gttj.files. web viewanother word should be said about the role of human nature to what i called...

22
How relevant is Human Nature to descriptive legal theory? Lucas Miotto – [email protected] Abstract: In this paper I claim that using human nature as a reason to abandon traditional legal theory and move to a more empirically-bound legal theory is mistaken. My argument is that a legal theory which purports to give a descriptive account of law needs not to constrain itself to the most salient psychological and biological properties human beings possess known through empirical analysis, as that would considerably, and without proper reasons, diminish legal theories´ range. One of the main examples within legal philosophy, to which I use to illustrate this point, is the Hartian defense of the possibility of a non-coercive legal system through the introduction of puzzled men: citizens disposed to follow the law regardless of being motivated by coercion. This example help us to show that the project of making a more general and detached descriptive legal theory is valuable and yields knowledge that cannot be obtained by descriptive theories of law that rely solely on empirical analysis and, thus, claim to depend heavily on human nature. Keywords: Legal Theory, Conceptual Analysis, Human Nature, Coercion.

Upload: trinhkhue

Post on 01-Feb-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

How relevant is Human Nature to descriptive legal theory?

Lucas Miotto – [email protected]

Abstract:

In this paper I claim that using human nature as a reason to abandon traditional legal theory

and move to a more empirically-bound legal theory is mistaken. My argument is that a legal

theory which purports to give a descriptive account of law needs not to constrain itself to the

most salient psychological and biological properties human beings possess known through

empirical analysis, as that would considerably, and without proper reasons, diminish legal

theories´ range. One of the main examples within legal philosophy, to which I use to illustrate

this point, is the Hartian defense of the possibility of a non-coercive legal system through the

introduction of puzzled men: citizens disposed to follow the law regardless of being

motivated by coercion. This example help us to show that the project of making a more

general and detached descriptive legal theory is valuable and yields knowledge that cannot be

obtained by descriptive theories of law that rely solely on empirical analysis and, thus, claim

to depend heavily on human nature.

Keywords: Legal Theory, Conceptual Analysis, Human Nature, Coercion.

Page 2: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

How relevant is Human Nature to descriptive legal theory?1

Lucas Miotto2

Introduction

It is common using human nature constraints in both political and ethical theories in order to

restrict what these theories can require from subjects. A famous objection to utilitarianism, for

instance, is that it is too demanding, for it turns into a moral obligation acts that humans,

given their nature, are not able to do. Another example is Rawls´ claim that there are some

factors associated with human beings that determine the choices available in the original

position, such as “limited altruism”, and “vulnerability to attack”. These factors – to which he

called “circumstances of justice” – are “conditions under which human cooperation is both

possible and necessary”3.

The rationale for using human nature as a constraint to these theories is that they are

normative theories that purport to tell us what we ought to do. If it is the case that we cannot

do – meaning that we are not able – what a theory requires, then that seems to be a strong

reason to abandon the theory because it does not fit the facts to which it should apply to.

But things go different in legal philosophy. Some legal philosophers – especially legal

positivists – tend to consider their theories both descriptive and general, and, therefore, not

only do not constrain their theories with human nature requirements but go even further

imagining scenarios without any human beings at all, such as a community of angels4. This is

not surprising, given that their purpose in elaborating a descriptive and general theory of law

is to provide an explanation of law and its properties in all circumstances it might exist.

Still, with the rising wave of naturalism and experimental philosophy, some legal

philosophers unsatisfied with the unrealistic and abstract tone of traditional legal theories are

starting to use empirical studies imported from neuroscience and cognitive psychology in

order to embody their philosophical descriptive theories of law. They are preoccupied in

elaborating a descriptive theory of actual law that focuses on its salient properties which,

arguably, are influenced by human biology and psychology and therefore are “real world” 1 This is a work in progress. Please do no quote without the author´s authorization.2 Masters candidate at PUC-Rio. Contact: lucasmiottol<at>gmail<dot>com3 Rawls, 1999, p. 109.4 Raz, Joseph, 1990, pp. 155-62.

Page 3: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

theories of law and not descriptions of angelic legal systems. Some go even further arguing

that the project of elaborating descriptive and general theories of law is deeply flawed and

cannot be plausibly pursued5.

I argue that these theorists go in the wrong direction and that the use of human nature

constraints offers any help if their project is still understood as philosophical and descriptive.

What happens is that by making the human nature constraint so determinative to the content

of their philosophical theories, they take the risk of unnecessarily reducing the scope of

application of their theories leaving some phenomena unexplained, or at best ill-explained.

Besides, by insisting on a descriptive theory empirically based, they take the further risk of

going too far away from the threshold of philosophy and thus producing philosophically

sterile theories with philosophical labels. To illustrate these points I give one example from

within legal philosophy: the controversies on the possibility of non-coercive legal systems.

Before that, I try to clarify the scope of my argument by distinguishing different kinds of legal

theories and the influence of human nature on them.

1. Varieties of Legal Theories

Having an institutional character seems to be a truism about law. Then, a theory of law would

inevitably be a sort of institutional theory. But there is a variety of institutional, and hence,

legal theories that one can draw: theories that only describe the institutions as they currently

work, theories that purport to establish general principles that should guide an institution,

theories about ideal institutions, theories about institutions that ought to be implemented,

theories about the most general aspects of institutions, and so forth. As one would imagine,

the relevance of human nature also varies according to the kind of theory one intends to

elaborate.

These theories are normally split into two groups:

(1) Descriptive Theories

(2) Normative Theories

Advocates of the first group are worried in providing a reliable description of what is at stake.

This group fits both factual institutional theories and conceptual institutional theories. The

descriptive character of the former theories is pretty clear, as this kind of theory purports to

describe what actually is going on with an existing institution: how it works, whether it is

5 See Priel (2010a), Priel (2010b) and Leiter (2011).

Page 4: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

effective or not, what are the features generally recognized as the central aspects of the

institution, and other related issues. This sort of theory is heavily, if not totally, dependent on

empirical analysis, for armchair speculation is not a reliable method for investigating, for

instance, whether a given institution is effective or not, or the main reason why people obey

the rules of this institution. Therefore, it is common to think that human nature is a crucial

aspect of such theories as they purport to describe, among other things, the ways institutions

are applied in human society.

The second kind of theory – conceptual institutional theories – purports to give a description

of the more general aspects of an institution which cannot be exclusively analyzed through the

lens of empirical analysis. The object of inquiry of this theory is not restricted to tokens of a

given institution, but to the basic properties and concepts that compose a type of an institution

and to the very properties and concepts that are necessary and sufficient for something to

count as an institution simpliciter. The characteristic marks of this kind of theory are the

employment of mental experiments using hypothetical situations, and the sort of questions

they intend to answer: conceptual questions. However, there are some controversies and

skepticism about the very descriptive character, merit and purpose of conceptual institutional

theories. One can argue, for example, that there is no point in making general descriptions of

institutions, for institutions are just social constructs that serve to be implemented in order to

fulfill some social purpose, and elaborating those general descriptions will not make them any

better in fulfilling such a purpose. Thus it is just a waste of time drawing detailed descriptions

of hypothetical scenarios such as a court where all judges are dworkinian Hercules judges or a

government of a community where all of its members are morally perfect, as such situations

will never obtain, and so the insight gained – if any – will be fruitless.

These are unfair criticisms and they ignore basically two things: the fact that hypothetical

scenarios are not employed for their literary fashion or for gaining knowledge about a

different world, and the fact that some aspects of the actual institutions could be seen in best

light by altering the scenario to which they apply. Contrarily to these thoughts, hypothetical

scenarios are employed to gain knowledge about what are the general characteristics of all

sorts of institutions, and that naturally encompasses actual institutions. That is, when we build

a thought experiment, say, of a government in a situation where all subjects are morally

perfect we are not aiming to describe something numerically distinct from the actual

government type, but instead how government would work in such a scenario and whether in

this situation it would lack or gain some properties.

Page 5: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

It is important to note that mental experiments are not restricted to conceptual institutional

theories; they can also be employed by science and by factual institutional theories. This is

pretty clear in economic theory where it is common to use the well-known homo economicus

as a simplification of human motivational behavior to achieve a better understanding of

market, such as how would be the distribution of goods in case everyone acted as free riders

or how the value of a given good would fluctuate in case everyone wants this specific good.

These fictional scenarios, thus, not only extend our knowledge of our institutions to situations

that did not obtain – an enterprise that would already be valuable just for the sake of

providing knowledge – but also can help us in building up institutions for attenuated

variations of the situations we already analyzed through the use of hypotheticals, and to avoid

certain tragic situations we predicted by using ideal situations. This example is of an

empirical analysis through and through. It shows that the mere fact of imagining an

hypothetical situation does not turns the analysis a priori, and that hypotheticals can be useful

also in scientific analysis and not only in conceptual analysis as it is commonly thought.

Skepticism about mental experiments would then not only be harmful to the projects of

conceptual theories, but also to the aims of empirical theories.

Among legal theories we can find the so called “General Jurisprudence”. The aim of General

Jurisprudence is much similar to those of conceptual institutional theories: provide a

description of the most general aspects of law, aspects that are present in all instances of law.

As with institutional theories, what distinguish General Jurisprudence from other inquiries are

the questions to which it intends to address. The classic question of General Jurisprudence is

“what is law?” and the answer to this question cannot be based entirely on conclusions drawn

from knowledge of one´s particular legal systems, as particular legal systems may have some

properties that are not necessary for something to count as an instance of law. This sort of

concern is a characteristic mark of traditional philosophical theories and they are told to be

capable of being made entirely from the armchair6. As one could imagine, traditionally human

nature plays a reduced role in this kind of theory, for it could employ thought experiments

violating human nature constraints either by imagining situations without human beings, or

6 For a defense of this kind of theory in philosophy see Williamson, The Philosophy of Philosophy. For a particular defense of this kind of theory in law see Shapiro, S. Legality, sp. Chap. 1. See also Raz Can There be a Theory of Law? Despite the fact that there are few works that explicitly defend this kind of theory in legal theory, many philosophers in fact do this kind of theory when they are doing legal philosophy. See, for instance, Himma 2000, Finnis 2011, Gardner 2006, Green 2008.

Page 6: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

situations with a distinct arrangement of the most salient psychological and biological

properties human beings possess.

The second group – normative theories – aims to provide theories that should be implemented

and complied, proposals for changings in actual institutions and institutional guiding

principles. Examples of such theories in legal philosophy are abundant. For instance, there are

theories about how to improve deterrence of punishment, or how to make legal norms more

effective. Also, there are a bunch of “critical theories” of law, such as feminist theories that

aims to a radical reform in legal institutions for achieving a more just state of affairs, and

theories of how to accommodate same-sex marriage into legal institutions.

The relevance of human nature here is pretty clear. One could not make normative legal

theories violating human nature constraints, such as the most salient biological and

psychological features of human beings, for this kind of legal theory purports to establish an

institution that aims to satisfy important human needs and help them to improve their social

world. Law could not without violating human nature constraints, for instance, try to

implement a theory of punishment that considers guilty whoever merely thinks about

committing a felony, or a theory of adjudication that requires judges to know the totality of

past and present judicial decisions in a jurisdiction in order to decide a case7.

Still, there is an important issue to clarify. When we talk about human nature constraints we

must understand it as referring to what humans cannot do, and not to what humans cannot

generally gather the will to do8. Certain psychological dispositions, such as moderate egoism,

are salient to human beings, and thus would partake in human nature constraints. But it is not

plausible to include them and some other similar salient features among human nature

constraints for the elaboration of normative legal theories as it would level down the quality

of the institutions we are to design and apply9. If the generality of men has a psychological

7 Note that there is a debate about whether it is possible to elaborate purely descriptive theories of law. if it turns out that it is impossible to have purely descriptive legal theories, then human nature constraints would apply also to what we now consider descriptive theories, as generally normative legal theories are worried to make law as best as possible for human development. See Finnis Natural Law and Natural Rights, Chap. 1. See also Bix, B. On the Dividing Line Between Natural Law and Legal Positivism. For a defense about the importance of Human Nature to legal theories see Priel, D. Towards Classical Positivism.

8 This objection is made by David Estlund (2011). The original argument is designed for political theories, but I think it perfectly suits normative legal theories.

9 Estlund also claims that saying that a theory does not applies to humans because they would not comply to it does not affect normative theories that ought to be implemented and complied, because he thinks that the deontic operator does not distribute over a conjunction and, then, the proposition “they ought not to comply” is not a negation to “ought to implement and comply”. I do not share this intuition, because despite the fact that ¬OC

Page 7: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

disposition of being violent to women, we would not give away an institution that

criminalizes violence against women for that reason alone. Also, we would not make a

taxation theory that allows subjects not to pay their tributes just because they are disposed not

to. Requiring too much from subjects would be wrong, but requiring just what they are

psychologically disposed to do would be damaging to the very purpose of having a legal

institution.

Another word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual

institutional theories. Given that the job of those theories is to describe institutions and they

are made by humans to help solving some human needs, then it would be part of the scope of

those theories to make a description of the very needs to which institutions were created to

solve. Some of those needs will be closely-tied to characteristics of human beings, such as

cognitive limitations and psychological dispositions. Thus, a complete description of a given

institution will have to mention those characteristics. Therefore, saying that human nature

plays a role in shaping this kind of theory is certainly true, but it offers no new insight on the

explanation of these theories, and it seems more likely that it is a fancy term added than some

substantial characteristic of the theories themselves. Saying that those theories cannot but

include human nature is simply saying that those theories cannot but include what is within

their object of explanation.

Having said this about legal theories and the relevance of human nature I will now turn to a

specific kind of legal theory: legal theories that purport to offer a description of actual law and

its salient features and yet want to keep the philosophical label. I will make a case against it

by presenting a controversy over coerced-based theories of law and the relevance of human

motivation to those theories.

2. An Example Within Legal Theory: Coerciveness of Law

The example of coerced-based legal theories I want to use to illustrate my point starts with H.

L. A. Hart´s critique of Austin and Kelsen´s legal theories. It is normally granted that Hart

was successful in arguing against the reduction of law to commands or sanctions and that his

introduction of power conferring rules, as much as the distinction between being obliged and

having an obligation constituted important, if not essential, components of law previously

ignored, or ill-explained by sanction-based theories.

does not constitute a direct negation of O(I & C), the truth of ¬OC is incompatible with the truth of O(I & C) if we keep the context constant. Though I cannot develop a detailed answer here.

Page 8: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

Among some of his well-known objections, Hart advances the claim that by focusing on

officials and on directives to apply sanctions, sanction-based theories are not able to explain

how law gives guidance to the puzzled man, i.e., the one who “is willing to do what is

required, if only he can be told what it is”10. This is the reason why he asks us to consider a

case where law were “equally if not more concerned with the puzzled man”11. In that case a

sanction-based account would not explain how puzzled men are guided by law, because

puzzled men follows the law regardless of being externally motivated by sanctions.

Nonetheless, some philosophers do not bite this bullet12. Schauer, for instance, claimed that by

underscoring the importance of the puzzled man Hart may have made an empirical claim

about human nature that is hardly corroborated by our reality. Hart seems to be assuming that

a significant number of subjects are puzzled men and, therefore, that sanction-based theories

have left aside without properly explaining how law offers guidance to a relevant portion of

subjects, namely those who follow the law not in virtue of its coercive aspect. This

assumption seems to go against both the fact that our actual legal systems have increased in

complexity and in number the forms of coercive regulation13 and also with some empirical

findings about human and animal behavior in the absence of sanctions14. The number of

puzzled men may be much smaller than Hart originally assumed and one of the possible

explanations for why sanctions and coercion appear as salient features of our current legal

systems is that we strongly need them to fulfill a pragmatic role given the psychological

motivation the generality of man possess.

Schauer continues to press and defended that the objection works against Hart if we interpret

his methodological commitments in an anti-essentialist manner. Following this interpretation

would lead to the conclusion that Hart was not worried about law in all possible worlds it

might exist but, contrarily, he was worried to describe law as it is15. Standing prima facie as

evidence to this view is Hart´s claim in The Concept of Law´s preface which states that the

book also intended to be an essay on descriptive sociology. According to Schauer, Hart

wanted a theory that “fits the facts” and used this criterion for objecting other theories16, such

10 Hart, 1994. p.4011 Idem.12 See Perry 2000, and Schauer 2010 pp. 6-7.13 Schauer, 2010 p. 7.14 See Cushmann, Fiery. The role of learning in punishment, prosociality, and human uniqueness. In: R. Joyce, K. Sterelny, B. Calcott & B. Fraser (Eds.) Signaling, Commitment and Emotion, Vol. 2: Psychological and Environmental Foundations of Cooperation. MIT Press: In Press.15 See Hart, 1994, Preface and Chapter 1.See also Hart 1995.16 Schauer, 2010 p.8.

Page 9: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

as Austin´s. In that case, by asking us to focus on the puzzled man he might be the one who is

not adequately describing the facts. If he wanted to be coherent in his methodology – Schauer

´s objection continues – he would rather need to acknowledge that sanctions and coercion are

salient features of our legal systems and cannot be considered mere “ancillary” aspects of law.

Nonetheless there are some reasons to think this interpretation of Hart´s methodological views

to be mistaken. First of all Hart´s claim about descriptive sociology needs to be clarified. Hart

had the conception – common at his time – that the right way of doing sociology was by the

employment of straightforward philosophical analysis rather than empirical investigation17.

He was mistrustful about sociology in general18 and in his late interview with David

Sugarman he assumed that he had suffered the “Oxford Disease” of distrust of sociology19.

Also, Nicola Lacey by examining Hart´s notebooks found a note which stated that “a better

formulation [of the descriptive sociology claim] would have been that the book provided the

‘normative concepts required for a descriptive sociology’”20. Thus, it is wrong to assume that

by mentioning sociology in the preface of his book Hart was willing to provide an

empirically-bounded analysis of law21. Second, in the Postscript of The Concept of Law Hart

affirmed that the aim of the book “was to provide a theory of what law is which is both

general and descriptive”22 and in so doing he gave us some guidance on how to interpret some

methodological aspects of his book that may be prone to dubious interpretation.

Leaving aside the problem about Hart´s methodological commitments and supposing for the

sake of argument that Hart´s legal theory was in General Jurisprudence´s shape, it is worthy

asking whether by focusing on a more general and detached analysis of law, Hart, and so the

ones who followed his methodology, missed what is really important about law, namely its

salient properties. The temptation of the critics here is to say that the case of coercion is just 17 See, Priel (2010, p.4).18 Lacey (2006, p. 953) illustrates that with the following passage: “Hart suggested that sociology can never match the test of empirical rigor it sets for itself. His view boils down to the idea that because the social sciences can never produce evidence as compelling as the evidence produced by the natural sciences, the social sciences are not worth pursuing.”19 See Sugarman (2005) especially p.289.20 Lacey (2006, p.949). Lacey also says that Hart´s project “was essentially a philosophical project, and its allusion to "descriptive sociology" was an unfortunately misleading attempt to signal his move away from the more rigidly conceptual theories of John Austin and Hans Kelsen in favor of an approach that helps us to look at the complex social phenomenon of law”.21 Though there are some passages where Hart seems to take into account some empirical data, there are several passages where Hart explicitly does straightforward conceptual analysis. See, as examples: pp.34-35; p. 42; p. 46; p. 57; p. 91. Also, Schauer is aware of the fact that there are some clear instances of conceptual analysis in Hart´s thought and to demonstrate that he quotes (2010 p.12) Hart´s reply to Cohen about whether sanctions were among the necessary ingredients of the concept of law where he makes a distinction of what is “logically necessary and what was present in the standard or normal case”.22 Hart, 1994, p. 239.

Page 10: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

one more example that makes clear that General Jurisprudence is a doomed project and will

not be able to yield important outcomes. Then, what we must do is to abandon General

Jurisprudence´s project and relying heavily on empirical considerations in order to make an

accurate philosophical description of law and its salience properties.

In response to these criticisms it is first arguable that Hart did not considered the coercive

aspect of law unimportant. He well assumed that it is “indispensable”23 in the actual world,

and one reason for this assumption is that he recognizes that law must pay some attention to

“universally recognized principles of conduct which have a basis in elementary truths

concerning human beings (…)”24 in order to be minimally efficacious, and by doing so

recognized the core importance of rules that restrict violence: “If there were not these rules

what point could there be for beings such as ourselves in having rules of any other kind? The

force of this rhetorical question rests on the fact that men are both occasionally prone to, and

normally vulnerable to, bodily attack.”25 However, he also defended the view that human

nature is contingent and therefore what is the case in the actual world may not be the case in a

different world law exists. Thus, a world where human beings are radically different from the

actuality would possess a radically different legal system: “If men were to lose their

vulnerability to each other there would vanish one obvious reason for the most characteristic

provision of law and morals: Thou shalt not kill”26. In sum, human nature would indeed be

important for law´s efficacy in the actual world, nonetheless it is not important to General

Jurisprudence´s endeavor.

Second, saying that Hart neglected the salience of coercion because he considered the

coercive aspect of law “ancillary” would be mistaken. By “ancillary” Hart did not mean

“unimportant”, but meant that the coercive aspect of law was a kind of backup used just in

case law could not guide subjects through its rules alone27. Then, “ancillary” here, should be

understood as “applied in second place”.

Third, and most important to our present concern, objecting that General Jurisprudence is a

doomed project because it is not able to produce important outcomes is misleading. First of

all, one should qualify what she means by “important outcomes”. Are important outcomes

those outcomes that increase our knowledge about law? If so, then General Jurisprudence

23 Hart, 1994 p. 39.24 Idem. p. 193.25 Idem. p. 195, italics added.26 Idem. p. 195. Emphasis in the original.27 See Shapiro, Scott. 2000, p. 207.

Page 11: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

would well satisfy it. Evidence for that is the progress legal philosophy went through the last

60th years or so, and that includes the abandoning of some implausible positions (such as

reducing all laws to commands), better formulation of the central problems of the area,

elaboration of important distinctions (primary and secondary rules, e.g.), and clarification of

central concepts (e.g. social practice, conventions, rules, authority). Or are important

outcomes just the outcomes that can be used to help lawyers and those who work with the

law, or outcomes that can be used to help law becoming a better institution? If these are the

case, then we would have only one option: abandoning all descriptive philosophical inquiry

and focus on normative inquiry. However this would be the opposite conclusion than the

advocate of empirical philosophical theories aimed by criticizing General Jurisprudence, for

she did not criticize it for its descriptive character, but for its conceptual character.

Another problematic point is that this skepticism about General Jurisprudence´s merits turns

out to be skepticism about the methodology of (traditional) philosophy in general. And there

is no way to arguing against the methodology of philosophy and proposing an alternative

philosophical methodology without entering into very kind of philosophical arguments that

one is criticizing. So, the proposal of an empirically-bound legal philosophy as a substitute for

General Jurisprudence cannot but be sustained by traditional philosophical arguments in order

to be justifiable.

Also, by turning our legal theories into an empirical description of law and its practice there

will be no difference in what sociological studies can find out about law and what philosophy

can do. There is no philosophical interest in knowing that, for instance, judges decide better

after lunch than some time before lunch. Still, I am not claiming that there is no interest

simpliciter in this kind of analysis. I accept that it is important, if not crucial for elaborating

normative theories of law, developing theories that makes law more effective and, for

instance, be able to help correcting witnesses’ biases and improve judges’ productivity, or

help to clarify what are the most common motives people employ in following law. But this

kind of analysis cannot answer whether judges have a moral duty to perform their work,

whether witnesses’ oath before the court not to lie constitute a indefeasible moral norm, or if

one can accept law just for prudential reasons, and whether law can be entirely explained in

terms of coercion. In sum, it does not answer any genuinely philosophical questions, as they

are conceptual questions rather than empirical.

Page 12: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

What all of it shows is that Hart one of General Jurisprudence´s practitioners, at least in the

discussion about coercion, did not even miss one of law´s salient properties – a worry that

some of his critics share. He recognized the important role coercion plays in the actual world,

though his project went further and he extended his analysis in order to explain how law

would regulate the behavior of an outlier subject, namely the puzzled man who has distinct

motivations from the ordinary man. Besides, with that extension he showed that a theory

solely focused on coercion would be an incomplete theory, for even if this theory could well

explain the salient aspects of law, it could not explain some more subtle and non-salient

aspects of it which are independent of coercion. Altering the scenario by imagining a distinct

possible world is just a tool to see those non-salient aspects of law in best light. Therefore,

restricting the scope of our descriptive theories of law to just what empirical analysis, and

thus human nature, can tell us is to exclude from our grasp a great amount of knowledge we

can have.

References:

BIX, Brian. On the Dividing Line Between Natural Law Theory and Legal Positivism. Notre

Dame Law Review, Vol. 75 pp 1613–24: 2000.

CUSHMANN, Fiery. The role of learning in punishment, prosociality, and human

uniqueness. In: R. Joyce, K. Sterelny, B. Calcott & B. Fraser (Eds.) Signaling, Commitment

and Emotion, Vol. 2: Psychological and Environmental Foundations of Cooperation. MIT

Press: In Press.

ESTLUND, David. Human Nature and the Limits (If Any) of Political Philosophy.

Philosophy & Public Affairs, Vol. 39, I. 3, pp.207-237: 2011.

FINNIS, John. Natural Law and Natural Rights. 2 ed. New York: Oxford University Press,

2011.

GARDNER, John. Law's Aim in Law's Empire. In Scott Hershovitz (ed), Exploring Law's

Empire. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.

GREEN, Leslie. Positivism and the Inseparability of Law and Morals. New York University

Law Review, Vol. 83, pp. 1035-58: 2008.

HART, Herbert. The Concept of Law. 2nd ed. Ed. P. A. Bulloch and J. Raz. Oxford:

Page 13: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

Clarendon, 1994.

___________. Theory and Definition in Jurisprudence. Proceedings of the Aristotelian

Society, Vol. 29, pp. 239–64: 1955.

HIMMA, Kenneth. H. L. A. Hart and the Practical Difference Thesis. Legal Theory, Vol. 6,

pp. 1-43: 2000.

LEITER, Brian. Naturalized Jurisprudence and American Legal Realism Revisited. Law and

Philosophy, Vol. 30. pp.499-516.

PERRY, Stephen R. Holmes versus Hart: The Bad Man in Legal Theory. In: The Path of the

Law and its Influence: The legacy of Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. Ed. BURTON, Steven J.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000

PRIEL, Dan. Jurisprudence and Psychology. In: New Waves in Philosophy of Law,

Forthcoming. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1715647.

__________. Towards Classical Legal Positivism. Osgoode CLPE Research Paper No.

20/2011: 2011. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1886517 .

__________. The Scientific Model of Jurisprudence, 2010a. Available at SSRN:

http://ssrn.com/abstract=1671543.

__________. Description and Evaluation in Jurisprudence. Law and Philosophy, Vol.29,

2010b.

RAWLS, John. A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition. Cambridge: The Belknap Press, 1999.

RAZ, Joseph. Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.

___________. Can There Be a Theory of Law. In: Martin P. Golding and William

Edmundson eds., The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Oxford:

Blackwell, 2005.

SCHAUER, Frederick. Was Austin Right After All? On the Role of Sanctions in a Theory of

Law. Ratio Juris, Vol. 23, n°. 1, p. 1-21: 2010.

SHAPIRO, Scott. Legality. Cambridge: The Belknap Press, 2011.

Page 14: gttj.files.   Web viewAnother word should be said about the role of human nature to what I called factual institutional theories. ... HART, Herbert

______________. The Bad Man and the Internal Point of View. In: The Path of the Law and

its Influence: The legacy of Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. Ed. BURTON, Steven J. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press, 2000.

WILLIAMSON, Timothy. The Philosophy of Philosophy. Blackwell Publishing, 2007.