elliott mendelson - foundations logic, language and mathematics

Upload: ray-meza

Post on 07-Jul-2018

225 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    1/282

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    2/282

    FOUNDATIONS:

    LOGIC,

    LANGUAGE,

    AND MATHEMATICS

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    3/282

    FOUNDATIONS:

    LOGIC LANGUAGE

    AND

    MATHEMATICS

    Edited by

    HUGUES LEBLANC, ELLIOTT MENDELSON,

    and

    ALEX ORENSTEIN

    Reprinted from

    Synthese,

    Vol. 60 Nos. 1 and 2

    SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V.

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    4/282

    TSBN 978-90-481-8406-4 ISBN 978-94-017-1592-8 (eBook)

    DOI 10

    .1007/978-94-017-1592-8

    AlI Rights Reserved

    Copyright © 1984 by Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

    Originally published by D. Reidel Publishing Company. Dordrecht. Holland in 1984

    Softcover reprint

    of

    the hardcover 1st edition 1984

    No

    part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or

    utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical,

    inc1uding photocopying, record ing

    or

    by any information storage and

    retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    5/282

    TABLE

    OF CONTENTS

    Series Editors' Preface 1

    Preface 3

    MELVIN

    FITTING I

    A Symmetric Approach to Axiomatizing Quan-

    tifiers and Modalities 5

    NICOLAS

    D .

    GOODMAN

    I

    The Knowing Mathematician 21

    RAYMOND

    D.

    GUMB

    I "Conservative" Kripke Closures 39

    HENRY HIZ

    I

    Frege, Lesniewski, and Information Semantics on the

    Resolution

    of Antinomies

    51

    RICHARD

    JEFFREY

    I

    De Finetti's Probabilism 73

    HUGUES L E BLANC

    and CHARLES

    G . MORGAN I

    Probability

    Functions and Their Assumption Sets

    -The

    Binary Case 91

    GILBERT HARMAN I Logic and Reasoning 107

    JOHN MYHILL I Paradoxes 129

    ALEX

    ORENSTEIN I Referential and Nonreferential Substitutional

    Quantifiers 145

    WILFRIED SIEG

    1

    Foundations for Analysis and Proof Theory 159

    RAYMOND

    M.

    SMULLY

    AN

    I

    Chameleonic Languages 201

    RAPHAEL STERN

    I

    Relational Model Systems: The Craft

    of

    Logic 225

    J. DILLER and

    A. S. TROELSTRA I

    Realizability and lntuitionistic

    Logic 253

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    6/282

    CITY

    COLLEGE 

    STUDIES 

    I

    N TH

    E  H

    IST

    OR

    Y AN

    D PH

    ILO

    SOP

    HY

    O

    F SC

    IEN

    CE

    AN

    D T

    ECH

    NOL

    OG

    Y:

    SER

    IES

    E

    DIT

    ORS

    '

    P

    REF

    AC

    R

    ecen t

      year

    s hav

    e see

    n the

      em e

    rgenc

    e of

    severa

    l new

      app

    roach

    es to

     

    the history and philosophy of science and technology. For one,  w hat

    w

    ere p

    erceiv

    ed b

    y man

    y as 

    separ

    ate, t

    houg

    h per

    haps

    relate

    d, fie

    lds o

    f

    i

    nquiry

     h av

    e com

    e to b

    e reg

    arded

     by m

    ore a

    nd m

    ore sc

    holar

    s as a

     singl

    e

    d

    iscipl

    ine w

    ith d

    iffer

    ent a

    reas

    of em

    phas

    is. I

    n thi

    s dis

    ciplin

    e any

     

    p

    rofou

    nd un

    ders

    tandin

    g so 

    deep

    ly int

    ertwi

    nes h

    istory

      and

      philo

    soph

    y

    t

    hat i

    t mig

    ht

    b

    e

    said

    , to

    parap

    hras

    e K an

    t, th

    at ph

    iloso

    phy w

    itho

    ut

    his

    tory

    i

    s

    em p

    ty an

    d his

    tory w

    ithou

    t phi

    losop

    hy

    is

     

    blind

    .

    Ano t

    her co

    ntem

    porar

    y tre

    nd in

    the h

    istory

     and p

    hilos

    ophy

     of sc

    ience 

    and

      tech

    nolog

    y ha

    s bee

    n to

    bring

      toge

    ther

    the E

    nglis

    h-spe

    aking

      and

    continental traditions in philosophy. The views of those who do analytic

    philos

    ophy

      and 

    the v

    iews

      of t

    he he

    rmen

    eutici

    sts h

    ave c

    om b

    ined

    to

    in f

    luenc

    e the

      thin

    king

    of so

    m e p

    hiloso

    pher

    s in t

    he E

    nglish

    -spea

    king

     

    wo

    rld,

    and o

    ver

    the la

    st de

    cade

      that 

    influ

    ence

    has b

    een

    felt i

    n the

     

    histo

    ry an

    d ph

    iloso

    phy o

    f sci

    ence.

     

    T

    here

      h

    as als

    o be

    en th

    e lon

    g

    s

    tandin

    g in

    fluenc

    e in 

    the

    West 

    of c

    ontin

    ental 

    think

    ers w

    orki

    ng on

     

    prob

    lems

      in

    the p

    hilos

    ophy

    of t

    echno

    logy.

      Thi

    s syn

    thesis

      of

    two

    trad

    itions

     has m

    ade

    for a

    riche

    r fund

      of id

    eas a

    nd ap

    proa

    ches

    that m

    ay

    change our conception of science and  technology.

    S

    till an

    other

     tren

    d tha t

     

    is

    in

    some

     ways 

    a com

    bina

    tion o

    f the

     previ

    ous

    tw o

     cons

    ists o

    f the

    work 

    of tho

    se ch

    aract

    erize

    d by s

    ome

    as the

     "Fri

    ends

    of D

    isco

    very"

      and

    by ot

    hers

    as the

      brin

    gers

    of the

      New

     Fu

    zzine

    ss".

    This a

    ppro

    ach t

    o the

    histor

    y and

     phil

    osoph

    y of s

    cienc

    e and

     tech

    nolog

    y

    conc

    entra

    tes o

    n

    cha

    nge, 

    prog

    ress,

    and discov

    ery.

    It

    ha

    s rai

    sed o

    ld

    episte

    molo

    gical 

    quest

    ions u

    nder

     the g

    uise

    of the

     prob

    lem o

    f rati

    onali

    ty

    in the

      scie

    nces.

    Altho

    ugh

    this a

    ppro

    ach h

    as its

      origi

    ns in

      the w

    ork

    of

    Th

    omas

      Kuh

    n in  

    the U

    nite

    d Sta

    tes, a

    t temp

    ts to

      expr

    ess h

    is ide

    as in

     

    explicit  set-theore tical or m odel-theoretic terms  are now centered

    in 

    Germ

    any.

    Synth

    ese

    60 (1984

    ) 1

    .

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    7/282

    2

    S E R I

    ES 

    E DI T OR S   PR E

    FA C E

    The m ore

      tradition

    al approac

    hes to the

      history an

    d philosop

    hy of

    science

      and techn

    ology cont

    inue as we

    ll, and prob

    ab ly will c

    ontinue as

     

    long as

      there are

      skillful p

    ractitioners

      such as

    Carl Hem p

    el, Ernest

     

    Nagel

    , and t h ~ i

    students. 

    Final

    ly, there a

    re still o t

    her approa

    ches that 

    address so

    me of the

     

    technic

    al problem

    s arising w

    hen we try

      to provid

    e an accou

    nt of belief

     

    a

    nd of rat

    ional choi

    ce . - T he

    se include

      efforts to

      provide 

    logical

    framework

    s within wh

    ich we ca

    n make sen

    se of these

      notions.

    This ser

    ies

    will

      at

    tempt to b

    ring toge

    ther work 

    from all o

    f these

    app

    roaches to 

    the history

      and philo

    sophy of sc

    ience and 

    technology

      in

    the belief that each has something to add to our understanding.

    The

    vo

    lumes of t

    his series h

    ave emerg

    ed either f

    rom lectur

    es given

    by autho

    rs while th

    ey served 

    as honorar

    y visiting p

    rofessors a

    t the City 

    C

    olleg e of N

    ew York o

    r from c on

    ferences sp

    onsored by

     th at instit

    ution.

    The

    City C

    ollege Pro

    gram in th

    e History 

    and Philos

    ophy of Sc

    ience

    an

    d Technolo

    gy overse

    es and dir

    ects these 

    lectures a

    nd confere

    nces

    wi

    th the fina

    ncial aid o

    f the Ass

    ociation fo

    r Philosop

    hy of Scie

    nce,

    P

    sychothera

    phy, and E

    thics.

    MA

    RTIN TAMNY 

    RA

    PHAEL STERN

     

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    8/282

    PRE

    FACE

    The

    pape

    rs in this  c

    ollection s

    tem largely

      from the

    conferenc

    e 'Foun

    dat

    ions: Log

    ic, Langua

    ge, and M

    athematic

    s ' held a t

      the Grad

    uate

    C en

    ter of the

    City Unive

    rsity of Ne

    w York on

     

    14

    -15 N o

    vember 1980

    .

    T h e

      conferen

    ce was sp

    onsored by

      the Phil

    osophy Pr

    ogram a t

    the

    G rad

    ua te Cen

    ter of th

    e City U

    niversity o

    f New Y

    ork .and 

    the

    Associatio

    n for Philo

    sophy of S

    cience, Psy

    chotherap

    y, and Eth

    ics. We

    w

    ish to exp

    ress our  g

    ratitude an

    d appreci

    ation to th

    ese organi

    zations

    a

    nd to than

    k the serie

    s editors,  R

    aphael S t

    ern and M

    artin T am n

    y, for

    their help with the conference and the  preparation of this collection . 

    Synthese

    60 (1 984) 3.

     

    HUGUE

    S

    LEBL

    ANC

    ELLI

    OTT ME

    NDELSON

    ALEX

    ORENS

    TEIN

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    9/282

    MEL YIN FITTING

    A SYMMETRIC APPROACH TO AXIOMATIZING

    QUANTIFIERS

    AND

    MODALITIES

    1 . I N T R O D U C T I O N

    We present an axiomatization of several of the basic modal logics, with

    the idea of giving the two modal operators 0 and 0 equal weight as far

    as possible. Then we present a parallel axiomatization of classical

    quantification theory, working

    our

    way up through a sequence of rather

    curious subsystems. It will be clear at the end that the essential

    difference between quantifiers and modalities

    is

    amusing in a vacuous

    sort of way. Finally

    we sketch tableau proof systems for the various

    logics we have introduced along the way. Also, the "natural" model

    theory for the subsystems of quantification theory that come up

    is

    somewhat curious. In a sense, it amounts to a "stretching

    out"

    of the

    Henkin-style completeness proof, severing the maximal consistent part

    of the construction quite thoroughly from the part of the construction

    that takes care of existential-quantifier instances.

    2. B A C K G R O U N D

    It is contrary to the spirit of what

    we

    are doing to take one modal

    operator as primitive and define the other, or, one quantifier as

    primitive and define the other. So, by the same token, we take as

    primitive all the standard propositional connectives too. Thus,

    we

    have

    available all of

    A,

    v,

    ~ , =>, 0 , 0,

    'V,

    3.

    We also take as primitive a truth

    constant

    T and a falsehood constant

    l..

    For our treatment of propositional modal logic we assume

    we

    have a

    countable list of atomic formulas, and that the set of formulas

    is

    built up

    from them in the usual way. We will use the letters "X",

    "Y''

    , etc., to

    denote such formulas.

    For quantification theory, we assume we have a countable list of

    variables and also a disjoint countable list of parameters. We will use

    the letters

    "x",

    "y",

    etc., to denote variables, and

    "a",

    "b",

    etc., to

    denote parameters. Formulas are built up in the usual way, with the

    understanding that a sentence contains no free variables, though it may

    Synthese

    60

    (1984)

    5-

    .19. 0039-7857/84/0601-0005 $01.50

    © 1984

    by D . Reidel Publishing Company

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    10/282

    6

     

    M E

    L V I

    N  F

    IT T

    IN

    G  

    con

    tain

      pa

    ram

    ete

    rs. W

    fo ll

    ow 

    th e 

    con

    ven

    tion

      th

    at if

    cp(x

    ) is

    form

    ula

     

    wit

    h on

    ly  x

    fr

    ee, 

    then

     

    cp(

     a) 

    is

     th

    e re

    sult

     of 

    repl

    acin

    g a

    ll fr

    ee o

    ccu

    rre

    nce

    s

    of 

    by  occurences of

    a

    in 

    cp

    W

    e w

    ill

    use

      Kr

    ipk

    e's 

    mod

    el 

    theo

    ry 

    for

    m o

    dal

    log

    ics 

    (and

      an

      an

    alo g

     

    for

      qu

    anti

    fica

    tion

    al 

    theo

    rie

    s, t

    o b

    e de

    scr

    ibed

      in

      Se

    ctio

    n 4

    ). F

    o r 

    us,

    a

    Kri

    pke 

    m o

    del

    is

    qua

    drup

    le ('

    fi,

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    11/282

    A

    X IO M A T I

    Z I NG  

    Q U A N

    T IFIERS A N D

    M O D A

    LITIES

    7

    Notice tha

    t (b)-(e) in

      the defin

    ition of a K

    ripke m o

    del above

    gives us

    flf-

    a

    iff

    If-

    a

    and flf-

    a2

    flf-

    f

    iff

    flf- {31 or

    f l f {32.

    Inde

    ed, this co

    uld be  use

    d instead o

    f (b)-(e).

    W e

     extend thi

    s uniform

    notation to

     the modal

     operators

     (as in Fitti

    ng

    [1]) by

     defining

    the v-formu

    las (neces

    saries) and

     1r-formula

    s (possible

    s)

    a

    nd their c

    omponents

      v

    0

    and 7To,

    respectiv

    ely, as  foll

    ows:

    v

     

    ox

    ~

      x

    v

    X

    ~ x  

    7T

    7To

    X

    ~ x

    N ot

    ice th at (f

    )-(h) in

    the definitio

    n of a  K ri

    pke m ode

    l above, ta

    ken

    togethe

    r w ith  (d),

      give us th

    e following

      equivalen

    t conditio

    ns:

    fo

    r every f E

    (f')

     

    f

    If-

    1r but

    f

    I. L

    v;

    for every

    E

    § -

    (x)

    ~

    cf>(a)

    The

    idea is, in

    a classical

    first-order

     model in w

    hich the d

    omain con

    sists

    of th

    e set of pa

    rame ters,

    an

    d

    each

    param eter

    is inte rpre

    ted as  nam

    ing

    itself: 

    Y is true i

    ff for all a ,

    Y(a) 

    is

    tr

    ue;

    o

    is true iff

    for som e a , o

    (a)

    is

    t

    rue.

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    12/282

    8

    M E L V I N FI T T I NG

    So much for background.

    3 . M O D A L L O G I C S , A X I O M A T I C A L L Y

    Let

    us

    assume that we have an axiomatization of the classical pro

    positional calculus, with modus ponens as the only rule. We will build

    on that in our introduction of rules and axioms pertinent to tfle modal

    operators.

    Modal logics are often formulated with a rule of necessitation, which

    we could give

    as

    vo

    v

    But this gives a central role to the v-formulas and, for no reason other

    than autocratic whim, we want to develop modal logic as far as possible

    giving equal weight to both v-and 1r-formulas, giving to both neces

    saries and possibles a fair share. After a certain amount of experimen

    tation we hit on the following curious rule:

    (M)

    1To v Vo

    1 T V V

    (we use M for modalization). As a matter of fact, rule M is a correct rule

    of inference, as the following argument shows.

    Suppose

    (W,

    , A,

    If-)

    is a Kripke model, and 1r

    0

    v

    v

    0

    is valid in it

    (holds at every possible world). Let

    r E

    W; we show

    flf- 1r

    v

    v.

    Well, if

    r E

    , that is, if

    r

    is queer, then

    r If-

    7T; so, trivially,

    r If-

    1T v

    v.

    Otherwise,

    f

    E

    Y

    DX::::>DY

    X::::>Y

    OX::::>OY

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    13/282

    AXI OMAT I Z I NG QUANT I FI E R S

    AND

    M ODAL I T I E S 9

    Then one may show,

    in

    the usual way, that replacement of proved

    equivalences holds as a derived rule:

    X = X'

    Z = Z '

    where Z' results from Z by replacing some occurrences of X in Z by

    occurrences of

    X' .

    Here we have used = as an abbreviation for mutual

    implication. (Actually a stronger version may be shown, concerning

    "semisubstitutivity" of implication, in which we must take into account

    the positiveness and negativeness of occurrences as well.

    The

    details

    needn't concern us here.)

    Now go back and look again at the justification we gave for rule

    M.

    In the argument that 7T v

    v

    held at the nonqueer world r we never

    needed that 7To v v

    0

    held at every world of the model; we only needed

    that it held at every world accessible from f. But to say that

    7To

    v v

    0

    holds at every world accessible from r is to say that D(

    7To

    v v

    0

    )

    holds at

    f. Thus, the same argument also shows the validity in all Kripke models

    of the schema

    (Ml)

    D[

    7To

    v

    vo]::) [ 7T

    v

    v].

    Let

    us

    add

    it

    as an axiom schema then.

    I f we do so, it is not hard to show that we have a complete axiomatic

    counterpart of the Kripke model theory as given in section 2.

    That is, X

    is

    provable in the axiomatic system just described iff

    X

    holds at every

    world of every Kripke model.

    To

    show this, one may show complete

    ness directly, using the now-common Lindenbaum-style construction,

    or one may show this axiom system is of equal strength with one

    standard in the literature, and rely on known completeness results. We

    skip the arguments.

    The logic axiomatically characterized thus far is called C in Seger

    berg [5]. It is the smallest

    regular

    modal logic (see Segerberg [5]).

    Now, in the model theory for C, one can have queer worlds in which

    everything is possible but nothing is necessary. Also there are no special

    conditions placed on the accessibility relation

    rJl,

    so there can be

    "dead-end" worlds, worlds from which no world is accessible. In such a

    world, everything is necessary, nothing

    is

    possible. So, our next item of

    business is

    to rule out such strange worlds.

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    14/282

    10

    MEL YIN FITTING

    Worlds in which nothing is necessary may be eliminated by postulat

    ing that something is necessary. Let us, then, add the axiom

    (M2) OT.

    The model theory appropriate to this (with respect to which one can

    prove completeness) is all Kripke models in which there are no queer

    worlds, that is , all normal Kripke models. The logic axiomatized thus

    far is the smallest normal logic, and is usually called K (see Segerberg

    [5]).

    Next, worlds in which nothing is possible may be eliminated

    by

    postulating that something

    is

    possible. We take as an axiom

    (M3) T.

    The model theory appropriate to this is all normal Kripke models in

    which every world has some world accessible to it.

    The

    logic

    is

    generally called D. (Again, see Segerberg [5]).

    Finally, we might want to restrict our attention to models in which

    each (normal) world

    is accessible to itself (in which the accessibility

    relation is reflexive). To do this one adds either (or both) of

    (M4)

    v ~

    vo

    7To

    ~ 7T

    The logic thus characterized

    is

    T.

    Note that T T is an instance of the second of these schemas, and

    since

    T is

    a tautology, T follows by modus ponens. Thus with M4

    added, M3 becomes redundant.

    REMARKS.

    One

    goes from C to K by adding

    OT

    as an axiom. It

    is

    of

    some interest to consider a kind of halfway point, where instead of

    adding

    OT as an

    assumed truth,

    we take it as a

    hypothesis.

    That is, form

    the set

    S

    of formulas

    X

    such that OT ~ X

    is

    provable

    in

    C. This set

    S

    is,

    itself, a (rather strangely defined) modal logic, intermediate between C

    and K. I t is closed under modus ponens, but not under rule M. Rather, it

    is closed under the weaker rule.

    0( 7To

    v

    vo)

    0(

    7TV

    v)

    '

    which

    is

    equivalent to Becker's rule. It

    is,

    in fact, the logic axiomatized

    in Lemmon [4]

    as

    P2, but without his axiom

    O X ~ X

    (our M4).

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    15/282

    AXI OMAT I Z I NG QU ANT I FI ER S

    AND M ODAL I T I E S 11

    If

    we

    strengthen things a bit, by considering those X such that

    DT

    :::>X

    is provable in C plus axiom M4, one gets the Lewis system S2 .

    (Again, see Segerberg [5], chapter four.)

    One can also play similar games with axiom M3 (0 T) to produce

    interesting logics. We know very little about them.

    4. QUANT I FI E D L OGI C S , AXI OM AT I C AL L Y

    There is an obvious analogy (of sorts) between the modal operators and

    quantifiers. What we do in this section is to parallel the development of

    section 3, substituting quantifiers for the modal operators to see how far

    the analogy extends when things are done the way we did. The idea

    is

    simple: ('v'x) may behave likeD, (3x) like 0, y like

    v

    and o ike ?T. This

    may be so;

    we

    will see.

    The language now is first order. Once again we assume a pro

    positional-logic base with modus ponens as the sole rule.

    First, the analog of rule M

    is

    rule (Q)

    o(a)

    v y(a)

    OV )

    And, as a matter of fact, this is a correct rule of inference in classical

    first-order logic. This argument is left to the reader.

    Using rule

    Q,

    one may show analogs of the results listed in section 3

    based on rule

    M.

    Thus, one may derive the usual inter definability of the

    quantifiers (again, as mutual implication), and one may show that

    replacement of proved equivalences holds as a derived rule.

    Now, if you actually thought through the "justification" of rule Q,

    almost certainly you also showed the validity, in all first-order models,

    of the schema

    (Ql) ('v'x)[o(x) v y(x)] :::> [o v y].

    So let us add it as an axiom schema. We might, by analogy, call the

    resulting logic QC. I t thus has rule

    Q

    and schema Ql.

    The following

    is

    a reasonable question: What

    is

    an adequate model

    theory for QC,

    one with respect to which completeness can-be shown?

    Well, the following rather curious one

    will

    do. We simply translate the

    corresponding modal model theory, making suitable adjustmer:ts to

    take care of the fact that quantified sentences have many instances, but

    modalized formulas have single components. We have chosen, for

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    16/282

    12

    MEL YIN FI T T I NG

    simplicity, to leave out any mention of the notion of an

    interpretation

    in

    a model. A more elaborate treatment would have to include it, but the

    following is enough for our purposes.

    A model

    is

    a quintuple

    (Cfi, « >, < P,

    < fl,

    If-)

    where: (1) CfJ is a nonempty

    set (of possible worlds); (2) « ~ Cfi; (3) < Pis a mapping from members of

    CfJ to nonempty sets of parameters; (4) < fl

    is

    a relation on Cfi; and (5) If-

    is

    a relation between members of CfJ and sentences such that

    for every f E

    Cfi,

    conditions (a)-( e) as in section 1;

    for every f E

    « >,

    (f) flf-(3x)cp(x) but fi,V-(Vx)cp(x);

    for every f E Cfi- « >

    (g) flf-(Vx)cp(x) iff for every dE CfJ such that f< /ld, and for

    every a E < } (d), d If- cp(a)

    (h) f If-: (3x)cp(x) iff for some dE CfJ such that f< fld, and for some

    a

    E

    < P(d),

    fl.

    If-

    cp(a).

    Now, a sentence

    X is

    a theorem of the logic

    QC

    iff

    X

    holds at every

    world of every such model. We leave the correctness half to the reader.

    Note that

    if

    cp(a) is provable in QC;so

    is

    the parameter variant cp(b).

    This

    will

    be of use in proving correctness. And we briefly sketch the

    completeness half in the next section.

    We note that we could restrict models so that, for each world f,

    < P(r)

    is a singleton. I t makes no difference. Now

    we

    can continue with

    our

    development, paralleling that of section 3.

    In the quantifier models above there can be

    "queer"

    worlds (mem

    bers of cp) in which everything exists, and hence no universal sentences

    hold. Such anomalies can be eliminated by adding the postulate

    (02) (Vx)T.

    Doing so gives us a logic we may call QK. An adequate model theory

    for it

    is

    one that consists of all models of the sort described above, but

    with« always empty, that

    is

    no "queer" worlds.

    Next, there may still be worlds from which no world is accessible. In

    such a world, every universal sentence holds, but no existential. They

    behave rather like empty-domain models of first-order logic. They may

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    17/282

    A X

    IO M ATIZI

    N G Q U

      NTIFIE

    R S

    AN

    D M O D A L

    ITIES

    1

    3

    be ru led out

    by add

    ing the ax

    iom

    (03)

    (3x)T.

    Let

    us call th

    e resulting

      logic QD.

     Its m od e

    l theory

    is

    tha

    t of QK

     with 

    the addi t

    ional requ

    irement that

     for  ever

    y w orld r

    there m us

    t

    be

    so m e

    w

    orld L

    l

    su c

    h tha t

    f ~ L l .

    Finally (?)

      we may

    add an  ana l

    og to M 4 ,

    namely

    (Q 4

    ) y  => y(a)

    or

    «5(a) >  «

    5

    (

    or both).

    A s m ight

    be

    ex pec ted,

    Q3 

    then   b ecom e s redun dan t . 

    We can

    call the

    logic thus

    axiom atize

    d

    QT.

    Its

    m o d el the

    ory is  that

    of Q

    D

    w

    ith the

    restr ict ion

      tha t  the a

    ccessibilit

    y rela t ion ~

    b e reflex

    ive.

    We

     have reac

    hed the

     

    end

    of

    o

    ur

    parallel

    developm

    ent (obviou

    sly,

    since we

      have matc

    hed every

    th ing  we d

    id in sect io

    n 3). 

    But

     

    we do n

    ot

    yet

    have the u

    sual first-

    order logic

    .

    O

    ne 

    d

    oesn't

    w ant

    classical fi

    rst

    order m

    odels with

    lots of po

    ssible  w o r l d ~

      in them

    : a classic

    al model

    should be

    a one-w

    orld m odel

    .

    N ow

    , to only co

    nside r one

    -wor ld Kr i

    p k e m odal

     m o d els is

    to trivialize

     

    m odal l

    ogic; it re

    nders  the

    m o d al ope

    ra to rs  usel

    ess. N eces

    sary tru th

    b

    e c o m es th

    e sam e th

    ing as tru

    th.

    T

    hat i

    s, A => DA

    is valid

    in all

    o n

    e -world m

    odels. Of c

    ourse , this

     is no t desi

    rable. M od

    al operato

    rs are 

    suppo

    sed to do

     s o m ething

    ; they are

     supposed t

    o have an

      effect; the

    y

    ought n

    ot be

    vacuou

    s .

    W ell, it i

    s precisely

     at this poi

    n t tha t m o d

    al operat

    ors

    and

    qua

    ntifiers

    diverge.

    Quan tifiers

     

    can

    be va

    cuous.

    L

    et cp be 

    a se

    ntence (he

    nce with

    no free va

    riables). Then

    ( Vx)cp o

    ught to

      mean no t

    h ing

    mor

    e

    than   cp

    itself. So

    our

    final quantificational axiom

    schema

    is, simply,

    (Q 5)

    cp => 

    ( Vx)c

    p,

    w here

    cp is a sente

    nce.

    When thi

    s is ad d ed ,

     convent io

    nal c lassica

    l first-orde

    r logic is

     

    the

     result.

    5.

     C

    O M PL E T E

    N ESS, HO

    W PR O V E

    D

    In

      a sense, t

    h e p ro o f o

    f the co m p

    leteness of

      the quant

    ifier system

     

    QC

     

    w ith r

    espec t to t

    h e m odel

    theory  pr

    esented in th

    e p revious

     sect ion is

      a

    stret

    ching out

      of th e usu

    al

    H

    enkin

    co m p leten

    ess p ro o f f

    or first-ord

    er

    logic

    .

    Let

    us

    sketch w hat

    we mean

     

    b

    y this.

    R ecall tha

    t th e u

    sual Henkin

      argume

    nt runs as

      follows.

    Take  a

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    18/282

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    19/282

    AXI OM AT I Z I NG QUANT I FI E R S A N D M ODAL I T I E S 15

    model to

    F,

    since ~ F E r

    F ·

    Notice that in the proof just sketched, the maximal consistent

    construction gives the worlds, while the existential instantiation moves

    things from one world to another. This

    is

    what we meant by "stretching

    out" the Henkin construction.

    Adding axioms (02)-(04) modifies the construction in obvious ways.

    We leave this to the reader.

    Now we can ask, What

    is

    the effect on this construction of also

    imposing that final axiom schema (05), cp:::;)

    (Vx)cp?

    Very simply, it

    makes things cumulative. Notice that, in our model, if fq[A, then

    moving from

    r

    to

    A,

    in effect, drops one quantifier from each sentence.

    But cp:::;) (Vx)cp allows us to add one quantifier,

    so-the

    effect

    is

    neutralized. Briefly, if we assume (05), then if fll- cp and

    fq[A,

    then

    A II- cp.

    For, if fll-

    cp,

    since also fll- cp:::;)

    (Vx)cp,

    we must have fii-(Vx)cp.

    And since fq[A, then

    A II-

    some-instance-of-cp. But since the quantifier

    was vacuous, this m e a n s ~

    II-

    cp. Now, that things are cumulative if

    (05)

    is

    imposed means the limit (=chain-union) part of Henkin's proof can

    be carried out. And thus a conventional classical model results.

    This sketch must suffice. Details, though slightly devious, are far

    from devastating.

    1. S E M ANT I C T AB L E AUX

    We show how the tableau system of Smullyan [7] for propositional logic

    may be extended to handle the logics discussed in section 4. We begin

    with a brief sketch of the system that suffices for propositional logic.

    First, proofs are in tree form (written branching downward). There

    are two branch-extension rules:

    a

    (If

    a

    occurs on a branch,

    a

    1

    and

    a

    2

    may be added to the end of the

    branch.

    I f

    f3 occurs on a branch, the end of the branch may be split, and

    {3

    1

    added to the end of one fork, {3

    2

    to the end of the other.)

    A branch

    is

    called closed

    if

    it contains A and ~ A for some formula

    A, or if it contains _1_, or if it o n t a i n s ~

    T.

    A tree is called closed if every

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    20/282

    16

    M EL

    VIN FIT TING

     

    branch is

    closed. A

      closed tre

    e with  ~

    X at the ori

    gin

    is

    , by d

    efinition, a

     

    proof

    of X.

    W e begin

      by addin

    g to the ab

    ove a  tab

    leau rule to

      give  the

    modal

    l

    ogic C . In

      words, th

    e rule  is as

    follows. If,

    on  a b

    ranch,  ther

    e are 

    v-for

    mulas, an

    d there is

      a 7T-for

    mula, then t

    hat 7T-f

    ormula may

    be

    repla

    ced by  1r

    0

    ,

    all the v-f

    ormulas by

      the corre

    sponding

    v

    0

    -formula

    s,

    and a

    ll oth er fo

    rmulas del

    eted.

    W

    e schemat

    ize this as

    follows. Fi

    rst, if S  is a

     set of  form

    ulas, defin

    e

    S# 

    =

    {

    Vo

     

    J v

    E S}.

    Then

    the rule

    is

    s,

    7T

    S#,

    7To

     

    (provided S#-

    4>),

    where this

     is to be int

    erpreted as

     follows: if

    S U { 

    1

    r} is

    the set of f

    ormulas

    on a bran

    ch, it may

      be replac

    ed

    by S

    #

    U {

    7

    To}  (pro

    vided 

    S

    # is

    not

    empty).

    EXAMPLE.

    W e show

    OX

    ::

    ~ o  

    ~ X

    is

    provable  using this rule. 

    The p

    roof begin

    s

    by

    puttin

    g

    ~

    O X ::J

    ~ 0 ~ X

    ) at the ori

    gin, then

    two a

    -rule applicati

    ons produ

    ce the  follo

    wing one-

    branch tre

    e:

    ~

      O X

    ::J

    ~ O

    ~ X)

    ox

    ~ ~

    o ~

    x

    o ~ x .  

    Now take

    S

    to consist of the first three formulas, and

    7T

    to  be 0

    ~ X .  

    The

    n

    S#

    = {X}

    , which is

     

    n

    ot em pty,

    so the rule

     says the se

    t of formul

    as

    on th

    e branch m

    ay be  rep

    laced by S#

    U {1r

    0

    }, n

    amely 

    X

    ~ x

    and this is

    closed

    RE

    MARK. Beca

    use of  the

      way trees

    are written

    , an occu

    rrence  of a

     

    for

    mula may

      be com m

    on to seve

    ral branch

    es, b u t

    we may  wis

    h to

    m

    odify (or d

    elete)  it u

    sing the ab

    ove rule o

    n only o n

    e branch.

    T h e n , 

    s

    imply,  first

      add new

    occurrence

    s of the fo

    rmula  at th

    e ends of

    all the 

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    21/282

    AXI OM AT I Z I NG

    QUANT I FI E R S

    AND M ODAL I T I E S

    17

    branches that are not to be modified, then use the above rule on the

    branch to be worked on.

    Now the other modal logics can be dealt with easily.

    The logic K was axiomatized by adding OT. In effect this says there

    are always v-formulas available, hence S# can always be considered to

    be nonempty. And, in fact, the appropriate tableau system

    forK is

    the

    one above without the provision that S# be nonempty.

    The logic D had

    T

    as an axiom. In effect, this says there

    is

    always a

    7T-formula around, so an explicit occurrence of 7T need not be present to

    apply the tableau rule. Properly speaking, a tableau system for D results

    from that of K by adding the additional rule:

    s

    S#

    Finally the logic

    Thad

    as an axiom schema v => v

    0

    • Well, simply add the

    tableau rule

    JJ

    JJo

    (it can easily be shown that the D-rule above is redundant).

    For quantifiers

    we

    proceed analogously of course. Thus, for a

    parameter a, and a set S of first-order sentences, let

    S(a) = {

    y(a) I

    y E

    S}.

    Then a tableau system for QC

    is

    the Smullyan propositional system

    plus the rule (to be read in a similar fashion to the one for C above)

    S, 5

    S(a), o(a)

    provided

    (1) a

    is

    new to the branch;

    (2)

    S

    (a) :f= c/>.

    For QK, drop the requirement that S(a) be nonempty.

    For

    QD

    , add the rule

    s

    S(a)

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    22/282

    1

    8

    M

    E L V

    IN  F I

    T T IN

    G  

    p

    rovid

    ed a

    is ne

    w to

    the b

    ranch

    .

    Fo

    r Q

    T, a

    dd th

    e rule

     

    Y

    -y(a)

     

    for

    any  p

    aram

    eter a.

    (

    This

    m ake

    s the

     QD 

    rule  r

    edund

    ant).

     

    And

     fin

    ally,

    for f i

    rst-or

    der lo

    gic  p

    roper

     we w

    ant th

    e "cu

    m ula

    tiven

    ess '

    tha

    t

    cp

     

    ::::>

    (

    Vx)cp

     bro

    ught;

      tha t

    is, as

    we go

     on

    in a  t

    ablea

    u con

    struc

    tion ,

    sente

    nces s

    hould

     nev

    er be

    delet

    ed. W

    ell, w

    e cou

    ld re

    place

     the QK

     ru

    le

    by

    S

    , o

     

    S , S(a

    ),

    o(a)

    pro

    vided

     a is

      new

    to th

    e bra

    nch.

    T

    he onl

    y other

     qua

    ntifie

    r ru l

    e now

     is

    Y

    -y(a)

     

    It i

    s no

    t har

    d to  s

    ee th

    at the

    se ar

    e equ

    ivale

    nt to

    the si

    m ple

    r set

    0

    o

    (a)

    a n

    ew

    Y

    -

    y(a)'

    an

    d we

      have

     exac

    tly th

    e firs

    t-orde

    r sys

    tem  o

    f Sm

    ullyan

      [7].

    B IB L IO G R A PH Y

    [1

    ] Fitti

    ng, M

    .: 1973

    , 'Mod

    el Exi

    ste nce

    T heore

    m s fo

    r M oda

    l and

    ln tuitio

    nistic

    Logics

    ',

    Jo

    urnal

    of

    Symb

    olic L

    ogic

    3

    8

    6

    13-627

    .

    [2]

      Kripk

    e ,  S.:

    1963,

    'S em a

    ntical

    Analys

    is  o f

    M odal

    Logic

      I, No

    rmal P

    ropos

    it ional

    Cal

    culi', Zeit

    schrift

    fur

    math

    ematische

    Logik u

    nd 

    G

    rundla

    gen d

    er M a t

    he m a t

    ik

    9, 

    67-9

    6 .

    [3] K

    ripke,

    S.: 19

    65, 'S

    em ant

    ic al A

    na lysis

      of M

    odal L

    ogic

    II ,  N o

    n-norm

    al M o

    dal

    Pro

    positi

    onal C

    alculi '

    , The The

    ory

    o

    f

    M

    od

    e l

    s, J. 

    W.

    Addiso

    n, L.

    H enki

    n and

    A .

    Tarsk

    i (eds.}

    , N orth

    -H olla

    nd Pu

    blishin

    g Co.,

    A mste

    rdam,

    pp. 2 0

    6 -2 2 0 .

     

    [4) Lemm on, E.: 1957, 'N ew Foundati ons for Lew is M odal Systems',

    Journal

    of

    Symbolic

    Logic

     22

     176-

    186 .

    [

    5]  Seg

    erberg

    , K .: 1

    971, An E

    ssay   i

    n Clas

    sical M

    odal L

    ogic,

    U p

    psala.

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    23/282

    A

    X

    IO

    MA

    T

    IZI

    NG

     Q

    U

    AN

    T

    IFI

    ER

    AN

    D

     M

    O D

    A

    L I

    T IE

    1

    [

    6]

    Sm

    ully

    an,

     R

    .: 19

    63,

      A

     Un

    ify

    ing

     Pri

    nci

    ple

    in Q

    ua

    nti f

    ic a

    tio n

     T h

    eo

    ry

    , P

    roc

    eed

    ing

    s of

    th

    e N

    atio

    na

    l A

    cad

    em

    y of

     Sc

    ien

    ces.

     

    [7) Smullyan, 

    R.: 

    1968, 

    First

    Order

    Logic,

    Springer-V erlag , Berlin .

    D e

    p t.

    of

    M a

    the

    m at

    ics

     

    L

    ehm

    an

     C o

    lle

    ge

    B

    ro

    nx, N

    1

    046

    U

    .S

    .A .

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    24/282

    NICOLAS

    D. G O O D M A N

    THE

    KNOWING MATHEMATIC

    IAN

    1.

    Mathematics is at the beginning of a new foundational crisis. Twenty

    years ago there was a firm consensus that mathematics

    is

    set theory and

    that set theory

    is

    Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (ZF). That consensus

    is

    breaking down.

    It

    is

    breaking down for two quite different reasons. One

    of these

    is

    a turning away from the excesses of the tendency toward

    abstraction in post-war mathematics. Many mathematicians feel that

    the power of the method of abstraction and generalization has, for the

    time being, exhausted itself. We have done about as much as can be

    done now by these means, and it is time to return once more to hard

    work on particular examples. (For this point of view see Mac Lane [16,

    pp. 37-38].) Another reason for this turning back from abstraction is

    the economic fact that society is less prepared now than it was twenty

    years ago to support abstract intellectual activity pursued for its own

    sake. Those who support research are asking more searching questions

    than formerly about the utility of the results that can reasonably be

    expected from projects proposed. Mathematicians, moreover, are in

    creasingly obliged to seek employment not in departments emphasizing

    pure mathematics, but in departments of computer science or statistics,

    or even in industry. Thus there

    is

    a heightened interest in applied and

    applicable mathematics and an increased tendency to reject as abstract

    nonsense what

    our

    teachers considered an intellectually satisfying level

    of generality. The set-theoretic account of the foundations of mathe

    matics, however,

    is

    inextricably linked with just this tendency to

    abstraction for its own sake. Mathematics, on that account, is about

    abstract structures which, at best, may happen to be isomorphic to

    structures found in the physical world, but which are themselves most

    definitely not in the physical world. Thus as mathematicians turn away

    from pure abstraction, they also become increasingly dissatisfied with

    the doctrine that mathematics is set theory ·and nothing else.

    There is also another reason for the breakdown of what we may call

    the set-theoretic consensus on the foundations of mathematics. That

    is

    Synthese

    60

    (1984) 21-38. 0039-7857/84/0601-0021 $01.80

    ©

    1984 by D. Reidel Publishing Company

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    25/282

    2

    2

    N IC

    O L AS

    D. G O

    O D M A N

    the b

    reakdow n

    of the  con

    sensus with

    in set  theo

    ry. Th

    e

    w

    ork of  G od

    el

    and

    Cohen  and

     Solovay a

    nd the rest

     has shown

     that Zerm

    elo-Fraen

    kel

    is a

    n astonishi

    ngly weak t

    heory, whi

    ch settles f

    ew of the is

    sues of cen

    tral

    con

    cern to the

      set theori

    st. Not on

    ly does it n

    ot settle t

    he continu

    um

    problem

    , but it also

      does  not

    settle the S

    ouslin  hyp

    othesis, th

    e Kurepa

    hyp

    othesis, th

    e structur

    e of the

    analytic h

    ierarchy,

    or the  ga

    p 2

    conjectu

    re. A  con

    temporary

      set theori

    st, faced

    with a  dee

    p-look ing

    problem

    , asks first

     n ot for a p

    roof or a co

    unterexam

    ple, but fo

    r a model.

    H e  doe

    s not  exp

    ect to  prov

    e or refut

    e a co njec

    ture, but

    to prove it

    indepe

    ndent. The

     num ber

    of indepen

    dent set-th

    eoretic ax

    ioms grow

    s

    alarmingly. More  and m ore exotic large cardinals are invented   and 

    studie

    d, though

    none of th

    em can be

      proved to

      exist.  M o

    re and  m o

    re

    comp

    lex combi

    natorial pr

    inciples ar

    e extracte

    d from  the

      st ructure

    of

    G odel's c

    onstructib

    le universe

     or from th

    e techniqu

    e of some

    intricate

    forcing a r

    g u m ent an

    d are then

    shown  to h

    old in som e

     models bu

    t not in

    others. I f

    mathemati

    cs is set t

    heory,  wh

    ich set the

    ory is  it?

    No one

    knows ho

    w to choo

    se am ong

    these  man

    y conflicti

    ng princip

    les. This

    situation

    , moreove

    r, has gone

      beyond t

    he point w

    here it is o

    f interest

    on

    ly to logi

    cians. A lg

    ebraists in

    terested in

    the struc

    ture of in

    finite

    abelian g

    roups must

     watch the

    ir set theor

    y (see [10]

    and [24]

    ). Analysts

    inte

    rested in th

    e structur

    e of topolog

    ical algeb

    ras must do

     the same

    (see

    [27

    ]

    ).

    Increas

    ingly it se

    ems that e

    very m athe

    matic ian w

    hose inter

    ests

    are  at a

    ll abstract

     

    is

    going t

    o be faced

      with the p

    roblem of

      choosing

    w

    hich set-th

    eoretic ax

    ioms to wo

    rk with. B

    ut it also

    seems  clea

    r that 

    th

    ere is no w

    ay within

    the presen

    t fram ewo

    rk to distin

    guish  whi

    ch of

    these a

    lternative

    set theorie

    s is the tr

    ue one - if

    that  que

    stion even

     

    m akes

      sense  any

      longer. Ea

    ch m athe

    matic ian m

    ust rely o

    n his own

    ,

    increasingly bewildered, intuition

    or

    taste. Evidently it

    is

    time to try to

    f

    ind a new

    framework

    .

    2.

    I suggest

      that both

      of the ab

    ove difficu

    lties with

    the set-th

    eoretical

    fou

    ndational

    consensus

    arise from

      the sam

    e source

    - namely,

      its

    str

    ongly redu

    ctionistic

    tendency.

    Most math

    ematical o

    bjects, as

    they

    o

    riginally pr

    esent them

    selves to u

    s, are not s

    ets. A natu

    ral number

     

    is

    not

    a transi

    tive set line

    arly o rder

    ed by the m

    embership

     relation.

    An ordered

     

    pair is

     not a doub

    leton of a s

    ingleton an

    d a double

    ton. A fun

    ction is no

    t

    a

      set of o r

    dered pairs

    . A real .n

    u m b er is n

    ot an  equ

    ivalence c

    lass of

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    26/282

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    27/282

    24 

    N IC

    O L

    A S D . 

    G

    O O

    D M

    A N

     

    di

    sjo

    int f

    rom

      th

    e un

    ive

    rse 

    of d

    isco

    urs

    e of

     the

     res

    t of

     sci

    enc

    e. In

     th

    inki

    ng 

    abo

    u t 

    pur

    e m

    athe

    m a

    tics

     w

    e en

    d up

      no

      lo

    nge

    r th

    inki

    ng 

    abo

    ut  a

      pa

    rt o

    f

    scie

    nce

    , bu

    t ra

    the

    r ab

    out

     a b

    eau

    ti fu

    l, au

    ste

    re s

    ubs

    titu

    te fo

    r sc

    ien

    ce.

    Thi

    s

    dev

    elo

    pm

    ent

    has

      me

    ant

      a 

    prog

    res

    sive

      im

    po

    veri

    shm

    ent

      of

    the

      ma

    the

    m

    at

    icia

    n 's 

    in tu

    itio

    n. 

    M an

    y m

    ath

    em

    atic

    ian

    s w

    ho 

    kno

    w s

    om

    e c

    om p

    lex

     

    an

    alys

    is d

    not

    kno

    w,

    or 

    do 

    not

      th

    in k 

    of,

      the

      co

    nn

    ecti

    on 

    bet

    w ee

    n

    a

    nal

    ytic

      fun

    cti

    ons

    and

      th

    e flow

     o

    f a

      flu

    id.  W

    he

    n I

      wa

    s ta

    ugh

    t co

    m p

    lex

     

    an

    alys

    is  in

      g

    rad

    uate

      sc

    hoo

    l, I

    wa

    s no

    t ta

    ugh

    t t

    hat

    con

    nec

    tion

    . H

    en

    ce 

    w

    hen

      th

    ink

    ing 

    abo

    u t

    ana

    ly ti

    c fu

    nct

    ions

      th

    ese

      ma

    the

    m at

    icia

    ns 

    can

    no t

     

    rel

    y o

    n th

    eir

      com

    m o

    nse

    nse

      in

    sig h

    t in

    to  t

    he 

    beh

    avi

    or o

    f w

    ate r

    . A

    gai

    n,

    many mathem aticians who  know some of  the  theory of rings and ideals

    do

      no

    t k

    now

      th

    e a

    lgor

    ithm

    s  w

    or

    ked

     out

     by

      K

    ron

    eck

    er a

    nd 

    oth

    ers

    to 

    co

    m p

    ute

     suc

    h id

    eals

    . W

    hen

     I w

    as 

    taug

    h t

    rin g

     the

    ory

     in 

    grad

    uat

    e sc

    hoo

    l, 

    was

      not

     tau

    gh

    t tho

    se 

    alg o

    rith

    ms

    . F o

    r th

    ese

     ma

    the

    m at

    icia

    ns a

    n i

    deal

     

    i

    not

     a c

    om p

    uta

    tion

    al 

    obje

    ct 

    but

    mer

    ely

     an 

    abs

    trac

    t se

    t sa

    tisfy

    ing

      cer

    tain

     

    clo

    sure

     co

    ndit

    ion

    s. T

    hus

     the

    y fi

    nd  i

    t dif

    ficu

    lt e

    ven

     to 

    con

    side

    r no

    ntr

    iv ia

    l

    exa

    m p

    les 

    of  t

    he 

    abs

    trac

    t th

    eor

    y th

    ey 

    hav

    e le

    arn

    ed.

    A n

    y in

    tu it

    ion

      the

    y

    ma

    y h

    ave

      mu

    st b

    e p

    urel

    y fo

    rm

    al. 

    T

    he

     se t

    -the

    ore

    tic 

    red

    ucti

    onis

    ts  h

    av

    e ex

    pla

    ined

      aw

    ay 

    the

      ob

    ject

    s

    we

    w

    ere

     try

    in g 

    to s

    tu dy

    , a

    nd n

    ow

     tho

    se o

    bje

    cts 

    are 

    no 

    long

    er 

    ther

    e to

     gu

    ide 

    u

    s. P

    erh

    aps

     

    i

    t is

    tim

    to b

    ring

      so

    me 

    of  t

    hem

      ba

    ck.

     

    3. 

    T h

    rou

    g h

    ou t

     mo

    st o

    f th

    e tw

    ent

    ieth

     cen

    tur

    y ph

    ysi

    cis t

    s ha

    ve 

    held

     th

    a t it

     

    is 

    no

    t p

    ossi

    ble

      ade

    qua

    tely

      to

      de

    scri

    be 

    the 

    phy

    sica

    l w

    orld

      w

    itho

    ut  t

    aki

    ng 

    in

    to a

    cco

    un t

     the

     ob

    serv

    er w

    ho

     col

    lect

    s th

    e d

    ata 

    that

     t he

     ph

    ysic

    al t

    heo

    ry 

    is 

    in tended  to predict and  explain.  B oth the theory  of relativity and 

    qu

    an

    tum

      m

    ech

    anic

    s a

    re  i

    n v

    ery

      la

    rge 

    par

    t th

    eor

    ies

      of

    the

      re

    lati

    on 

    bet

    w ee

    n th

    e o

    bse

    rve

    r an

    d th

    e p

    hys

    ical

    rea

    lity 

    tha

    t he

      ob

    serv

    es.

    N ei

    the

    r

    the

    ory

    , ho

    we

    ver,

      de

    nies

      th

    e re

    alit

    y o

    r th

    e o

    bjec

    tivi

    ty 

    of t

    he 

    exte

    rna

    l

    rea

    li ty

      th

    at is

    b

    ein

    g o

    bse

    rved

    . A

    lth

    oug

    bo t

    h t

    heo

    ries

      in

    volv

    e

    a

    f

    ar-r

    each

    ing

      ad

    m ix

    tur

    e o

    f ep

    iste

    m o

    log

    y in

      th

    eir 

    bas

    ic d

    esc

    ript

    ion

      of

    p

    hys

    ical

      rea

    li ty

    , ne

    ithe

    r th

    eor

    y c

    an  l

    egit

    im a

    tely

     be

     acc

    use

    d o

    f id

    eali

    sm.

    T

    he

    ob

    serv

    er 

    and

      th

    e

    exte

    rna

    l p

    hys

    ical

      re

    ality

      w

    ith 

    wh

    ich

      he

      is

    c

    on

    fron

    ted

      ar

    e b

    o th

      ir

    redu

    cib

    ly 

    pres

    upp

    ose

    d. 

    In 

    thi

    s se

    nse

      th ese 

    th

    eori

    es  a

    re 

    fund

    am

    ent

    ally

      dua

    list

    ic . 

    T w

    enti

    eth

    -cen

    tur

    y m

    ath

    em a

    tici

    ans

    , on

      th

    e o

    th er

      ha

    nd,

    hav

    e s

    oug

    ht 

    to

      ma

    inta

    in 

    the

      mo

    nis

    tic 

    cha

    rac

    te r 

    of 

    thei

    r di

    scip

    lin

    e.

    Th

    e cla

    ssic

    al

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    28/282

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    29/282

    26

    NICOLAS

    D.

    G O O D M A N

    extensive or meaningful mathematics. Nevertheless, the constructive

    tradition has the very great merit of having emphasized and studied the

    epistemic aspects of mathematics. Those aspects have been largely

    ignored by classical mathematicians.

    The debate between the classical and intuitionistic positions on the

    foundations of mathematics can thus be viewed

    as

    a disagreement

    between two opposed, mutually exclusive, monisms. Each denies that

    the other's reality is of any fundamental significance.

    It

    is like a debate

    on the foundations of physics between a strict Newtonian who denies

    that observability is of any fundamental consequence and a strict

    phenomenalist who denies that our sense experiences refer to any

    knowable reality outside of ourselves. Obviously such a debate is

    unlikely to be fruitful. In physics the fruitful step was the step to a

    dualistic view which emphasized both the role of the observer and the

    role of the reality being observed. It is the thesis of the present essay

    that a similar dualistic view on the foundations of mathematics is both

    possible and desirable.

    4 .

    The observer in quantum mechanics or in the theory of relativity is a

    very highly idealized physicist. He has no subjective bias. He does not

    forget anything. He has no deficiencies of experimental technique. His

    attention never wavers. He never sleeps. In our theory, then, we may

    expect that the knowing mathematician will be similarly idealized. In

    particular, we

    will

    assume that his powers of concentration are poten

    tially infinite.

    There

    is to be no finite bound on the complexity of the

    computations he can carry out

    or

    on the length of the proofs he can

    construct. As I have argued in another place (see [9]), this is a very

    considerable idealization of what is the case for human mathematicians

    or even for the human race viewed collectively as a single mathemati

    cian. Thus the knowing mathematician of our theory is himself to be

    conceived as a mathematical abstraction. His introduction into the

    theory is a step not toward a constructivistic impoverishment of

    mathematics, motivated by doubt about the metaphysical underpin

    nings of set theory, but rather toward an enrichment of classical

    mathematics by the introduction of a new and more extensive vocabu

    lary.

    The

    point

    is

    not to consider only those objects which can be

    known, but rather to consider what aspects of arbitrary objects are

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    30/282

    T H E KNOWI NG MATHEMATIC IAN

    27

    knowable

    in

    principle.

    Thus, although our knowing mathematician

    is

    to be thought of as

    only potentially infinite, he

    is

    not to be thought of as somehow situated

    in

    the physical world. All he does

    is

    mathematics. He has no properties

    that do not follow from his being an idealized mathematician. In this

    respect he resembles the idealized physicist of quantum mechanics

    or

    of

    the theory of relativity.

    Although our goal is to reverse the set-theoretic reductionism of the

    last few decades, it

    is

    clear that we cannot do that in one fell swoop. It

    makes no sense to write down a theory having as its primitives all the

    notions which, in an unanalyzed form, have

    ever

    played a role in

    mathematical practice. Such a theory would be ugly and, presumably, a

    conservative extension of its set-theoretic fragment. It would give no

    new insight. The point is not to reintroduce old notions for the sake of

    not explaining them away.

    The

    point, rather,

    is

    to try to rebuild our

    mathematical intuition by gradually enriching it with notions and

    principles that are not known to be reducible to set theory.

    Thus

    I

    suggest that our first draft of such a theory should be a set theory, but a

    set theory enriched with intensional epistemic notions.

    The

    first theory

    of the sort I have

    in

    mind was based on arithmetic and

    is

    to be found

    in

    Shapiro [23].

    Then

    Myhill in [17] proposed a theory based on set theory

    but

    in

    which the arithmetic part was still, so to speak, singled

    out

    in the

    very syntax of the theory. Finally, in [8], I proposed a theory that

    is

    strictly set theoretic. A similarly motivated but independent and

    formally very different theory can be found in the recent work of

    Lifschitz (see [14] and [15]).

    The theory I will discuss here is the theory of my [8]. I t is a modal set

    theory, with membership as its only nonlogical primitive, and with

    Lewis's S4 as its underlying logic. The modal operator of S4

    is

    to be

    read epistemically. Thus

    O

    means that is knowable.

    5.

    In one respect, at least, our theory will resemble quantum mechanics

    more than it does the theory of relativity.

    The whole point of the theory

    of relativity is to relate the observations of different observers. In the

    mathematical case this does not seem to make much sense. Troelstra in

    [26] considers two mathematicians, one of whom communicates num

    bers to the other without giving him complete information about how

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    31/282

    28 N IC O L

    A S D.  G

    O O D M AN

     

    those num

    bers a re o

    btained. The

    o th er m

    athem atic

    ian, then,

    is able  to

    make certa

    in predict

    ions abou t

      the future

      behavior

    of the  first

      mathe

    matic

    ian. This

    entire  p ic

    ture, how

    ever, seem

    s to m e

    more clos

    ely

    relat

    ed to what

     happens in

     empirical

     science th

    an to anyth

    ing that g

    oes

    on  in

    mathemati

    cs. M athem

    aticians e

    xchange c

    omplete i

    nformation

    .

    T hey

    do no t gen

    erally  hid

    e all or

    part of their

    algorithms

      from  eac

    h

    other. M

    oreover,

    in contrast

    to the situa

    tion in phy

    sics, I do n

    ot see that

     

    it make

    s sense t

    o suppose

      that  one

      mathem a

    tician  som

    ehow  has

     

    preferen

    tial access

     to some p

    art of math

    ematical r

    eality. On

    this basis,

     

    th

    en, it seem

    s to m e ad

    equa te to c

    onsider th

    e case o f o

    nly on

    e

    kn

    ower. 

    T his

    is

    analogous to the  situation  in quantum m echanics, w here 

    one

    does not

      usually co

    nsider the

      effect of

    having m o

    re than

    one experi

    m enter.

    Thus

     

    w h

    en, in 

    our theory, we

     write Ocp,

     we take th

    is to m ean

     that the

    f

    ormula

    cp is know ab

    le to our id

    ealized m a

    them aticia

    n . W e say

    "know

    able"  ra th

    er than "know

    n" bec

    ause of th

    e logic of S

    4. Let us r

    ecall the

    rules of

    that system.

      In additi

    on to  th

    e usual  rule

    s of the c

    lassical

    p

    redica te ca

    lculus, we

      have  the

    follow ing m

    odal  rules

    :

    1.

    Ocp--7cp.

    2

    . 0cp--?0

    0cp.

    3.

    0  1\ 0

    p --7 1/1)

     

    --7

    01/J.

    4.

    From

     1-

    cp

    infer Ocp.

    If we tak

    e 0 to m e

    an 'know n

    ', then  the

    third of the

    se rules as

    serts tha t

    whenever

     our math

    ematician

      can make

      an infere

    nce, he ha

    s already

    done so.

    Even

    an idealized mathem atician presumably does not follow

    out every p

    ossible ch

    ain of infe

    rence. Thus

    we must

     

    ta

    ke 0 to

      m ean

    '

    know able ' .

     On this re

    ading, the

     first of ou

    r rules asse

    rts tha t eve

    rything

    k

    nowable

    is true. T

    he second a

    sserts  that

      anything

    knowable

    can be

    k

    nown to

    be knowabl

    e.

    O

    ne m ig

    ht argue f

    or this by n

    oting 

    that if < > is

     

    ever kn

    own, it wi

    ll then 

    be

    k

    nown t o b

    e know n, a

    nd hence k

    nown to b

    e

    knowab

    le. The t

    hird rule a

    sserts  th a

    t if both

    a conditio

    nal and it

    s

    an teced

    ent ar

    e

    kn

    owable, the

    n the cons

    equent is k

    nowable. F

    inally, the

     

    fourth ru

    le derives

    from our co

    nfidence i

    n our

     

    very

     system o f a

    xioms. If

    we

    actually pr

    ove a claim

    , then w

    e know  th a

    t claim   to

    be true, an

    d so

    tha

    t claim  

    is knowable.

    t seems

     to have b

    een G ode l

     in [7] w ho

     first obser

    ved that S

    4 can be

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    32/282

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    33/282

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    34/282

    T H E KNOWING MAT HE MAT I C

    IAN

    31

    function such that . . . . In order to see that there really are mathemati

    cal notions independent of set theory, let us consider a familiar example

    that is actually rather closely connected with

    our

    idea of mathematical

    knowability in principle. I am thinking of Church's thesis.

    The standard account is that there was a vague and unanalyzed

    informal notion of computability in principle, and that

    Church, Turing

    ,

    Kleene, and Post offered alternative analyses of this notion in set

    theoretic terms that turned out to be equivalent. As usual, let us refer to

    a function satisfying the formal definition as recursive. Church's thesis

    is

    then the vague and premathematical claim that recursiveness coincides

    with computability in principle. It has even been urged that the

    replacement of computability in principle by recursiveness

    is

    analogous

    to the replacement of the informal eighteenth-century notion of con

    tinuity by the formal nineteenth-century

    concept

    defined using epsilons

    and deltas (see Shapiro [22]

    ).

    Note, however, that the two analyses

    function quite differently

    in

    practice.

    The

    informal notion of continuity

    is

    used only heuristically to motivate the epsilon-delta definition.

    Once

    the epsilon-delta definition has been given, no further reference is made

    to the informal notion. The practicing analyst who uses the notion of

    continuity thinks in terms of the epsilon-delta definition, or in terms of

    some other definition equivalent to that definition on the real line.

    Every assertion about continuity is explicitly justified by means of the

    epsilon-delta definition. The contemporary recursive-function theorist,

    on the

    other

    hand, uses the informal notion of computability constantly.

    He thinks in terms of that notion, rather than in terms of one of the

    standard formal definitions. Proofs in the theory of recursive functions

    usually no longer refer to the formal definitions

    at

    all.

    If

    it becomes

    relevant to relate the theory to

    one

    of the formal definitions, this

    connection

    is

    established by a global appeal to

    Church's

    thesis.

    The

    analyst says, "This function

    is

    continuous because I have shown that it

    satisfies the epsilon-delta definition."

    The

    recursion theorist says, "This

    function

    is

    recursive because I have shown how to

    compute

    it."

    The

    role of the formal, set-theoretic definition

    in

    the two cases could not be

    more different.

    It might be suggested that we are still so close to the time when the

    definition of recursiveness was first given that there has not been time

    for the formal notion to drive

    out

    the informal notion it is intended to

    replace.

    The

    historical evidence, however, points in the opposite

    direction.

    The

    early papers in the theory of recursive functions were

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    35/282

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    36/282

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    37/282

    34

    NICOLAS

    D.

    G O O D M A N

    recursively enumerable set can exhaust the truths of any nontrivial

    mathematical theory. Thus, at least as far as we could know, the

    problem of intensionality does arise.

    9.

    When we do set-theoretic mathematics, we reason about sets, not about

    descriptions of sets. Nevertheless, when we reason epistemically about

    particular sets, asking ourselves questions such as whether we could

    actually construct a set with a certain property, we are necessarily

    dealing not with the sets themselves, but only with defining criteria. As

    a mathematical abstraction, at least, it is

    not difficult to construct a

    language in which every set has a defining criterion. For, form a

    "language" in the logician's sense having a name for every set. Then

    the set

    A is

    defined by the criterion, 'x belongs to A'

    .

    Of course, in this

    language, the set A

    will

    also have many other defining criteria, some of

    which may not be knowably equivalent to this one. Although no human

    being could learn this language, we often talk as though we were using a

    finite fragment of it. A mathematician who has proved the existence of

    a set with a certain property but does not know any actual criterion for

    membership

    in

    such a set will not hesitate to introduce a name for a

    particular such set. For example, he may write as follows:

    "Thus

    we see

    that there exists a regular ultrafilter. Let D be such an ultrafilter. We

    know that

    D

    has such and such property. Hence . . . . " As an illustration

    of this procedure, let L be a language of the sort described.

    Every set has a defining criterion expressible in

    L.

    These criteria can

    be thought of as representatives , of the sets. For all mathematical

    purposes, these representatives will do the work of the sets. Member

    ship

    in

    a set

    is

    just satisfaction of the corresponding membership

    criteria. The usual axiom of extensionality, which asserts that two sets

    with the same members are identical, tells us that two defining criteria

    which are satisfied by the same objects are representatives of the same

    set. Thus, in the spirit of the usual set-theoretic reductionism, we may

    think of a set as an equivalence class of these defining criteria under the

    relation of being satisfied by the same objects. (Actually, as this

    construction

    is

    carried out in my paper [8], it is technically somewhat

    more complex. The problem is that some criteria will not be exten

    sional. Thus sets should be thought of as equivalence classes of

    hereditarily extensional criteria. But these details need not concern us

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    38/282

    T HE

    K N O W I N G

    M A T H E M A T I C

    IAN

    35

    here.)

    The relation of extensional identity is not the only interesting

    equivalence

    relation

    on the

    defining criter ia expressible in

    our language

    L. A

    somewhat stronger

    relation

    is

    the relation which holds

    between

    two of these criteria when it is knowable that they apply to exactly the

    same

    objects.

    Let me

    refer to this relation as

    modal

    extensional identity.

    Criteria

    that

    are modally extensionally identical

    can

    be thought of as

    representatives

    of the

    same set-theoretic property or

    attribute.

    More

    formally, by a

    property

    let us

    mean

    an equivalence class of defining

    criteria

    under

    the relation of modal extensional identity.

    Then

    we

    can

    interpret

    our

    modal

    set theory

    as being

    about

    properties.

    In this way, interpreting

    our

    theory as being a

    theory

    of

    properties

    rather

    than a theory of sets, the problems of interpretation we men

    tioned

    above

    disappear. For, two properties

    that can

    be known to apply

    to the same objects will have exactly the same properties expressible in

    the language of

    our

    theory.

    Thus

    if we adopt a modal axiom of

    extensionality asserting that

    properties

    that can be known to apply to

    the same things are identical, then we will have full substitutivity of

    identity.

    10.

    Let me now suggest that the

    above

    construction of properties from sets

    is exactly backwards. The historical development, at least, went in the

    other

    direction. Sets first appeared in mathematics in the form of

    properties expressed in some language - say mathematical

    German.

    That is to say, the defining criteria are historically the primary objects .

    These

    properties

    were studied by impredicative

    and

    nonconstructive

    methods, so that it was clear very early that mathematical German was

    not

    adequate

    to formulate all possible such

    properties

    (for what

    amounts to this point , see Borel [3, pp. 109-11 0]).

    Thus

    sets were

    introduced

    as

    mathematical

    abstractions to support a notion of

    property

    that

    had

    come detached

    from the idea of expressibility in any particular,

    or even

    any possible, language. The

    problem

    then

    arose about

    what

    criterion of identity

    one

    should use for these strange new mathematical

    objects

    . In

    the

    positivistic intellectual climate of the turn of the

    century,

    it was not difficult to arrive at a consensus that extensional identity was

    the only possible criterion. As a

    matter

    of fact, however,

    some

    sort of

    intensional identity may be more suitable for pre-set-theoretic mathe-

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    39/282

    36

    NICOLAS D . G O O D M A N

    matical practice. Thus I suggest that we should go back to the situation

    in, say, 1880, when it was not yet clear what it should mean to say

    that

    two sets are identical. In

    that

    situation it makes sense

    to

    suggest

    that

    two sets are identical just in case it can be known that they have exactly

    the same elements. Given

    that

    we

    have

    an adequate logic of knowabil

    ity, which we do , this suggestion may be more fruitful than the generally

    accepted one. To avoid confusion today, however, we should probably

    not refer to the resulting objects as sets, but as properties.

    1 1 .

    Once

    it

    is

    clear

    that the

    theory we want to write down

    is

    a theory of

    properties in

    the above

    sense, it is not difficult to write down the axioms

    by imitating ZFC (that is,

    Zermelo-Fraenkel

    set theory with the axiom

    of choice).

    For

    the details, I refer thti

    reader

    to [8]. The resulting theory

    is as rich as set theory. ZFC is faithfully interpretable in it. As a matter

    of fact, the theory is richer than set theory. For example,

    in

    it we can

    express that we have actually constructed an object, rather than merely

    proved

    it to exist. Most of the basic

    constructive

    notions are easily

    expressible. Of course, the underlying metaphysical position is not at all

    intuitionistic,

    but

    Platonistic.

    What remains is to try to develop set theory and analysis in this new

    framework, trying to exploit its additional expressive power. As we do

    so, we should be able to develop sufficient intuition for the epistemic

    component

    of the new framework that we

    can

    begin to think informally

    about

    the knowing mathematician without having to rely

    on

    any

    formalization, including ours.

    Then

    we should be led to ask new

    questions and to find new

    phenomena

    that will enrich classical

    mathe

    matics.

    It

    seems rational to hope that the resulting sharpening of

    our

    set-theoretic intuition will

    either

    lead to new insight into the apparently

    unanswerable questions of set theory, or else will enable us to see that

    those questions are not really very important or very central after all.

    What is more important is that by working with intensional notions

    directly connected with

    our

    actual mathematical experience - by

    considering mathematical knowledge, computability, and construction

    as ingredients of our universe of discourse rather than as merely

    psychological aspects of

    our

    work - we may restore

    some

    of the

    concrete mathematical intuition that we

    have

    lost. In this way we may

    gradually break down the prestige of

    set-theoretic

    abstraction and

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    40/282

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    41/282

    3

    8

    NI C OL A

    S D

    .

    G O O D

    M A N

    [1

    8] Quine, W

    . V.: 1976,

    'Three Grades 

    of Mod al Invo

    lvem ent' , in 

    The Ways

    of Paradox

    and Other

     Essays, rev. e

    d. , Harvard  

    U.P. , Cambri

    dge, Mass., p

    p. 158-176. 

    [19] Randolph ,

    J.

    F.: 1968,

    Basic Real and Abstract Analysis

    Academic Press, New

    York.

    [20] Roge

    rs, H.: 1967

    , Theory of

    Recursive

    Functions an

    d Effective C

    omputability

    McGraw-Hil

    l, New York .

     

    [21] Ro

    senlicht, M.:

      1968, Intr

    oduction

    to

    A

    nalysis, Scott,

    Foresman, G

    lenview, III . 

    [22] S

    hapiro, S.: 'O

    n Church 's T

    hesis ' , Typesc

    ript.

    [23] Shapi

    ro, S.: 1984, '

    Epistemic

    r i t ~ m e t i c

    and

     Intuitionistic

      Ari thmetic ',

    to ap pear in

    S. Shapiro (e

    d .), Intensio

    nal Mathema

    tics, North-Ho

    lland Pub. C o

    ., New York.

     

    [2

    4] Shelah,

    S. : 1979,

    'On Well Orderin

    g and More o

    n Whitehead

    's Problem', A

    bstract

    79T-E47,

    Notices Amer

    . Math. Soc

    ., 26, A-442 . 

    [2 5] Shoenfield , J. R.: 1972, 

    Degrees

    of

    Unsolvability, 

    N orth-Holland , Amsterdam .

    [26] T

    roelstra,

    A .

    S

    .: 1968, '

    The The ory of C h

    oice Sequenc

    es', in B. Va n

     R ootselaar a

    nd

    J. F

    .

    Staal (eds.),

      Logic , Met

    hodology and

     Philosophy

    of Science I l

    l

    N

    orth-Hollan d

    ,

    A m st

    erdam , pp. 20

    1 - 223 .

    [27] 

    Williamson, 

    J

    .

    H.: 1979, 

    Review of

    Topological

    Algebras by E .

      Beckenstein

    , L.

    Na

    rici, and

    C.  Suffel, Bull

    . Am

    er

    . Mat

    h. Soc. (New S

    eries) 1

    ,

    237-

    244.

    Dept. of M

    athematics

    Suny-Buff

    alo

    A m h

    erst, NY 142

    60

    U .S.A.

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    42/282

    R AYM OND D. GUMB

    "CONSERVATIVE"

    KRIPKE

    CLOSURES*

    0. I N T R O D U C T I O N

    Computable Kripke closures are properties of relations which have

    closures in, roughly speaking, the sense of the transitive closure. They

    were introduced in [8] to generalize Kripke-style tableaux con

    structions and were studied from a model-theoretic perspective by

    Weaver and Gumb [19].

    In section 1 of this paper, we review the properties of computable

    Kripke closures. In section 2, we state four additional laws that can be

    imposed on computable Kripke closures and state properties of the

    closures determined by these laws. In a sense, all four of our laws

    require closures to be "conservative". However, regarding later sec

    tions, it

    is

    more revealing to classify two of the laws as being

    commutative and two as being conservative.

    In the remaining sections, we sketch applications of these laws

    in

    modal logics having a Kripke-style relational semantics: simplifying

    Kripke-style tableaux constructions (section 3), proving the Craig

    Interpolation Lemma (section 4), establishing Henkin-style complete

    ness proofs (section 5), and providing a somewhat plausible prob

    abilistic semantics (section 6). At least in modal logic, our laws carve

    out natural classes of properties of binary relations.

    1. C OM P UT AB L E KR I P KE C L OS UR E S

    The presentation of the computable Kripke closures

    in

    this section

    is

    much the same as that

    in

    [8, section 5]. A model-theoretic study of the

    first-order Kripke closures using a different notation can be found

    in

    [19].

    A (binary) relational system

    is

    a pair i i =(a-, r), where a-

    is

    a nonvoid

    set and

    r

    sa-Xu

    is

    a (binary) relation on

    a-.

    Let

    BR

    be the class of

    relational systems. Understand Pr

    s;

    BR to be a property of relations if Pr

    is

    closed under isomorphisms. Let Pr be a property of relations, and let

    Synthese

    60

    (1984) 39-49. 0039-7857/84/0601-0039 $01.10

    © 1984

    by

    D.

    Reidel Publishing Company

  • 8/18/2019 Elliott Mendelson - Foundations Logic, Language and Mathematics

    43/282

    4

    0

    R A

    YM O

    N D D

    . G

    UM B

     

    i

    i = (u,

     

    r

    ) an

    d ii+

    = (u+,

    r+)

    be re

    lation

    al sy

    stems

    . W e

      say  t

    hat  r+

    is  a

     

    Pr-re

    lation

      (on

    u+) if

      i

    i

    +

    E Pr

    . W e

    call

    r

    +

    the

     

    Pr

    -closu

    re

    of r (on

    u +

    ) and

     

    writ

    er+=

     

    p

    ru •

    (r) if u s

     u +,

    r s r+

    , a

    nd r+

    is th