consciousness and cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 r. kanai et al./consciousness and cognition xxx...

13
Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual and attentional failures of awareness Ryota Kanai a, * , Vincent Walsh a , Chia-huei Tseng b,c a Institute of Cognitive Neuroscience & Dept. of Psychology, University College London, 17 Queen Square, WC1N 3AR London, United Kingdom b Department of Psychology, National Taiwan University, Taipei, Taiwan c Department of Psychology, The University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong article info Article history: Received 2 January 2010 Available online xxxx Keywords: Visual awareness Attention Signal detection theory Type II Attentional blindness Perceptual blindness Vision abstract Conscious visual perception can fail in many circumstances. However, little is known about the causes and processes leading to failures of visual awareness. In this study, we introduce a new signal detection measure termed subjective discriminability of invisibility (SDI) that allows one to distinguish between subjective blindness due to reduction of sensory signals or to lack of attentional access to sensory signals. The SDI is computed based upon subjec- tive confidence in reporting the absence of a target (i.e., miss and correct rejection trials). Using this new measure, we found that target misses were subjectively indistinguishable from physical absence when contrast reduction, backward masking and flash suppression were used, whereas confidence was appropriately modulated when dual task, attentional blink and spatial uncertainty methods were employed. These results show that failure of visual perception can be identified as either a result of perceptual or attentional blindness depending on the circumstances under which visual awareness was impaired. Ó 2010 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. 1. Introduction Conscious visual perception can be impaired in many circumstances such as when a visual stimulus is degraded or when we are distracted by other stimuli (Kim & Blake, 2005). Such instances of stimulus blindness have revealed that visual stimuli are processed in many brain regions even when they do not reach visual awareness (Lin & He, 2009). However, the causes and processes leading to failure of visual awareness are likely to be different depending on the circumstances under which visual awareness is impaired. Disruption of visual awareness could occur when stimulus signals are degraded to the degree that they are hardly indistinguishable from any signal at all (Dehaene, Changeux, Nacache, Sackur, & Sergant, 2006; Lamme, 2003, 2004). Even if sensory signals remain strong, they could go unnoticed when attention was distracted by other stimuli (Chun & Potter, 1995; Dehaene et al., 2006; Norman & Bobrow, 1975; Pashler, 1994; Sigman & Dehaene, 2006)(Fig. 1). In other words, psychophysically induced unawareness seems to be divided into perceptual blindness, in which subjective invisibility is caused by suppression of low-level sensory signals, and attentional blindness, in which observers fail to notice the presence of a target due to failure to access low-level signals despite their presence. However, it has been difficult to operationally distinguish these causes of blindness. Yet, the distinction of the two is critical for understanding the neuronal mechanisms underlying conscious visual perception (Block, 2007; Lamme, 2006). The two levels of awareness failure have also been proposed on the basis of neuroimaging studies of conscious face per- ception (Block, 2007). In a study with binocular rivalry with faces and houses as stimuli, the activity in the fusiform face area (FFA) was suppressed when conscious perception of a face was impaired by a competing stimulus presented to the other eye 1053-8100/$ - see front matter Ó 2010 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003 * Corresponding author. Fax: +44 020 7813 2835. E-mail addresses: [email protected], [email protected] (R. Kanai). Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Consciousness and Cognition journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/concog Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual and attentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Upload: others

Post on 12-Aug-2020

4 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Consciousness and Cognition

journal homepage: www.elsevier .com/locate /concog

Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework fordistinguishing perceptual and attentional failures of awareness

Ryota Kanai a,*, Vincent Walsh a, Chia-huei Tseng b,c

a Institute of Cognitive Neuroscience & Dept. of Psychology, University College London, 17 Queen Square, WC1N 3AR London, United Kingdomb Department of Psychology, National Taiwan University, Taipei, Taiwanc Department of Psychology, The University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong

a r t i c l e i n f o

Article history:Received 2 January 2010Available online xxxx

Keywords:Visual awarenessAttentionSignal detection theoryType IIAttentional blindnessPerceptual blindnessVision

1053-8100/$ - see front matter � 2010 Elsevier Incdoi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

* Corresponding author. Fax: +44 020 7813 2835E-mail addresses: [email protected], kanair@gma

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., etattentional failures of awareness. Consciousne

a b s t r a c t

Conscious visual perception can fail in many circumstances. However, little is known aboutthe causes and processes leading to failures of visual awareness. In this study, we introducea new signal detection measure termed subjective discriminability of invisibility (SDI) thatallows one to distinguish between subjective blindness due to reduction of sensory signalsor to lack of attentional access to sensory signals. The SDI is computed based upon subjec-tive confidence in reporting the absence of a target (i.e., miss and correct rejection trials).Using this new measure, we found that target misses were subjectively indistinguishablefrom physical absence when contrast reduction, backward masking and flash suppressionwere used, whereas confidence was appropriately modulated when dual task, attentionalblink and spatial uncertainty methods were employed. These results show that failure ofvisual perception can be identified as either a result of perceptual or attentional blindnessdepending on the circumstances under which visual awareness was impaired.

� 2010 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.

1. Introduction

Conscious visual perception can be impaired in many circumstances such as when a visual stimulus is degraded or whenwe are distracted by other stimuli (Kim & Blake, 2005). Such instances of stimulus blindness have revealed that visual stimuliare processed in many brain regions even when they do not reach visual awareness (Lin & He, 2009). However, the causes andprocesses leading to failure of visual awareness are likely to be different depending on the circumstances under which visualawareness is impaired. Disruption of visual awareness could occur when stimulus signals are degraded to the degree that theyare hardly indistinguishable from any signal at all (Dehaene, Changeux, Nacache, Sackur, & Sergant, 2006; Lamme, 2003,2004). Even if sensory signals remain strong, they could go unnoticed when attention was distracted by other stimuli (Chun& Potter, 1995; Dehaene et al., 2006; Norman & Bobrow, 1975; Pashler, 1994; Sigman & Dehaene, 2006) (Fig. 1). In otherwords, psychophysically induced unawareness seems to be divided into perceptual blindness, in which subjective invisibilityis caused by suppression of low-level sensory signals, and attentional blindness, in which observers fail to notice the presenceof a target due to failure to access low-level signals despite their presence. However, it has been difficult to operationallydistinguish these causes of blindness. Yet, the distinction of the two is critical for understanding the neuronal mechanismsunderlying conscious visual perception (Block, 2007; Lamme, 2006).

The two levels of awareness failure have also been proposed on the basis of neuroimaging studies of conscious face per-ception (Block, 2007). In a study with binocular rivalry with faces and houses as stimuli, the activity in the fusiform face area(FFA) was suppressed when conscious perception of a face was impaired by a competing stimulus presented to the other eye

. All rights reserved.

.il.com (R. Kanai).

al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andss and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Page 2: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

Fig. 1. A schematic conceptualization of perceptual and attentional blindness (A) and contingency matrices used in the analyses of classical Type II task andin subjective discriminability of invisibility (B and C). Usually conscious report consists of sufficient neuronal responses at a sensory processing stage andaccess of the information at a decision stage for a report. However, if the sensory information is not accessed successfully, conscious report is hindereddespite the presence of strong responses of sensory neurons (Attentional blindness). If sensory signals are suppressed in an early stage, conscious report ishampered despite the attempt to cognitively access the information (Perceptual blindness). (B) A Type II performance is calculated by substituting correcttrials with high confidence as ‘‘hits” and incorrect trials with high confidence as ‘‘false alarms” at a second-level, respectively. (C) In the calculation of SDI,instead of aggregating hit (or miss) and correct rejection (or false alarm) trials as correct (or incorrect) trials, the second-level contingency matrix isconstructed only for trials on which observers reported the absence of a target, i.e., correct rejections and misses.

2 R. Kanai et al. / Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx

(Tong, Nakayama, Vaughan, & Kanwisher, 1998). On the other hand, a visual extinction patient exhibited FFA activity evenwhen he failed to consciously register the face presented in his left visual field due to a competing stimulus on the right (Reeset al., 2000). The former case of binocular rivalry can be interpreted as suppression of visual signals in FFA or even at earlierstages, whereas the latter case appears to be due to lack of attentional (or cognitive) access to the information of the facepresent in the FFA.

Despite the mounting evidence, it has been difficult to operationally distinguish at a behavioural level the suppression oflow-level sensory signals and failure to access sensory signals, because they both result in the same responses, i.e., reports ofabsence of stimuli. Moreover, the fact that attention often boosts sensory signals independent of awareness (Koch &Tsuchiya, 2007) makes it difficult to separate the effect of attentional access from modulation of sensory signals.

The goal of the present study was to introduce a framework to distinguish perceptual and attentional blindness andexamine the framework in light of empirical data from a series of psychophysical experiments. To illustrate the idea behindthe development of such a framework, we first provide an overview of signal detection theory (SDT) (Green & Swets, 1966;Macmillan & Creelman, 2005) as applied in awareness studies and discuss their limitations.

1.1. Objective sensitivity: Type I signal detection theory

The most common use of SDT in experimental psychology is a Type I task in which observers make decisions in a pres-ence–absence judgment task or in a stimulus discrimination task. In Type I SDT, objective sensitivity independent of decisioncriterion is computed. In a presence–absence judgment task, for example, observers make judgments as to whether a stim-ulus is present or absent. Trials in a presence–absence judgment task are categorized into the following four types:

1. Type I hits: stimulus present & response present.2. Type I correct rejections: stimulus absent & response absent.3. Type I misses: stimulus present & response absent.4. Type I false alarms: stimulus absent & response present.

From the z-scores of hit and false alarm rates (i.e., hits as a proportion of present trials and false alarms as a proportion ofabsent trials), sensitivity measures such as d0 or the AUC (the Area Under the ROC curve) are computed and they are used ascriterion free measures of sensitivity (see a standard textbook on SDT for the formulas of these measures; e.g., Green & Swets,1966; Macmillan & Creelman, 2005).

Null sensitivity to a stimulus (i.e., d0 � 0, misses and false alarms make up 50% of responses) has been used as evidence ofno awareness under experimental situations (e.g., Dagenbach, Carr, & Wilhelmsen, 1989; Eriksen, 1960; Fowler, Wolford,Slade, & Tassinary, 1981; Kemp-Wheeler & Hill, 1988; Marcel, 1983; Nolan & Caramazza, 1982; Schurger, Pereira, Tresiman,

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andattentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Page 3: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

R. Kanai et al. / Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx 3

& Cohen, 2009; Schwiedrzik, Singer, & Melloni, 2009). The advantage of using objective Type I sensitivity as a marker forabsence of awareness is that it does not involve subjective estimates of awareness and thus provides a conservative criterionwhen experimenters wish to ensure that stimuli evoked no awareness (Cheesman & Merikle, 1984).

However, this criterion may be too stringent to capture the nature of awareness in some cases. For example, blindsightpatients with a lesion to the visual cortex can detect visual stimuli above a chance level while they claim to have no sub-jective experiences of the stimuli (Stoerig & Cowey, 1997; Weiskrantz, 1998). Similar situations have been reported in nor-mal healthy observers under various experimental conditions (Kolb & Braun, 1995; Lau & Passingham, 2006). Objectivesensitivity as measured by Type I SDT would indicate that observers are aware of the stimuli in these situations, becausethey could detect the presence of a stimulus. However, this is in contradiction with the subjective reports of absence ofawareness. Thus, the objective sensitivity (e.g., d0 = 0) is insufficient to capture possible dissociations between objective per-formance and subjective report of conscious percepts.

1.2. Subjective sensitivity: Type II signal detection analysis

One way to overcome the limitation of the objective criterion of awareness is to collect introspective reports of observers’confidence while performing an objective Type I task. In the classical Type II task, observers are asked to report their con-fidence of their correctness in an objective Type I task and the relationship between objective correctness and subjective con-fidence is analyzed (Fig. 1B). The idea is that if observers were aware of a stimulus, their correct responses would beaccompanied by high confidence, while low confidence would be linked with incorrect trials. Thus, if observers were awareof stimuli, they would be able to adjust their confidence according to correctness of their responses.

Performance in a Type II task – observers’ ability to distinguish their objective correctness based on confidence ratings – iscalculated from the following four types of second-level responses:

1. Type II hits: correct response & high confidence.2. Type II correct rejections: incorrect response & low confidence.3. Type II misses: correct response & low confidence.4. Type II false alarms: incorrect response & high confidence.

From the proportions of Type II Hits and Type II False Alarms, criterion-free sensitivity measures such as d0 or AUC can becomputed (Galvin, Podd, Drga, & Whitmore, 2003; Kunimoto, Miller, & Pashler, 2001; Pollack & Decker, 1958), and Type II per-formance has been used as a criterion for conscious awareness (Kolb & Braun, 1995; Kunimoto et al., 2001; Persaud, McLeod, &Cowey, 2007; Szczepanowski & Pessoa, 2007). The idea is that if Type I performance is above chance, but Type II performance isat chance, the observers cannot access the sensory signals used for the Type I task. The recently proposed post-decision wager-ing (PDW) is a variant of Type II task in which observers are asked to wager on their Type I decision (Persaud et al., 2007). ThePDW has been successfully applied to capture a variety of dissociations between objective performance and subjective aware-ness including blindsight (Persaud et al., 2007; but see Clifford, Arabzadeh, & Harris, 2008; Dienes & Seth, 2010).

While this approach has been successful in capturing the subjective nature of conscious awareness, the classical Type II taskis not suitable for probing the different mechanisms underlying miss trials. As we argue in the next section, it is essential to keepseparate the four trial types (i.e., hits, correct rejections, misses and false alarms) without aggregating them as correct (hits andcorrect rejections) and incorrect trials (misses and false alarms). However, the classical Type II tasks reported to date alwayscombined hits and correct rejections as correct trials and misses and false alarms as incorrect trials. This aggregation doesnot allow separate analyses on the confidences of misses from those of false alarms, despite their potentially very differentcauses of errors. Moreover, most studies in the past employed a discrimination task between orientations (Wilmzig, Tsuchiya,Fahle, Einhäuser, & Koch, 2008), shapes (Lau & Passingham, 2006) or locations (Szczepanowski & Pessoa, 2007). In such cases,hits and correct rejections were interchangeable and were thus arbitrarily assigned to one response or to the other.

1.3. Dissociation of perceptual blindness and attentional blindness

To dissociate perceptual blindness and attentional blindness, the four trial types need to be kept separate instead ofaggregating them as correct and incorrect trials. This is because perceptual and attentional blindness make distinct predic-tions as to the confidence rating behaviors for trials when they reported absence of a stimulus (i.e., misses and correct rejec-tions). In perceptual blindness, sensory signals are already weak before they reach the decision stage and are hardlydistinguishable from no signals at all. Thus, if observers tried to access the sensory signals, they would feel confident thatthere was no stimulus. This predicts that for perceptual blindness, observers cannot discriminate misses and correct rejec-tions when they reported absence of a stimulus (Fig. 1c). In attentional blindness, on the other hand, the process of accessingsensory signals is disrupted due to psychophysical manipulations such as attentional distraction by a concurrent task. Insuch cases, observers would be able to adjust their confidence depending upon the availability of attentional resources atthe time of stimulus detection. This predicts that for attentional blindness, observers will be able to discriminate missesand correct rejections by their confidence ratings.

As an illustration, consider disappearances of salient stimuli in motion-induced blindness or interocular suppression as inbinocular rivalry. In these psychophysical phenomena, we feel that stimuli are invisible. This might result in high confidence

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andattentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Page 4: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

4 R. Kanai et al. / Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx

in reporting absence of a stimulus if one was not informed of the fact that illusory disappearances could be induced by stim-ulus manipulations. On the other hand, when observers missed a target due to attentional distraction, they might have afeeling that they have missed a target because they could not pay full attention to the task. In the former case, observerswould not be able to lower their confidence in reporting absence of stimuli, whereas in the latter case, they would be ableto lower their confidence in accordance with their performance. In this study, we examine whether the differences in sub-jective impression of this sort could be captured by comparing confidence ratings for miss trials.

To formally quantify observers’ ability to adjust their confidence in psychophysically induced failures of awareness, weintroduce an index termed subjective discriminability of invisibility (SDI). The SDI was developed based on Type II analysis(Galvin et al., 2003; Pollack & Decker, 1958), but computes Type II performance only for trials in which observers reportedabsence of a stimulus, namely, misses and correct rejections (Fig. 1c). This measure quantifies how confidence ratings fortrials with impaired awareness (miss trials) differ from those with no target (correct rejections). Based on the rationale de-scribed earlier, we predict that SDI performance would fall to a chance level for perceptual blindness but remain abovechance for attentional blindness.

The goal of the present study is to examine the new measure, SDI, in various circumstances under which visual awareness isimpaired (Fig. 2). To do so, we applied the measure of the SDI while suppressing subjective visibility of a stimulus by contrastreduction, backward masking (Breitmeyer & Ogmen, 2006), flash suppression (Wolfe, 1984), dual task (Lee, Itti, Koch, & Braun,1999), attentional blink (Raymond, Shapiro, & Arnell, 1992) and increase in spatial uncertainty (Foley & Schwarz, 1998) (seeSection 2 for full details of the experiments). In all the six tasks, the target was presented on only 50% of the trials and observerswere asked to report the presence or absence of a target stimulus together with their confidence rating (high, mid or low).

2. Materials and methods

2.1. Stimuli and procedure

Visual stimuli were presented on a 19-inch CRT monitor using Psychtoolbox 3 running on Matlab (Brainard, 1997; Pelli,1997). In all the experiments, the task was to report the presence or absence of the target probe together with their

Fig. 2. Four manipulations to reduce detection performance. (A) Low contrast stimuli. (B) Backward masking. (C) Flash suppression was used to controldominant eye in binocular rivalry. A test probe was presented either on the suppressed eye or on the dominant eye. (D) In the dual task experiment, a visualsearch task, in which observers were required to detect the presence of the letter ‘T” among ‘L’s, was used to withdraw observers attention from a targetprobe. The attentional demand was manipulated by varying the number of the search task. (E) In the attentional blink experiment, a stream of letters werepresented at the rate of 59 ms per item (35 ms on and 24 ms off). The first target (T1) was defined by the red colour and observers were required to identifythe letter. The second target (T2) was the letter ‘X’ and observers were required to report the presence or absence of the letter. (F) Spatial uncertainty wasmanipulated by giving a single cue for target position or non-predictive cues directing all the eight locations. (For interpretation of the references to colourin this figure legend, the reader is referred to the web version of this article.)

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andattentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Page 5: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

R. Kanai et al. / Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx 5

confidence rating in three levels; low (completely guessing), medium and high (certain). The stimulus parameters for eachexperiment are summarized below. In all the experiments, the target was presented on half of the trials and was absent inthe remaining half.

2.1.1. ContrastSix naïve observers participated in the luminance probe detection task. The contrast of the target was varied between

5.0%, 6.5%, 8.0%, 9.5% and 11.0%. The sigma of the Gaussian probe was 0.22�. The target was presented for 24 ms belowthe fixation. The distance between the fixation and the centre of the target was 4.38�. One block of trials consisted of 220trials. The timing of the target onset was varied between 1 and 3 s from the beginning of a trial. The moment in whichthe target was potentially presented at a probability of 50% was indicated by a brief colour change of the fixation cross fromblack to red. Within a block, there were 20 target-present trials for each contrast level and an equal number of target-absenttrials. We included fixation control trials in which the subjects had to respond to the colour change of the fixation cross (9%of trials). Each participant completed a minimum of three blocks (i.e., 60 target-present trials per contrast) and on average3.67 blocks.

2.1.2. Backward maskingSix naïve observers participated in this experiment. The target probe was identical to the contrast experiment above,

but the contrast was fixed at 40%, which is well above the detection threshold when isolated alone without a mask. Themask consisted of black and white hollow square frames each subtending 0.57� � 0.57� (see Fig. 2B). The detection per-formance was manipulated by adjusting the inter-stimulus interval between the probe and the mask between 12 ms,24 ms, 35 ms 47 ms, 94 ms and 188 ms. The mask was presented for 253 ms. As in the contrast experiment, we includedfixation control trials in which the subjects had to respond to the colour change of the fixation cross. Within a block, therewere a total of 132 trials. There were 10 target-present trials per ISI and a total of 60 target-absent trials and 12 fixationcontrol trials.

2.1.3. Flash suppressionSix observers participated in this experiment. Stimuli were orthogonal gratings (45� and 135� in orientation), which were

presented to each eye. They were presented with a temporal offset, i.e., the second stimulus was presented 1470 ms after theonset of the first stimulus. This temporal offset is known to be effective at flipping the percept to a new stimulus (flash sup-pression) (Wolfe, 1984). A probe was presented 365 ms after the onset of the flash suppression either to the suppressed eyeor to the dominant eye. The probe was a Gaussian-enveloped (sigma = 106 ms) luminance blob superimposed on one of thegratings. The sigma of the spatial Gaussian envelope was 0.22� and its peak was 1.32� below fixation. Within a block, thecombinations of orientation and eye (left-eye 45� or right-eye 45�), and the stimulus presentation order (left eye first orright-eye first) were counterbalanced across trials. The target-present trials across the four counterbalanced conditions werecollapsed into suppressed eye trials and dominant eye trials, depending on whether the probe was presented either to thedominant eye (i.e., the eye to which the second stimulus was presented) or to the suppressed eye (i.e., the eye to which thefirst stimulus was presented). On half of trials, the probe was absent. Within a block, there were 12 dominant eye trials, 12suppressed eye trials and 24 target-absent trials. All subjects completed a minimum of three blocks and on average 3.5blocks.

2.1.4. Dual taskSix observers participated in this experiment. The target probe was the luminance Gaussian blob used in the contrast

experiment and its contrast was fixed at 30%, well above all observers’ detection thresholds. In the concurrent visual searchtask, subjects were required to report the presence or absence of the target letter ‘T’ among distractor ‘L’s. The letters wererandomly oriented and were presented at an eccentricity of 2� for 58 ms. After a blank period of 177 ms, F-shaped masks,which overlapped with both ‘T’s and ‘L’s, were presented for 177 ms. The Gaussian probe was presented during the last24 ms of the letter array presentation. The number of the items in the search array was varied between 1, 2, 4 and 8 acrosstrials. Within a block, there was a total of 160 trials. There were 20 target-present trials per number of items in the searcharray and a total of 80 target-absent trials were randomly mixed across trials. All subjects completed three blocks of trials(i.e., 480 trials in total).

2.1.5. Attentional blinkSix observers participated in the attentional blink experiment. For the rapid serial visual presentation (RSVP), all the

alphabet except for the letters ‘I’, ‘O’, and ‘W’ were used and the same letter was not repeated in an RSVP. The letters werepresented in black with the 80 point bold Helvetica font, and subtended 2.8� vertically. On one trial, 16 letters were pre-sented in the RSVP. The task was to report the identity of the first target (T1) indicated by the red colour and to reportthe presence or absence of the second target, a black letter ‘X’ (T2) in the RSVP stream together with confidence ratingfor the T2 report. T1 was presented at either the 4th, 6th or 8th temporal position in the RSVP. For each position, T1–T2 lagsof 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, and 7 were tested for equal numbers of trials. Data from different T1 positions were collapsed. 120 trials per lagwere tested per observer.

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andattentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Page 6: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

6 R. Kanai et al. / Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx

2.1.6. Spatial uncertaintySix observers participated in the spatial uncertainty experiment. The probe was the luminance Gaussian blob as in the

contrast and backward masking experiments and was presented at one of the eight positions at an eccentricity of 6.58�.The peak luminance of the probe was 2.5 times the 79.4% correct detection threshold for each target location, which wasdetermined for an individual observers by a 1-up-3-down staircase with 2-interval forced choice before the main experi-ment. At the beginning of a trial, either a single predictive cue (a white line subtending 4.38� from the fixation point) ornon-predictive cues pointing all the eight possible target positions were presented for 706 ms. After 353 ms, the probewas presented at one of the eight locations on 50% of trials. When only one cue was presented, the probe was always pre-sented at the location indicated by the cue. The probe was presented for an equal number of trials in each of the eight posi-tions. Observers completed a minimum of 128 trials (8 [probe positions] � 2 [levels of cue number] � 2 [present and absenttrials]). The data from different probe positions were pooled, resulting in a minimum of 32 trials per condition.

2.2. Analysis

2.2.1. Objective detection sensitivityIn order to quantify objective detection sensitivity, we constructed an ROC curve by plotting hit rates against false alarm

rates. Two inflection points were included in the ROC curve using the confidence data (Green & Swets, 1966; Macmillan &Creelman, 2005). The objective detection performance was quantified as the area under the ROC curve.

2.2.2. Subjective discriminability of invisibilityWe constructed a second-level ROC curve for trials in which subjects reported absence of a target (i.e., miss trials and

correct rejection trials) with two inflection points. The rate of high-confidence correct rejections (analogous to hits in thefirst level ROC) was plotted against the rate of high-confidence miss trials (analogous to false alarm in the first levelROC). The SDI was quantified as the AUC of the second-level ROC curve (Szczepanowski & Pessoa, 2007; Wilmzig et al., 2008).

3. Results

3.1. Objective performance

Objective performances for target detection were impaired by the relevant manipulation for each task (Fig. 3). In the con-trast reduction experiment (Fig. 3A), the detection performance decreased with decreasing the contrast (Spearman’s q= 0.57,p < .01). In the backward masking experiment (Fig. 3B), the objective performance monotonically increased as the inter-stim-ulus interval (ISI) between the target and the mask increased (q = 0.72, p < .001). In the flash suppression experiment(Fig. 3C), the detection performance for a probe presented to a suppressed eye was significantly lower than that for a probepresented to a dominant eye (t(5) = 5.32, p < .01). In the dual task experiment (Fig. 3D), the detection performance decreasedas the number of items in the search array increased (q = �0.57, p < .01). In the attentional blink experiment (Fig. 3E), thedetection performance was lower when the lag between T1 and T2 was short (q = 0.57, p < .01). Finally, in the spatial uncer-tainty experiment, the objective performance decreased when potential target positions was uncertain (Fig. 3F; t(5) = 3.47,p < .05). These results confirm that we obtained expected performance deteriorations for all the six task types.

3.2. Subjective discriminability of invisibility

To compare the SDI performance across different experimental manipulations, we selected the condition for each of thesix tasks that yielded a comparable level of sensitivity reduction in objective performance (AUC = 0.7) (indicated by the graystripes in Fig. 3). To illustrate the process of computing the SDI values, the histograms of confidence ratings for miss and cor-rect rejection trials are shown for the visibility suppression conditions for the six tasks (Fig. 4). ROC curves were constructedbased on the confidence histograms by plotting the cumulative probability function of the confidence in correct rejectiontrials against the cumulative probability function of the confidence in miss trials (Fig. 5).

We tested whether SDI was statistically greater than chance (one-tailed t-test against 0.5) for the six tasks (Fig. 6). The SDIwas not significantly greater when the target visibility was suppressed in the contrast (t(5) = �0.393, p = .64), backwardmasking (t(5) = 0.13, p = .45) and flash suppression (t(5) = �0.04, p = .51) conditions. By contrast, it was significantly greaterin the dual task (t(5) = 2.37, p < .05), attentional blink (t(5) = 2.21, p < .05) and spatial uncertainty (t(5) = 2.60, p < .05) exper-iments. These statistical analyses support the notion that the former three types of visual phenomena lead to subjectiveblindness indistinguishable from physical absence, whereas observers can distinguish the invisibility induced by the latterthree manipulations from physical absence.

3.3. Standard Type II performance

To compare SDI measures with a more traditional approach, we computed AUC for the standard Type II performance (see,Fig. 1b). For all the six manipulations, the Type II AUC performance was significantly higher than chance including the threemanipulations that were classified as perceptual blindness by SDI. This is due to the trials in which observers reported

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andattentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Page 7: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

Fig. 3. Results of the six experiments. Objective detection performance (gray circles) are plotted against the task manipulation for each experiment (A–F).The shaded conditions are the visibility suppression conditions in which the objective AUC was closest to 0.7 in each task.

R. Kanai et al. / Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx 7

presence of a target stimulus (i.e., hits and false alarms). Given that observers would be more confident when they detect atarget (i.e., hits) than when they simply guessed (false alarms), the above-chance Type II performance is not surprising. Inother words, the aggregation of different types of correct trials (hits and correct rejections) and incorrect trials (missesand false alarms) obscures the nature of the failures specifically involved in a target miss, because observers performed aType II task well for the response-present trials. This comparison demonstrates the point that SDI is preferable to a moreconventional Type II analysis for dissociating perceptual and attentional blindness.

3.4. Subjective discriminability of invisibility (full version)

Finally, we computed the SDI for all the conditions in the six tasks. We observed decreases in the SDI performance asobjective visibility was reduced by reducing the contrast (Fig. 7A), backward masking (Fig. 7B) and by flash suppression(Fig. 7C). On the other hand, the SDI remained above chance even when the objective performances were decreased by dualtask (Fig. 7D), attentional blink (Fig. 7E) or spatial uncertainty (Fig. 7F). These patterns of results corroborate the finding thatunawareness due to contrast reduction, backward masking and flash suppression are categorized as perceptual blindness,whereas unawareness due to dual task, attentional blink and spatial uncertainty are categorized as attentional blindness.Interestingly, the SDI performances for the tasks categorized as perceptual blindness (i.e., contrast reduction, backwardmasking and flash suppression) were above chance when the objective sensitivity was high. For example, the SDI for highcontrast stimuli (Fig. 7A) is classified as attentional blindness in our definition, as the value remained well above chance.This implies that when observers missed a high contrast target, they are aware that somehow they were not paying enoughattention on those trials and reduced their confidence accordingly. Thus, observers could attribute the reason for missing atarget of high contrast stimuli to some internal (attentional) state, whereas they could not subjectively distinguish a missedlow contrast target from no stimulus. One important implication of this finding is that the distinction between perceptualand attentional blindness is not simply attributable to the design of a psychophysical experiment, but depends on the levelof reduction in objective visibility.

4. Discussion

Our present results show that impairments of objective detection performance due to contrast reduction, backwardmasking and flash suppression were accompanied by a decline of the subjective discriminability of invisibility (SDI) to

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andattentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Page 8: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

Fig. 4. Histograms of confidence ratings for miss and correct rejection (CR) trials under visibility suppression. The probability of confidence ratings isgraphed for low, medium and high confidences for (A) contrast reduction, (B) backward masking, (C) flash suppression, (D) dual task, (E) attentional blinkand (F) spatial uncertainty experiments. The total number of miss and CR trials for computing the probability distributions is shown in the insets. In all thepsychophysical manipulations, conditions that produced suppression of visibility (indicated by the shades in Fig. 3; objective AUC � 0.7) were used toproduce these graphs.

8 R. Kanai et al. / Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx

chance performance, whereas the SDI for the dual task, attentional blink and spatial uncertainty experiments remainedabove chance even when their objective performances declined by a comparable degree.

We refer to the former cases as perceptual blindness and the latter cases as attentional blindness. The distinction betweenthese two types of blindness supports the idea that suppression of visual awareness takes place as a consequence of reduc-tion in the sensory signal level and/or failure to exert attentional access to the sensory signals. Our findings suggest that dif-ferent types of visibility manipulation differentially interfere with those processes required for conscious report.

4.1. Comparison with Type II performance

To compare our results with conventional Type II performance, we computed subjective AUC for the Type II task by com-bining hits and correct rejections as correct trials and misses and false alarm rates as incorrect trials. In all the six tasks, theType II performance was significantly above chance (Fig. 6B). Thus, the classical Type II performance did not differentiateperceptual and attentional blindness. The above-chance Type II performance was due to the general tendency that confidenceratings are low for false alarm trials and high in many hit trials. Thus, the contamination of the trials in which observersreported the presence of a target obscured the qualitative difference between perceptual and attentional blindness. Theseresults validate the point that only report-absent trials should be included in the SDI analysis to quantify observers’ abilityto distinguish induced invisibility from physical absence of a stimulus.

4.2. Comparison with criterion shifts

One SDT-based method to capture the mechanisms underlying subjective blindness is to assess the decision criterion un-der experimental manipulations. The decision criterion (e.g. c0) can be computed from the z-scores of hit and false alarmrates. If the decision criterion were set too high for the signal to be reported as ‘seen’, this would result in strong stimulibeing reported as absent (e.g., Super, Spekreijse, & Lamme, 2001). Previous studies suggested that shifts in decision criteriamight underlie various pathological impairments of visual awareness such as neglect (Ricci & Chatterjee, 2004) and blind-sight (Azzopardi & Cowey, 1997, 1998; Lau, 2008). Moreover, it has been shown that decision criteria become more conser-vative in attentional blindness, repetition blindness (Caetta & Gorea, 2010), motion-induced blindness (Caetta, Gorea, &Bonneh, 2007) and visual extinction in normal observers (Gorea & Sagi, 2000, 2001, 2002). The notion of criterion shifts pro-vides a useful theoretical framework to account for how strong sensory signals could go unnoticed by observers withoutinvoking subjective judgments about awareness of stimuli.

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andattentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Page 9: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

Fig. 5. ROC analysis of SDI for group data under visibility suppression. Receiver-operating characteristics (ROC) curves for confidence ratings in correctrejection (CR) trials are plotted against confidence ratings in miss trials for (A) contrast reduction, (B) backward masking, (C) flash suppression, (D) dualtask, (E) attentional blink and (F) spatial uncertainty experiments. In each curve, two inflection points are taken as the cumulative probability distributionsof rated confidence (see Fig. 4). Subjective discriminability of invisibility (SDI) was calculated as the area under the ROC curve. In all the psychophysicalmanipulations, conditions that produced suppression of visibility (indicated by the shades in supplemental Fig. 3; objective AUC � 0.7) were used toproduce these graphs.

R. Kanai et al. / Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx 9

To compare our SDI analyses with decision criterion, we computed normalized decision criteria c0 ( = �0.5 (z(Hit) + z(FA))/d0) for the six tasks under the conditions in which the target was clearly visible in most trials (Fig. 8A) and under the con-ditions in which visibility was suppressed (Fig. 8B). The results show that the criteria were neutral when the suppression wasweak (Fig. 8A) except for the flash suppression task for which the criterion was significantly negative, indicating a liberalcriterion in this task. The neutral criterion is optimal in the sense that responses yield the greatest number of correct trials.On the other hand, the criteria were significantly positive in the reduced visibility conditions we used for the SDI analysis. Allthe task manipulations shifted the criterion positively, indicating a more conservative decision criterion under these condi-tions (Fig. 8C). The shift in criterion was significant in all the task manipulations except for the dual task condition. The ob-served positive shifts in decision criteria are consistent with a number of studies reported by Gorea and colleagues (Caetta &Gorea, 2010; Caetta et al., 2007; Gorea & Sagi, 2002).

In our experimental results, a commonly used criterion measure did not show clear differences between the tasks, reveal-ing general upshifts in criterion whenever the visibility was reduced by any manipulation. However, it should be noted thatour criterion measures were slightly different from those developed by Gorea and colleagues. The criterion measure we usedis c0 as referred to in Macmillan and Creelman (2005), but this is not identical to c0 (=z(FA)) used in Gorea and Sagi (2000) orin Caetta et al’s study (2010). Our current experimental design does not allow direct comparison with their measure, sincetheir criterion measure also requires blocked trials for each condition to estimate the false alarm rate separately. Thus,although both Type I criteria and SDI aim to capture the causes of reporting absence in the presence of strong sensory signals,further studies are needed to establish their exact relationships.

While criterion shift explains misses induced by subjective visibility manipulations, a potential caveat is that criterion-based analysis does not directly test whether criterion shifts affect perceptual state or decision making. Specifically, it ispossible that even though observers responded that a stimulus was absent, they might have some awareness, but simplyreported absence due to the conservative criterion. This is one of the rationales behind adopting Type II performance as amarker for awareness. Further studies that manipulate decision criterion (e.g., Summerfield & Koechlin, 2008) combinedwith a Type II task may be informative for resolving this issue.

4.3. Putative origins of perceptual and attentional blindness

The distinction between perceptual and attentional blindness can be understood in terms of accessibility of the critical cog-nitive process for each task (Corallo, Sackur, Dehaene, & Sigman, 2008). In perceptual blindness, the lack of discriminability

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andattentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Page 10: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

Fig. 6. SDI and Type II performance for the six experiments under comparable objective performance (AUC � 0.7). (A) SDI performance under visibilitysuppression. The left three bars did not show a SDI greater than chance (p > .05), whereas the SDI for the experiments shown by the right three bars weregreater than chance (p < .05). (B) Type II performance under visibility suppression. In all tasks, Type II performance was significantly greater than chance(p < .05). Abbreviations are C (contrast reduction), BM (backward masking), FS (flash suppression), DT (dual task), AB (attentional blink) and SU (spatialuncertainty).

10 R. Kanai et al. / Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx

between correct rejections and misses implies that a trial-by-trial fluctuation of the critical factor leading to invisibility is notaccessible to the mechanisms for estimating confidence. In other words, the cause of a failure to detect a target occursindependent of internal factors that can be monitored by observers. One such example of fluctuation is that of ongoing neuralactivity. Recent studies showed that the amplitude (Romei et al., 2007) and phase (Busch, Dubois, & VanRullen, 2009) ofongoing alpha activity determines visibility of a stimulus presented at the threshold strength (i.e., perceptual blindness con-ditions). However, the information contained in such fluctuations does not seem to be available for confidence decisions, thusresulting in unawareness of the target, which is subjectively indistinguishable from physical absence.

On the other hand, when objective visibility is impaired by dual task, attentional blink or spatial uncertainty, the state ofthe fluctuation relevant for the task performance seems to be available to observers and thus incorporated into their decisionon confidence rating. In other words, observers were able to adjust their confidence depending on their internal state. Forexample, observers may monitor how much attention they were able to allocate to the target detection task in the dual taskexperiment (Yeh & Wickens, 1988). If failure of attentional allocation is the critical factor for a target miss in a given task,such subjective trial-by-trial estimates of attentional availability for the task can predict their correctness. In such a case,observers can correctly attribute their potential target miss to their inattention to the target.

A previous study found a fundamental difference between unawareness induced by backward masking and attentionalblink (Sergent & Dehaene, 2004). Observers in that study gave confidence ratings for target visibility in an all-or-none fashionduring the attentional blink, whereas they gave confidence ratings in a more continuous scale for a masked target. This dif-ference was interpreted as follows: attentional blink is caused by a failure of bottom-up signals accessing the global work-space (Baars, 1997; Dehaene, Sergent, & Changeux, 2003), whereas perception of a masked stimulus depends on the gradualactivation of sensory regions. The conclusion drawn from our present study is consistent with this view: attentional blink is afailure of attentional access, whereas backward masking reduces visibility by curtailing activations of sensory signals.

4.4. Limitations of meta-cognitive approach to awareness

In the present study, we took the position that meta-cognition of perception reflects awareness (e.g., Kunimoto et al.,2001). A common criticism of this approach, including SDI as well as to any attempt to define a marker for awareness, is thatoperational markers are not a direct measurement of awareness. Instead, their interpretations should be limited to what theoperational marker directly measures (Hulme, Friston, & Zeki, 2009). In this sense, our SDI is also limited and what it directlymeasures is the ability to distinguish psychophysically induced suppression of visibility from physical absence of stimuli,

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andattentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Page 11: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

Fig. 7. SDI performance for the six experiments. SDI performance is plotted against the task manipulation for each experiment (A–F).

Fig. 8. Decision criteria for the six tasks. (A) Decision criteria when the target was clearly visible. (B) Decision criteria when target visibility was reduced. (C)Criteria shifts when visibility was reduced (the difference between A and B). Statistical significances are indicated by asterisks (� for p < .05, �� for p < .01,��� for p < .001). Abbreviations are C (contrast reduction), BM (backward masking), FS (flash suppression), DT (dual task), AB (attentional blink) and SU(spatial uncertainty).

R. Kanai et al. / Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx 11

namely, meta-cognition of subjective blindness to stimuli. Nevertheless, our experimental results indicate that SDI can beused to demonstrate that there are qualitative differences among commonly used psychophysical manipulations for reduc-ing visibility, presumably due to distinct underlying mechanisms.

5. Concluding remarks

In summary, our results support the idea that failure of visual awareness could arise from suppression of early perceptualsignals or failure of attentional access. This distinction offers a natural account for the intuition that in some types of sub-jective invisibility such as binocular rivalry, we have the impression that a target is phenomenally invisible (i.e., awarenessof absence), whereas in other types of manipulations such as attention demanding situations, we do have a sense that wemissed a target (i.e., absence of awareness). Finally, the SDI analyses reported here can be applied to probe the nature ofother circumstances of impaired awareness such as crowding (Toet & Levi, 1992) or motion-induced blindness (Bonneh,Cooperman, & Sagi, 2001) as well as deficits of visual awareness caused by brain lesions (Humphreys, Romani, Olson,Riddoch, & Duncan, 1994; Weiskrantz, 1997).

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andattentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Page 12: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

12 R. Kanai et al. / Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Victor Lamme, Ned Block, Naotsugu Tsuchiya, Neil Muggleton and Daw-An Wu for comments onan earlier version of the manuscript. This work was supported by Human Frontier Science Foundation for R.K. and the U.K.Medical Research Council (G0700929) for V.W.

References

Azzopardi, P., & Cowey, A. (1997). Is blindsight like normal, near-threshold vision? Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States ofAmerica, 94, 14190–14194.

Azzopardi, P., & Cowey, A. (1998). Blindsight and visual awareness. Consciousness and Cognition, 7, 292–311.Baars, B. J. (1997). In the theatre of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Block, N. (2007). Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30, 481–548.Bonneh, Y., Cooperman, A., & Sagi, D. (2001). Motion-induced blindness in normal observers. Nature, 411, 798–801.Brainard, D. H. (1997). The psychophysics toolbox. Spatial Vision, 10, 433–436.Breitmeyer, B. G., & Ogmen, H. (2006). Visual masking: Time slices through conscious and unconscious vision. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Busch, N. A., Dubois, J., & VanRullen, R. (2009). The phase of ongoing EEG oscillations predicts visual perception. Journal of Neuroscience, 29, 7869–7876.Caetta, F., & Gorea, A. (2010). Upshifted decision criteria in attentional blink and repetition blindness. Visual Cognition, 18, 413–433.Caetta, F., Gorea, A., & Bonneh, Y. (2007). Sensory and decisional factors in motion-induced blindness. Journal of Vision, 7(7), 1–12.Cheesman, J., & Merikle, P. M. (1984). Priming with and without awareness. Perception and Psychophysics, 36, 387–395.Chun, M. M., & Potter, M. C. (1995). A two-stage model for multiple target detection in rapid serial visual presentation. Journal of Experimental Psychology:

Human Perception and Performance, 21, 109–127.Clifford, C. W. G., Arabzadeh, E., & Harris, J. A. (2008). Getting technical about awareness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12, 54–58.Corallo, G., Sackur, J., Dehaene, S., & Sigman, M. (2008). Limits on introspection. Psychological Science, 19, 1110–1117.Dagenbach, D., Carr, T. H., & Wilhelmsen, A. (1989). Task-induced strategies and near-threshold priming: Conscious influences on unconscious perception.

Journal of Memory and Language, 28, 412–443.Dehaene, S., Changeux, J.-P., Nacache, L., Sackur, J., & Sergant, C. (2006). Conscious, preconscious, and subliminal processing: A testable taxonomy. Trends in

Cognitive Sciences, 10, 204–211.Dehaene, S., Sergent, C., & Changeux, J.-P. (2003). A neuronal network model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data during conscious

perception. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 100, 8520–8525.Dienes, Z., & Seth, A. (2010). Gambling on the unconscious: A comparison of wagering and confidence ratings as measures of awareness in an artificial

grammar task. Consciousness and Cognition, 19, 674–681.Eriksen, C. W. (1960). Discrimination and learning without awareness: A methodological survey and evaluation. Psychological Review, 67, 279–300.Foley, J. M., & Schwarz, W. (1998). Spatial attention: Effect of position uncertainty and number of distractor patterns on the threshold-versus-contrast

function for contrast discrimination. Journal of the Optical Society of America A – Optics and Image Science and Vision, 15, 1036–1047.Fowler, C. A., Wolford, G., Slade, R., & Tassinary, L. (1981). Lexical access with and without awareness. Journal of Experimental Psychology – General, 110,

341–362.Galvin, S. J., Podd, J. V., Drga, V., & Whitmore, J. (2003). Type 2 tasks in the theory of signal detectability: Discrimination between correct and incorrect

decisions. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 10, 843–876.Gorea, A., & Sagi, D. (2000). Failure to handle more than one internal representation in visual detection tasks. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences

of the United States of America, 97, 12380–12384.Gorea, A., & Sagi, D. (2001). Disentangling signal from noise in visual contrast discrimination. Nature Neuroscience, 4, 1146–1150.Gorea, A., & Sagi, D. (2002). Natural extinction: A criterion shift phenomenon. Visual Cognition, 9, 913–936.Green, D., & Swets, J. A. (1966). Signal detection theory and psychophysics. New York: John Wiley.Hulme, O. J., Friston, K. F., & Zeki, S. (2009). Neural correlates of stimulus reportability. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 21, 1602–1610.Humphreys, G. W., Romani, C., Olson, A., Riddoch, M. J., & Duncan, J. (1994). Non-spatial extinction following lesions of the parietal lobe in humans. Nature,

372, 357–359.Kemp-Wheeler, S. M., & Hill, A. B. (1988). Semantic priming without awareness: Some methodological considerations and replications. Quality Journal of

Experimental Psychology, 40A, 671–692.Kim, C. Y., & Blake, R. (2005). Psychophysical magic: Rendering the visible ‘invisible’. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9, 381–388.Koch, C., & Tsuchiya, N. (2007). Attention and consciousness: Two distinct brain processes. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11, 16–22.Kolb, F. C., & Braun, J. (1995). Blindsight in normal observers. Nature, 377, 336–338.Kunimoto, C., Miller, J., & Pashler, H. (2001). Confidence and accuracy of near-threshold discrimination responses. Consciousness and Cognition, 10, 294–340.Lamme, V. A. F. (2003). Why visual attention and awareness are different. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 12–18.Lamme, V. A. F. (2004). Separate neural definitions of visual consciousness and visual attention; a case for phenomenal awareness. Neural Networks, 17,

861–872.Lamme, V. A. F. (2006). Towards a true neural stance on consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, 494–501.Lau, H. C. (2008). A higher-order Bayesian decision theory of perceptual consciousness. Progress in Brain Research, 168, 35–48.Lau, H. C., & Passingham, R. E. (2006). Relative blindsight in normal observers and neural correlate of visual consciousness. Proceedings of the National

Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 103, 18763–18768.Lee, D. K., Itti, L., Koch, C., & Braun, J. (1999). Attention activates winner-take-all competition among visual filters. Nature Neuroscience, 2, 375–381.Lin, Z., & He, S. (2009). Seeing the invisible: The scope and limits of unconscious processing in binocular rivalry. Progress in Neurobiology, 84, 195–211.Macmillan, N. A., & Creelman, C. D. (2005). Detection Theory: A User’s Guide (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press.Marcel, A. J. (1983). Conscious and unconscious perception: Experiments on visual masking and word recognition. Cognitive Psychology, 15, 197–237.Nolan, K. A., & Caramazza, A. (1982). Unconscious perception of meaning: A failure to replicate. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 20, 23–26.Norman, D. A., & Bobrow, D. G. (1975). On data-limited and resource-limited processes. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 44–64.Pashler, H. (1994). Dual-task interference in simple tasks: Data and theory. Psychological Bulletin, 116, 220–244.Pelli, D. G. (1997). The VideoToolbox software for visual psychophysics: Transforming numbers into movies. Spatial Vision, 10, 437–442.Persaud, N., McLeod, P., & Cowey, A. (2007). Post-decision wagering objectively measures awareness. Nature Neuroscience, 10, 257–261.Pollack, I., & Decker, L. R. (1958). Confidence ratings, message reception, and the receiver operating characteristic. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America,

30, 286–292.Raymond, J. E., Shapiro, K. L., & Arnell, K. M. (1992). Temporary suppression of visual processing in an RSVP task: An attentional blink? Journal of

Experimental Psychology – Human Perception and Performance, 18, 849–860.Rees, G., Wojciulik, E., Clarke, K., Husain, M., Frith, C., & Driver, J. (2000). Unconscious activation of visual cortex in the damaged right hemisphere of a

parietal patient with extinction. Brain, 123, 1624–1633.Ricci, R., & Chatterjee, A. (2004). Sensory and response contributions to visual awareness in extinction. Experimental Brain Research, 157, 85–93.

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andattentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003

Page 13: Consciousness and Cognition · 2015-11-25 · 2 R. Kanai et al./Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective

R. Kanai et al. / Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2010) xxx–xxx 13

Romei, V., Brodbeck, V., Michel, C., Amedi, A., Pascual-Leone, A., & Thut, G. (2007). Spontaneous fluctuations of posterior alpha-band EEG activity reflectvariability in excitability of human visual areas. Cerebral Cortex, 18, 2010–2018.

Schurger, A., Pereira, F., Tresiman, A., & Cohen, J. D. (2009). Reproducibility distinguishes conscious from nonconscious neural representations. Science, 327,97–99.

Schwiedrzik, C. M., Singer, W., & Melloni, L. (2009). Sensitivity and perceptual awareness increase with practice in metacontrast masking. Journal of Vision,9(10), 18.

Sergent, C., & Dehaene, S. (2004). Is consciousness a gradual phenomenon? Evidence for an all-or-none bifurcation during the attentional blink. PsychologicalScience, 15, 721–728.

Sigman, M., & Dehaene, S. (2006). Dynamics of the central bottleneck: Dual-task and task uncertainty. PLoS Biology, 4, 1227–1238.Stoerig, P., & Cowey, A. (1997). Blindsight in man and monkey. Brain, 120, 535–559.Summerfield, C., & Koechlin, E. (2008). A neural representation of prior information during perceptual inference. Neuron, 59, 336–347.Super, H., Spekreijse, H., & Lamme, V. A. F. (2001). Two distinct modes of sensory processing observed in monkey primary visual cortex (V1). Nature

Neuroscience, 4, 304–310.Szczepanowski, R., & Pessoa, L. (2007). Fear perception: Can objective and subjective awareness measures be dissociated? Journal of Vision, 7(4), 1–17.Toet, A., & Levi, D. (1992). The two-dimensional shape of spatial interactions zones in the parafovea. Vision Research, 32, 1349–1357.Tong, F., Nakayama, K., Vaughan, J. T., & Kanwisher, N. (1998). Binocular rivalry and visual awareness in human extrastriate cortex. Neuron, 21, 753–759.Weiskrantz, L. (1997). Consciousness lost and found: A neuropsychological exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Weiskrantz, L. (1998). Blindsight. A case study and implications (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Wilmzig, C., Tsuchiya, N., Fahle, M., Einhäuser, W., & Koch, C. (2008). Spatial attention increases performance but not subjective confidence in a

discrimination task. Journal of Vision, 8(5), 1–10.Wolfe, J. M. (1984). Reversing ocular dominance and suppression in a single flash. Vision Research, 24, 471–478.Yeh, Y.-Y., & Wickens, C. D. (1988). Dissociation of performance and subjective measures of workload. Human Factors, 30, 111–120.

Please cite this article in press as: Kanai, R., et al. Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual andattentional failures of awareness. Consciousness and Cognition (2010), doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.06.003