german berrios_historia de la neuropsiquiatría (eng)

Upload: chicoparekeyolanda

Post on 07-Apr-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/3/2019 German Berrios_Historia de la neuropsiquiatra (eng)

    1/10

    The concept of neuropsychiatry

    A historical overview

    German E. Berriosa,*, Ivana S. Markovab,1

    aDepartment of Psychiatry, University of Cambridge, Addenbrookes Hospital, Box 189, Hills Road, Cambridge, CB2 2QQ, UKbDepartment of Psychiatry, University of Hull, Coniston House, East Riding Campus, Willerby, HU10 6NS, UK

    Abstract

    The elusive nature of the social practice called neuropsychiatry

    is the most important obstacle for writing its history. At different

    times, and in different countries, the term has been used to name

    different ideological and professional packages. Choosing any of

    these as the prototype would, however, bias and regionalize the

    historical account. One solution is to identify an ideological marker

    or common denominator. To spin its yarn, this paper has chosen the

    foundational claim (putatively common to all practitioners of

    neuropsychiatry) that all mental disorders are disorders of the

    brain. Three among its results are worth noting. One is that the

    meaning and exercise of neuropsychiatry will continue to depend

    on social, economic and political factors; this augurs future

    instability. The second is that each time that the foundational claim

    has been uttered in history it has meant something different.

    Further research is needed to clarify whether this is due to the way

    in which the claim becomes inscribed in different cultural niches;

    what is clear is that by using the foundational claim as a marker it

    is not possible to establish a continuity in the progress of

    neuropsychiatry. The third finding is that users of the foundational

    claim require the use of a concept of matter and in this paper

    plain and baroque types of matter have been identified. To

    explain the origin of mind, those using the plain notion need to

    resort to external ingredients and their narratives incorporate bits of

    the real world. Users of the baroque definition do not need such

    aids. It is not for the historian to judge which of these two

    definitions is more felicitous and more conducive to the moral and

    aesthetic edification of psychiatry and her patients. D 2002

    Elsevier Science Inc. All rights reserved.

    Keywords: Brain; Concepts; History; Ideas; Mind; Neuropsychiatry

    Introduction

    This paper is on the history of the concept of neuro-

    psychiatry. This commission can be discharged only par-

    tially because there is no stable, positive definition of

    neuropsychiatry nor a conceptual core or fulcrum has yet

    been identified that may join up the historical periods duringwhich neuropsychiatry is said to have predominated. Fur-

    thermore, little is known about the epistemic nature and

    value of the foundational claims of neuropsychiatry, e.g., its

    concept of matter and the belief that mental disorders are

    disorders of the brain. Lastly, little research has been done

    on how the economic and social network within which

    neuropsychiatry has established itself contributes to its

    overall success.

    To deal with the above, the following strategy has been

    followed: a working definition of neuropsychiatry is

    offered; a core claim chosen as leitmotif, namely, that

    mental diseases are diseases of the brain; and a classifica-tion of matter (plain and baroque) is proposed. To illustrate

    that absence of conceptual continuity between utterances of

    core claims, writers have been chosen whose work spans a

    period of about 350 years.

    Although tempted, we have resisted rounding up the

    usual suspects. Some like Griesinger, Meynert or Wernicke

    were included because they already live in the pantheon of

    neuropsychiatry; Les Empecheurs de penser en ronde were

    chosen (Jackson, von Monakow) because they were irrev-

    erent and creative and, although paid lip service to, have

    been kept at a safe distance; yet others because their claims

    have been misunderstood (Cabanis, Bayle) or little known

    0022-3999/02/$ see front matterD 2002 Elsevier Science Inc. All rights reserved.

    PII: S 0 0 2 2 - 3 9 9 9 ( 0 2 ) 0 0 4 2 7 - 0

    * Corresponding author. Tel.: +44-1223-336-965; fax: +44-1223-336-

    968.

    E-mail addresses: [email protected] (G.E. Berrios), ismarkova@p-

    sych.hi-net.co.uk (I.S. Markova).1 Also corresponding author. Tel.: + 44-1482-466-960;

    fax: + 44-1482-466-966.

    Journal of Psychosomatic Research 53 (2002) 629638

  • 8/3/2019 German Berrios_Historia de la neuropsiquiatra (eng)

    2/10

    (Hartley, Battie, Georget). In a way, the choice does not

    matter for all are there to illustrate the point that throughout

    the years the foundational claim that mental disorders are

    disorders of the brain has meant different things. Similarly,

    current neuropsychiatry is likewise another reinterpretation

    of the foundational claims whose specific features are

    determined by the new technologies available and thesocioeconomic needs that they are presumed to meet. No

    doubt the future will see many more with their own claims

    to truth and progress.

    Definitions

    Neuropsychiatry has been defined according to assump-

    tions, investigative techniques, type of patient it deals with,

    therapeutic value or combinations thereof.2 However, nei-

    ther cross-culturally nor trans-historically can neuropsychia-

    try

    3

    be considered as a unitary activity: in response to socialand economic need, different types will predominate in

    different contexts.4 All types share the foundational assump-

    tion5 that mental disorders are caused by changes in the

    physical conformation of the brain.6 Although unamenable

    to ascertainment, this noninferential claim generates

    lower-level predictions, empirically testable as cross-sec-

    tional correlations.7 The belief that findings of a positive

    covariance at the lower level legitimate the foundationalist

    claim is unwarranted (see below).

    Psychiatry is a protean discipline8

    and neuropsychiatryone of its incarnations. In contrast to others, however, it has

    persistent exclusivist claims.9 These need accounting as

    does the fact that they have not been subjected to empirical

    ascertainment.10 In view of the above, it is not surprising

    that the history of neuropsychiatry is presented as one of

    darkness to light; although convenient, this received

    view requires revision.

    History of neuropsychiatry as history of what?

    If there is no unitary core to neuropsychiatry, then what isits history the history of?11 Is the history of neuropsychiatry

    more like the history of, say, a real object (horse, orchid,

    chair, Rosetta stone), a purview (aesthetics, ethics), a dis-

    ease (dementia, anxiety disorders); a social practice (priest-

    2 Although the definition of neuropsychiatry is notthe objective of this

    paper, a historian cannot do without one. Definitions such as it is a branch

    of medicine that deals with the relationship between neural processes and

    psychiatric disorders [41] are too general. Combined definitions pose

    even more trouble: a prominent focus of neuropsychiatry is the assessment

    and treatment of patients with psychiatric illnesses or symptoms associated

    with brain lesions or dysfunction . . . Neuropsychiatry also encompasses

    those symptoms that lie in the gray zone between the specialties ofneurology and psychiatry: impairment of attention, alertness, perception,

    memory, language, and intelligence. Fundamental to neuropsychiatry is the

    effort to link psychopathology with measurable brain deficits. Where

    psychiatric symptoms are likely to stem from brain disorders, but where the

    state of technology has not developed sufficiently to establish brain

    syndrome linkages, neuropsychiatry must assume the leadership in

    pursuing such associations. . . .Many human conditions that currently are

    not considered to be in the province of medicine, will, by virtue of

    neuroscience discovery, eventually become regarded as neuropsychiatric

    disorders. This re-conceptualization will be of historic and monumental

    significance to the individuals who suffer from these conditions and to

    society . . . a second reason for revitalizing the neuropsychiatric paradigm is

    to reduce the stigma associated with psychiatric symptoms. . . [42]. This in

    crescendo definition starts by describing what neuropsychiatry does, irrupts

    into the gray zones, and ends up bidding for many human conditions.Then, it introduces a foundational claim (effort to link mental symptoms to

    measurable brain deficits); and the technology alibi (on this historical

    concept see below); lastly, it justifies neuropsychiatry as a stigma reducing

    paradigm. With this definition, the historian finds his/her work cut out!3 There is also an activity called behavioural neurology whose

    concepts and practice seem to overlap with those of neuropsychiatry and

    neuropsychology [43].4 For example, during the 19th century, differences can be found

    between European countries in regards to the meaning and practice of

    neuropsychiatry. These reflect not only international rivalries but also

    internecine disputes about whose consulting rooms these patients

    should patronize.5 A foundationalist claim provides a discipline with its epistemic force

    (i.e., knowledge creating capabilities) but cannot be empirically proven.

    6 Saying that mental disorders have a cause is already biasing the

    explanatory die in one direction. For equally cogent is the claim that people

    do things for reasons. Causes and reasons constitute, in fact, different

    universes of accounting and are governed by different theories and rules. At

    a deeper level, the view that mental disorders are effects can be challenged

    and the alternative proposed that they are waning and waxing processes.

    There is no empirical way to finding out which of these works better.Thus, the view that mental disorders must have a cause, and that that

    cause must lie in the brain, remains an article of faith. Its plausibility is a

    mirage created by the fact that it fits in with current social expectations.7 Correlations express (incompletely) partial covariances. A correlation

    means that some proxy variables (not mind and brain) covary. The

    epistemic value of the claim therefore fully depends on the quality of the

    proxying. It is rather surprising that while the mathematics of correlations

    are acceptably studied, the logic and epistemology of covariation and the

    assessment of proxying have been neglected.8 The definition psychiatry is a branch of medicine that deals with

    mental disorder begs too many questions. At a deeper level, psychiatry

    appears to be just another discipline created by society to perform certain

    anthropological, managerial and policing duties. Under the aegis of

    medicine and science, psychiatry creates representations of man in normality

    and abnormality, and based on these categories, accounts and managerialguidelines. A discipline is a package of ideologies, techniques and social

    practices which fulfils a role in social organization. A representation is an

    image, model, view, concept or other definitional form that helps someone to

    think of something. Because the sensory windows, cognition and language

    are machines to generate public representations of the world, representa-

    tional theory is central to human culture.9 This concerns the claim that all mental disorders are related to

    changes in the brain.10 It is a fascinating aspect of evidence-based medicine that it is not

    very good at applying its own rules to itself, for example, little empirical

    research seems to exist comparing neuropsychiatry with others types of

    psychiatry in terms of overall therapeutic success, etc.11 These types of questions are answered by historiography, which is the

    set of ideological principles, techniques and methods used to write history.

    G.E. Berrios, I.S. Markova / Journal of Psychosomatic Research 53 (2002) 629638630

  • 8/3/2019 German Berrios_Historia de la neuropsiquiatra (eng)

    3/10

    hood, cobblery, medicine, palmistry), an ideology (realism,

    idealism), or a blatant construct (French revolution, guilt,

    prostitution). Some may say that none of the above, for

    neuropsychiatry is a true science. Interestingly enough, this

    view demands only one (and narrow) form of history

    of neuropsychiatry.12

    In this paper, neuropsychiatry is conceived of as theloose activity of researchers who share certain foundational

    claims and enact them in specific research programmes. In

    each historical period, both the foundational claims and the

    apparatus that such groups put in practice will vary accord-

    ing to theoretical context and socioeconomic structure.

    Specifically therefore, this paper will select as its chain of

    being13 the bold belief that mental disorders are all reflec-

    tions of changes in the brain. In turn, this foundational claim

    will allow us to identify neuropsychiatric approaches to

    mental disorder since at least the 17th century.

    The foundational claim

    The claim that the body (brain) houses the human soul

    (or mind),14 and the claim that changes (lesions) in the

    conformation or constitution of the body (brain) cause

    mental disorder, are historically independent and not alto-

    gether clear.15 For example, at the beginning of the 19th

    century, there was a debate as to whether the mind or soul

    was located in the cerebrospinal fluid or the cortex [1].

    Likewise, during the middle of the 19th century, the view

    was still defended (by many) that because the soul (mind)

    was a marker of the divine, it could not become divided or

    diseased. To save the view that mental disorders wererelated to the body, writers resuscitated the proposal that

    organs other than the brain, such as the stomach [2], heart

    [3] or hypochondrium [4], might contribute to the format-

    ting of the mind and its diseases.

    The claim that the body (brain) houses the human soul

    (or mind) is used often by materialist thinkers, i.e., by those

    who believe that at the time the world came into being there

    was only matter [5]. So their problem is to explain where

    mind came from. According to the type of matter (body,

    brain, res extensa, etc.) they prefer, users divide up into two

    groups. Some play with a plain concept of matter (i.e., for

    them matter is a bundle of atoms, fields, strings or whatever,

    but has not got any hidden qualities that can be used to

    explain what issues out of matter-like mind). Others playwith a baroque concept of matter (matter includes dynamic

    qualities of the type that can explain the origin of mind).16

    This is why when it comes to explaining the origin and

    shape of the mind, the plain matter people have to search

    for additional resources in the context in which the opera-

    tion occurs. Baroque matter people, on the other hand,

    have less difficulty in that they can find explanations in their

    own concept of matter.

    17th century

    Willis and Sydenham

    Claims that some forms of mental disorder are related to

    the body can be found in the 17th century literature:

    melancholy is commonly defined, a raving without a fever

    or fury, joynd with fear and sadness; whence it follows to

    be a complicated affect of the brain and of the heart; for, that

    melancholick17 persons rave, it proceeds from the fault of

    the brain,18 and the disorder of the animal spirits residing in

    it; but that they are sadand timorous, this is attributed to the

    passion of the heart. [3].19 Willis (1621 1675) was a

    baroque matter fellow and packed sufficiently into his

    conception of the body (or brain) to explain specific featuresof mind or madness. This was part of his iatro-chemical,

    Paracelsian inheritance [6].

    While Willis happily paired up brain and heart, Syden-

    ham (16241689), who fancied himself as a hater of theory

    and a no-nonsense empiricist [7] chose the blood as his

    12 It is a narrative mainly consisting of tales of discoveries and

    biographies.

    13 Chain of being refers to Arthur Lovejoys (1936) model for thehistory of ideas [44] although his assumption that there are some ideas in

    western culture that keep recurring century after century and that are sub

    specie aeternitatis has been severely contested (on the history of ideas, see:

    Kelley [45]; Bevir [46]).14 The literature on the relationship between the mind and the body is

    large albeit repetitive; work on when and why the brain became the

    representative of the body is less so; indeed, the question of whether the

    abandonment of the stomach and heart as sources of patterned emotions

    resulted from hard empirical research or simply because it became

    obvious has not yet been answered.15 The relationship between these two claims is asymmetrical and

    empirical. Indeed, the claim that brain disease causes mind disease is not

    logically dependent upon the belief that the mind resides in the brain (this

    because the former could be plausibly made without the second being true.).

    16 This view is already present among Greek atomists who claimed that

    atoms could have different shapes and sizes and used these differences

    (in addition to their movement) to account for differences in the visible

    objects [47].

    17 The 17thcentury medical concept of melancholiaincludeddisorderswhich would currently go under names such as schizophrenia [48].

    18 It must not be forgotten that Willis reference to the brain occurs in

    the wake of the Cartesian claim that the pineal gland acted as a bridge

    between thinking substance and extended substance (mind and body).19 This statement can be variously interpreted. For example, Willis

    allusion to the heart can be seen as an early reference to the autonomic

    nervous system. This who said it first approach to history is

    congratulatory but barren and it is from this perspective that Willis has

    been called a neuropsychiatrist [49]. More plausibly, the same statement

    can be seen as a metaphorical redescription (in terms of the new

    explanatory categories of the 17th century) of that obscure phenomenon

    called melancholia. This approach is more promising for at least it

    identifies the historical period when a powerful allegory was introduced

    into the history of psychiatry.

    G.E. Berrios, I.S. Markova / Journal of Psychosomatic Research 53 (2002) 629638 631

  • 8/3/2019 German Berrios_Historia de la neuropsiquiatra (eng)

    4/10

    explanatory medium: this arises from too vivid and exalted

    crasis of the blood. There is also another sort of mania,

    which succeeds long-continued intermittent fevers, and at

    last degenerates into idiocy.20 This comes from weakness

    and vapidity of blood, brought on by over-long fermenta-

    tion [8]. Here we see the blood (as a proxy representation

    of the body) providing Sydenham with the required meta-phorical help (vivid and exalted blood = mania).21 In this

    sense, he is also a baroque matter man.

    These claims about the bodily origin of mental disorder

    sound as hard as any that we may read nowadays. In what

    consists their similarity? There will be little point in saying,

    poor Willis and Sydenham, if only they had had fMRI! If

    our historical point is right, that ideological packages have

    internal coherence and respond to the availabilities and

    needs of the time, then fMRI would have offered Willis

    nothing as his representation of the brain and the mind was

    not coached in visual metaphors. Indeed, his views that

    melancholia and mania were associated with the brain, heartor blood resulted from a narrative about animal spirits and

    the iatro-chemical structure of the body.22

    18th century

    Hartley and Battie

    David Hartleys (17051757) post-Newtonian views of

    matter and his belief in Lockean associationism date him

    neatly as an 18th century thinker [9]. He believed that

    mental disorder was related to distortions in the vibration

    pattern of brain fibres. For example, he explained thedifference between a normal thought and a delusion: thus

    suppose a person, whose nervous system is disordered, to

    turn his thoughts accidentally to some barely possible good

    or evil. If the nervous disorder falls in with this, it increases

    the vibrations belonging to its ideas so much, as to give it a

    reality, a connection with self. For we distinguish the

    recollection and anticipation of things relating to ourselves,

    from those of things relating to other persons, chiefly by the

    difference of strength in the vibrations, and in their coa-

    lescences with each other [10]. Vibrations affecting brain

    fibres (matter) play a central role in Hartleys explanation of

    mental symptoms.23 Vibrations are produced by external

    stimuli (as strings vibrate in response to plucking by a

    finger) and the fibre itself contributes naught to the response

    pattern. This makes Hartley a plain matter fellow.

    William Battie (17031776) rejected the view that the

    brain was a gland, that nerves were hollow and that sensation

    was due to the circulation of a nervous fluid [11]: themedullary substance was solid and sensation occurred as

    the result of pressure on the nerves.24 He, however, also ex-

    plained insanity in terms of vibratory mechanisms: insanity

    was preceded by nervous overexcitation and followed by

    nervous insensitive. Without any externalstimulus, the sub-

    ject may see fire or hear sounds (i.e., have hallucinations

    and refer them to an external cause). This he called original

    madness; on the other hand, an anomalous internal stimulus

    to the nerves could cause similar experiences but in that case

    the subject had consequential madness [12]. Battie followed

    Hartley and also sponsored a plain concept of matter.

    Cabanis

    Towards the end of the 18th century, and based on a

    reconceptualization of matter and mind, Pierre Cabanis

    (17571808)25 proposed a new approach to their relation-

    ship. His was a view born out of a combination of

    associationism, materialism and vitalism. An assiduous

    visitor of Madame Helvetius salon at Auteuil,26 Cabanis

    was influenced by the work of Condillac, Helvetius, La

    Mettrie and dHolbach. In a complex and ambiguous theory,

    which according to vantage point speaks with many voi-

    ces,27 Cabanis went further than any of his predecessors.

    For example, among all the Ideologues,28 he nailed hisflag the highest on the materialistic mast.29

    20 The meaning of the putative clinical association between mania

    and idiocy is very unclear here for the categories themselves were used

    with a sense that we cannot really fathom [50].21 This carry over from Paracelsian times that an excess of some

    substance will lead to an increase in the corresponding behaviour (and vice

    versa) is still present in current psychopharmacological thinking.22 What we do not know is whether in the privacy of their consulting

    rooms Willis and Sydenham used with their patients the same narrative to

    justify their treatments. It is likely that they did, as only a few decades

    earlier, Napier, the great early 19th century physician, had used his own

    brand of descriptive and explanatory narrative to justify his treatments [51].

    23 It was after Newton that the split takes place between those who

    continue talking about animal spirits and others who chose about the new

    concept of vibration [52]. The latter metaphor was clearly more in keeping

    with the spirit of the 18th century and caught on quickly [53].24 This view is also discussed by Hobbes: Every great agitation or

    concussion of the brain (as it happened from a stroke, specially if the stroke

    be upon one eye) whereby the optic nerve suffereth any great violence,

    there appeareth before the eyes a certain light, with light is nothing without

    (from Hobbes, 1651 quoted in Rand, 1912, p. 150 [54]).25 For biographical details, see Cerise [55] and Staum [56]. Cabanis

    was a prototypical Enlightenment thinker: broad, progressist, interested inpolitics, the sciences and the humanities and imbued by the materialistic

    philosophy and vitalism characteristic of his period (on the former, see

    Rosen [57], Picavet [58] and Temkin [59]; on the latter, see Huard [60] and

    Roger [61]).26 After the death of her husband in 1771, Madame Helvetius moved

    her salon to the quiet village of Auteuil where it saw its golden period [62].27 Ferrater Mora [63] once said that Cabanis concept would satisfy the

    most staunch defender of materialism or spiritualism.28 Despectuous name given by Napoleon to a group of thinkers

    (including Cabanis) that opposed his imperialistic politics [64].29 Cabanis will forever be known as the man who said that the brain

    secretes thought as the liver does bile. Chazaud [65] has offered an

    important analysis of the way in which this quotation, taken out of context,

    was used by antimaterialist writers to discredit Cabanis.

    G.E. Berrios, I.S. Markova / Journal of Psychosomatic Research 53 (2002) 629638632

  • 8/3/2019 German Berrios_Historia de la neuropsiquiatra (eng)

    5/10

    However, his view of matter is baroque for as Moravia

    [13] once wrote, it . . .comprises a full array of forces and

    properties from whose physico-chemical combination even

    the most complex living organisms may emerge. From

    the neuropsychiatric viewpoint, Cabanis believed that his

    baroque matter (which included a number of functions and

    vital energy) could give rise fully to a complex mind.However, he also believed that this kind of analysis

    (namely of how matter gives rise to mind) could only be

    carried out against the context of a science of man, a sort

    of philosophical anthropology which not only included

    physiology but also language and hermeneutics. This

    allowed him to develop an integrated definition of body

    which as sources of patterns of sensations included, in

    addition to the brain, the heart, stomach and genitalia.30

    This encyclopaedic approach to the study of man went

    out of fashion during the 19th century and it is no wonder

    that Cabanis ideas were misunderstood and distorted;

    without context, his view of the mind sounds like grossmaterialism [14].

    19th century

    Georget and Bayle

    An example of the new materialism can be found in

    the writings of E. Georget (1795 1828), a disciple of

    Pinel and Esquirol. He escaped the 18th century views of

    the latter by modifying their nosology, emphasising the

    organic aetiology of mental disorder, introducing the tech-nology alibi (that although all mental disorders are

    caused by changes in the brain in some cases we cannot

    yet demonstrate it due to lack of the appropriate tech-

    nology)31 and by adopting Bichats vitalism.32 The latter

    provided Georget with a baroque view of matter.

    Georgets theoretical views seemed at the time to be

    reinforced by the precocious work of his contemporary A.J.

    Bayle (1799 1858), who put forward a unitary view of

    general paralysis (i.e., that dementia and mental disorder are

    both features of the same disease) as opposed to the dualview predominant at the time [15]. Bayles work has been

    considered by some as the first demonstration that mental

    disease is physical disease, and hence, conventional histor-

    ians have treated his report as the beginning of neuro-

    psychiatry [16]. In regard to this, Quetel [17] has made

    the following (correct) comment: General paralysis thus

    defined might have done no more than figure in psychiatry

    nosography (though difficult to situate in the nosography of

    Pinel and Esquirol) had it not fitted in so well with the

    arguments of those who believed that the etiology of mad-

    ness was necessarily organic. . . For the first time, then,

    something had been discovered in the brains of the insane!Moreover, these anatomo-pathological lesions were not only

    to make general paralysis the model of organic mental

    disease, they were also to swing the psychogenetic concep-

    tion of madness.

    Griesinger

    It is to Wilhelm Griesinger (18171868) that the (apo-

    cryphal) quotation has been attributed that all mental dis-

    eases are just diseases of the brain. Griesinger grew up

    during one of the most turbulent periods of German culture

    [1820].33 Materialist biologism, the beginnings of a physi-

    ology specific for living organisms, vitalism and roman-ticism in arts and politics are only some of the ideologies

    that influenced him into being active in student politics and

    30 It would be nonsense to consider this proposal as an anticipation

    of the views expressed by James and Lange (who also differed from

    each other). In Cabanis time, the bodily organs were still allowed to talk

    to the brain about the world. This went beyond the descriptions of the

    natural functions of the organs but included rich complexes of feelingsand cognitions perceived as emanating directly from them. The entrails

    have since been exiled into the silent shadows and can whisper nought,

    not even primary, simple sensations (as they did in Lange and James).

    For Cabanis, bodily organs could still generate complex feeling patterns

    and meanings for the cognitivist view of the brain had not yet been

    developed. The study of these concepts might pay handsome dividends

    to those neuropsychiatrists interested in understanding the generation of

    what is called somatizations, unexplained medical symptoms, etc. etc.

    For the issue of whether the body below the neck contributes to the

    cognitive organization of the mind remains wide open. This question is

    central to the Continental work on coenesthesia. Lukewarm efforts to

    deal with this issue can be found in Anglo-Saxon theories on the

    relationship between hypochondria and heightened awareness of bodily

    sensations [66,67].

    31 Used by Kraepelin, and still quoted nowadays, the technology alibi

    is not a scientific hypothesis but the tail end of a foundationalist syllogism:

    the mind is represented in the brain! the mind is tantamount to a set of

    behaviours!hence, all behaviours are represented in the brain! abnormal

    behaviours are still behaviours!hence, all abnormal behaviours have

    brain representation! the fact that no representation can be found must

    therefore be due to faulty techniques. It goes without saying that if some

    representation was eventually found, it would be wrong (by the fallacy of

    affirmation of the consequent) to suggest that it confers any truth on theearlier propositions of the syllogism.

    32 Vitalism is a doctrine according to which the origin and phenomena

    of life results from a principle which is different from the physical and

    chemical ones that sustain matter in general. Bichat reacted against

    metaphysical vitalism, i.e., the idea that the vital principle was part of

    nature; for Bichat, such a principle can only be understood if it is

    incorporated into each tissue as sensitivity and contractibility [6870].33 Griesinger was a physician [71] (the concept of psychiatrist did not

    exist at the time) with interests as wide as mental disorder and public health

    in Egypt (for a considerable period of time he worked in Cairo) (on his

    work on infections diseases, see Lasegue [72]). His contribution is limited

    to a textbook [73], a few papers and the foundation of a wonderful Journal,

    the Archiv fur Psychiatrie und Nervenkrankheiten. He was also interested in

    the institutional and therapeutic aspects of asylum care.

    G.E. Berrios, I.S. Markova / Journal of Psychosomatic Research 53 (2002) 629638 633

  • 8/3/2019 German Berrios_Historia de la neuropsiquiatra (eng)

    6/10

    changed his mind about the foundations of medicine.34 The

    Textbook of Mental Pathology and Therapeutics is an

    important book, not so much because of its clinical con-

    tentGriesinger was 28 when he published it and had little

    psychiatric experience so he borrowed most of his cases

    from French and German sourcesbut because of its

    philosophical maturity and imaginative proposals, such asthe view that mental disorders were constituted by ele-

    mentary units of analysis, which provided the conceptual

    basis for the development of descriptive psychopathology.35

    Put back into its context, and corrected by what the

    words involved meant in the 1840s, the claim that all

    mental disorders are disorders of the brain becomes a

    complex one. Griesinger reacted badly against gross Ger-

    man materialism [21] and was keen on the new physiology

    of Wunderlich, Roser and Muller. His concept of lesion,

    therefore, was not anatomical but physiological. It is in this

    new (and ambiguous) space of the new physiology [22] that

    Griesinger decided to locate mental disorders. No wonderthat his decision has been open to varied interpretations; for

    example, his (related) view that many psychological events

    occur in nonconscious spaces has led some to consider

    Griesinger as a pioneer of psychodynamic psychiatry [23].

    Griesingers neuropsychiatric concepts, particularly that

    of his new physiological space, cannot be translated into

    21st century categories without distortion. Although they

    were still organic or biological in nature, mental events

    occurring in this new space did not necessarily leave foot-

    prints for the neuropathologist to see [24]. Thus, the concept

    of anatomical lesion is replaced by that of physiological

    lesion, a fascinating and transitional concept, that towards

    the end of the century, ineluctably led to that of psycho-logical lesion. In this new realm, mental disorders, although

    happening in the brain, do not necessarily have representa-

    tion. After learning this, neuropsychiatrists interested in the

    brain region where god or morality might reside may no

    longer want to worship at Griesinges altar. Griesinger seems

    to have been also a crypto-dualist in that he was not interested

    in extracting mind out of matter; as such his views by-pass the

    neat distinction between plain and baroque matter.

    Meynert

    Influenced by Darwinian evolution and by the new physiology, Meynert (1833 1892) sought to correlate

    development and function and form. Meynerts views on

    the nature of mental disease have given rise to controversy.

    Associationism, localizationism, top-to-bottom inhibition,

    regional cerebrovascular variations and neuronal nutritional

    status were the five pillars upon which he based his

    speculations on the nature and localization of mental illness

    [25]. He based his speculative view of the ego as an inner

    representation on Herbarts associationism; localizationism

    led him to consider projection and association fibres as a

    communication network by means of which inhibition of

    subcortical functions and cross-boundary lateral talk

    could take place, respectively. Putative changes in cerebralblood supply helped Meynert to explain physiological states

    (e.g., sleep), symptoms (e.g., obsessions and hallucinations)

    and diseases (e.g., mania, melancholia). Nutritional changes

    at the cellular level, resulting from haemodynamic changes

    or from congenital defect, were considered as the ultimate

    causal mechanism.

    The contribution of Meynert to the aetiology of mental

    illness is not easy to assess and opinions among historians

    have been divided. As opposed to his solid neurohistolog-

    ical work, with few exceptions, his clinical writings (e.g.,

    the concept of Amentia) [26,27] have not withstood the

    test of time. He has been portrayed as a brain mythologizerbut this accusation neglects the heuristic role that metaphor

    plays in science and the fact that he had a romantic, poetic

    approach to the language of neuroanatomy, and this often

    spilt over into his neuropsychiatry. The first volume of his

    Psychiatrie [25] is just a textbook of neuroanatomy with

    in passim references to psychological concepts like ego or

    memory and how these issue out of brain [28]. He also

    believed that brain activity depended upon brain nutrition

    and the latter was controlled by vasomotor activity from

    which follows that circulatory disturbance can lead to

    mental disorder.36 Meynert believed that matter (the cortex)

    started as a tabula rasa and, in this sense, he can be

    considered as a sponsor of the plain matter view [25].Why Meynert never published the second (clinical) volume

    of his book remains unclear but it is likely that he did not

    have the patience to fit the cases he had collected into the

    narrow schema delineated in the first volume.

    Wernicke

    A disciple of Meynert, Karl Wernicke (18481905), is

    considered as one of the most important psychiatrists of the

    late 19th century [29]. His range and depth of thought were

    such that, had he not died young, psychiatry might now live

    in a Wernickian world, i.e., his views on classification, thegeneration of mental symptoms and the relationship between

    brain and behaviour would have superseded Kraepelins.

    From the perspective of neuropsychiatry, the three most

    important contributions of Wernicke are: (1) a model to

    encompass all brain-related diseases (whether so-called

    psychiatric or neurological); (2) the development of a

    35 On the relevance of Griesinger for the development of descriptive

    psychopathology, see Berrios [50]; on the ideological background of

    Griesingers textbook, see Arens [75].

    36 This latter speculation has been seized upon by historians as

    foreshadowing the debate between cortical and subcortical dementia [76];

    one could easily add to that that the same speculation is also redolent of the

    way in which much of current neuroimaging work is conceptualized.

    34 On the connection of his neuropsychiatric views with social and

    dynamic psychiatry, see Dietze and Voegele [23] and Schrenk [74].

    G.E. Berrios, I.S. Markova / Journal of Psychosomatic Research 53 (2002) 629638634

  • 8/3/2019 German Berrios_Historia de la neuropsiquiatra (eng)

    7/10

    pathophysiological modelto mediate between the brain and

    behavioura model which had until then been absent from

    psychiatry (including from Kraepelins work) [30]; and (3)

    the introduction of the first neuropsychological approach

    to mental symptoms [31].

    Central to Wernickes model was the idea that the brain

    of man was endowed with a system of projection and(transcortical) association fibres, and that the latter was the

    organ of consciousness and of the highest intellectual

    functions [31]. Lesions of the projection fibres gave rise

    to focalized pathology and neurological disease; pathology

    of the association system generated mental illness. In this

    sense, Wernickes organ of association is redolent of the

    concept of neural network and, in current jargon, he was

    more of a connectionist [32] than a conventional local-

    izationist. Although well hidden from view, Wernicke seems

    to have entertained a view of matter richer than Meynerts.

    By his time, however, the old concept of baroque matter (as

    a matter that contained hidden qualities and mechanismswhich could explain how matter and mental disorders

    emerged) had gone together with vitalism (at least in the

    area of neurobiology) [33]. Hence, it is not possible to

    classify his views according to our types.

    Les Empecheurs de penser en ronde

    It is an interesting question why Jackson, von Monakow,

    Goldstein and Guiraud, have not had more impact on neuro-

    psychiatry. It remains a challenge to find out why their

    innovative ideas are paid lip service but never allowed to

    fertilize neuropsychiatry. There is only space here to touch

    upon the former two. They have been chosen for differentreasons: Jackson because he has had more impact on

    Continental (Janet, Ribot, Freud, Goldstein, Piaget, Guiraud,

    Ey) than Anglo-Saxon psychiatry or psychology [34]; and

    von Monakow because his extraordinarily interesting views

    about longitudinal localization of mental symptoms, etc., are

    little known in the Anglo-Saxon world [35].

    In general, the history of medicine (and psychiatry) tends

    to be the history of the victors. The victors do not need to

    have truth or reason on their side but just find themselves in

    the adequate social conjuncture. In each historical period,

    there are also losers and by symmetry they do not need to be

    wrong or without reason. The historian of ideas is thereforeas interested in the losers as in the victors, for the ideas of

    the former are often imaginative, coherent and irreverent

    and hence threatening to the social order. In this sense, the

    writers included in this section were all losers.

    Jackson

    J.H. Jackson (18341911)37 spent most of his clinical

    life giving opinions on the nature of mental disorder. In

    1894, he published The Factors of Insanities (FI), a paper

    of relevance to neuropsychiatry [34]. There is little written

    on Jacksons contribution to psychiatry [36]; and on his lack

    of impact on British psychiatry.38

    Jackson had a hierarchical model of the nervous system

    with the upper layers inhibiting the bottom ones. Evolution

    pushed function from less to more complexity but lessstability; dissolution39 was a force that pushed in the oppos-

    ite direction.40 Jackson proposes that insanity41 originates

    from the action of four factors.42 Factor 1 concerns the

    depth of dissolution. Factor 2 concerns the the person

    who has undergone dissolution.43 Factor 3 relates to the

    rate of dissolution, i.e., how slow or fast the removal of

    control was. Factor 4 is also about personal variables and

    provides lists of putative elements and themes around which

    positive mental symptoms may concrescence. Together with

    Factor 2, Factor 4 feeds meaning into Jacksons model.44 The

    Factor of Insanities is about the way in which the four

    factors interact to give rise to two classes of symptoms(positive and negative) [37]. The model is unable to generate

    37 On Jackson, see Critchley and Critchley [38] and Lopez Pinero [77].

    38 The issue of why Jacksons thinking has had so little influence on

    British, and later, Anglo-Saxon psychiatry (as compared with Neurology),

    is interesting [78]. Some years ago, the symptoms of schizophrenia were

    classified into positive and negative but neither the terminology nor the

    underlying model were in fact Jacksonian but Reynoldian [37]. Because of

    this error, it was predicted that the positive/negative nomenclature will

    disappear [79].39 On the concepts of evolution and dissolution in Jackson, see

    Smith [80,81].40 Jacksons conceptual model was not meant to be mapped onto the

    real CNS and he said so. However, efforts have been made to findanalogical links [82,83].

    41 Insanity according to Jackson is a generic term tantamount to any

    departure from mentation and hence refers both to ordinary physiological

    states (e.g., sleep), chronic brain diseases and temporary toxic states. He

    seems to have advocated a continuity (rather than a categorical) view of

    mental disease, which in practice stretches from physiological states to all

    gradations of insanity. In this regard, he introduces the concept of mental

    diplopia by which he meant clashing definitions of the same behaviour

    such as using insanity for proper madness and for a mild degree of

    drunkenness. Jackson wondered why postepileptic coma (which he calls

    acute temporary dementia and has a strong negative element) is not

    considered as an insanity by alienists while postepileptic mania is!

    Jacksons concept of insanity or dissolution is only meaningful when

    compared against a standard, and he seems to use the state of the same

    person before the disease.42 Jackson mentioned but declined to develop his views on a fifth

    factor. This concerned the possibility that dissolution might affect regions

    or localities of the highest cerebral centres.43 20 years earlier, Jackson (1874) describes Factor 2 as the kind of

    brain in which reduction occurs [84]. This rephrasing may reflect maturity

    of thinking and a mellowing in attitudes towards the mentally ill. Jackson

    lists two aspects of being a person that influence the shape of the ensuing

    insanity (variables pertaining to the individual and genetics) but does not

    provide an account nor tells whether the variability is quantitative or

    qualitative. Personal factors, according to him, show best in states of minor

    dissolution. Features pertaining to the person include age, intelligence,

    education; and genetic factors concerned not on the inheritance of specific

    mental disorders but of a tendency to give out to dissolution.44 For an analysis of this paper, see Berrios [85].

    G.E. Berrios, I.S. Markova / Journal of Psychosomatic Research 53 (2002) 629638 635

  • 8/3/2019 German Berrios_Historia de la neuropsiquiatra (eng)

    8/10

    predictions on specific symptoms (such as hallucinations,

    delusions, imperative ideas, depressions, retardation, etc.).

    His views on mind, matter, their relationship and the

    foundational claim are difficult to map in a coherent way.

    He was so much of a dualist that he borrowed Cliffords

    concept of concomitance45 to explain how mind and

    matter might interact.46

    In this sense, Jackson escapes theplainbaroque matter dichotomy used in this paper as this

    applies to materialist thinkers.

    Jacksons stance vis-a-vis the foundationalist claim is

    equally unclear. It is true that he believed that all insanities

    were related to the brain, but his concept of insanity is so

    utterly different from what was going on in his time and

    indeed nowadays, that it is difficult to link the two. For him,

    insanity was: (1) on a continuum with other states such as

    drunkenness or dreaming (hence, he called them states of

    temporal insanity); and (2) only its negative symptoms

    actually reflected pathology (i.e., lesions or dissolution of

    the higher, human, inhibiting layers of the brain); positivesymptoms were the expression of evolution, of normal

    activity produced by the release of normal tissue.

    When put together, his views do not tally well. Given his

    strong dualism, one would have thought that his concept of

    mind was sufficiently autonomous and ontologically inde-

    pendent to contain even its own diseases. Although not a

    religious man [38], it is likely that, at some level, Jackson

    still harboured the (19th century) belief that the mind (or

    soul) was an indivisible and intangible principle inhabiting

    the (indivisible) temple of the cortex, and as such it was

    beyond the reach of disease.

    von Monakow

    Constantin von Monakow (18531930) authored three

    books, founded three journals, became a mentor to major

    international figures [39] and together with R. Mourgue, a

    French psychiatrist and historian of science, wrote one of

    the most important (and neglected) 20th century books on

    neuropsychiatry. von Monakow and Mourgue (1928) started

    by proposing the notion of Horme, i.e., the tendency of all

    living beings to develop all their genetic potential [39]. In

    each individual, the Horme is governed by Syneidesis, i.e.,

    by a principle that regulates and balances all instincts in the

    interest of the given individual. These principles govern both function and structure, and hence, Monakow and

    Mourgue develop a neuropsychiatric model of the type that

    Guiraud [40] called dynamo-morphological.

    Based on the assumption that neuropsychiatry is a sub-

    field of biology, the authors imported into neuropsychiatry

    the notion of chronogenetic localization. This concept

    required that the variable time be built as a parameter into

    all neuropsychiatric phenomena. Functions (e.g., move-

    ment) are processes, which like music, unfold in time and

    according to a specific kinetic melody. Hence, it would bea mistake to attempt to localize processes (i.e., brain

    functions) in terms of specific brain sites (i.e., space alone).

    Since most mental symptoms are considered as resulting

    from disordered brain function, it follows that it would be

    equally erroneous to try to localize symptoms to specific

    brain addresses. Influenced by Jackson, von Monakow and

    Mourgue believed that chronogenetic localization was a late

    acquisition in evolutionary time, and hence, regarded it as a

    complex but unstable mechanism.

    One of the implications of the concept of chronogenetic

    localization is that both cross-sectional studies and tra-

    ditionallongitudinal studies (as collections of cross-sectionalsnapshots) are inadequate for the capture of neuropsychiatric

    symptoms. The latter, von Monakow and Mourgue insisted,

    have to be observed as they unfold in time according to their

    own kinetic melody; for example, a hallucination is fully

    understood only when an entire token or hallucinatory

    episode, which may last minutes or hours, has been studied.

    In addition to its conventional cross-sectional features,

    such an episode includes real longitudinal information, such

    as modulations in intensity, changes in imagery and accom-

    panying emotions, which can only make sense when inte-

    grated along a time dimension. From an aetiological

    viewpoint, knowledge of these longitudinal variables may

    in fact provide more information on the brain localization ofthe symptom than traditional static snapshots.

    Conclusions

    Neuropsychiatry can be defined as a package of ideo-

    logies and social practices loosely woven around the foun-

    dational claim that mental disorders are disorders of the

    brain. In some psychiatric constituencies, such as the Anglo-

    Saxon one, neuropsychiatry has become the predominant

    incarnation of psychiatry. This predominance is due to its

    ability to embrace the images of man, society and tech-nology demanded by the postmodernist world. One of those

    images concerns the claim that mental disorders are related

    to the brain, and part of its history has been studied in this

    paper. One finding has been that although during the last

    300 years the claim has been regularly uttered, on each

    occasion, it has meant something else. The second finding is

    that those who have uttered it can be divided into those who

    used a plain or baroque concept of matter; this distinction

    breaks down after the division of the 19th century when

    vitalism and other qualitative forms of animating matter

    disappear from neurobiology. To explain the development

    and complexities of the mind, sponsors of the plain view of

    45 On Clifford (1845 1879), see Berrios [86].46 Jackson (1932) wrote: The doctrine I hold is: first that states of

    consciousness (or, synonymously, states of mind) are utterly different from

    nervous states; secondly, that the two things occur togetherthat for every

    mental state there is a correlative nervous state; third, that, although the two

    things occur in parallelism, there is no interference of one with the other.

    This may be called the doctrine of Concomitance [87].

    G.E. Berrios, I.S. Markova / Journal of Psychosomatic Research 53 (2002) 629638636

  • 8/3/2019 German Berrios_Historia de la neuropsiquiatra (eng)

    9/10

    matter need to resort to external resources; sponsors of the

    baroque view of matter do not.

    The history of neuropsychiatry is yet to be written.

    Regional studies need to be undertaken of other components

    of the neuropsychiatric package such as its performance as

    social practice, its rhetoric, its relationship to science,

    neurobiology, technology and big industry (psychopharma-cology, medical insurance, neuroimaging, genetics). These

    regional histories will then have to be brought together in

    order to understand the success of the set of activities that go

    under the generic name of neuropsychiatry. Anything less

    cannot work.

    Acknowledgments

    To the memory of Professor Roy Porter, great historian of

    medicine and psychiatry, recently deceased.

    References

    [1] Hagner M. The soul and the brain between anatomy and Naturphilo-

    sophie in the early nineteenth century. Med Hist 1992;36:133.

    [2] Broussais FJU. De lIrritation et de la Folie. Paris: Delaunay, 1828.

    [3] Willis T. The London practice of physick. London: Thomas Bas-

    set, 1685.

    [4] Whytt R. The works of Robert Whytt. Edinburgh: T. Becket, 1768.

    [5] Lange FA. The history of materialism. London: Routledge & Kegan

    Paul, 1957.

    [6] Hughes JT. Thomas Willis 1621 1675. His life and work. London:

    Royal Society of Medicine, 1991.

    [7] Dewhurst K. Dr. Thomas Sydenham (1624 1689). Berkeley: Univer-sity of California Press, 1966.

    [8] Sydenham T. The works of Thomas M.D. Sydenham (Translated by

    R.G. Latham). London: Sydenham Society, 1850.

    [9] Allen RC. David Hartley on human nature. New York: State Univer-

    sity of New York Press, 1999.

    [10] Hartley D. Observations on man, his frame, his duty and his expect-

    ations. 6th ed. London: Thomas Tegg and Son, 1834.

    [11] Leigh D. 18th and 19th centuries. The historical development of psy-

    chiatry, vol. 1. Oxford: Pergamon, 1961. pp. 51 6.

    [12] Battie W. A treatise on madness. London: J. Whiston and B.

    White, 1758.

    [13] Moravia S. Cabanis and his contemporaries. In: Cabanis P-J-G, editor.

    On the relationship between the physical and moral aspects of man,

    vol. 1. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1981. pp. vii xliv.

    [14] Besancon S. La philosophie de Cabanis. Paris: Les Empecheurs depenser en rond, 1997.

    [15] Bayle ALJ. Traite des Maladies du cerveau et de ses membranes.

    Paris: Gabon, 1826.

    [16] Berrios GE. Depressive pseudodementia or melancholic dementia:

    a 19th century view. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry 1985;48:393 400.

    [17] Quetel C. History of syphilis. Cambridge: Cambridge University

    Press, 1990.

    [18] Westphal C. Nekrolog fur Griesinger. Arch Psychiatr Nervenkr

    1868;1:76074.

    [19] Marx O. Wilhelm Griesinger and the history of psychiatry: a reassess-

    ment. Bull Hist Med 1972;46:51944.

    [20] Wahrig-Schmidt B. Der junge Wilhelm Griesinger in Spannungs-

    feld zwischen Philosophie und Physiologie. Tu bingen: Gunter Narr,

    1985.

    [21] Gregory F. Scientific materialism in nineteenth century Germany.

    Dordrecht: Reidel, 1977.

    [22] Schiller J. Physiology struggle for independence in the first half of the

    nineteenth century. Hist Sci 1968;7:6489.

    [23] Dietze HJ, Voegele GE. Wilhelm Griesingers contribution to dynamic

    psychiatry. Dis Nerv Syst 1965;26:582779.

    [24] Berrios GE. Griesinger. In: Porter R, editor. Dizionario Biografico

    della Storia della Medicina delle Scienze Naturali (Liber Amicorum),vol. 2. Florence: Franco Maria Ricci, 1987. pp. 12930.

    [25] Meynert T. Psychiatry. A clinical treatise on diseases of the fore-brain.

    New York: G.P. Putnam, 1885.

    [26] Pappenheim E. On Meynerts amentia. Int J Neurol 1975;9:311 26.

    [27] Levy-Friesacher CH. Meynert Freud Amentia. Paris: Presses Uni-

    versitaires de France, 1983.

    [28] Marx O. Nineteenth century medical psychology: theoretical prob-

    lems in the work of Griesinger, Meynert, and Wernicke. Isis 1970;

    61:35570.

    [29] Lanczik M. Der Breslauer Psychiater Carl Wernicke. Sigmaringen:

    Jan Thorbecke, 1988.

    [30] Kraepelin E. Der psychologische Versuch in der Psychiatrie. Psychol

    Arb 1896;1:191.

    [31] Wernicke C. Grundrider sychiatrie in klinischen Vorlesungen. Leip-

    zig: Thieme, 1906.[32] Stein DJ, Ludik J, editors. Neural networks and psychopathology.

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

    [33] Wheeler LR. Vitalism: its history and validity. London: Whitherby,

    1939.

    [34] Jackson JH.The factors of insanities. MedPress Circ 1894;108:615 9.

    [35] Monakow von C, Mourgue R. Introduction Biologique a LEtude de la

    Neurologie et de la Psychopathologie. Paris: Alcan, 1928.

    [36] Dewhurst K. Hughlings Jackson on psychiatry. Oxford: Sandford

    Publications, 1982.

    [37] Berrios GE. Positive and negative symptoms and Jackson: a concep-

    tual history. Arch Gen Psychiatry 1985;42:957.

    [38] Critchley M, Critchley EA. John Hughlings Jackson. Father of Eng-

    lish neurology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.

    [39] Mourgue R. Lvre et la personnalite du Professeur Constantin von

    Monakow (1853 1930). LEncephale 1931;26:417 28.[40] Guiraud P. Psychiatrie Generale. Paris: Le Francois, 1950.

    [41] Reber AS. The Penguin dictionary of psychology. London: Penguin

    Books, 1995.

    [42] Yudofsky SC, Hales RE. Introduction. In: Yudofsky SC, Hales RE,

    editors. Textbook of neuropsychiatry. 3rd ed. Washington: American

    Psychiatric Press, 1997. pp. xxii xxiii.

    [43] Benson DF. The history of behavioural neurology. Neurol Clin 1993;

    11:17.

    [44] Lovejoy AO. The great chain of being. Cambridge: Harvard Univer-

    sity Press, 1936.

    [45] Kelley DR, editor. The history of ideas. Canon and variations. Ro-

    chester: Rochester University Press, 1990.

    [46] Bevir M. The logic of the history of ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press, 1999.

    [47] Cappelletti AJ. Ensayos sobre los atomistas griegos. Caracas: Socie-dad Venezolana de Ciencias Humanas, 1979.

    [48] Berrios GE. Melancholia and depression during the 19th century. A

    conceptual History. Br J Psychiatry 1988;153:298 304.

    [49] Vinchon J, Vie J. Un maitre de la neuropsychiatrie au XVIIe siecle;

    ThomasWillis (1662 1675)(sic). AnnMed Psychol 1928;86:109 44.

    [50] Berrios GE. The history of mental symptoms. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press, 1996.

    [51] McDonald M. Mystical bedlam. Cambridge: Cambridge University

    Press, 1981.

    [52] Yolton JW. Thinking matter. Materialism in eighteenth-century Brit-

    ain. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983.

    [53] Jackson SW. Force and kindred notions in eighteenth century neuro-

    physiological and medical psychology. Bull Hist Med 1970;44:397

    410, 539554.

    G.E. Berrios, I.S. Markova / Journal of Psychosomatic Research 53 (2002) 629638 637

  • 8/3/2019 German Berrios_Historia de la neuropsiquiatra (eng)

    10/10

    [54] Rand B. The classical psychologists. London: Constable, 1912.

    [55] Cerise. Notice. Rapports au Physique et du Moral de lhomme par P-J-

    G Cabanis. Paris: Fortin and Masson, 1843. pp. iix.

    [56] Staum MS. Cabanis. Enlightenment and medical philosophy in the

    French Revolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980.

    [57] Rosen G. The philosophy of ideology and the emergence of modern

    medicine in France. Bull Hist Med 1946;20:328 39.

    [58] Picavet F. Les Ideologues. Paris: Alcan, 1891.[59] Temkin O. Materialism in French and German Physiology of the early

    nineteenth century. Bull Hist Med 1946;20:3227.

    [60] Huard P. Quelques Idees sur la structure de la matiere vivante au

    XIXeme siecle; leur incidence sur la pratique medicale. Clio Med

    1974;9:5764.

    [61] Roger J. Les sciences de la vie dans la pensee Francaise du XVIIIe

    siecle. France: Albin Michel, 1993.

    [62] Guillois A. Le salon de Madame Helvetius, Cabanis et les ideologues.

    Paris: Calmann Levy, 1894.

    [63] Ferrater Mora J. Diccionario de Filosofia. Buenos Aires: Editorial

    Sudamericana, 1958.

    [64] Barth H. Wahrheit und Ideologie. Zurich: Manesse, 1945.

    [65] Chazaud J. Cabanis et la production de la pensee. Inf Psychiatr

    1993;69:53944.

    [66] Barsky AJ. Patients who amplify bodily symptoms. Ann Intern Med1979;91:6370.

    [67] Berrios GE. Hypochondriasis: history of a concept. In: Starcevic

    DR, Lipsitt DR, editors. Hypochondriasis: modern perspectives

    on an ancient malady. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001.

    pp. 3 20.

    [68] Haigh E. Xavier Bichat and the medical theory of the eighteenth

    century. London: Wellcome Institute for the History of Medicine,

    1984 (Suppl 4).

    [69] Pickstone JV. Vital actions and organic physics: Henry Dutrochet

    and French physiology during the 1820s. Bull Hist Med 1976;

    50:191212.

    [70] Lain-Entralgo P. Sensualism and vitalism in Bichats Anatomie Gen-

    erale. J Hist Med Allied Sci 1948;3:4764.

    [71] Walser HH. Wilhelm Griesinger-von der Inneren Medizin zur Psychia-

    trie. Gesnerus 1986;43:197204.

    [72] Lasegue. Etudes psychologiques sur les hommes celebres; Guillaume

    Griesinger. Ann Med Psychol 1872;30:15 23.

    [73] Griesinger W. Die Pathologie und Therapie der psychischen Krank-

    heiten. 2nd ed. Stuttgart: Krabbe, 1861.

    [74] Schrenck M. Griesingers neuropsychiatrischen Thesen und ihre so-

    zialpsychiatrischen Konsequenzen. Nervenarzt 1968;39:441 50.

    [75] Arens K. Wilhelm Griesinger: psychiatry between philosophy and

    praxis. Philos Psychiatr Psychol 1996;3:14763.[76] Whitehouse PJ. Theodor Meynert: foreshadowing modern concepts of

    neuropsychiatric pathophysiology. Neurology 1985;35:38991.

    [77] Lopez Pinero JM. John Hughlings Jackson (1835 1911). Evolution-

    ism and neurology. Madrid: Editorial Moneda, 1973.

    [78] Berrios GE. Henri Ey, Jackson et les idees obsedantes. Evol Psychiatr

    1977;42:68599.

    [79] Berrios GE. Positive and negative signals. A conceptual history. In:

    Marneros A, Andreasen NC, Tsuang NT, editors. Negative versus

    positive schizophrenia. Heidelberg: Springer, 1992. pp. 827.

    [80] Smith CUM. Evolution and the problem of mind: Part I. Herbert

    Spencer. J Hist Biol 1982;15:55 88.

    [81] Smith CUM. Evolution and the problem of mind: Part II. John Hugh-

    lings Jackson. J Hist Biol 1982;15:24162.

    [82] Kennard C, Swash M. Hierarchies in neurology. A reappraisal of a

    Jacksonian concept. London: Springer, 1989.[83] Dubrovsky B. Evolution of nervous system and psychiatry. Conse-

    quences of the vertical and horizontal duality of the evolutionary

    process. J Psychiatry Neurosci 1993;18:24559.

    [84] Jackson JH. On the scientific and empirical investigation of epilepsies.

    Med Press Circ 1874-1876 (reprinted in Taylor J. Selected Writings

    of John Hughlings Jackson, vol. 2. London: Hodder and Stoughton.

    1932, pp. 162273).

    [85] Berrios GE. Introduction to the factors of insanities. Hist Psychiatry

    2001;12:35373.

    [86] Berrios GE. Introduction to body and mind by C.K. Clifford. Hist

    Psychiatry 2000;11:311 7.

    [87] Jackson JH. Evolution and dissolution of the nervous system. Croon-

    ian lectures delivered at the Royal College of Physicians. In: Taylor J,

    editor. Selected writings of John Hughlings Jackson, vol. 1. London:

    Hodder and Stoughton, 1932. pp. 4575.

    G.E. Berrios, I.S. Markova / Journal of Psychosomatic Research 53 (2002) 629638638