mere

    reason pursues this goal by removing religious claims from the realm

    of theoretical reason and referencing their significance to regulative

    and symbolic meaning (Rossi & Wreen 1991).

    The whole history of German Idealism from Kant onward can be read,

    as Paul Redding has suggested, as the history of perspectivism (Red-

    ding 2009). Perspectivism means first of all the renunciation of the

    idea that the world can be examined by the subject objectively, that is,

    from a Gods-eye point of view. When the subject knows an object,

    she does not know the object in itself, but the object as far as it is

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    7/28

    360 Politics and religion in the new century

    known by the knower. It follows that in the process of knowledge the

    subject knows her self by knowing the object.

    It is true that the classic proofs of the existence of God sometimesreappear in different formfor instance, the new formulations of the

    ontological proof by Schelling and Hegel. However, these proofs ap-

    pear in a very different context. For example, when Hegel refuses

    Kants confutation of the ontological proof as nave and barbarian, he

    is perfectly aware that he is not presenting, properly speaking, an

    argument. In fact, Hegel preliminarily assumes that an infinite, that is,

    the Absolute, exists. According to Hegel, the ontological proof seemsto make sense only from a particular point of view, only, so to say, in a

    particular hermeneutic horizonthe one opened by Kants transcen-

    dental move. It is not the content of the religious claims that is

    disputed, but its significance for the human being.

    Using a different philosophical language, it could be said that there is

    no epistemology of God. That is, claims about God (existence as well

    as non-existence claims) are truth-apt: they can be true or false be-

    cause they have a factual meaning. However, there is no evidence to

    support one thesis or the otherthat is, claims on God are not episte-

    mologically cognitive: their truth-values are unknowable to us, as there

    is no way to increase the degree of rational belief in such claims.

    Therefore, a clear distinction between philosophy and theology is

    introduced by Kant. Theology bases itself on a revelation, which is

    presupposed a priori and which theology develops argumentatively by

    focusing on the content of that revelation. Conversely, philosophy

    cannot presuppose any revelation. Even if philosophy of religion fo-

    cused on a particular revelation, it is not its content that it is

    questioned, but its significance for the human being.

    Furthermore, philosophy of religion is different from religious phi-

    losophy. Philosophy of religion assumes religion as an object of

    investigation. In doing so, it remains philosophy and does not become

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    8/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 361

    religion. Its approach can be critical, analytical, hermeneutical or

    whatever, but it cannot be abandonment to religion or a fusion with it.

    The definition philosophy of religion expresses a relationship, thatbetween philosophy and religion. When there is a fusion between

    philosophy and religion, this relationship is not possible anymore.

    This is what happens in religious philosophy, a kind of knowledge in

    which the philosophical element receives its validity and its funda-

    mental meaning exclusively from its object, that is, the divine. The

    paradigm of religious philosophy can be found in the neoplatonic

    tradition. For instance, in Plotinus the content and the object of phi-

    losophy have a clear sacral dimension. The doctrine of knowledge is a

    doctrine of salvation, for the dialectical steps of the return of the soul

    to the One, although presented in a rational form, constitute an up-

    ward movement through the various phases of the emanationistic

    process, up to the grasp of the supreme truth and to the fusion with it.

    In philosophical approaches like this, philosophy loses its specificity:

    there is no distinction between rational process and longing for God.7

    According to this normative criterion (which I will refer to as the

    post-Kantian criterion), philosophy of religion is that discipline

    which focuses on possible relationships between philosophy and relig-

    ion broadly conceived (not a specific revealed religion), in the same

    way in which philosophy of law focuses on the relation between phi-

    losophy and the notion of law (not the Australian law or the Italian

    law), and philosophy of history focuses on the relation between phi-

    losophy and the meaning of history (if any), not American history orFrench history. To emphasise the broadness of the term religion, the

    discipline could also be defined as the relation between philosophy

    and religious experience. That is, philosophy of religion should take

    into consideration not only the meaning of actual and organised sys-

    7 For an in-depth explanation of the distinction between philosophy of religion,

    theology and religious philosophy see (Ravera 1995).

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    9/28

    362 Politics and religion in the new century

    tems of beliefs and doctrines, but also all those (practical or intellec-

    tual) experiences of transcendence coming from outside organised

    systems. Moreover, the term religious experience stresses once againthat religion is not primarily considered by philosophy as a proposi-

    tional knowledge.

    The analytic-anglophone tradition has adopted the normative crite-

    rion according to which any philosophical questions that arise in

    connection with religion properly belong to philosophy of religion

    (inclusive criterion). The continental tradition has instead adopted the

    normative criterion according to which only the questions that arisein connection with the regulative and symbolic meaning of religion

    properly belong to philosophy of religion, whereas questions that arise

    in connection with the theoretical contentof religion do not belong to

    it ( post-Kantian criterion).8 The main reason why, I think, the ana-

    lytic-anglophone tradition has not assumed the criterion adopted by

    the continental tradition is because it has rejected Kantian and post-

    Kantian perspectivism.

    Therefore Koons and Craigs arguments for the existence of God9 and

    reasoning about the nature of divine attributes, together with

    Dawkins and Smiths arguments against the existence of God, can be

    considered philosophies of religion according to the inclusive crite-

    8

    Of course I am generalising. Doubtless it is possible to find some philosophieswhich belong (geographically and/or methodologically) to the analytic-

    anglophone tradition which adopt the post-Kantian criterion, as well as it is

    possible to find some philosophies which belong (geographically and/or method-

    ologically) to the continental tradition which adopt the inclusive criterion.

    However, these can be considered exceptions within a general trend that usually

    shares the same criterion.

    9 On Craigs Kalam cosmological argument, see Oppy (2006: 13754); on Koons

    contingency-based cosmological argument, see Oppy (2006: 12530).

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    10/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 363

    rion;10 but cannot be considered philosophies of religion according to

    the post-Kantian criterion. In fact, the new theists take for granted a

    form of theism based on Christian revelation, on which they develop arevived natural philosophy. The new atheists often refuse to engage

    with the theist philosophers arguments because they take for granted

    that religion itself is nothing more than superstition.

    As a consequence of this general picture, if one takes a superficial look

    at the current debate, one could get the feeling that it is necessary to

    side with either one group or the other. It could even seem that a

    philosopher should not deal with religion and should stigmatise it as achildish form of superstition or, in case she wants to deal with relig-

    ion, she should commit herself to the demonstration of the existence

    of God, to the definition of the divine attributes or, as the new theists

    do, to the clarification of the scientific validity of the theory of intelli-

    gent design. Of course there are other possibilities between these

    extremes in philosophy of religion (and there are many positions that

    are actually occupied). There are, for example, many importantly

    different varieties of atheism as well as many importantly different

    varieties of theism. However, if one looks at the current debate in the

    English-speaking world, it still seems that philosophy of religion has

    to be approached from a theistic or from an atheistic standpoint.11

    10

    This is the reason why books on arguments about the existence of God areclassified in the philosophy of religion section of the catalogues of the major

    anglophone scholarly publishers (Cambridge University Press, Oxford University

    Press, Routledge, Blackwell, etc.). The cataloguers are not making a linguistic or

    conceptual mistake in so classifying these books. They are simply applying a

    normative criterion commonly adopted within the tradition they belong to.

    11 To be more precise, the agnostic standpoint should be added. In fact, those who

    hold an agnostic standpoint are by definition less predisposed to engage a debate

    on religion. I will elaborate on this point later on.

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    11/28

    364 Politics and religion in the new century

    IV. Theist and atheist metaphilosophy of naturalism

    The mirror-like positions of the new theists and of new atheists could

    remind one of the enemy twins referred to by the cultural theorist

    Ren Girard (1986: 125ff). The enemy twins fight each other vigor-

    ously, but they need each other, as both of them build their identity in

    opposition to their adversary.

    Despite the frontal opposition that could lead one to think that these

    two positions have nothing in common, the standpoint of new theists

    and the standpoint of the new atheists mirror each other. Theyhave

    something in common. They both assume that religion is a theory.

    They assume that philosophy can and/or should consider religion as a

    system of theoretical propositionsso that it is possible, for instance,

    to increase the rationality of a specific claim regarding the existence of

    God.

    The assumption that religion is a theory seems to be based on a kind

    of meta-naturalism.12 Atheist philosophers profess a methodological

    naturalismwhich, according to the new theists, entails metaphysicalnaturalism (cf. Forrest 2000: 729)13conceived as that approach

    which considers supernatural phenomena as nonexistent or not in-

    herently different from natural hypothesis. On the other hand, the

    new theists profess a natural philosophy that welcomes supernatural

    12 The adoption of a naturalistic perspective also explains the rejection of the post

    Kantian tradition, as Sebastian Gardner recently pointed out: the kinds of phi-losophical positions most intensively worked on and argued about in non-

    historical, systematic analytic philosophy are predominantly naturalisticand

    thus, on the face of it, not in any immediate and obvious sense receptive to the

    central ideas of German idealism (Gardner 2007: 19).

    13 Forrest examines the question of whether methodological naturalism entails

    philosophical (ontological or metaphysical) naturalism. She concludes that the

    relationship between methodological and philosophical naturalism, while not one

    of logical entailment, is the only reasonable metaphysical conclusion.

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    12/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 365

    explanations of natural phenomena. In both cases, religion is consid-

    ered as a theory, whose propositional content is then rejected (for it

    expresses something which does not exist, or which can be explainednaturally) or assumed (for it is taken as the ground of natural phe-

    nomena).

    A good (although inevitably partial) account of this approach to relig-

    ion can be found in Quentin Smiths paper The metaphilosophy of

    naturalism (2001). Smith complains about the consideration of athe-

    ism as a subfield of the philosophy of religion: atheism is usually

    classified as a body of counter-arguments against the cosmological,teleological and ontological arguments, and counter-arguments

    against the arguments from religious experience. Conversely, Smith

    argues, Atheism should be considered as a defence of naturalism

    against skeptical attacks, and thereby to play a foundational role in

    justifying the presuppositions of positive naturalist philosophy. On

    this account theism should be considered as a subfield of naturalism,

    namely, as a skepticism about the basic principles of naturalism. As

    the final consequence of this reclassification move, [Philosophy of

    religion] disappears, to be replaced by a new subfield of naturalism,

    namely, [skepticism about naturalism], with skeptical arguments

    being put forth and argued against, with the aim in mind of further

    developing the argumentative foundations of the naturalist world-

    view.

    The position of the new theists could be expressed by the same words,

    by just inverting the term atheism and theism: theism should beconsidered as a defence of natural philosophy (expressing supernatu-

    ral explanations of natural phenomena) against skeptical attacks. Even

    in this case, philosophy of religion ultimately disappears, to be re-

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    13/28

    366 Politics and religion in the new century

    placed by a subfield of theology, namely, apologetics (defence of theis-

    tic positions against atheist attacks), (cf. Cottingham 2005).14

    In the post-Kantian view, religion cannot be considered as a theory.The arguments that can be offered in support of claims to know that

    there is a God or of claims to know that there is no God are not ade-

    quate to justify the commitment required by the extreme positions

    (new theism and new atheism).15

    The rational arguments supporting religion are not adequate to justify

    the required commitment. The lack of rational or empirical proofs is

    compensated by the believers with faith, a non-rational componentthat provides the believer with the required degree of commitment.

    Faith is thus considered by religion as a merit, or a gift, or both (ac-

    cording to the different theological conceptions). The attempts of the

    new theists to compensate this lack with new rational or empirical

    proofs paradoxically aim to dismiss faith. If one day our microscopes

    discovered the words made by God in every cell (provided that they

    have not been genetically engineered by a race of super-intelligent

    aliens), the existence of God would become a mere fact, and not a

    merit or a gift anymore.

    Once it is accepted that no rational or empirical evidence is sufficient

    to claim the existence or the non-existence of God, and that this lack

    of rational and empirical proofs is compensated by the believers with

    faith in order to reach the required degree of commitment, the ques-

    14 In this recent and interesting book, Cottingham rejects the view of religion as atheory. A religious outlook he writes, is never, or at any rate not typically,

    adopted on the basis of an inference to the best explanation (22). Later on, he

    stresses that theistic commitments are not derived as a conclusion from the

    preponderance of philosophical arguments, or put forward as a scientific hy-

    pothesis providing the best explanation for certain empirical data (131).

    15 This objection does not apply to a belief in God (or non-belief) marked by a

    degree of caution.

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    14/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 367

    tion arises: what is compensating the same lack for the atheists, so that

    they can reach the required degree of commitment?

    In order to answer this question, it is useful to consider the work ofsome philosophers of the post-Kantian tradition: Gabriel Marcel and

    Paul Ricoeur. This exposition will also try to make clear what philoso-

    phy of religion should be according to the post-Kantian criterion.

    V. Post-Kantian meta-philosophy of religion

    In the late 1920s, Gabriel Marcel was one of the protagonists, and

    maybe the main character, of a heated debate with some atheist phi-

    losophers of that time, like Jean-Paul Sartre, Georges Bataille and

    Albert Camus. The historical context and the philosophical approach

    of these atheist philosophers were, of course, very different from the

    current context and the philosophical prospective of the new atheist

    philosophers. Instead of the scientific atheism (shared by Dawkins,

    Harris and Smith), Sartre, Bataille and Camus shared a nihilistic athe-

    ism based on Nietzsches notion of the death of God. There is noGod, there are no metaphysical values of any kind: according to them,

    human beings have to accept this existential situation.

    According to Marcel,16 the point is that these nihilist philosophers

    present atheism as something evident or more rational than faith in

    God. Despite the difference of historical context and philosophical

    approach, the general assumption of these nihilist philosophers is the

    same assumption that can be reached in the statements of the newatheists. The judgment God does not exist is, they say, more evident

    and/or more rational than the judgement God exists. One of the

    most exemplary expositions of this argument is that expressed by

    Norwood Russell Hanson (1972) in What I do not believe: while there

    16 Marcels arguments are taken from Homo viator: introduction to a metaphysic of

    hope (1951).

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    15/28

    368 Politics and religion in the new century

    are good reasons for believing that God does not exist, there are no

    good reasons for believing that God does exist.

    According to Marcel, atheism is neither evident nor more rational.The non-existence of God cannot be proved, in the same way that the

    existence of God cannot be proved. It is not the task of philosophy of

    religion to demonstrate the existence of God or the immortality of the

    soul. Following in Pascals footsteps, Marcel claims that the belief in

    the existence of God, as well as the belief in the non-existence of God,

    is the result of a wager. It is just as much an act of faith as the opposite

    choice. In other words, at the root of every philosophy (or, better, atthe root of every human existence) there is always a wager. In this

    way, Marcel provides an answer to the question what is compensat-

    ing the lack of rational and empirical proofs for the atheists, so that

    they can reach the required degree of commitment? According to

    Marcel, the answer is faitha non-rational component that pro-

    vides the unbeliever with the required degree of commitment in the

    non-existence of God. It has to be noted that the wager argument, as it

    is reproposed by Marcel, does not claim to be a convincing argument

    for taking steps to become a believer in a specific revealed religion

    (such as Christianity for Pascal). As Diderot (1875: 167)17 pointed out,

    an imam could just as well reason the same way: Pascals argument

    cannot decide among different religions. Insofar as faith is a non-

    rational component, its content is not rationally determined.18 The

    conversion to a specific faith requires a higher degree of commitment

    than that required by the (simple) assertion of the existence of God

    17 See Hacking (1994: 24) and Jordan (1994: 10113). I am grateful to Paul Crit-

    tenden for having called my attention on this point.

    18 Claiming that the content of faith does not need to be rationally determined

    does not imply the claim that reasonableness does not play any role in the choice

    of ones own faith. One could consider her own religion as more reasonable, but

    the judgement is, of course, culturally determined and highly subjective.

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    16/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 369

    (regardless of the fact that it is then identified with a personal God,

    with a superior being pantheistically conceived or with anything else).

    Marcel does not try to defend this argument, not even by claiming itat least gets us to theism (the so-called generic theism answer).19

    Insofar as Marcel belongs to the philosophical tradition opened by

    Kants transcendental move, he is not interested in the content of the

    religious claim here. His approach here is phenomenological20he is

    phenomenologically describing how believers and unbelievers com-

    pensate the lack of rational and empirical proofs. Marcel goes further.

    He wonders: what does determine our decision to bet on the existence

    or on the non-existence of God? Behind a wager, Marcel argues, there

    is a desire, if not even a will. Marcel writes: There is, then, an emo-

    tional element lurking beneath the apparently objective and rational

    assertion or claim made by the unbeliever; and what is more, deeper

    thought on the matter will show us that it could not be otherwise

    (Marcel 1949: 208).

    From this point of view, the whole nihilistic thought appears like a

    form of dogmatism generated by a will: I want reality to be of such

    sort that it gives me no grounds for expecting any salvation or cher-

    ishing any hope (Marcel 1951: 199). This is Nietzsches greatest

    lesson: once metaphysics has been definitely abandoned, we have to

    face the fact that at the roots of every taking of sides, both existentially

    and theoretically speaking, there is a will.

    When one commits herself to theism or atheism (or all the more so to

    a specific kind of theism or atheism), she is not primarily choosingaccording to the prior probabilities she assigns to the theoretical

    19 See Jordan (1994: 10113) and Armour-Garb (1999: 11938). The generic

    theism answer runs into the Professors God objection: God could reward

    those who humbly remain sceptical in the absence of evidence, and not those who

    adopt theism. Cf. (Martin 1990: 22938; Mackie 1982: 20003).

    20 On Marcel and phenomenology, see Bubbio (2005: 5570).

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    17/28

    370 Politics and religion in the new century

    propositions constituting the standpoint she is taking. Although cul-

    ture, social influences, existential experiences and the like can and do

    play a relevant role in the decision-making process, the decisive de-terminant is somehow a reflection of how one wants the world to be.21

    Besides deciding to bet on the existence or on the non-existence of

    God, there is a third option. One could say that the matter is too un-

    clear or uncertain to make a definite decision, and then she would

    chose not to bet (agnosticism). However, even this is a decision and,

    qua talis, it is moved importantly by desire and will (as well as the

    cultural, social and existential determinants mentioned above). Thisposition is different from (scientific or nihilistic) atheism, and from

    rational theism because it seems less exposed to the risk of turning

    into a form of dogmatism. At a meta-philosophical level (the matter

    of religion is too unclear or uncertain to rationally make a definite

    decision), it can be considered as the standpoint of a post-Kantian

    philosophy of religion. Nevertheless, it can become dogmatic if the

    agnostic position is considered not meta-philosophically, but philoso-

    phically or existentially, that is, if the content of the agnostic

    proposition is considered more rational than that of the atheist or

    theist propositions (the matter of religion is too unclear or uncertain,

    so that the only rational decision is not to decide). The content of the

    agnostic proposition is not more rational, as it is equally moved by

    desire and will.

    21 This outcome is similar to the weak faith proposed by the Italian philosopher

    Gianni Vattimo in Belief(1999), whose original title is Credere di credere (which

    literally means I believe that I believe). Although this conception can be consid-

    ered as a relativisation of faith, it is not so far from some theological

    interpretations of the Augustine doctrine ofprevenient grace, insofar as it allows

    persons to engage their free will to choose the salvation offered by God (or to

    reject it).

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    18/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 371

    There are no successful arguments for the conclusion that God exists

    or does not exist. Therefore, if the post-Kantian normative criterion is

    applied, hypothesis and theories that insist in presenting argumentsfor the existence or for the non-existence of God do not belong to (the

    discipline of) philosophy of religion.

    It has been previously said that according to the post-Kantian crite-

    rion, philosophy of religion is that discipline which focuses on

    possible relations between philosophy and religion broadly conceived.

    It has also been said that philosophy of religion should not focus on

    the content of religious claims, but on their significance for the humanbeing. Therefore, what does a philosophy of religion conceived in this

    way look like? One of the most representative philosophies of this

    tradition is the hermeneutics developed by Paul Ricoeur.22

    According to Ricoeur, the passage from metaphysics to hermeneutics,

    that is, from a dogmatic thought that wants to reach absolute and

    objective truths to a thought which recognises that truth is not an

    object and can be partially reached only through interpretations, is not

    painless. A hermeneutics of the sacred must pass through the so-called

    school of suspicion: Marx, Nietzsche and Freud provide philosophy

    with the tools necessary for demystification. Only by learning not to

    confuse religion with the ideological superstructures of a particular

    form of society or with the psychological projections of consciousness,

    is it possible to establish a real dialogue between philosophy and

    religion.23

    22 Paul Ricoeurs main mentor was, not by chance, Gabriel Marcel. See Blundell

    (2003: 89102).

    23 Cottingham not only supports a bare compatibility between philosophy,

    psychoanalysis and religion, that is, the mere possibility of co-existence between

    our three domains of thought. He also suggests that these three areas of human

    reflection can be seen as intimately intertwined (Cottingham 2005: 73).

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    19/28

    372 Politics and religion in the new century

    Ricoeur argues that an authentic philosophy of religion necessarily is

    a hermeneutics of symbols. According to Ricoeur, the symbol is a sign

    able to transmit a meaning. Ricoeur says that the main feature of asymbol is opacity: an opacity that can be penetratedbut never solved

    in perfect transparency. The rationalisation of the sacred and of the

    question of evil, which is always indissolubly bounded to religion,

    ended up dissolving the symbolic and regulative meaning of religious

    experience itself. Hence, Ricoeurs conclusion: that it is necessary to

    undo the concept, to pass through the defeat of knowledge to find

    that meaning in the symbols of religious experience.

    The meta-philosophical standpoint of a position such as that held by

    Ricoeur implies that religious experience is taken as an important part

    of the human experience (at least in the great majority of human cul-

    tures). Insofar as every person faces the problem, whether defining

    herself an agnostic, an atheist or a theist (and, more specifically, a

    Christian, a Muslim, a scientific or nihilistic atheist and so on), she

    somehow goes through a religious experience. This experience thus

    deserves to be considered by a philosopher qua philosopher (and not

    qua believer, unbeliever or agnostic).24 A philosophy of religion con-

    24 To consider religion only as a social and psychological phenomenon, so that it

    should be studied only by human sciences such as anthropology, sociology and

    psychology, is quite reductive, as much so as ascribing the so-called religious

    conflicts and the phenomenon of terrorism exclusively or primarily to the reli-

    gious element. Sam Harris (2004) writes: There are days when almost everyheadline in the morning papers attests to the social costs of religious faith, and the

    nightly news seems miraculously broadcast from the fourteenth century (236). I

    would ask of Harris whether the headlines in the morning papers really attest

    to the social costs of religious faith or they rather attest to the religious costof the

    socialand economic conflicts. It is a serious mistake to merely identify terrorism

    and religious fundamentalism. But if it is true that terrorism easily develops

    within religious fundamentalism, it is also true that the latter is often just an

    expression of deeper economic and social conflicts.

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    20/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 373

    ceived as a hermeneutics of religious experience does not demand a

    demonstration of the truth, but is meant to be a dialogue between

    philosophy and religion, while recognising both of them as expres-sions of the human being.

    Ricoeurs philosophy is a good example of this hermeneutics of reli-

    gious experience. However, it could be said that Ricoeurs approach

    has its limits. The irreducibility of symbols to non-symbolic concepts

    represents a serious problem for a philosophy of religion that aims to

    play a role in the establishment of a dialogue among different religious

    experiences. Our times, characterised by a loss of shared values and bythe confrontation (if not conflict) between different cultures, seem to

    issue to philosophy the challenge of expressing itself on the possibility

    of a thought usable and able to be shared. A symbol is richer than a

    concept because of its opacity, which makes it inexhaustible. And its

    opacity can be penetrated because a symbol refers to a complex system

    of signs, references and other symbols as well. This system is what we

    name culture. Hence, a symbol is completely meaningful only

    within a particular culture. When our main demand becomes the goal

    to find a common cultural language that may be accepted and shared

    among different cultures, a symbol unfortunately loses the greater part

    of its richness and sometimes even its utility.

    Therefore, the great challenge for philosophy of religion today seems

    to be to maintain its own speculative vocation and delineate suitable

    limits for a space of possible sharing, while at the same time establish-

    ing a dialogue among different religious traditions. The point is thatreligion is, as Kant argued, the realm of regulative and symbolic

    meanings. However, the pursuance of that aim implies the use of

    concepts. In fact, concepts can (potentially) establish a relation with

    all the symbolic contexts. Of course this process of translation of a

    symbol into concept does not happen without a degree of impover-

    ishment of the symbol.

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    21/28

    374 Politics and religion in the new century

    A hint for dealing with this problem can be found in Kant. It has been

    said that Kant removed religious claims from the realm of theoretical

    reason and related their significance to regulative and symbolic mean-ing. Ricoeur (and most of the hermeneutic tradition together with

    him) emphasised the symbolic aspect of this move. Hegel emphasised

    the regulative aspect of it.

    In the light of recent revisionist readings (such as those of Robert B.

    Pippin, Terry Pinkard and Paul Redding), Hegels notion of God can

    be philosophically considered in a Kantian way, that is, as an idea

    playing a regulative role (rather than as a super-entity). Conceived inthis way, Hegels account of God appears to be formed by symbolically

    expressed ideas. Philosophy does not dismiss religion, but preserves it

    (Pinkard 2000: 578). Concepts only partially succeed in translating

    symbolic content into rational content. Concepts fail because they do

    not exhaust the symbolbut, in so doing, they maintain the symbolic

    inexhaustibility. This failure is not philosophically useless. This kind

    of approach does not claim to exhaust the meaning of a religious sym-

    bol (rational dogmatism) and does not limit itself to expressing what a

    religious symbol is not (negative theology). It allows one to mark the

    border between what can be expressed theoretically and what is sig-

    nificant regulatively and symbolically, thus continuing the

    philosophical project started by Kant with Religion within the bounda-

    ries of mere reason. Further, it shows how religious symbols play a

    regulative role in the interaction among individuals and constitute

    their identities (cf. Redding 2007: 17599).25

    Thus, religion can beviewed as something clearly personal but not exclusivelysubjective.26

    25 See also Bielefeldt (2003).

    26 This point can be fruitfully expanded through further developments.

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    22/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 375

    VI. Conclusion

    In conclusion, it is time to come back to the question which has been

    proposed for investigation, namely, whether the inclusive criterion

    (any philosophical questions that arise in connection with religion

    properly belong to philosophy of religion) can be challenged by an-

    other normative criterion with a higher degree of reasonableness. The

    alternative that has been examined is the post-Kantian criterion,

    which can be formulated as follows: any philosophical questions that

    arise in connection with the symbolic or regulative meaning of relig-

    ion, and not with its propositional content, properly belong tophilosophy of religion. Questioning the disciplinary belonging of

    some theses and publications (such as those of the new atheists and

    the new theists) is not just a problem of linguistic idiosyncrasy, as the

    answer to this question potentially sets the agenda for philosophy of

    religion itself.

    If the inclusive criterion is applied, philosophy of religion seems des-

    tined to remain trapped in a pros/cons discussion between theism andatheism. Theist philosophers will keep defending arguments for the

    existence of God (and will try to find new ones). Atheist philosophers

    will keep attacking arguments for the existence of God (and will try to

    find new arguments for the non-existence of God). Others will simply

    not engage the debate and/or will dismiss religion as superstition. In

    the long run, philosophy of religion is destined to disappear. It will be

    absorbed by two subfields: a subfield of atheist naturalism and a sub-

    field of a theistic natural philosophy. Of course there are other

    possibilities between these extremes, and maybe a philosophy of relig-

    ion not conceived only as a skeptical subfield is possible for both

    (reasonable) religious believers and non-believers. However, this is the

    point: the meta-philosophy of religion supporting the inclusive crite-

    rion conceives philosophy of religion as a set of theoretical

    propositions regarding the content of religion. Hence, one can: a) try

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    23/28

    376 Politics and religion in the new century

    to demonstrate that these propositions are true, b) try to demonstrate

    that these propositions are false, or c) stand aside, or show that none

    of these arguments are powerful enough to be convincing.27

    The difference between the extremes of the new atheists and the new

    theists, on the one hand, and more moderate thinkers, on the other,

    concerns the degree of commitment to the factual contents of reli-

    gious propositionsit does not concern the accepted meta-

    philosophical standpoint, which is basically the same. In both cases,

    religious propositions are thought of as provided with factual content,

    and the differences concern the degree of probability or plausibilityascribed to these propositions. In a few words, the new atheists and

    the new theists are more dogmatic than the more moderate philoso-

    phers. Yet both of them consider religion to be a theory. If this is

    philosophy of religion, then it does not seem to meet the contempo-

    rary need for dialogue between different religious traditions. Insofar

    as a theory is an explanation or a model of given phenomena, it can

    only be right or wrong (or improvable). I will not accept a dialogue

    with those who support a different theory, if I think their theory has

    been proved wrong. Thus the new theists will not accept a dialogue

    with believers of other faiths, likewise the new atheists will not accept

    a dialogue with any kind of religious believers, as they are both dog-

    matic. The more moderate philosophers are not exposed to the risk of

    dogmatism, so they will stand aside: a position that can promote toler-

    ance among different faiths, but not a real dialogue.

    If the post-Kantian criterion is applied, then different consequencesfollow. To consider the religious fact as an important part of the hu-

    man experience (not only as a psychological or social fact, but as a

    symbolic and regulative dimension of the human being) is not to

    claim a particular religion (or religious experience) as true or more

    27 It seems to me that the latter is the position expressed by Graham Oppy (2006).

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    24/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 377

    authentic than others. The support of a specific religion (or of a spe-

    cific atheist faith) cannot be considered as the outcome of a

    philosophy. A philosopher who does not (personally) believe in theexistence of God is notautomatically an atheist philosopher, insofar as

    she recognises the symbolic and regulative value of religion. In the

    same way, a philosopher who does (personally) believe in God is not

    necessarily a Christian, a theist or a religious philosopher, insofar as

    she recognises the non-rational component of her personal commit-

    ment and does not consider her faith as the premise or the outcome of

    her philosophy.28 The boundary between an analysis of regulative

    value and symbolic significance on the one hand, and a religious claim

    (like the affirmation of the existence of God) on the other, cannot be

    exceeded. For instance, Leslie Stevenson, commenting on John

    Cottinghams statement (2005: 80) that One is able to affirm that

    God exists as one apprehends depths of value and significance in the

    world asks: Is anyone who finds value and significance in the world

    thereby affirming the existence of God? (Stevenson 2006: 47476). If

    the post-Kantian criterion is adopted, the philosophical answer to thisquestion is no. Of course it can be questioned whether the idea of a

    personal God is more consistent with the presence of value and sig-

    nificance in the world precisely because it is personalbut in doing

    so, we are exceeding the boundaries of philosophy (of religion) and we

    are trespassing in religious philosophy or in theology.

    It seems to me that there are several reasons why the post-Kantian

    criterion can be considered to be more reasonable than the inclusivecriterion (at least by ordinary standards of reasonableness). First, it

    defines more accurately the boundaries that distinguish philosophy of

    religion, religious philosophy and theology. Second, it better defines

    the object of the discipline, namely, the possible relations between

    28 From this point of view, there could be, so to say, a Christian who is a philoso-

    pher, but not a philosopher who is Christian.

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    25/28

    378 Politics and religion in the new century

    philosophy and religion broadly conceived (not a specific revealed

    religion), so that the discipline can be considered on a par with other

    philosophical disciplines (such as philosophy of language or philoso-phy of law). Third, by conceiving the notion of religion as the set of

    all possible religious experiences, it includes in the field all those

    (practical or intellectual) experiences of transcendence which do not

    belong to a specific system of religious belief and which are devoid of

    a corresponding propositional knowledge (such as mysticism).

    Fourth, by accepting Nietzsches lesson that at the root of every side-

    taking there is a will, it acknowledges the importance of emotional

    and voluntary components of religious beliefs. Fifth, the post-Kantian

    criterion thus firmly refuses any kind of dogmatism. Sixth, and most

    important, it allows philosophers to open a real dialogue between

    different religious traditions.

    Within a real dialogue between philosophy and religion, the religious

    element cannot be reduced to psychological intimacy or arbitrary

    subjectivity, insofar as a personal belief does not conflict with an ac-

    ceptance of the function of philosophy as the norm or criterion of

    every judgment. Paraphrasing the Italian hermeneutic philosopher

    Luigi Pareyson, it could be said that when one commits a common

    work to demands of reason, she admits that everybody else do the

    same. If someone should demonstrate to me, on rational grounds, that

    I am wrong, I will withdraw as readily as I would speak in the name of

    reason, in case I discover someone in error and demonstrate to her the

    precise source of her error. And let it be noted that I do not permitmyself to be convinced by the other as that particular person who

    holds a particular belief, but as one who induces me to listen to the

    voice of that reason I was unable to hear, and which now we both

    exercise, she in convincing me of my error and I in permitting myself

    to be convinced, (cf. Pareyson 1/1952: 8396; 1995: 6579).

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    26/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 379

    Philosophy of religion can really play a role in the contemporary

    world in so far as it remains philosophy. Put differently, philosophy of

    religion can speak every religious language in so far as it speaks aphilosophical language, and not a religious one. Philosophy of religion

    is neither Christian or Islamic, atheist nor theist. This does not

    mean that it must necessarily be neutral, but that its outcome should

    be the result of a philosophical analysis that takes its object seriously;

    and not just the development of a thesis or a belief taken for granted

    or assumed a priori.

    In conclusion, I think that philosophy of religion can play a funda-mental role in the contemporary society insofar as it is able to go

    beyond the meta-philosophical naturalistic view of religion as a the-

    ory. In this case, it will significantly contribute to the overcoming of

    all possible dogmatisms (either religious or atheist) and to building

    bridges between different religious traditions.

    References

    Armour-Garb B (1999). Betting on God. Religious Studies, 35: 11938.

    Avise JC (1998). The genetic gods: evolution and belief in human affairs.

    Cambridge, MA & London: Harvard University Press.

    Bebbington DW (1989). Evangelicalism in modern Britain: a history from

    the 1730s to the 1980s. London: Unwin Hyman.

    Bielefeldt H (2003). Symbolic representation in Kants practical philosophy.New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Blundell B (2003). Creative fidelity: Gabriel Marcels influence on Paul

    Ricoeur. In A Wiercinski(Ed), Between suspicion and sympathy: Paul

    Ricoeurs unstable equilibrium, (pp89102). Toronto: The Hermeneutic

    Press.

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    27/28

    380 Politics and religion in the new century

    Bubbio PD (2005). If there is a plot: Gabriel Marcel and second-degree

    reflection. In A Wiercinski (Ed), Between description and interpretation:

    the hermeneutic turn in phenomenology, (pp5570). Toronto: The Her-meneutic Press.

    Cottingham J (2005). The spiritual dimension: religion and human value.

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Diderot D (187577). Pensees philosophiques. In J Assezat (Ed), Oeuvres,

    LIX.(I). Paris: Garnier Frres.

    The Center for Science and Culture, Discovery Institute [Online]. Top

    questions, number one what is the theory of intelligent design?Available:www.discovery.org/csc/topQuestions.php [Accessed 2007, September 23].

    Dixon T (2002). Scientific atheism as a faith tradition. Studies in History

    and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 33: 33759.

    Forrest B (2000). Methodological naturalism and philosophical natural-

    ism: clarifying the connection. Philo, 3(2): 729.

    Gardner S (2007). The limits of naturalism and the metaphysics of Ger-

    man idealism. In E Hammer (Ed), German idealism: contemporary

    perspectives (pp1949). London & New York: Routledge.

    Girard R (1986). The scapegoat. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University

    Press.

    Hanson NR (1972). What I dont believe. In S Toulmin & H Woolf (Ed),

    What I do not believe and other essays, (pp30931). Reidel: Publisher

    Dordrecht.

    Harris S (2004). The end of faith: religion, terror, and the future of reason.

    New York: WW Norton & Company.

    Hobsbawm E & Ranger T (1992). The invention of tradition. Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press.

    Jordan J (1994). The many-gods objection. In Id, gambling on God: essays

    on Pascals wager, (pp10113). Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Kant I (1998). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge & New York: Cam-

    bridge University Press.

  • 8/2/2019 Bubbio - Met a Philosophical Reflections on Theism and Atheism in the Current Debate

    28/28

    Metaphilosophical reflections on theism and atheism 381

    Mackie JL (1982). The miracle of theism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Marcel G (1949). Being and having. K Farrer (Trans). Glasgow: Glasgow

    University Press.Marcel G (1951). Homo viator: introduction to a metaphysic of hope. E

    Craufurd (Trans). Chicago: Regnery Company.

    Martin M (1990).Atheism. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Oppy G (2006).Arguing about gods. Cambridge: Cambridge University

    Press.

    Pareyson L (1952). Lunit della filosofia. Filosofia 4(1): 8396; Filosofia e

    Teologia 1(1995): 6579. A Di Lascia (1953) (Trans), The unity of phi-losophy, Cross currents 4(1): 5769. Now in PD Bubbio (forthcoming)

    (Ed), Existence, interpretation, freedom: selected writings. Aurora, Colo-

    rado: Davies Group.

    Pinkard T (2000). Hegel: a biography.Cambridge: Cambridge University

    Press.

    Ravera M (1995). Introduzione alla filosofia della religione. Torino: Utet

    Libreria.Redding P (2007).Analytic philosophy and the return of Hegelian thought.

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Redding P (2009). Continental idealism: Leibniz to Nietzsche. London:

    Routledge.

    Rossi PJ & Wreen M (1991). Kants philosophy of religion reconsidered.

    Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Smith Q (2001). The metaphilosophy of naturalism. Philo, 4(2): 195215.Sorrell T (1991). Scientism: philosophy and the infatuation with science.

    London & New York: Routledge.

    Stenmark M (1997). What is scientism? Religious Studies 33(1): 1532.

    Stevenson L (2006). The spiritual dimension. Review by J Cottingham.

    The Philosophical Quarterly, 56(224): 47476.

    Vattimo G (1999). Belief. London: Polity Press.