equilavent but separate: the role of mathematics in deleuze and guattari

Upload: jody-collins

Post on 04-Apr-2018

212 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    1/20

    Jody Collins

    LIT255

    4/28/2012

    Equivalent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    This paper explores the ways that mathematics functions as the

    organizing mechanism the three chaoids (philosophy, science, and art) as

    presented in What is Philosophy? by Gilles Deleuze and Flix Guattari. Ipostulate that philosophy can be correlated with nomadic science, with

    problematics, and thus creates planes of immanence out of chaos, while

    science correlates with royal science, axiomatics, and creates planes of

    reference. Art begins with axiomatics, then covers it with problematics,

    creating a new dimensional space: the plane of composition.

    Further, I propose that phenomenal reality is created out of the

    incessant shuttle of translation between the three planes by the mind/brain,

    either through a top-down or a bottom-up approach. Neither approach is

    reciprocal, since the starting point modifies what and were the end point will

    be. The three chaoids are equivalent, but not reducible one to another. This

    paper will focus less on the specific characteristics of the three chaoids as it

    will inquire into the connective links between them, illuminating that which

    separates the chaoids into distinct parts and at the same time allows them to

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    2/20

    Collins 2

    interact with one another in the arena of thought. The mechanism by which

    the chaoids move and create order out of chaos is mathematics, not solely in

    its common use on manipulating numbers, but also in its linguistic function.

    The primary tension in What is Philosophy? is between philosophy and

    science, between concept and function. The difference between the two can

    be found as the difference between the two types of mathematics as

    explained by Daniel W. Smith:

    . . .the ontology of mathematics is not reducible to axiomatics, but

    must be understood much more broadly in terms of the complex

    tension between axiomatics and what he [Deleuze] calls

    problematics. Deleuze assimilates axiomatics to major or royal

    science, . . . which constantly attempts to effect a reduction or

    repression of the problematic pole of mathematics, itself wedded to a

    minor or nomadic conception of science. (412)

    Thus, what Deleuze and Guattari refer to as science is not so much science

    as used in common parlance, but rather royal science, axiomatics or

    theorematics, which offsets a philosophy which corresponds with the

    nomadic science, problematics. The two poles of mathematics can never

    be reconciled, since they approach chaos from utterly opposite ways.

    Axiomatics, or science, relinquishes the infinite, infinite speed, in order to

    gain a reference able to actualize the virtual (Deleuze and Guattari 118,

    italics in original). Problematics, or philosophy, on the other hand, retains the

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    3/20

    Collins 3

    infinite and gives consistency to the virtual through concepts (ibid ). Smith

    concurs, saying: In the minor geometry of problematics, figures are

    inseparable from their inherent variations, affections, and events; the aim of

    major theorematics, by contrast, is to uproot variables from their state of

    continuous variation in order to extract from them fixed points and constant

    relations (416). Problematics deals in change, while science desires to slow

    change down so that points of reference may be calculated. Since the two

    approaches have different methods and goals with regard to chaos, to

    change, they can never parallel each other, though they are capable of

    intersecting, interacting, and influencing each other.

    The interaction between problematics and axiomatics is enacted upon

    the field of mathematic logic, what Simon Duffy terms the logic of the

    calculus of problems (565). It is not calculus as such, nor even

    mathematical problems per se, which are at stake here, but rather theinteractions within calculus which can be imposed upon the interaction of the

    chaoids in What is Philosophy? . Duffy continues to say that this logic is not

    simply characteristic of the relative difference between Royal and nomadic

    science . . . It is rather characteristic of the very logic of the generation of

    each mathematical problematic itself (ibid). While it is clear that there are

    inherent differences between philosophy and science, between problematics

    and axiomatics, it is not their differences with which this calculus is primarily

    concerned. It focuses, instead, with the creation of the actual out of the

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    4/20

    Collins 4

    virtual, and on the inevitable reversion of the actual to the virtual. It is

    concerned, in short, with creation from chaos.

    A brief explanation of chaos as conceptualized by Deleuze and Guattari

    here is useful, since the nature of chaos can by no means be assumed. In

    What is Philosophy? they state:

    Chaos is defined not so much by its disorder as by the infinite speed

    with which every form taking shape in it vanishes. It is a void that is

    not a nothingness but a virtual , containing all possible particles and

    drawing out all possible forms, which spring up only to disappear

    immediately, without consistency or reference, without consequence.

    Chaos is an infinite speed of birth and disappearance. (118, italics in

    original)

    Hence, what characterizes chaos is infinite speed and infinite possibility,

    pure change. According to Deleuze and Guattari, chaos has three

    daughters, depending on the plane that cuts through it: these are the

    Chaoids art, science, and philosophy as forms of thought or creation

    (208, italics in original). The chaoids, for all that they provide us with ordered

    reality, are not easily controlled: Philosophy, science, and art want us to

    tear open the firmament and plunge into the chaos (202). Mathematics is

    what keeps the chaoids from dissolving our thoughts in the chaos of reality,

    by placing a system of checks and balances upon their operations and by

    providing them a mechanism with which to move from chaos to order.

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    5/20

    Collins 5

    This is why Deleuze and Guattari specifically give the term chaoids

    to philosophy, science, and art, because the three desire chaos, are born of

    chaos, and yet they enter chaos to bring back order, manipulate the fabric of

    potential to create the actual: They are the three planes, the rafts on which

    the brain plunges into and confronts chaos (ibid 210). All three chaoids

    derive meaning and order from chaos in different ways, as mandated by the

    mathematic system which models them. It is the virtual which the chaoids

    seek to express: by keeping infinite speed in the form of absolute survey to

    give the virtual consistency, by actualizing the virtual through limiting the

    infinite, or by manipulating the limits of the actual to extract the sensations

    of the virtual philosophy, science, and art.

    When confronting chaos, the virtual which the chaoids seek to act

    upon is called the event. The event holds within it both a problem and a

    solution, and as all possibilities are contained within chaos, so too is themultiplicity of events drawn from chaotic possibility. As Bent Sorensen says:

    The problem appears as a real multiplicity by being produced as a

    problematic; the problem becomes an event (125-126). Thus, what first

    approaches and captures the event is philosophy as problematics. Deleuze

    and Guattari concur, saying: It is a concept that apprehends the event, its

    becoming, its inseparable variations (158, italics in original). The concept, a

    purely philosophical tool, first grasps the problem that is the event within

    chaos, and with the problem it must grasp the solution, since the two are

    twinned. Sorenson continues to say that at the same time as the solution is

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    6/20

    Collins 6

    inscribed in the actual event of the problem, the relevant problem to which it

    is a solution, must be counteractualized into its virtual phase, in a perpetual

    state of becoming, that is, becoming a ctualized (126, italics in original). The

    problem as event is always already virtual, and any solution to the problem,

    be it in the form of concept, function, or aesthetic construction, necessarily

    presupposes the actualized problem and re-inscribes the problem in the

    virtual. This is why events are always becoming and never are.

    An event cannot be actualized without retaining recourse to the

    infinite, the virtual. Even in the actualization of an event through states of

    affairs, the function in science, the event maintains a virtuality which eludes

    capture by functions. As Deleuze and Guattari put it: No doubt, the event is

    not only made up from inseparable variations, it is itself inseparable from the

    state of affairs, bodies, and lived reality in which it is actualized or brought

    about. But we can also say the converse: the state of affairs is no moreseparable from the event that nonetheless goes beyond its actualization in

    every respect (159). Philosophy may speak the event, but science

    actualizes the event through states of affairs, and both are necessary for the

    event to be drawn from chaos (ibid 21). In its need to actualize the event,

    however, science is actually attempting to destroy the event, to sever it from

    its connection to the infinite, to grasp it whole and thus make it be.

    Science cannot apprehend becomings.

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    7/20

    Collins 7

    Here we must turn again to mathematics to see how philosophy and

    science interact to effectuate the event. Smith argues that:

    . . . mathematics is replete with events, to which he [Deleuze] grants

    full ontological status, even if their status is ungrounded and

    problematic; multiplicities in the Deleuzian sense are themselves

    constituted by events. In turn, axiomatics, by its very nature,

    necessarily selects against and eliminates events in its effort to

    introduce rigor into mathematics and to establish its foundations.

    (413)

    We can see how philosophy, operating as problematics, can apprehend the

    event, while axiomatic science struggles with the event. Problematics grasps

    the event, the problem, and creates a solution. In creating a solution,

    however, the problem is thrown back into virtuality, into chaos, and a new

    event arises to fuel philosophys movement. Axiomatics, on the other hand,

    attempts to wrest the event whole from chaos, to embody it within a state of

    affairs, to reign it in with functions, and in so doing to remove from the event

    that which makes it the event the virtual problem in the first place.

    Axiomatics is primarily concerned with solutions, and problematics primarily

    with the problems, though both encounter the event whole.

    Smith goes on to say that problematics and axiomatics (minor and

    major science) together constitute a single ontological field of interaction,

    with the latter perpetually effecting a repression or more accurately, an

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    8/20

    Collins 8

    arithmetic conversion of the former (414). The phenomenal reality of an

    event necessitates both branches of mathematics, both philosophy and

    science, since without embodiment the event cannot appear. But it is also

    here that mathematics transcends mere numerical manipulation and enters

    the linguistic register. It is the translation of the event from problematics to

    axiomatics and back again which allows our apprehension of the event.

    Deleuze and Guattari concur, saying: The task of philosophy when it creates

    concepts, entities, is always to extract an event from things and beings . . .

    space, time, matter, thought, the possible as events (33). Axiomatics

    embodies the event in things and beings, and philosophy in turn

    disembodies the event and places it back within the virtual. It is the

    translation, the constant shuttle between science and philosophy, which

    creates change, movement.

    The path between embodiment and the virtual does not remain thesame coming up as it is going down. Here enters the difference between

    differential and integral calculus within the logic of the differential calculus of

    problems. Simon Duffy explains the mathematic difference as follows: The

    differential calculus consists of two branches which are inverse operations:

    differential calculus, which is concerned with calculating derivatives, or, in

    Leibnizian terms, differential relations or quotients; and integral calculus,

    which is concerned with integration, or the calculation of the infinite sum of

    the differentials in the form of series (566). The differential calculus thus

    contains two approaches: differential calculus, or axiomatics, and integral

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    9/20

    Collins 9

    calculus, or problematics. Though both are contained within the calculus, the

    difference is crucial it is the difference between a top-down or a bottom-up

    approach, and the starting point determines the outcome.

    Placing the difference between integration and differentiation back into

    the context of What is Philosophy? , we see how the paths between the

    virtual and the actual alter their shape depending on the approach, and how

    science and philosophy modify each other:

    Science passes from chaotic virtuality to the states of affairs and

    bodies that actualize it. However, it is inspired less by the concern for

    unification in an ordered actual system than by a desire not to distance

    itself too much from chaos, to seek out potentials in order to seize and

    carry off a part of that which haunts it, the secret of the chaos behind

    it, the pressure of the virtual.

    Now, if we go back up in the opposite direction, from states of

    affairs to the virtual, the line is not the same because it is not the same

    virtual (we can go down it as well without it merging with the previous

    line). The virtual is no longer the chaotic virtual but rather virtuality

    that has become consistent, that has become an entity formed on a

    plane of immanence that sections the chaos. This is what we call the

    event, or the part that eludes its own actualization in everything that

    happens. (155-156, italics in original).

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    10/20

    Collins 10

    The path of science is the path of differential calculus, of embodying the

    virtual in states of affairs, of incessantly calculating derivatives in order to

    impose reason on chaos. To move back from this place, from embodiment

    back to the virtual, from science to philosophy, however, takes us back not

    to the original chaotic virtuality from which science calculated the

    differential, but rather to a new virtuality, a virtuality ordered by integral

    calculus. The creation of the differential comes at the price of creating the

    integral. The path is never the same twice chaotic virtuality is lost in the

    mathematical operation as translation.

    We must not forget, however, that even in the actualization of the

    virtual through functions and bodies, there is always a part of the virtual

    which resists embodiment. The event cannot be separated from its virtuality,

    from its continual becomings. As Smith points out, in the calculus, the

    differential is by nature problematic, it constitutes the internal character of the problem as such, which is precisely why it must disappear in the result

    or solution. On the other hand, . . . the differential provides him [Deleuze]

    with a mathematical symbolism of the problematic form of pure change

    (426, italics in original). Even though the differential functions in science as a

    way to embody the virtual, the form of the differential itself speaks to the

    virtual which cannot be contained by it. The form of the differential, or, to

    slip into the linguistic register, the sign of the differential, is problematic, and

    as such points to the virtual, to the event which it cannot through its function

    apprehend.

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    11/20

    Collins 11

    The differential is the sign of the virtual, which is how Deleuze and

    Guattari can say that science is paradigmatic , whereas philosophy is

    syntagmatic (124, italics in original). Science looks to the meaning, the

    solution within the differential, and so misses the event, the becoming, which

    is immanent to the sign of the differential and which is acted upon by

    philosophy. As Smith argues, one might say that while progress can be

    made at the level of theorematics and axiomatics, all becoming occurs at

    the level of problematics (424). Science can certainly lay claim to progress,

    insofar as progress consists of creating solutions to more and more

    problems. The problems themselves, however, their becomings, cannot be

    truly addressed by science. It is the arena of problematics, of philosophy,

    which is capable of dealing with events in their virtuality, in their constant

    flux.

    Science and philosophy clearly operate in different ways. They both,however, operate upon the same thing: both delve into chaos to create order

    through mathematics. But as Deleuze and Guattari say, when an object a

    geometrical space, for example is scientifically constructed by functions, its

    philosophical concept, which is by no means given in the function, must still

    be discovered (117, italics mine). The operations of a scientific function

    cannot lead us to the philosophical concept which is operating in dialogue

    with the function. The very fact that such a function exists, however, its very

    form, points to a problematic behind its construction. This is why Smith

    suggests that axiomatics is a foundational but secondary enterprise in

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    12/20

    Collins 12

    mathematics, dependent for its very existence on problematics (422).

    Although this line of reasoning is persuasive, we must nonetheless

    remember that the event, the problem, cannot remain only a virtuality, but

    must be embodied in states of affairs. Moving from science to philosophy

    suggests that the philosophical concept appears prior to the scientific

    function, but moving in the opposite direction suggests that the concept is

    merely derived from the function. Deleuze and Guattari explain this tangle,

    claiming that nonphilosophy is found where the plane [of immanence]

    confronts chaos. Philosophy needs a nonphilosophy that comprehends it; it

    needs a nonphilosophical comprehension just as art needs nonart and

    science needs nonscience (218, italics in original). Each chaoid requires the

    existence of the other two in order to function: The three planes, along with

    their elements, are irreducible (ibid 216). The three inform each other,

    though none can work in parallel with another. Each chaoid is equal to the

    others; none can appear first or work better, since the three are equally

    dependent on each other and equally distinct from each other.

    The need of one chaoid for another refers us back to the necessity of

    translation posited earlier. Smith acknowledges this need, stating that what

    is crucial in the interaction between the two poles [axiomatics and

    problematics] are thus the processes of translation that take place between

    them (423). The translation between the chaoids occurs in the brain, at the

    level of thought: The brain is the junction not the unity of the three

    planes (Deleuze and Guattari 208, italics in original). It is crucial to

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    13/20

    Collins 13

    recognize that the chaoids are never unified, not even when translated and

    communicated within thought. Rather, they intersect, relate, and inform

    each other within the space of thought, within the brain. As Sorensen claims:

    Thinking itself is a practice that is able to produce the plane of immanence,

    just as science and art are . . . The infinite movement of thought makes it

    capable of traversing vast distances and multiple flows in a single flash, and

    as a practice thinking draws a plane that maps these distances and these

    flows (127). Although the planes which philosophy, science, and art draw

    are different, all three planes are used by thought to cut the chaos and

    create order.

    Thus far my discussion has been mostly limited to the interaction

    between science and philosophy, between axiomatics and problematics. The

    third chaoid, art, has been intentionally placed to one side, because while

    the mathematical interaction between science and philosophy is relativelyclear, the inclusion of art carries with it the potential to muddy the waters.

    Smith, however, provides us with a rather oblique point of entry for art:

    Even in mathematics, the movement from a problem to its solutions

    constitutes a process of actualization; though formally distinct, there is no

    ontological separation between these two instances (432). We have already

    seen how philosophy and science deal with the problem event and its

    solution(s). Art enters the scene between philosophy and science, in the

    process of actualization. Since all three chaoids must confront chaos to

    bring order, and since all three are by nature distinct, each has its own

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    14/20

    Collins 14

    method for dealing with the virtual and the actual. Philosophy creates a

    plane of immanence, science creates a plane of reference, and art creates a

    plane of composition . This is how Deleuze and Guattari define art:

    Composition, composition is the sole definition of art. Composition is

    aesthetic, and what is not composed is not a work of art (191). Art draws

    from axiomatics and problematics, but is not either it is the composition of

    elements from the two poles.

    Art as composition must be distinguished from the kind of composition

    which science creates. Art is not the construction of functions or equations,

    though it may borrow from or be built upon just such an axiomatic

    foundation. Deleuze and Guattari claim emphatically that technical

    composition, the work of the material that often calls on science . . . is not to

    be confused with aesthetic composition, which is the work of sensation. Only

    the latter fully deserves the name composition , and a work of art is neverproduced by or for the sake of technique (191-192, italics in original).

    Composition includes technique, but is never simply reducible to technique.

    Art also borrows from philosophy, in that it interacts with a becoming,

    with an event. Deleuze and Guattari explain the difference between

    conceptual becoming and aesthetic becoming by saying that there are

    sensations of concepts and concepts of sensations. It is not the same

    becoming. Sensory becoming is the action by which something or someone

    is ceaselessly becoming-other (while continuing to be what they are) . . .

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    15/20

    Collins 15

    whereas conceptual becoming is the action by which the common event

    itself eludes what is (177). For the concept, the event escapes actualization,

    even escapes itself. For art, on the other hand, the event is constantly

    composed in such a way that it becomes other, that is, it is composed so that

    it presents itself and presents an other, simultaneously.

    Art deals with the event as self and other, as two contrasts welded into

    one sensation, and as such, it uses both axiomatics and problematics in its

    composition. This use of both branches of mathematics is directly addressed

    by Deleuze and Guattari: Abstract art, and then conceptual art, directly

    pose the question that haunts all painting that of its relation to the concept

    and the function (183). Although art is neither a concept nor a function,

    both are necessary starting points for art to be realized.

    The primary role of art is to withdraw sensation from chaos, and

    though art may use axiomatics or problematics as a starting point, it goes

    beyond the capabilities of either branch of mathematics alone. This is clear

    when Deleuze and Guattari say: Art enjoys a semblance of transcendence

    that is expressed not in a thing to be represented but in the paradigmatic

    character of projection and in the symbolic character of perspective (193).

    Art borrows from the paradigmatic nature of science and the syntagmatic

    nature of philosophy to compose something which is greater than the sum of

    its parts, to give sensation to the event. Just as the event needs philosophy

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    16/20

    Collins 16

    to give it meaning and science to give it form, so too does it need art to give

    it sensation.

    Also like philosophy and science, art must go through a series of

    translations to produce sensation. Deleuze and Guattari explain this

    aesthetic translation process, saying:

    On this plane of composition, as on an abstract vectorial space,

    geometrical figures are laid out cone, prism, dihedron, simple plane

    which are no more than cosmic forces capable of merging, being

    transformed, confronting each other, and alternating . . . The planes

    must now be taken apart in order to relate them to their intervals

    rather than to one another and in order to create new affects. (187)

    The interaction between problematics and axiomatics, the form and meaning

    of mathematical shapes and functions, is dismantled by art, rearranged, and

    translated into an aesthetic form. Not only is art translating science and

    philosophy, it is translating itself, changing the form and meaning of a cube

    into the form and meaning of say, a room, which itself takes on the form and

    meaning of something else within the context of the artwork.

    Art, then, operates under the same guidelines as both science and

    philosophy. It is still modeled upon mathematics, even if secondhand. If art is

    to be found in mathematics pure, however, Smith may provide an avenue:

    Transfinites and infinitesimals are two types of infinite number, which

    characterize degrees of infinity in different fashions (422). Transfinites and

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    17/20

    Collins 17

    infinitesimals are always becoming-others: they are both infinite and not-

    infinite. To a person untrained in mathematics, they can even provide

    sensation, if only the sensation of vertigo.

    The relationship between art and infinity is as unique to art as the

    respective relationships between philosophy and science are to infinity.

    Deleuze and Guattari explain the respective relationships by stating that

    philosophy wants to save the infinite by giving it consistency . . . Science,

    on the other hand, relinquishes the infinite in order to gain reference (197).

    Art, in its turn, wants to create the finite that restores the infinite (ibid).

    Each chaoid acts upon infinity, upon virtuality, upon chaos, to shape

    something orderly. Philosophy clings to the infinite, science creates the

    finite, and art moves through both to create something finite which captures

    an infinity: Even if the material lasts for only a few seconds it will give

    sensation the power to exist and be preserved in itself in the eternity that coexists with this short duration (ibid 166, italics in original). There is a

    degree of infinity inherent in every piece of art, even in a short series of

    musical notes. For the space of the duration of the composed material, the

    sensation extracted from chaos exists infinitely. Creating the infinite within

    the finite is the work of art.

    Creation drawn from the infinity of chaos is what characterizes thought

    across all three planes of philosophy, science, and art. Deleuze and Guattari

    sum the relationship between the three chaoids, saying:

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    18/20

    Collins 18

    The three thoughts intersect and intertwine but without synthesis or

    identification. With its concepts, philosophy brings forth events. Art

    erects monuments with its sensations. Science constructs states of

    affairs with its functions. A rich tissue of correspondences can be

    established between the planes. But the network has its culminating

    points, where sensation itself becomes sensation of concept or

    function, where the concept becomes concept of function or of

    sensation, and where the function becomes function of sensation or

    concept. (198-199)

    The threads which hold the three planes together are the threads of

    mathematics, of mathematics as problematics, as axiomatics, as infinite

    numbers. The suture points where the chaoids intersect one another are the

    points where form, meaning, and sensation come together in the

    mathematical narrative of the mind. Equivalent, but separate, philosophy,science, and art move us though chaos and into ordered, phenomenal,

    reality.

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    19/20

    Collins 19

    Works Cited

    Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. What is Philosophy? . New York: Columbia

    University Press,

    1994. Print.

    Duffy, Simon. The Role of Mathematics in Deleuzes Critical Engagement

    with Hegel.

    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 17.4 (2009): 563-582.

    Print.

    Smith, Daniel W. Mathematics and the Theory of Multiplicities: Badiou and

    Deleuze

    Revisited. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (2003): 411-449.

    Print.

  • 7/30/2019 Equilavent but Separate: The Role of Mathematics in Deleuze and Guattari

    20/20

    Collins 20

    Sorensen, Bent Meier. Immaculate Defecation: Gilles Deleuze and Flix

    Guattari in

    Organization Theory. The Sociological Review 53 (2005): 120-133.

    Print.