code switching and x-bar theory: the functional head constraint

18
Code Switching and X-Bar Theory: The Functional Head Constraint Author(s): Hedi M. Belazi, Edward J. Rubin and Almeida Jacqueline Toribio Source: Linguistic Inquiry, Vol. 25, No. 2 (Spring, 1994), pp. 221-237 Published by: The MIT Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4178859 . Accessed: 07/02/2014 12:43 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . The MIT Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Linguistic Inquiry. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Upload: sajeeb-zaman

Post on 21-Oct-2015

50 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

DESCRIPTION

Code Switching and X-Bar Theory: The Functional Head Constraint

TRANSCRIPT

Code Switching and X-Bar Theory: The Functional Head ConstraintAuthor(s): Hedi M. Belazi, Edward J. Rubin and Almeida Jacqueline ToribioSource: Linguistic Inquiry, Vol. 25, No. 2 (Spring, 1994), pp. 221-237Published by: The MIT PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4178859 .

Accessed: 07/02/2014 12:43

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

The MIT Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Linguistic Inquiry.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Hedi M. Belazi Code Switching and X-Bar Edward J. Rubin T Almeida Jacqueline Theory: e unc iona ea

Toribio Constraint

It is well known that many bilinguals who are able to speak fluently in two languages, or language varieties, often switch between these linguistic codes. Code switching can be inter- or intrasentential, the former constrained by social and discourse constraints, the latter, of relevance for the present discussion, constrained also by properly syntactic principles. Herein, we demonstrate that code switching obeys the Functional Head Con- straint, a refinement of Abney's (1987) proposal that functional heads "f-select" com- plements. It is this dependency that restricts switching between a functional head and its complement in code switching. Switching is disallowed, for example, between C? and IP, between 10 and VP, between Neg? and VP, between D? and NP, and between QO and NP in the Tunisian Arabic-French and Spanish-English code-switching data that we consider here. By contrast, switching between a lexical head and its complement proceeds unimpeded. Thus, code switching provides evidence, not available in mono- lingual speech, for a necessary refinement of f-selection, a constraint of Universal Gram- mar.

1 Introduction

In this article we concentrate on intrasentential code switching by Tunisian Arabic- French and Spanish-English bilinguals, examples of which appear in (1).1

This article has benefited from the comments of Wayne Harbert, Jim Gair, and several anonymous Lin- guistic Inquiry reviewers. We would also like to thank the participants at the Second Annual Western Con- ference on Linguistics (University of Texas at El Paso, 1990) and the Twelfth Symposium on Spanish and Portuguese Bilingualism (Florida International University, 1991). The names of the authors appear in alpha- betical order.

' Code switching among fluent adult bilinguals should be distinguished from language interference and borrowing. For discussion of these distinctions, see Pfaff 1979 and Sankoff and Poplack 1981. Code switching has been the subject of research by numerous linguists (see Stevens 1974, Abbassi 1977, Bentahila and Davies 1983, M'barek and Sankoff 1988, Eid 1988, and Belazi 1991 with respect to Arabic-French, and Timm 1975, Gumperz 1976, Pfaff 1979, Poplack 1980, 1981, 1983, among others too numerous to cite, with respect to Spanish-English code switching).

221 Linguistic Inquiry, Volume 25, Number 2, Spring 1994

221-237 ? 1994 by The Massachusetts Institute of Technology

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

222 HEDI M. BELAZI, EDWARD J. RUBIN, AND ALMEIDA JACQUELINE TORIBIO

(1) a. Tunisian Arabic-French Je lui ai dit bas yi-xarraz il karhba ce matin. I him have told that he-takes.out the car this morning 'I told him to take the car out this morning.'

b. Spanish-English This morning mi hermano y yo fuimos a comprar some milk. this morning my brother and I went to buy some milk 'This morning my brother and I went to buy some milk.'

Our working hypothesis is that competent or balanced bilinguals and marginally competent bilinguals demonstrate disparate behaviors in code switching. In fact, Poplack (1980) suggests that code-switching behavior may be used to measure bilingual ability in that intrasentential switches imply a greater degree of competence in the two grammars involved, whereas intersentential switches do not generally necessitate grammatical com- petence in both languages. Also pursuing this line of inquiry, Belazi (1991) demonstrates that fluent Tunisian Arabic-French bilinguals are more sensitive to grammatical con- straints on switching than their nonfluent counterparts, concluding that degree of bilin- gualism must be taken into consideration in any study of code switching. These findings indicate that the degree of balance in the competence of the two languages involved correlates with the degree of competence in code switching. With this in mind, we limit this study to code switching by fluent bilinguals.2

Of particular interest to us is the fact that intrasentential code switching is not haphazard-there are certain syntactic regularities underlying the switching process. Proposals for the syntactic constraints on code switching are, in fact, frequent in the literature (see Gingr'as 1974, Timm 1975, Gumperz 1976, Pfaff 1976, 1979, Wentz 1977, Kachru 1978, Sankoff and Poplack 1981, Singh 1981, Woolford 1983, 1984a,b, 1985, Joshi 1985, Di Sciullo, Muysken, and Singh 1986, and references cited therein). The question, therefore, is not whether code switching obeys any structural constraints, but what the best way to characterize them is, and whether they can be made to follow from independently motivated, more general principles.3 For ease of exposition, we discuss

2 The data discussed in this article are drawn from King, Toribio, and Villarreal 1991 and Belazi 1991; the data were collected by eliciting grammaticality judgments and were further corroborated by recordings of natural conversation.

3 It is worth noting, however, that there are some linguists who have despaired of finding any constraints or principles underlying code switching. For example, Lance (1975) claims that there are perhaps no syntactic restrictions on where the switching can occur. Labov (1971:457) is often cited as referring to Spanish-English code switching as "the irregular mixture of two distinct systems." We briefly consider some possible expla- nations for these apparently contradictory findings. First, there is the issue of bilingual competence, already mentioned. Valdes (1976) found that patterns of alternation were similar for bilinguals of the same level of competence. Therefore, the divergent code-switching behavior on the part of bilinguals may derive from varia- tions among the speakers in their command of the component languages (see Zentella 1981). In fact, the distinction between matrix and embedded language that is crucial to much code-switching work may be in- dicative of a lack of balance in the two languages of the bilinguals whose speech is at issue. Second, there are attitudinal considerations. It has been found that although competence in two languages is necessary, it is an insufficient precondition for successful code switching. Valdes (1981) and Lipski (1985) claim that membership

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

CODE SWITCHING AND X-BAR THEORY 223

four general and often-cited principles, illustrated in (2)-(5), which have been formulated to constrain code switching. Later we relate the conclusion of our discussion to the equally well known conception of code switching set forth by Woolford (1983, 1984a,b, 1985).

(2) Government Constraint (Di Sciullo, Muysken, and Singh 1986) a. If Lq carrier has index q, then yqrax b. In a maximal projection ymax, the Lq carrier is the lexical element that

asymmetrically c-commands the other lexical elements or terminal phrase nodes dominated by ymax.

(3) Free Morpheme Constraint (Poplack 1981) A switch may occur at any point in the discourse at which it is possible to make a surface constituent cut and still retain a free morpheme.

(4) Equivalence Constraint (Poplack 1981) Codes will tend to be switched at points where the surface structures of the languages map onto each other.

(5) Constraint on Closed-Class Items (Joshi 1985) Closed-class items (e.g., determiners, quantifiers, prepositions, possessive, Aux, Tense, helping verbs) cannot be switched.

The Government Constraint of Di Sciullo, Muysken, and Singh (1986) disallows switching when a government relation holds between elements. In this way, they argue, the data fall out of a general principle of syntactic coherence that holds true of all natural language, not just of code switching. On this account, the Lq carrier of a governed category must have the same Lq index as its governor, as shown in (6).

(6) Xi

Y max Xq yq

Zq

in a community in which code switching is practiced and valued may also be a prerequisite for code switching. Third, the ease with which counterexamples to the constraints proposed for code switching are found may be attributable to differences in the methods of data collection and the selection of the data on which generalizations are based. We have cautioned that not all instances of language mixing can be considered code switching. Still, many researchers use the same labels to refer to different phenomena, failing to determine whether the speech sample under investigation in fact constitutes a code switch or instead represents some other mani- festation of language contact. Decisions concerning data collection and selection prove difficult in code-switch- ing research, given the nature of the data that are the focus of interest. Work on bilingual discourse has made use of a wide variety of methodologies, chief among these being interviews and naturalistic recordings. Un- fortunately, these approaches in isolation are of little value to a study of grammar; such methods yield data that may not reflect speakers' underlying linguistic competence (see Zentella 1985). It is clear that an analysis of some of these factors is a pressing topic of investigation for sociolinguists, psycholinguists, educators, and others.

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

224 HEDI M. BELAZI, EDWARD J. RUBIN, AND ALMEIDA JACQUELINE TORIBIO

It is the operation of Poplack's (1981) Free Morpheme Constraint that accounts for the nonoccurrence of the Spanish-English forms in (7).

(7) *Estoy eat-iendo. am eat-ING 'I am eating.'

In accordance with Poplack's (1981) Equivalence Constraint, code switching is allowed, for example, in (8a), where the grammars of Spanish and English coincide, but not in (8b), where the grammars differ with respect to the placement of object pronouns.

(8) a. (cs) The student brought the homework para la profesora. (Sp) El estudiante trajo la tarea para la profesora.

the student brought the homework for the professor (Eng) The student brought the homework for the professor.

b. (cs) *I saw lo. (Sp) ( Yo) lo vi.

I him/it saw (Eng) I saw him/it.

Finally, in Joshi's (1985) model, the Constraint on Closed-Class Items bars switching of closed-class items. Thus, for instance, the Marathi postposition cannot be switched for the English preposition, as shown in (9).

(9) *some chairs-war (Joshi 1985) some chairs-on 'on some chairs'

The first of these constraints, Di Sciullo, Muysken, and Singh's Government Con- straint, fails in that it is too restrictive. The constraint predicts, among other things, that the complementizer of a complement or relative clause must be in the same language as the governing head, rather than that of the complement clause. But, as demonstrated in the Spanish-English and Tunisian Arabic-French code switching in (10) and (11), the complementizer is in the language of the complement clause, not in the language of the governing head.

(10) a. The professor said que el estudiante habia recibido una A. the professor said that the student had received an A 'The professor said that the student had received an A.'

b. El profesor dijo that the student had received an A. the professor said that the student had received an A 'The professor said that the student had received an A.'

c. *The professor said that el estudiante habia recibido una A. the professor said that the student had received an A 'The professor said that the student had received an A.'

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

CODE SWITCHING AND X-BAR THEORY 225

d. *El profesor dijo que the student had received an A. the professor said that the student had received an A 'The professor said that the student had received an A.'

(11) a. Id-dwa qu' il m'a donne n'est pas bon. the-medicine that he me has given NEG is NEG good 'The medicine that he gave me is not good.'

b. Le medicament illi ?ta-hu:-li ma hu-s' baehi. the medicine that gave.he-it-me NEG it-NEG good 'The medicine that he gave me is not good.'

c. *Id-dwa illi il m'a donne n'est pas bon. the-medicine that he me has given NEG is NEG good 'The medicine that he gave me is not good.'

d. *Le medicament que ?ta-hu:-li ma hu-sg baehi. the medicine that gave.he-it-me NEG it-NEG good 'The medicine that he gave me is not good.'

The Government Constraint makes other incorrect predictions. In particular, it in- correctly predicts that the complements of a verb and the verb itself must be in the same language, in other words, that complement clauses, direct and indirect objects, and complement prepositional phrases must be in the same language as the verb. Moreover, it predicts that adjectives must be in the same language as the noun modified and that complements of a preposition must have the same language index as the preposition itself; as we will show, the data contradict these predictions.

Poplack's Free Morpheme Constraint and Equivalence Constraint fail in another way, in that they are insufficiently restrictive. The Free Morpheme Constraint states that code switching is impossible between a bound morpheme and its host. However, this constraint fails to explain why switching is impossible even between certain free morphemes. For example, note that switching is disallowed between the perfect auxili- ary, a free morpheme, and its complement, the past participle, as demonstrated in (12).

(12) a. *The students had visto la pelicula italiana. the students had seen the movie Italian 'The students had seen the Italian movie.'

b. *Los estudiantes habian seen the Italian movie. the students had seen the Italian movie 'The students had seen the Italian movie.'

c. *Je serai sae:fir-t fi-l-4as`ra. I-will.be went-I at-the-ten 'I will have gone by ten o'clock.'

d. *N-ku:n parti a dix heures. I-will.be gone at ten hours 'I will have gone by ten o'clock.'

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

226 HEDI M. BELAZI, EDWARD J. RUBIN, AND ALMEIDA JACQUELINE TORIBIO

That the Equivalence Constraint is also insufficiently restrictive is shown by ex- amples (10) through (12). In the case of Spanish-English code switching, switching should be possible at numerous junctures, including the one preceding the complement clause in (lOc-d) and preceding the past participle in (12a-b), since the word orders of Spanish and English are equivalent in these constructions. But, in fact, code switching is dis- allowed at these locations. Similarly, the grammars of Tunisian Arabic and French are parallel in the relative clause construction in (llc-d) and the perfective construction in (12c-d), yet code switching results in ungrammaticality. Switching is unacceptable between the complementizer and its clausal complement and between the perfective auxiliary and its complement. In other words, these elements must be in the language of their complements. These restrictions would have to be characterized by means of constraints functioning alongside the Equivalence Constraint.

It is worth mentioning here that in the data collected from educated Tunisian Arabic- French bilinguals, not one instance was found where a C0 was not in the language of its complement. In fact, speakers employed various circumlocutions in order to avoid such structures. Consider the attested example in (13a).

(13) a. C'est le fer qui donne . . . illi yi-ha:rib l'anemie. it's the iron that gives that it-fights the anemia 'It's iron that gives, that fights anemia.'

b. C'est le fer qui donne l'anemie. it's the iron that gives the anemia 'It's iron that gives anemia.'

c. *C'est le fer qui yi-ha:rib l'anemie. it's the iron that it-fights the anemia 'It's iron that fights anemia.'

d. C'est le fer illi yi-ha:rib l'anemie. it's the iron that it-fights the anemia 'It's iron that fights anemia.'

In this example the speaker starts with the French sentence (13b), C'est le fer qui donne l'ane'mie, which means 'It's iron that gives anemia'. Realizing his mistake, the speaker rephrases the sentence, bringing in the Tunisian Arabic verb ha:rib 'fight'. How- ever, this self-correction would initially lead to a switch between the French comple- mentizer and the Tunisian Arabic complement, which, as we showed above, is disallowed (13c). So the speaker backs up and changes the language of the complementizer to Tunisian Arabic (13d). Certainly linear order cannot account for this self-correction, as the Equivalence Constraint would predict; nor could the Free Morpheme Constraint, given that all the relevant morphemes are, in fact, free.

Similar restrictions obtain in switching between a determiner and its complement, as shown by the ungrammatical code-switched Spanish-English sentence in (14). (Note that the pattern in (14) is acceptable as an instance of borrowing, which we would indicate

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

CODE SWITCHING AND X-BAR THEORY 227

by writing the Spanish word in normal type, in order to indicate its reanalysis as English. This phenomenon must be carefully distinguished from the code switching under con- sideration here. It should be stated, however, that even fully competent code switchers are able to make use of this process (see footnote 1).)

(14) *He is a demonio. 'He is a devil.'

Since Spanish and English share the DP-internal order Det-N, the Equivalence Con- straint cannot be invoked in accounting for the unacceptability of (14) as a code-switched utterance.

In contrast, Joshi's Constraint on Closed-Class Items does make the correct pre- dictions for the code-switching data presented thus far: it predicts the inadmissibility of switching at the C?, 10, and D? already discussed. However, in drawing the closed-/open- class distinction, this constraint predicts that switching will be disallowed between a preposition, a closed-class item, and its complement, a prohibition that is not attested in the data under consideration here:4

(15) a. Sa Vae:t ni-tkalmu Val l'anemie. sometimes we-speak about the anemia 'Sometimes we speak about anemia.'

b. J'ai joue avec il-ku:ra. I have played with the-ball 'I played with the ball.'

More seriously, the Constraint on Closed-Class Items fails on theoretical grounds. The open-/closed-class distinction is not a grammatical notion and therefore should not im- pinge on the process of code switching, which, we claim, is governed by properly gram- matical principles. Thus, Joshi's constraint fails on empirical and theoretical grounds.

In summary, then, it is evident that Di Sciullo, Muysken, and Singh's Government Constraint is too restrictive. Although these authors are correct in positing that a struc- tural constraint is operative in code switching, the data indicate that only a subset of the places where government holds are impossible sites for switching. By contrast, Poplack's Free Morpheme Constraint and Equivalence Constraint go a long way toward accounting for the attested patterns of code switching, but they are insufficiently re- strictive, even when they are operating in conjunction, and thus allow a grammar to overgenerate. In addition, the Equivalence Constraint, which is formulated in linear terms, would weaken the theory of grammar as a whole; a theory of grammar that includes constraints formulated in linear terms is weaker than a theory of grammar that includes only hierarchically defined constraints. A similar criticism can be leveled against

4 The ungrammaticality of switching in the Marathi-English data presented in (9) may be explained on independent grounds, namely, the fact that Marathi is postpositional whereas English is prepositional; we return to this possibility in section 2.3.

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

228 HEDI M. BELAZI, EDWARD J. RUBIN, AND ALMEIDA JACQUELINE TORIBIO

the Constraint on Closed-Class Items: in relying on extragrammatical notions, it expands the set of grammatically significant categorial generalizations and, in so doing, diminishes the strength of the theory of grammar that includes it.

2 A New Analysis

2.1 Switching between a Functional Head and Its Complement

How, then, can we account for the attested patterns of grammaticality? We agree with Di Sciullo, Muysken, and Singh (1986) that the relevant constraints on code switching should be stated in hierarchical terms. Moreover, it is desirable to exploit distinctions and relations already present in the grammar. Therefore, in accounting for the attested data, we will invoke the well-established distinction between functional heads, such as Co and Do, and lexical heads, such as V0 and No.

Abney (1987) proposes that there exists a special relation between a functional head and its complement, which he calls f-selection. Following Chomsky (1993), we will as- sume that f-selection is one member of a set of feature-checking processes. If we assume also that one of the relevant features being checked is language, we then capture the patterns of grammaticality attested in code switching. That is, we assume that a functional head requires that the language feature of its complement match its own language feature, just as it might require some other feature of its complement to match its own corre- sponding feature (e.g., the tense of C0 'for' must be matched by the tense of IP, which must therefore be headed by 'to'). We will refer to the effects of the feature-checking process in its application to the language feature of functional heads and their comple- ments as the Functional Head Constraint, under the assumption that this is a specific application of a more general process. This constraint is given in (16).

(16) The Functional Head Constraint The language feature of the complement f-selected by a functional head, like all other relevant features, must match the corresponding feature of that func- tional head.

The Functional Head Constraint is operative in all speech, although, of course, the effects of checking of the language feature become apparent only in code switching, and, in particular, in switching between a functional head and its complement. This is not surprising since functional heads are generally required to select the features of their complements, and, we claim, language is one such feature. On this view, it is to be expected that the language feature is checked in all and only those domains in which it is standardly assumed that f-selection of features obtains. As predicted, code switching between a lexical head and its complement proceeds unimpeded; we present such data in section 2.2.

The Functional Head Constraint, henceforth FHC, thus restricts switching between a functional head and its complement by invoking the strong relation that exists between them. Switching is disallowed between a C0 and its IP complement, as in (10) and (11),

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

CODE SWITCHING AND X-BAR THEORY 229

and between D? and NP, as in (14). Let us now turn to consider other categories that have been identified as functional heads, to determine whether they too behave in accordance with the FHC.

Ritter (1991) has identified a functional category, Nom, which is intermediate be- tween DP and NP and is headed by such elements as quantifiers and numbers. We predict that switching will be disallowed between Nom and its complement NP. This prediction is borne out by the data that follow:

(17) a. Ktib dix livres. wrote.he ten books 'He wrote ten books.'

b. *Ktib ?as'ra livres. wrote.he ten books 'He wrote ten books.'

(18) a. Pocos estudiantes finished the exam. few students finished the exam 'Few students finished the exam.'

b. *Pocos students finished the exam. few students finished the exam 'Few students finished the exam.'

Pollock (1989) has identified Neg? as a functional head. We predict that switching should be unacceptable between Nege and its complement VP; again, the data bear this out:

(19) a. *Je ne hib-ha pas. I NEG like-it NEG

'I don't like it.' b. *Ana ma l'aime-s'.

I NEG it like-NEG 'I don't like it.'

(20) a. *EI hombre no wants the book. the man NEG wants the book 'The man doesn't want the book.'

b. *The man doesn't quiere el libro. the man doesn't wants the book 'The man doesn't want the book.'

Rivero (to appear) has identified Modal as a functional head; as predicted, switching is disallowed between a modal auxiliary and VP:

(21) a. *Je serai sae.fir-tfi-1-Vasra. I will.be went-I at-the-ten 'I will have gone by ten o'clock.'

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

230 HEDI M. BELAZI, EDWARD J. RUBIN, AND ALMEIDA JACQUELINE TORIBIO

b. *N-ku:n parti 'a dix heures. I-will.be gone at ten hours 'I will have gone by ten o'clock.'

c. Je serai parti fi-l- Vas'ra. I will.be gone at-the-ten 'I will have gone by ten o'clock.'

d. N-ku:n sae.fir-t a dix heures. I-will.be went-I at ten hours 'I will have gone by ten o'clock.'

(22) a. *The police officers have visto un ladron. the police officers have seen a thief 'The police officers have seen a thief.'

b. *Los policias han seen a thief. the police officers have seen a thief 'The police officers have seen a thief.'

c. The police officers have seen un ladron. the police officers have seen a thief 'The police officers have seen a thief.'

d. Los polici[as han visto a thief. the police officers have seen a thief 'The police officers have seen a thief.'

Thus, independently motivated functional heads exhibit the behavior predicted by the FHC. Note that the elements of the recently rearticulated Infl are analyzed as func- tional heads and thus, we predict, are subject to the FHC. Furthermore, if our proposal is correct, code-switching data can provide independent empirical corroboration for proposed functional heads: any proposed functional head must obey the FHC.

2.2 Switching between a Lexical Head and Its Complement

In contrast to the restriction against switching between a functional head and its com- plement, switching between a lexical head and its complement occurs quite freely. (23) demonstrates the possibility of switching between a verb and its complement, and (24) demonstrates the possibility of switching between a preposition and its complement.

(23) They used to serve bebidas alcoholicas en ese restaurante. they used to serve drinks alcoholic in that restaurant 'They used to serve alcoholic beverages in that restaurant.'

(24) SaVae:t ni-tkalmu Lal l'anemie. sometimes we-speak about the anemia 'Sometimes we speak about anemia.'

Thus, it has been demonstrated that all, and only, functional heads fall under the

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

CODE SWITCHING AND X-BAR THEORY 231

scope of the relevant constraint. Moreover, if we are correct in positing the Functional Head Constraint, then we can subsume the Free Morpheme Constraint under our anal- ysis, given current proposals (e.g., Rivero, to appear, Chomsky 1991, Baker, Johnson, and Roberts 1989, Kayne 1989, Pollock 1989) in which inflectional morphemes are treated as functional heads. The fact that switching is disallowed between a head and an in- flectional morpheme, as in (25) and (26), can be viewed as evidence in favor of these analyses, given the treatment of code switching put forward here.

(25) *Suf-t da:r-s. saw-I house-PL 'I saw the houses.'

(26) *We dance-amos chacha. we dance-IPL cha-cha 'We dance cha-cha.'

To summarize the discussion thus far, we have demonstrated that code switching is restricted by the relation of f-selection in the manner discussed above. The proposed Functional Head Constraint accounts for the nonoccurrence of switching between a functional head and its complement. In positing the FHC, we subsume the Free Mor- pheme Constraint, the Equivalence Constraint, and, to the extent that they are correct, the Government Constraint and the Constraint on Closed-Class Items, under a more general principle.5

5 An apparent problem for our analysis was brought to our attention by an anonymous reviewer; the difficulty lies in determining the language of an IP. Consider in this respect the contrast illustrated by the following sentences:

(i) Je lui ai dit [que [les enfants [xarz-u]]]. I him have told that the children left-they 'I told him that the children left.'

(ii) *Je lui ai dit [illi [les enfants [xarz-u]]]. I him have told that the children left-they 'I told him that the children left.'

An analysis of these patterns of grammaticality requires further discussion. Let us assume a strict cyclical application of the FHC, in the spirit of Chomsky (1993). Within I', then, the FHC is met: on the well-motivated assumption that I? contains only the abstract (i.e., language-free) feature specification [3pl, + tense], I is not in conflict with the [ + Arabic] VP. On this account, the verb is base-generated with its morphology, as again suggested by Chomsky. A functional head that is null, like 10, is thus "language-free" in the sense that it is unmarked with respect to the language feature and thus, in this domain, does not conflict with the positive feature marking of its complement (overt auxiliaries, on the other hand, bear the language feature of the overt lexical items). Next, within the domain of IP, 10 acquires the specification [ + French] by agreement with the French specifier (a function of spec-head agreement), and this feature percolates up to IP. Thus, I? may have different specifications according to the domain under consideration. Given that we assume strict cyclicity, the FHC cannot look back at the previous cycle to reevaluate the head-complement relation. Moving up to the domain of C', we note that Co must be [ + French], as is IP, in order for the structure to be well formed according to the FHC. Since Co is not null, it is marked with the language feature, here [ + Arabic]. Thus, the FHC correctly predicts that (ii) is ungrammatical. (It is worth noting that the raising of the Arabic verb to 10 does not change 10 to [+Arabic] since raising is merely adjunction to 10 (Pollock 1989); that is, 10 remains [ + French] in the domain of IP.)

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

232 HEDI M. BELAZI, EDWARD J. RUBIN, AND ALMEIDA JACQUELINE TORIBIO

2.3 Switching between Heads and Modifiers

What of switching between an adjective and the noun it modifies? The component lan- guages of the code-switching samples under consideration differ with respect to the placement of adjectives. Tunisian Arabic allows adjectives only in postnominal position; by contrast, French allows postnominal adjectives and a small set of prenominal adjec- tives, for example, beau 'beautiful, nice'. And whereas English allows prenominal ad- jectives except when these adjectives occur with a complement or an adjunct and are therefore not head-final, Spanish allows postnominal adjectives and a small set of pre- nominal adjectives. How does the code switcher reconcile the difference in adjective placement? Consider the data in (27).

(27) a. J'ai une voiture mizyaena. I have a car nice 'I have a beautiful car.'

b. *i'and-i karhba belle. at-I car nice 'I have a beautiful car.'

The data indicate that switching is possible where the adjectives and nouns obey the grammars of the languages from which they are drawn. Since Tunisian Arabic ad- jectives are postnominal, mizyaena 'nice' must appear postnominally in a code-switching environment, as in (27a). Since French nouns can look to the right for adjectival modi- fication, voiture 'car' is satisfied. By contrast, the sentence in (27b) indicates that, even though the Tunisian Arabic noun karhba 'car' is satisfied by looking to the right for adjectival modification, switching is not possible because the French adjective belle 'nice', a member of the set of French prenominal adjectives, does not obey the grammar of French with respect to its placement.

Let us assume that the principle in (28) is operative in all linguistic behavior. In accordance with (28), a word obeys the grammar (i.e., the grammatical constraints) of the language from which it is drawn.

(28) The Word-Grammar Integrity Corollary A word of language X, with grammar Gx, must obey grammar Gx.

The Word-Grammar Integrity Corollary (WGIC) derives from the assumption, following Chomsky (1993), that lexical entries are associated with morphological and syntactic features. Since this is true of all lexical entries in all languages, it must be true of code switching as well.

Consider now the phrases in (29)-(30), from Spanish-English code switching.

(29) a. *la mujer proud the woman proud 'the proud woman'

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

CODE SWITCHING AND X-BAR THEORY 233

b. *the woman orgullosa the woman proud 'the proud woman'

(30) a. Ia mujer proud of her position the woman proud of her position 'the woman proud of her position'

b. the woman orgullosa de su puesto the woman proud of her position 'the woman proud of her position'

(29a) is predicted to be ungrammatical by the WGIC since, even though the Spanish noun mujer 'woman' is satisfied by finding an adjective to its right, the grammar of English requires that 'proud' be prenominal. (29b) is also predicted to be ungrammatical, but for different reasons: the Spanish adjective orgullosa 'proud' must appear postnom- inally, but the English noun must be modified to its left by a simple adjective.6

How can we account for (30a)? Let us assume that English grammar contains a frequently attested constraint on prenominal modifiers, namely, that they be head-final. This constraint, for whatever reason it may exist, accounts for the postnominal position of English APs with complements, as in the gloss of (30a). We therefore predict that such an English AP could appear postnominally in a code-switched phrase with a Spanish noun that looks for an adjective to the right, precisely the situation presented in (30a).

(30b) is explained in a similar way. The English noun woman in (30b) can be modified by an AP to the right if and only if that AP is not head-final. The Spanish AP orgullosa de su puesto 'proud of her position' is not head-final and does appear to the right, where Spanish APs normally occur. Thus, the grammars of all the words are satisfied, and the WGIC correctly distinguishes between (29) and (30).

The ill-formedness of Joshi's data in (9) can be handled in like fashion. Recall that in Marathi-English code switching, the Marathi postposition cannot follow an English noun. The ungrammaticality of sentences such as (9) led Joshi to posit his Constraint on Closed-Class Items. On the other hand, we claim that the ungrammaticality of the code switch is due to independent constraints on the directionality of Case assignment. An English NP looks to its left for Case, just as an English noun looks to its left for simple adjectival modification. The English NP is thus not satisfied, even though the Marathi Case assigner assigns Case to the left and is located to the right.

3 Conclusion

We have seen that a principles-and-parameters style approach to Universal Grammar, such as the one proposed here, can account not only for unilingual competence, but also

6 These examples are also correctly predicted by the Equivalence Constraint. However, we have pointed out that the WGIC has more general applications and is thus preferable.

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

234 HEDI M. BELAZI, EDWARD J. RUBIN, AND ALMEIDA JACQUELINE TORIBIO

for code-switching competence (see also Rubin and Toribio, to appear).7 By invoking the FHC, an empirically necessitated modification of Abney's notion of f-selection, together with the WGIC, we can now account for code-switching data without recourse to any ad hoc constraint or intergrammar of code switching, as favored by considerations of economy. In fact, this idea is not altogether new: Woolford (1984a:78), in accounting for code switching in wh-constructions, formulates a conception of code switching ac- cording to which ". . . the pattern of grammatical and ungrammatical code-switching versions of these constructions follow[s] entirely from principles of grammar in the Gov- ernment Binding framework that apply to monolingual sentences and no additional stip- ulations unique to code-switching have to be added." The hypothesis developed here, and further articulated in Toribio and Rubin, to appear, is likewise consistent with a research program in which patterns of code switching are thought to be not only rule- governed, but constrained solely by Universal Grammar.

References

Abbassi, Abdelaziz. 1977. A sociolinguistic analysis of multilingualism in Morocco. Doctoral dis- sertation, University of Texas at Austin.

Abney, Steven P. 1987. The English noun phrase in its sentential aspect. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.

Baker, Mark, Kyle Johnson, and Ian Roberts. 1989. Passive arguments raised. Linguistic Inquiry 20:219-251.

Belazi, Hedi M. 1991. Multilingualism in Tunisia and code-switching among educated Tunisian bilinguals. Doctoral dissertation, Cornell University, Ithaca, N.Y.

Bentahila, Abdelali, and Eirlys E. Davies. 1983. The syntax of Arabic-French code-switching. Lingua 59:301-330.

Chomsky, Noam. 1991. Some notes on economy of derivation and representation. In Principles and parameters in comparative grammar, ed. Robert Freidin, 417-454. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Chomsky, Noam. 1993. A minimalist program for linguistic theory. In The view from Building 20: Essays in linguistics in honor of Sylvain Bromberger, ed. Kenneth Hale and Samuel Jay Keyser, 1-52. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Di Sciullo, Anne-Marie, Pieter Muysken, and Rajendra Singh. 1986. Government and code-mixing. Journal of Linguistics 22:1-24.

Eid, Mushira. 1988. Principles for code-switching between Standard and Egyptian Arabic. Al- cArabiyya 21:51-79.

7 In Rubin and Toribio, to appear, we make clear the natural role that the FHC plays in the general theory of grammar proposed by Chomsky (1993). Specifically, we argue that Chomsky's work indicates a context in which it is quite natural to expand Abney's notion of f-selection to include the selection of a matching language feature. In Chomsky's system, functional heads check features of elements in their checking domains only. The FHC ensures that the features of functional heads match the features of their internal domains. Combining Chomsky's notion of morphological checking with the notion of f-selection reformalized as the FHC provides a conception of grammar in which functional heads have a unified role. Not only do functional heads act as checkers of the Case features of elements in their checking domains, but they also relate to the elements of their internal domain by means of abstract feature-matching. In this way, f-selection, as conceived in the FHC, is of a similar nature to morphological checking, and together they form a natural class of processes by which derivations are driven.

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

CODE SWITCHING AND X-BAR THEORY 235

Gingras, Rosario. 1974. Problems in the description of Spanish/English intrasentential code- switching. In Southwest areal linguistics, ed. Garland D. Bills, 167-174. San Diego, Calif.: University of California Institute for Cultural Pluralism.

Gumperz, John J. 1976. The sociolinguistic significance of conversational code-switching. In Papers on language and context: Working papers 46, 1-46. Language Behavior Research Laboratory, University of California at Berkeley.

Joshi, Aravind. 1985. Processing of sentences with intrasentential code switching. In Natural language parsing: Psychological, computational and theoretical perspectives, ed. David R. Dowty, Lauri Karttunen, and Arnold M. Zwicky, 190-205. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- versity Press.

Kachru, Braj. 1978. Toward structuring code-mixing: An Indian perspective. International Journal of the Sociology of Language 16:28-46.

Kayne, Richard. 1989. Null subjects and clitic climbing. In The null subject parameter, ed. Osvaldo Jaeggli and Kenneth J. Safir, 239-261. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

King, Andrew, Almeida J. Toribio, and Regina Villarreal. 1991. The correlation of a code-switching syntactic hierarchy to the degree of language balance/dominance in Spanish-English bilin- guals. Paper presented at the Twelfth Symposium on Spanish and Portuguese Bilingualism, Florida International University, January 1991.

Labov, William. 1971. The notion of "system" in creole languages. In Pidginization and cre- olization of languages, ed. Dell Hymes, 447-472. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Lance, Donald. 1975. Spanish-English code-switching. In El lenguaje de los Chicanos: Regional and social characteristics used by Mexican Americans, ed. Eduardo Hernandez-Chavez, Andrew D. Cohen, and Anthony F. Beltramo, 138-153. Arlington, Va.: Center for Applied Linguistics.

Lipski, John M. 1985. Linguistic aspects of Spanish-English language switching. Special Studies #25. Center for Latin American Studies, Arizona State University, Phoenix.

M'barek, Mohamed Nait, and David Sankoff. 1988. Le discours mixte arabe/francais: emprunts ou alternances de langue? Canadian Journal of Linguistics 33:143-154.

Pfaff, Carol W. 1976. Functional and structural constraints on syntactic variation in code-switch- ing. In Papers from the Parasession on Diachronic Syntax, 248-259. Chicago Linguistic Society, University of Chicago, Chicago, Ill.

Pfaff, Carol W. 1979. Constraints on language mixing: Intrasentential code-switching and bor- rowing in Spanish/English. Language 55:291-318.

Pollock, Jean-Yves. 1989. Verb movement, Universal Grammar, and the structure of IP. Linguistic Inquiry 20:365-424.

Poplack, Shana. 1980. Sometimes I'll start a sentence in Spanish and termino en Espanlol: Toward a typology of code-switching. In Spanish in the United States: Sociolinguistic aspects, ed. Jon Amastae and Lucia Elfas-Olivares, 230-263. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Poplack, Shana. 1981. Syntactic structure and social function of codeswitching. In Latino lan- guage and communicative behavior, ed. Richard P. Duran, 169-184. Norwood, N.J.: Ablex.

Poplack, Shana. 1983. Bilingual competence: Linguistic interference or grammatical integrity? In Spanish in the U.S. setting: Beyond the Southwest, ed. Lucia Elfas-Olivares, 107-129. Rosslyn, Va.: National Clearinghouse for Bilingual Education.

Ritter, Elizabeth. 1991. Two functional categories in noun phrases: Evidence from Modern He- brew. In Perspectives on phrase structure: Heads and licensing (Syntax and Semantics 25), ed. Susan D. Rothstein, 37-62. San Diego, Calif.: Academic Press.

Rivero, Maria-Luisa. To appear. Clause structure and V-movement in the languages of the Bal- kans. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 11.

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

236 HEDI M. BELAZI, EDWARD J. RUBIN, AND ALMEIDA JACQUELINE TORIBIO

Rubin, Edward J., and Almeida J. Toribio. To appear. Feature checking and the syntax of language contact. In Selected papers from the XXII Linguistic Symposium on Romance Languages, ed. Jon Amastae, Grant Goodall, Mario Montalbetti, and Marianne Phinney. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

Sankoff, David, and Shana Poplack. 1981. A formal grammar for code-switching. Papers in Lin- guistics 14:3-45.

Singh, Rajendra. 1981. Grammatical constraints on code-mixing: Evidence from Hindi-English. Canadian Journal of Linguistics 30:33-45.

Stevens, Paul. 1974. French and Arabic bilingualism in North Africa with special reference to Tunisia: A study of language attitudes and language use patterns. Doctoral dissertation, Georgetown University, Washington, D.C.

Timm, L. A. 1975. Spanish-English code-switching. El porque and how-not-to. Romance Philology 28:473-482.

Toribio, Almeida Jacqueline, and Edward J. Rubin. To appear. Code-switching in generative grammar. In Spanish in contact, ed. John Jensen and Ana Roca. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

Valdds, Guadalupe. 1976. Social interaction and code-switching patterns. In Bilingualism in the bicentennial and beyond, ed. Gary D. Keller, Richard V. Teschner, and Silvia Viera, 52- 85. Jamaica, N.Y.: Bilingual Press.

Valdes, Guadalupe. 1981. Code switching as deliberate verbal strategy: A microanalysis of direct and indirect requests among bilingual Chicano speakers. In Latino language and com- municative behavior, ed. Richard P. Duran, 95-107. Norwood, N.J.: Ablex.

Wentz, James Paul. 1977. Some considerations in the development of a syntactic description of code-switching. Doctoral dissertation, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.

Woolford, Ellen. 1983. Bilingual code-switching and syntactic theory. Linguistic Inquiry 14:520- 536.

Woolford, Ellen. 1984a. On the application of wh-movement and inversion in code-switching sentences. Revue Quebecoise de Linguistique 14:77-86.

Woolford, Ellen. 1984b. Systematic differences in the code-switching judgments of balanced ver- sus second-language bilinguals. Paper presented at the VIII Symposium on Spanish and Portuguese Bilingualism, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, November 1984.

Woolford, Ellen. 1985. Transformations and constituent structure in code-switching. Paper pre- sented at the Linguistic Theory and Second Language Acquisition Working Conference, MIT, October 1985.

Zentella, Ana Celia. 1981. "Hablamos los dos, we speak both": Growing up bilingual in el barrio. Doctoral dissertation, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia.

Zentella, Ana Celia. 1985. The fate of Spanish in the United States: The Puerto Rican experience. In Language of inequality (Contributions to the Sociology of Language 36), ed. Nessa Wolfson and Joan Manes, 41-59. Amsterdam: Mouton.

(Belazi) English Department Institute of Banking/SAMA P.O. Box 10820 Riyadh 11443 Saudi Arabia

(Rubin) Department of Modern Languages and Linguistics Cornell University 203 Morrill Hall Ithaca, New York 148534701

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

CODE SWITCHING AND X-BAR THEORY 237

and

Program in Linguistics 316 H.B.C. Syracuse University Syracuse, New York 13244

(Toribio) Department of Spanish and Portuguese University of California Santa Barbara, California 931064150

This content downloaded from 27.147.173.52 on Fri, 7 Feb 2014 12:43:05 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions