hernandez derrida political possibilities

Upload: abrightside

Post on 06-Jul-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    1/30

    MabiniReview 

    POLYTECHNIC UNIVERSITY OF THE PHILIPPINES

    Institute of Social History

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    2/30

    Published byPolytechnic University of the Philippines

    Ofce of the Vice President for Research, Extension,Planning and Development

    INSTITUTE OF SOCIAL HISTORY 

    S-415, 4th Floor, South Wing, Main Academic Building

    Tel. No. 716-78-32 local 314 | Telefax 716-4033

    www.pup.edu.ph

    PHILIPPINE COPYRIGHT, 2012 by

    Polytechnic University of the Philippines

    The Mabini Review, No. 1, Vol. 1

    First Year of Publications, 2008

    ISSN: 2012-2144

    All rights reserved.

    No part of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any means,

    except brief quotations for a review, without permission in writing

    from the Publisher.

    Illustrator 

    Jayson C. Jimenez

    Printed by

    Ofce of the Vice President for Research, Extension,Planning and Development

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    3/30

    T a b l e o f C o n t e n t s

    P R E F A C E

    M A J O R A R T I C L E S

    i

    3

    71

    115

    47

    95

    AXIOMS OF CHOICE

    Virgilio A. Rivas 

    ON “EVIL, SIN AND THE FALL”:

    FOUCAULT’S CRITIQUE OF THE

    CHRISTIAN PROBLEMATIZATION

    OF THE FLESH

     Kristoffer Bolaños 

    DERRIDA’S IMPOSSIBLE JUSTICE

    AND THE POLITICAL POSSIBILITIES

    OF DECONSTRUCTION

     Michael Roland F. Hernandez 

    JOHN SEARLE AND THE

    IS-OUGHT PROBLEM

    Jeremiah Joven Joaquin

    TOWARDS A RADICAL

    RECONSTRUCTION OF THE HUMAN

    VISAGE: FROM NBIC CONVERGENCETO SINGULARITY TALK 

     Marciana Agnes G. Ponsaran

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    4/30

    B O O K R E V I E W S

    129

    137

    135

    WHAT CAN PHILOSOPHY DO IN THE

    PRESENT?

    A Reading of Badiou and Zizek’s

    Philosophy in the Present

    Jayson C. Jimenez 

    THE BELOVED IDIOM

    A Reading of Villafania’s Pinabli

    & Other Poems

     Dennis Andrew S. Aguinaldo

    PRUDENTE AS REVOLUTIONIST

    AND PROPHET

     Alfredo O. Cuenca, Jr.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    5/30

    143

    152

    L I T E R A R Y 

    162

    145

    156

    PREFACE TO THE LITERARY

    SECTION

     Alfredo Cuenca, Jr.

    MJ RAFAL

    Ulat sa Tula

     Ars Poetica ng Makata sa Karsel ng Sarili

    Kung Ita-tag Mo Sila Makikilala Kang

    Makata at Sisikat sa Tula

    ELAINE LAZARO

    Bread and Fish

    The Height Of…

    Kulam

    I Wonder How Real Writers Write

    DENNIS ANDREW S. AGUINALDO

    Days of Going Nowhere

    ForeparentsPortrait, After 31 Years

    The Grandfather Lullaby

    C O N T R I B U T O R S

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    6/30

    B E C O M I N G 

     by Jeric Palada

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    7/30

    Derrida’s ImpossibleJustice and the

    Political Possibilities ofDeconstruction*

    MICHAEL ROLAND F. HERNANDEZDepartment of PhilosophyAteneo de Naga University

    Thinking between Metaphysics and Politics

    To think the relation between Metaphysics and Politics is to encounter

    the age-old problem that links the essence of the philosophical

    with the political. It is to think, following the tradition of Plato and

    Aristotle, the nature of the polis  (or city-state) from the perspective of the

    truth as expounded by philosophy and as ideally ruled by philosophers.

    Within the ancient Greek schema, such reflection on the nature of thepolitical is itself grounded on the metaphysical notion of the Platonic

    Good as it should be manifested in the polis. In Plato’s Republic ̧ the good

    of the polis can only be determined in terms of the demand for the good

    of each individual citizen. But these particular goods in themselves are

    participations in that ideal universal Good which serves as the source of

    everything.This gesture implies, for Plato, that ethics (which is about the

    self and its relation to the other) is essentially structured for politics and

    these two together, in turn, require Plato’s metaphysical concept of the

    Good in order to determine their own proper objects, namely, the goodof the self in relation to the other and the common good. That politics

    depends on metaphysics is ultimately, however, just another expression

    of the truth that inseparably links the nature of philosophy with the

    political. Philosophy has always been political through and through and

    it is this relation that we want to understand in this paper.

    *A paper presented to the Philosophy Department of the Polytechnic

    University of the Philippines (PUP) in Manila on January 28, 2011.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    8/30

    M a j o r A r t i c l e s

    | M A B I N I R E V I E W 72

    Every discourse necessarily has its own political agenda. Even

    in a small philosophical conference like this, the attempt to understandpolitical issues from the perspective of philosophical episteme and not

    only from ordinary political opinion [doxa] is the metaphysico-political

    gesture par excellence.“Every philosophical colloquium necessarily has a

    political signification”1 and this is not only due to what has linked the

    essence of the philosophical with the essence of the political but because

    political implications give philosophical truths more weight, makes

    them appear more serious, and somehow endows them with a profound

    character or identity. Philosophically, then, to speak of political themes

    is a very difficult task for this entails that one be a real philosopherand an expert on political affairs. I must caution you then that I am

    neither both. Although this constitutes an effective disclaimer, I wish to

    emphasize though that the task of thinking about politics is incumbent

    not only upon us philosophers but on all of us citizen-dwellers in the

    state. It is from this responsibility that I get the audacity to speak before

    you today.

    As a student of both philosophy and of law, I cannot but be

    incessantly concerned with what concretely happens in the social andpolitical spheres. The many social and political pathologies of our

    time demand an ever-increasing commitment to the demands of both

    philosophic reflection and concrete involvement. This means that we

    must not only be content in contemplating the eternal truths of being but

    must also translate these truths into concrete social and political action.

    With these in mind, I wish to propose to you this afternoon Jacques

    Derrida’s deconstruction as an alternative way by which we can look at

    our present social and political experiences.

    Having been dubbed as the likely heir to the masters of

    suspicion—Marx, Nietzsche and Freud—Derrida arguably stands as

    one of the most enigmatic and controversial philosopher of our present

    time. His deconstruction, incorrectly understood by “conservative

    know-nothings”2  as  primarily   a method or a strategy for reading

    1Jacques Derrida,  Margins of Philosophy ̧ trans. Alan Bass (Chicago,

    University of Chicago Press, 1982), iii.2This description is provided by Richard Rorty in his polemic both against

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    9/30

    M . R . H e r n a n d e z | Derrida’s Impossible Justice

    | An Interdisciplinary Journal 73

    texts, has almost always been viewed with suspicion by traditional

    philosophers who see in him nothing but a despiser of common senseand the traditional democratic values of truth, reason, and objective

    knowledge. Such reduction of deconstruction into “some sort of entirely

    formalistic method based on an unproven philosophy of language” is

    what characterized the appropriation of deconstruction by generations

    of scholars in the humanities.3 For this reason, this charge of semiotic

    reductionism tended to confine deconstruction into the realm of the

    philosophy of language that ultimately has nothing to do with the

    concrete conditions of human life. More specifically, this means that

    deconstruction as the “sort of thing Derrida does” has little or nopractical value in the realm of politics. Might this not therefore confirm

    Richard Rorty’s initial impression about Derrida being good as a “private

    ironist” but insignificant as a “public liberal?”4

    It is at this point that I wish to address the temptation to

    consider Jacques Derrida’s deconstructive project as a relapse back into

    political quietism and despairing resignation from the horrors of politics.

    Following Simon Critchley’s suggestion, I will also advance the idea that

    it is possible to conceive of deconstruction as important in articulatingthe source of a concrete moral obligation and political disposition to help

    alleviate the other’s suffering.5 But in order to do this, it is necessary to

    Derrida’s critics and fans in the Anglo-American tradition that confines

    Derrida and what he does to that sort of “deconstruction” that seeks binaries

    in texts, overturns the hierarchical relation and pronounces that there is

    contradiction within the text which serves as its central message. Rorty claimsthat this thinking produced tens of thou-sands of readings which are formulaic

    and boring. (See Richard Rorty, “Some Remarks on Deconstruction and

    Pragmatism” in Deconstruction and Pragmatism, ed. Chantal Mouffe [London:

    Routledge, 1996], 13-18; 15).

    3Simon Critchley, “A Dedication to Jacques Derrida-Memoirs” in German

     Law Journal Vol. 6. No. 1 (2005): 26.

    4Rorty, “Some Remarks on Deconstruction and Pragmatism,” in

     Deconstruction and Pragmatism, 17.

    5Simon Critchley, “Is Derrida a Private Ironist or a Public Liberal” in

     Deconstruction and Pragmatism, 19-40; 33.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    10/30

    M a j o r A r t i c l e s

    | M A B I N I R E V I E W 74

    clarify what deconstruction is all about, the end  or goal at which Derrida

    aims, and the political possibilities arising from these considerations.

    In what follows then, I will first provide Jacques Derrida’s brief

     biographical sketch that insinuates his perennial political concerns.

    Second, I will provide a description of deconstruction as something

    that takes place within the text following Critchley’s suggestion of

    deconstruction as a kind of “double reading.” And third, I will relate

    this movement to the problem of justice and to its resulting political

    possibilities.

    Derrida’s Political Concerns

    Jacques Derrida was born in 1930 in El Biar, in French-occupied

    Algeria to Jewish parents. Being Jewish, Derrida realized at a very

    young age the problems connected with specific identities and racial

    discrimination. As a young kid, he was forced out of school on several

    instances because only a 7% limit on the school population was allocated

    for Jewish students and on another occasion, he had to withdraw from

    school because of anti-semitic practices. Moving from Algiers to Franceas a teenager, he was twice refused entrance into the prestigious  Ecole

     Normale Superieure , the school of France’s elite.

    Eventually however, he was admitted into the  Ecole at the

    age of 19 and began working with the leftist journal Tel Quel , a group

    that espoused radical reforms from the government in favor of the

    marginalized. Although his early training was in phenomenology,

    Derrida acknowledges Nietzsche, Freud, Saussure, Heidegger and

    Levinas, as among those who largely influenced his thought. He credits

    the above mentioned thinkers in the development of his over-all approach

    to reading texts—what was to be later called “deconstruction.”

    It was in 1967 however when Derrida acquired his status as a

    philosopher of worldwide importance. He simultaneously published

    three books: Of Grammatology , Writing and Difference , and Speech and

     Phenomena, where he discusses what would be later termed as standard

    deconstructive vocabularies such as logocentrism, phonocentrism,

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    11/30

    M . R . H e r n a n d e z | Derrida’s Impossible Justice

    | An Interdisciplinary Journal 75

    metaphysics of presence, trace, supplement, and the infamous

    “différance .”

    In these works, he sought to question the traditional privileging

    of the authority of presence and Being [Sein or esse ] and the values of

    truth, rationality and knowledge. Such gestures put him as one of the

    leading figures, together with Michel Foucault, of what was labeled as

    ‘French post-structuralism.’ As a prolific writer, Derrida wrote many

    important works which would range from topics of metaphysics and

    epistemology to question of aesthetics, culture, and politics. It was

    however in his discussion of Marx and his later works on friendship,6 democracy,7 law,8 political decision,9 apartheid,10 sovereignty, nationalism

    6See Jacques Derrida, Politics of Friendship, trans. George Collins (London

    and New York: Verso, 1997), 1-74.

    7Ibid., Chapter Four: “The Phantom Friend Returning (In the Name of

    Democracy),” 75-106. Also Jacques Derrida, “Remarks on Deconstruction

    and Pragmatism,” in Deconstruction and Pragmatism, 77-88.

    8See Jacques Derrida, “Force of Law: The Mystical Foundation of

    Authority” in 11 Cardozo Law Review [1990], 920, 967. The above is a 1989

    lecture during a conference on deconstruction and justice convened by the

    philosopher and legal theorist Drucilla Cornell that was subsequently published

    in Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice , [edited by Drucilla Cornell, et al.

    (New York: Routledge, 1992), 3-67; also published in Jacques Derrida, Acts of

     Religion, edited with an introduction by Gil Anidjar (New York, Routledge,

    2002), 228-298]. In this lecture, Cornell asked Derrida to address the questionof “deconstruction and the possibility of justice” where he had to address a

    text by Walter Benjamin on violence.

    9Derrida,  Politics of Friendship, Chapter Five, “On Absolute Hostility:

    The Cause of Philosophy and the Specter of the Political,” 112-133; see also

    Derrida’s dialogue with Giovanna Borradori in  Philosophy in a Time of Terror  (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2003), 130ff. Henceforth PTT.

    10See Jacques Derrida, “Racism’s Last Word” in  Psyche: Inventions of theOther , Volume I, trans. Peggy Kamuf, 377-86; and “The Laws of Reflection:

    Nelson Mandela, in Admiration,” trans. Mary Ann Caws and Isabelle Lorenz,

    Volume II, 63-86.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    12/30

    M a j o r A r t i c l e s

    | M A B I N I R E V I E W 76

    and cosmopolitanism,11 hospitality,12 the university and the teaching of

    philosophy,13

     terrorism14

     and many other socio-political philosophemes,that strategically demonstrates the potent force that deconstruction

    acquires when it links “the essence of the philosophical to the essence

    of the political.”15

    Here, it would be a mistake to trace or reduce Derrida’s political

    concerns to his biographical life. But it is obvious that his early experiences

    of discrimination in life were to play a large part in his promotion of

    the cause of the marginalized “other” in his later thought. If there is

    one positive thing that Derrida is telling us about deconstruction, itwould be the claim that deconstruction is about the other, an opening

    to “an alterity which necessarily calls, summons, and motivates it.”16 

    Deconstruction has always been about the other whom we must address

    as a matter of justice. Contrary then to the claim that deconstruction

    is an “enclosure in nothingness,” Derrida offers deconstruction as a

    way out of this enclosure within linguistic subjectivism and theoretical

    solidification.

    11See for instance Borradori, 130-134; also Jacques Derrida, Schurken

    [Rogues], (2003). Not yet translated into English at the time this article was

    written.

    12See for instance Borradori,  Philosophy in a Time of Terror, 125-130; also

    Jacques Derrida, On Hospitality: Anne Dufourmantelle invites Jacques Derrida to

     Respond  (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2000).

    13See for instance Jacques Derrida, “The Principle of Reason: The

    University in the Eyes of its Pupils,” trans. Catherine Porter and Edward

    Morris, Diacritics ̧13 (1983): 3-20.

    14See Borradori, Philosophy in a Time of Terror , 113ff.

    15Derrida, Margins of Philosophy , 111.

    16Jacques Derrida, “Deconstruction and the Other” in  Dialogue with

    Contemporary Continental Thinkers , ed. Richard Kearney (Manchester:

    Manchester University Press, 1984), 118.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    13/30

    M . R . H e r n a n d e z | Derrida’s Impossible Justice

    | An Interdisciplinary Journal 77

    Deconstruction as Double-Reading

    At this point, we can use Critchley’s characterization of

    deconstruction in terms of double-reading as a heuristic device in

    presenting deconstruction as something that happens within texts.

    Accordingly, deconstruction is “something that takes place in a text”

    as in a text that loses its own “construction”   so as to open itself to a

    multiplicity of meanings.17 For Critchley, what is first involved in this

    process is to provide a “patient, rigorous, and  scholarly   reconstruction

    of a text” as a powerful, primary layer of reading that remains faithful

    to original context of the text and intention of the author in the form ofthe dominant commentary.18 From this first layer of reading, a second

    moment of reading is opened up by interpretation where the text’s

    intended meaning [its vouloir-dire ] is purportedly contradicted by certain

    “blind spots” in the text.19  This opens up the text into a multiplicity

    of meanings other than that sanctioned by authorial intent. But this

    “rupture” is something that is sanctioned from within the text itself rather

    than imposed from the outside. It is this opening up from within the

    text itself which characterizes deconstructive reading as parasitic: “the

    reader must both draw their sustenance from the host text and lay theircritical eggs within its flesh.”20 Deconstruction then can be conceived as

    a subject-less process in the sense that “the text deconstructs itself rather

    than being deconstructed.”21 Within Derrida’s intention, a deconstructive

    reading therefore is an ambiguous gesture since while it must necessarily

    carve itself out of a structuralist problematic , it nevertheless remains, more

    importantly, as an antistructuralist gesture.

    Considering deconstruction as double-reading, one can see

    that what Derrida philosophically exemplifies is a patient, meticulous,

    scrupulous, open and questioning engagement with texts. This means

    17Jacques Derrida, “Letter to a Japanese Friend” in Derrida and Differance

    (Evanston, Il: Northwestern University Press, 1988), 1-5; 2.

    18Critchley, “A Dedication to Jacques Derrida-Memoirs,” 26.

    19Ibid., 26-7.

    20Ibid., 27.21Ibid.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    14/30

    M a j o r A r t i c l e s

    | M A B I N I R E V I E W 78

    that the activity called deconstruction is not some form of nihilistic

    textual free play that threatens to undermine our traditional values ofrationality, morality and other values of Western liberal democracy.

    Rather, it is a careful reading and thinking of texts considered as an

    ethical demand.22 Deconstruction in fact, as Critchley insightfully claims,

    is pedagogy23 inasmuch as it teaches us to deal with texts responsibly as

    a matter of justice.

    In this context, we can see that deconstruction, as something

    that takes place within the text, is itself the ethical gesture that lets the

    text be structurally open to the other. Here, the other must be understoodas that which has always been appropriated and therefore neglected

     by the whole philosophical tradition. By opening a text to its other,

    deconstruction opens up the space for the possibility of justice, that is,

    the possibility of addressing that which tradition has always thought to

     be “impossible” as the not-possible, beyond possible—beyond thought,

    language and presence. Here, I am taking broad strokes in delineating

    how Derrida’s deconstructive project can be related to the exercise of

     justice and hence, to political decision. Inasmuch as it opens up the

    space for the possibility of addressing the other, then, deconstruction isitself justice.

    Deconstruction is Justice

    What does it mean to say that “deconstruction is justice?”

    Derrida explains this assertion in the context of the tension between law

    (droit ) and justice. In his essay “Force of Law: The Mystical Foundation

    of Authority,” a lecture delivered during a conference organized by the

    philosopher and legal theorist Drucilla Cornell in 1989, Derrida sets out

    to distinguish between law and justice. Accordingly, law refers to the

    history of right, of legal systems, and justice. As such, the law could be

    deconstructed.24 There is a history of legal systems, of rights, of laws, of

    22Ibid., 28.

    23Ibid., 27.

    24Jacques Derrida, “The Villanova Roundtable: A Conversation with

    Jacques Derrida” in John Caputo,  Deconstruction in a Nutshell   (New York:

    Fordham University Press, 1997), 16.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    15/30

    M . R . H e r n a n d e z | Derrida’s Impossible Justice

    | An Interdisciplinary Journal 79

    positive laws, and this history is the history of the transmutation of laws.

    The law can be improved and replaced by another one. Every time youreplace the law by another one, a system by another one, or you improve

    it, that is a kind of deconstruction and critique. As such, the law can be

    deconstructed and has to be deconstructed.25 This is the condition of

    historicity, revolution, morals, ethics and progress. But Derrida says that

    “justice is not the law;” and he goes to explain:

    Justice is what gives us the impulse, the drive or the

    movement to improve the law, that is, to deconstruct the

    law. Without the call for justice we would not have anyinterest in deconstructing the law. That is why I said

    that the condition for the possibility of deconstruction

    is a call for justice. Justice is not reducible to the law,

    to a given system of legal structures. That means that

     justice is always unequal to itself. It is non-coincident

    with itself.26

    The unfolding of justice as the motivating force or impulse

    for the deconstruction of presence clarifies the question of “what isdeconstruction all about?” If we are to make any theoretical or practical

    sense of “what is there to” or “the point about deconstruction,” it would

    to be this sense of justice that serves as its goal or end. Deconstruction

    is all about justice and Derrida expresses this claim within the context

    of the law:

    Justice in itself, if such a thing exists, outside

    or beyond law, is not deconstructible. No more

    than deconstruction itself, if such a thing exists.

    Deconstruction is justice.27

    In order to understand this better, Derrida makes a distinction

     between justice as the relation to the other and the idea of justice as law

    or as right. Justice as law or right is justice as it is dispensed by the legal

    25 Ibid.

    26Ibid., 16ff.27Derrida, “Force of Law,” 14-15.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    16/30

    M a j o r A r t i c l e s

    | M A B I N I R E V I E W 80

    system. It is limited to what the law, understood as the history of rights

    and legal systems, defines and calculates in terms of an economy ofreciprocal duties and obligations. What can be calculated within the law

    is the existence of rights that grounds certain privileges such as the right

    to property, education, etc., and the determination of “justice as right”

    that results from the correct application of particular legal principles to

    specific situations. What is right can be calculated, as when we say that

    this deed deserves one month, two years, three decades, or four centuries

    of imprisonment based on a certain set of laws. In this way, one can

    determine within the law whether one is just, i.e., in terms of what is

    right or not when his actions conform to the norm or not. As such, rightis reduced to a matter of calculation. However, the fact that a decision is

    rightly calculated does not mean that it is just. Derrida explains:

    Law is an element of calculation, and it is just that

    there be law, but justice is incalculable; and aporetic

    experiences are the experiences, as impro-bable as they

    are necessary, of justice, that is to say of moments in

    which the decision between just and unjust is never

    insured by a rule.28

    Justice is not a matter of theoretical determination and goes

     beyond the certainty of theoretical judgment or knowledge. To illustrate

    this, Derrida gives the example of a judge, who, in order to be just, must

    not be contented in the mere application of the law.

    To be just, the decision of the judge, (...) must not

    only follow a rule of law or a general law but must also

    assume it, approve it, confirm its value, by a reinstituting

    act of interpretation, as if ultimately nothing previously

    existed of the law, as if the judge himself invented the

    law in every case. No exercise of justice as law can be

     just unless there is a “fresh judgment.”29

    28Ibid., 14.29Ibid., 23.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    17/30

    M . R . H e r n a n d e z | Derrida’s Impossible Justice

    | An Interdisciplinary Journal 81

    The judge therefore

    [Has] to reinvent the law each time. If he wants

    to be responsible, to make a decision, he has not

    simply to apply the law, as a coded program to a given

    case, but to reinvent in a singular situation a new just

    relationship; that means that justice cannot be reduced

    to a calculation of sanctions, punish-ments or rewards.

    That may be right or in agreement with the law but that

    is not justice.30

    Justice, then, ultimately is not the law and “law (droit ) is not

     justice.”31 For this reason, as long as one remains on the level of legal

    application, one cannot be “sure” that he is just. One can never say that

    someone is just or a decision is just in the present as long as he does not

    leave the current system of the law in order to treat each case as an

    “other.” Since justice has to do with the absolutely other, every case

    requires a decision based on “an absolutely unique interpretation, which

    no existing rule can or ought to guarantee absolutely.” Thus, one can

    only say that he is “legal or legitimate” i.e., “in conformity with a stateof law, with the rules and conventions that authorize calculation but

    whose founding origin only defers the problem of justice,”32 but he can

    never claim to be “just.”

    In short, for a decision to be just and responsible, it must, in its

    proper moment if there is one, be both regulated and without regulation:

    it must conserve the law and also destroy or suspend it enough to reinvent

    it in each case, rejustify it, at least reinvent it in the reaffirmation and the

    new and free confirmation of its principle.33

    In this case, the kind of justice found in the present order or

    system of the law is always a limited justice that ought to be supplemented

    30Derrida, “Villanova Roundtable,” 24.

    31Derrida, “Force of Law,” 15.

    32Ibid., 23.33Ibid.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    18/30

    M a j o r A r t i c l e s

    | M A B I N I R E V I E W 82

     by the idea of justice as relation to the other. This justice as relation to

    the other operates from the outside of the law in order to open its insidetowards that which it is unable to say or capture within the system. The

    law is a closed system, “finite, relative and historically grounded,” and it

    is only opened up by an infinite and absolute justice that “transcends the

    sphere of social negotiation and political deliberation.”34 As such, this

    [j]ustice if it has to do with the other, with the infinite distance of the

    other, is always unequal to the other, is always incalculable. You cannot

    calculate justice.35

    Justice as Gift

    That justice is incalculable brings us to the conclusion that

     justice is not a matter of reciprocation. Justice demands that it not be

    reciprocated and for this reason must be seen outside the economy of

    exchange. Justice is therefore like the gift: both go beyond calculation

    and resist appropriation. For Derrida, the gift is something that can

    never be appropriated.36  It never appears as such and is never equal

    to gratitude, to commerce, to compensation, or to reward. The gift is

     beyond the circle of gratitude and reappropriation and for this reason;no gratitude can be proportionate to a gift. One cannot even be thankful

    for a gift. As soon as one says “thank you” for a gift, the gift is erased,

    is cancelled, is destroyed. “A gift should not even be acknowledged as

    such.”37 If something is given, it should not appear as such to the one

    who gives it or to the one who receives it. This is paradoxical, but that is

    the condition for the gift to be given. In Given Time , he explains:

    For there to be a gift, it is necessary [ilfaut ] that the

    donee not give back, amortize, reimburse, acquit himself,

    enter into a contract, and that he never have contracted

    34Borradori, Philosophy in a Time of Terror, 164.

    35Ibid., 24.

    36Derrida’s most comprehensive account of the gift is contained in his

     book Given Time: I. Counterfeit Money , trans. Peggy Kamuf (Chicago: University

    of Chicago Press, 1992).37Derrida, “Villanova Roundtable,” 18.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    19/30

    M . R . H e r n a n d e z | Derrida’s Impossible Justice

    | An Interdisciplinary Journal 83

    a debt. (...) The donee owes it to himself   even not to give

     back, he ought not to owe [il a le devoir de ne pas devoir]and the donor ought not count on restitution...38

    The gift calls upon us for expenditure without reserve, for a

    giving that wants no payback, for distribution with no expectation of

    retribution, reciprocity or reappropriation. “To give a gift requires that

    one then forgets and requires the other to forget, absolutely, that a gift

    has been given, so that the gift, if there is one, would vanish without a

    trace.”39

    It is thus necessary, at the limit, that he not recognize  

    the gift as gift. If he recognizes it as gift, if the gift

    appears to him as such, if the present is present to him as

     present , this simple recognition suffices to annul the gift.

    Why? Because it gives back, in the place, let us say, of

    the thing itself, a symbolic equivalent. (...) The symbolic

    opens and constitutes the order of circulation in which

    the gift gets annulled.40

    This is the same condition in which justice must share. A justice

    that appears as such, that could be calculated, a calculation of what is

     just and not just, that says what must be given in order to be just, is not

     justice at all. Rather, justice must partake of the idea of a gift without

    exchange, of a relation to the other that is utterly irreducible to the moral

    rules of circulation, gratitude, recognition as symmetry.41  As beyond

    calculation, it partakes of the structure of that which is to come, going

     beyond the comprehension by ordinary theoretical knowledge and the

    38Derrida, Given Time , 13.

    39Caputo, Deconstruction in a Nutshell, 144.

    40Derrida, Given Time , 13.

    41Derrida explains that economic calculation has to do with priority of

    absolute subjectivity. Thus to speak of a justice as gift is to go beyond the

    authority of subjectivity, beyond any egoism, and also of any reciprocity,

    much like in the manner of Christ’s sacrifice. (See Jacques Derrida, The Gift of

     Death, trans. David Wills [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995], 102.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    20/30

    M a j o r A r t i c l e s

    | M A B I N I R E V I E W 84

    language of presence. A justice that does not become a gift, in the end,

     becomes mere social security and economics.

    To speak, then, of justice as the relation to the other is to

    emphasize that element of incalculability which is not found in the

    experience of justice as law or justice as right. This “incalculable justice”

    is what we refer to as the “point” to deconstruction. It is that on account

    of which we embark on the endless and difficult task of examining,

    clarifying, and criticizing texts in order to open it up and articulate what

    has always been repressed, displaced, or margi-nalized by the tradition.

    This enunciation of the plight of what is continuously marginalizedwithin the structures of  present  history, politics, economics, law, and so

    forth, follows Levinas’ definition of justice as the relation to the other.42 

    This relation to the other, Derrida claims, is all that there is to justice and

    he explains this thus:

    Once you relate to the other as other, then

    something incalculable comes on the scene, something

    which cannot be reduced to the law or history of

    legal structures. This is what gives decon-struction itsmovement, i.e., to constantly suspect, to criticize the

    given determinations of culture, of institutions, of legal

    systems, not in order to destroy them or simply to cancel

    them, but to be just with justice, to respect this relation

    to the other as justice.43

    An (Im)possible Justice to Come

    Justice calls us to respond to the call of the other, which, as

    radical alterity, is that which exceeds the totality of presence. But to

    respond to the other as other, in terms of the language of the other,

    is to open up to the experience of justice as an impossibility. Justice

    moves us to respond towards something which is not present, is not in

    the present, and can never be fully realized in the present. The call of

    42See Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority ,

    trans. Alphonso Lingis (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1969), 89.43Derrida, “Villanova Roundtable,” 18.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    21/30

    M . R . H e r n a n d e z | Derrida’s Impossible Justice

    | An Interdisciplinary Journal 85

     justice moves us to respond towards an other that is never present but

    can only be hoped for in a future to come. Justice is impossible becauseit is to come; it is a hope and a waiting directed to an otherto come in

    the future. This impossibility is what makes deconstruction as a passion

    for the impossible, a desire which we desire beyond side, what we love

    like mad.

    And deconstruction is mad about this kind of

     justice. Mad about this desire for justice. This kind

    of justice which isn’t law, is the very moment of de-

    construction at work in law and the history of law, inpolitical history and history itself...44

    “Justice is an experience of the impossible,”45  Derrida

    claims, and it requires the experience of the aporia as a “non-road,”

    as “something that does not allow passage,” outside the scope of any

    calculation. Without this experience of the aporia, “[a] will, a desire, a

    demand for justice (...) would have no chance to be what it is, namely,

    a call for justice.”46 Justice as an impossible experience of the aporia is

    situated outside the element of calculation within the legal system. Itis this justice beyond calculation, and even one that resists calculation,

    which gives the law its impetus to be always on the way for a greater

    appropriation of justice. Justice comes to the law as its impossible

    condition, i.e., a condition which the law cannot capture and can never

     justify before itself. Thus, justice is something that cannot be determined

     by the performance of obligations or duties that one is bound to do under

    the law. Justice is the condition without which there would be no law, or

    the possibility of the law. Here, we can say that the essence of justice is

    to have no essence, to be in disequilibrium, to be disproportionate with

    itself, never to be adequate to itself, never identical with itself. Having no

    essence, justice therefore never exists and the fact that it does not exist is

    essential to justice. Since it has no essence and does not exist, justice can

    never be calculated and demands that it not be calculated. And since it

    cannot be calculated, justice is therefore undecon-structible.

    44Derrida, “Force of Law,” 25.

    45Ibid., 16.46Ibid.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    22/30

    M a j o r A r t i c l e s

    | M A B I N I R E V I E W 86

    Justice is not deconstructible and this goes hand in hand with

    the deconstructibility of the law. In this “interval   that separates theundeconstructibility of justice from the deconstructibility of the law,”47 

    deconstruction takes place to punctuate the law in order to safeguard

    the possibility of justice. This point is what answers the question about

    the connection between deconstruction and the possibility of justice:

    deconstruction is what opens up the possibility for justice and this

    possibility is that which prevents the law from being legalistic, from being

    a closed system concerned only with legitimation and with rectitude.

    Such undeconstructibility clarifies an important point about the nature  of

     justice: justice is not a thing, among others, that we subject to unendingdeconstruction. While it is true that there is no end to deconstruction

    and everything  is deconstructible, justice

    (...) if such a ‘thing’ ‘exists,’ is not a thing . Justice

    is not a present entity or order, not an existing reality

    or regime; nor it is even an ideal eidos   toward which

    we earthlings down below heave and sigh while

    contemplating its heavenly form. Justice is the abso-

    lutely unforeseeable prospect (a paralyzing paradox) invirtue of which the things that are deconstructed are

    deconstructed.48

    The fact that justice exceeds law and calculation however does

    not mean that we could not or should not calculate. Left to itself, this

    incalculability of justice might be reappropriated for the worst cases of

    calculation within institution, states, and others. Instead, Derrida insists,

    “incalculable justice requires us to calculate” not only within the law but

    also in those other fields that cannot be separated from it.49 In fact, we

    “have to calculate as rigorously as possible.” However, “there is a point

    or limit beyond which calculation must fail, and we must recognize

    that.”50 He continues:

    47Derrida, “Force of Law,” 15.

    48Caputo, Deconstruction in a Nutshell , 133.

    49Derrida, “Force of Law,” 28.50Derrida, “Villanova Roundtable,” 19.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    23/30

    M . R . H e r n a n d e z | Derrida’s Impossible Justice

    | An Interdisciplinary Journal 87

    Not only must  we calculate, negotiate the relation

     between the calculable and the incalculable, andnegotiate without the sort of rule that wouldn’t have

    to be reinvented there where we are cast, there where

    we find ourselves; but we must  take it as far as possible,

     beyond the place we find ourselves and beyond the

    already identifiable zones of morality or politics or

    law, beyond the distinction between national and

    international, public and private, and so on.51

    By setting the calculability of the law and its institutions againstthe incalculability of justice, an important point is clarified in this relation

     between law and justice. Incalculable justice is beyond the law but it

    strategically remains as law and politics’ inexhaustible demand. Justice

    is always à venir , to come, and its structural possibility as an imminent

    future is what continually moves both law and politics always toward

    a fuller precipitation of justice. Law and politics must therefore always

    look upon justice as that which is to come, à venir . This is because the

    legitimacy of the legal order cannot be offered except in retrospect, i.e.,

    force and violence are what is present at the founding moment of the lawand justice only comes afterwards as its justification.52

    Thus, we see that Derrida’s passion for impossible justice is what

    makes deconstruction as a movement towards, as a kind of waiting for, an

    (im)possible future.53 Deconstruction itself is “a movement towards the

    future,”54 which can only operate on the basis of this idea of impossible

     justice, i.e., an “infinite ‘idea of justice’.” Derrida explains:

    [T]he deconstruction of all presumption of a

    determinant certitude of a present justice itself operates

    51Derrida, “Force of Law,” 28.

    52Borradori, Philosophy in a Time of Terror , 164.

    53See John Caputo, “Introduction” in The Prayers and Tears of Jacques Derrida: Religion without Religion (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press,

    1997), xvi-xxvi; 1-6.54Ibid., 131.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    24/30

    M a j o r A r t i c l e s

    | M A B I N I R E V I E W 88

    on the basis of an infinite “idea of justice,” infinite

     because it is irreducible, irreducible because owed tothe other, before any contract, because it has come, the

    other’s coming as a singularity that is always other.55

    This impossible justice, identified here with the infinite “idea

    of justice,” is what characterizes deconstruction as a deeply affirmative

    enterprise. It is therefore a vocation, a response to a call and for this

    reason, can never be merely negative. Deconstruction is therefore an

    enterprise whose affirmative character is beyond being positive, beyond

    the distinction between positive and negative. And it owes its affirmativecharacter to this undeconstructible, infinite “idea of justice” that is owed

    to the other and hence

    [Irreducible] in its affirmative character, in its

    demand of gift without exchange, without circulation,

    without recognition or gratitude, without economic

    circularity, without calculation and without rules,

    without reason and without rationality.56

    Such impossible and infinite justice is, Derrida continues, what

    we can recognize, indeed accuse, or identify as “madness,” and “perhaps

    another sort of mystique.”57 Mad and unpresentable though it may be,

    however, this justice which impassions us to deconstruct towards the

    future doesn’t wait. “It [justice] is that which must not wait.”58 Justice is

    therefore imminent and this imminence is what agitates the coherence of

    the present in order to show its structural inconsistency. For this reason,

     justice plays a part in a future which must be distinguished from a future

    that can only “always reproduce the present.”59 In fact, it is this futural

    dimension that is inseparable from the very idea of a deconstructive

     justice.

    55Derrida, “Force of Law,” 25.

    56Ibid.

    57Ibid.

    58Ibid., 26.59Ibid., 27.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    25/30

    M . R . H e r n a n d e z | Derrida’s Impossible Justice

    | An Interdisciplinary Journal 89

    Justice remains, is yet, to come à venir , it has an, it

    is à-venir , the very dimension of events irreducibly tocome. It will always have it, this à-venir , and always has.

    Perhaps it is for this reason that justice, insofar as it is

    not only a juridical or political concept, opens up for

    l’avenir  the transformation, the recasting or refounding

    of law and politics. (...) There is an avenir  for justice and

    there is no justice except to the degree that some event

    is possible which, as event, exceeds calculation, rules,

    prog-rams, anticipations and so forth...60

    This “to come” of justice is the structural orientation that moves

    it along towards the future, making it unpresentable, uncalculable,

    undeconstructible, and impossible. As such, the future is what disturbs

    the present beyond itself so as to open itself to the call of justice. Here,

    to say that justice is present is to do the most unjust thing since this

    amounts to a closing off of the future, and consequently, to the ultimate

    impossibility of justice.61

    The Gift of Messianic Justice

    In this vein, we can see that the irreducible structural futurity

    of justice is what ultimately constitutes the enigma of finite human

    responsibility. If justice is to come and deconstruction is a waiting for

    an impossible future, does this not condemn us to a useless, passive, and

    non-committal quietism that merely awaits the fatalistic coming of the

    inevitable ‘unthinkable, unnameable, undeconstructible, unpresentable,

    impossible?’ On the contrary! The deconstructive waiting for the

    coming of impossible justice is precisely what opens us to the experience

    of singular responsibility. This impossible justice is what calls us and

    provides that interruption of the present so that we can move with

    responsibility towards the future. Because of this responsibility, it is

    possible to move towards the experience of justice, which as à venir ,

    is what keeps us ready to receive that which is to come. For Derrida,

    deconstruction as a kind of waiting for the impossible is precisely possible

    60Ibid.61Caputo, Prayers and Tears , 81.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    26/30

    M a j o r A r t i c l e s

    | M A B I N I R E V I E W 90

     because of this openness to receive the coming of the other in a future

     justice to come. This openness paves the way for a responsible answerto an “unforeseeable future” which, as called forth by justice, partakes

    of that “universal structure” in our  present   experience that readies the

    human person for the reception of that which is to come.

    As soon as you address the other, as soon as you

    are open to the future, as soon as you have a temporal

    experience of waiting for the future, of waiting for

    someone to come: that is the opening of experience.

    Someone is to come, is now  to come. Justice and peacewill have to do something with this coming of the

    other, with the promise. Each time I open my mouth,

    I am promising something. When I speak to you, I am

    telling you that I promise to tell you something, to tell

    you the truth. Even if I lie, the condition of my lie is

    that I promise to tell you the truth. So the promise is

    not just one speech act among others; every speech act

    is fundamentally a promise. This universal structure of

    the promise of the expectation for the future, for thecoming, for the fact that this expectation of the coming

    has to do with justice…62

    This universal structure is what Derrida calls as the “messianic

    structure” since it is that which is in our present experience  that readies us

    for the reception of that salvation that comes from a justice to come,

    an other to come, and ultimately, a Messiah or a God who is to come.

    The “messianic” has to do with the “absolute structure of the promise,

    of an absolutely indeterminate, (…) a structural future, a future always

    to-come, à venir .”

    The messianic future is an absolute future, the

    very structure of the to-come that cannot in principle

    come about, the very open-endedness of the present

    that makes it impossible for the present to draw itself

    into a circle, to close in and gather around itself. The

    62Caputo, Deconstruction in a Nutshell , 22-3.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    27/30

    M . R . H e r n a n d e z | Derrida’s Impossible Justice

    | An Interdisciplinary Journal 91

    messianic is the structure of the to come that exposes

    the contingency and deconstructibility of the present,exposing the alterability of (…) the “powers that be,”

    the powers that are present, the prestigious power of

    the present.63

    The messianic is a structure of experience which  prevents our

    present experience from being self-contained in its present. The messianic

    is what allows us to encounter the other, as “something that we could

    not anticipate, expect, fore-have, or fore-see, something that knocks our

    socks off, that brings us up short and takes our breath away.”64 By virtueof the messianic structure, it is possible for us to address “god” and the

    “other” with the word: “Come” [Viens ]. It is what enables us to always

    pray, plead, and desire the coming of the Messiah.

    E p i l o g u e :  In Lieu of a Conclusion

    To speak of the political possibilities of deconstruction is tospeak in general terms of how deconstruction, as such, can become

    relevant for our actions in the political sphere. As what I have tried to

    show, deconstruction as an openness to the other is a positive response

    to the ethical demand occasioned by the “that-which-is-to-come.” That

    which is to come is the other to whom we must respond in justice and

    infinite responsibility. To address the other requires the experience of

     justice which is not limited to what the law dictates or provides but to that

    experience of justice as relation to the other—beyond law, conventions,

    and institutions. This notion of justice beyond the law, beyond the rules

    of reciprocity is what Derrida aptly characterizes as impossible. Such

    impossibility is what ultimately characterizes deconstruction as an

    impossible enterprise but nevertheless gives it an internal dynamism as a

    movement towards the future. This movement towards the future is what

    makes the deconstruction of the political sphere a search for that non-

    violent and non-appropriative relation that finds its model in Derrida’s

    63Ibid., 162.64Ibid.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    28/30

    M a j o r A r t i c l e s

    | M A B I N I R E V I E W 92

    understanding of friendship. Such ethical relation can be construed as

    the basis for a political decision that aims at an ever-fuller experience of justice. To speak then of the political possibilities of deconstruction is

    to recognize that deconstruction, like philosophy, is essentially political

    through and through. And this deconstruction of our being political is

    one of the responsible ways to exercise our wonder in being human and

    the fact of our being-with-others.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    29/30

    M . R . H e r n a n d e z | Derrida’s Impossible Justice

    | An Interdisciplinary Journal 93

    R e f e r e n c e s

    Benjamin, W. “Critique of Violence.” In Walter Benjamin Selected

    Writings,Vol. 1. Massachusetts: The Belknap Press, 1999.

    Borradori, G.  Philosophy in a Time of Terror.  Chicago: University of

    Chicago Press, 2003.

    Caputo, J.  Deconstruction in a Nutshell. New York: Fordham University

    Press, 1997.

     ________. The Prayers and Tears of Jacques Derrida: Religion without Religion. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997.

    Cornell, D., ed.  Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice. New York:

    Routledge, 1992.

    Critchley, S. “A Dedication to Jacques Derrida-Memoirs.” German Law

    Journal, 6  (1), 2005.

    Derrida, Jacques. Psyche: Inventions of the Other. Translated by P. Kamuf,

    et al. Stanford, California:Stanford University Press, 2008.

     ________. Rogues: Two Essays on Reason. Translated by P. A. Brault, & M.

    Naas. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005.

     ________. Eyes of the University: Right to Philosophy 2. Translated by J.

    Plug, et al. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004.

     ________. Acts of Religion. Edited by G. Anidjar. New York: Routledge,

    2002.

     ________. On Hospitality: Anne Defourmantelle Invites Jacques Derrida to

     Respond. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2000.

     ________. The Ethics of Deconstruction: Derrida and Levinas. West Lafayette:

    Purdue University Press, 1999.

     ________. Politics of Friendship.  Translated by G. Collins. London and

    New York: Verso, 1997.

     ________. “ Is Derrida a Private Ironist or a Public Liberal?” In Deconstruction

    and Pragmatism, ed. C. Mouffe. Translated by S. Critchley. London:

    Routledge, 1996.

  • 8/17/2019 Hernandez Derrida Political Possibilities

    30/30

    M a j o r A r t i c l e s

    | M A B I N I R E V I E W94

     ________. “Remarks on Deconstruction and Pragmatism.” In

     Deconstruction and Pragmatism, ed. C. Mouffe. Translated by S. Critchley.London: Routledge, 1996.

     ________. The Gift of Death.  Translated by D. Willis. Chicago and

    London: The University of Chicago Press, 1995.

     ________. Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning,and

    the New International. Translated by P. Kamuf. New York: Routledge.

    1994.

     ________. Given Time I: Counterfeit Money.  Translated by P. Kamuf.Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1992.

     ________. The Force of Law: The Mystical Foundation of Authority.”

    In  Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice, ed.  D. Cornell. New

    York: Routledge, 1992.

     ________.  “Letter to a Japanese Friend.” In  Derrida and Différance .

    Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1988.

     ________. “Deconstruction and the Other.” In Dialogue with ContemporaryContinental Thinkers, ed. R. Kearney. Manchester: Manchester

    University Press, 1984.

     ________. Derrida, J. “The Principle of Reason: The University in the

    Eyes of its Pupils.” Diacritics  (13), 13-20, 1983.

     ________. Margins of Philosophy.  Translated by A. Bass. Chicago:

    University of Chicago Press,1982.

     ________. Of Grammatology.  Translated by G. C. Spivak. Baltimore:Johns Hopkins University Press, 1976.

    Hoffman, F. “Epilogue: In Lieu of Conclusion.” German Law Journal, 6  

    (1), 2005.

    Levinas, E. Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. Translated by A.

    Lingis. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1969.

    Rorty, R. “Some Remarks on Deconstruction and Pragmatism.”

    In  Deconstruction and Pragmatism, ed. C. Mouffe. Translated by S.Critchley. London: Routledge, 1996.