infinite games and analytic sets

3
Infinite Games and Analytic Sets Author(s): David Blackwell Source: Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, Vol. 58, No. 5 (Nov. 15, 1967), pp. 1836-1837 Published by: National Academy of Sciences Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/58114 . Accessed: 08/05/2014 11:46 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . National Academy of Sciences is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 11:46:34 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Upload: david-blackwell

Post on 08-Jan-2017

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Infinite Games and Analytic Sets

Infinite Games and Analytic SetsAuthor(s): David BlackwellSource: Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America,Vol. 58, No. 5 (Nov. 15, 1967), pp. 1836-1837Published by: National Academy of SciencesStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/58114 .

Accessed: 08/05/2014 11:46

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

National Academy of Sciences is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access toProceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 11:46:34 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 2: Infinite Games and Analytic Sets

INFINITE GAMES AND ANALYTIC SETS* BY DAVID BLACKWELL

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY

Communicated September 21, 1967

We show in this note that Kuratowski's coreduction principle for analytic sets" 3 is a consequence of a theorem of Gale and Stewart2 on infinite games of perfect in- formation.

A subset A of a complete separable metric space Y is analytic if there is a continu- ous function f from Q to Y with A = fQ where Q is the space of infinite sequences of positive integers.

Kuratowski's coreduction principle asserts that (1) If A,B are analytic subsets of Y, there are analytic sets A,,B1 such that

(a) AlDA,B,DB, (b) A1 U B,= Y, (c) A, nB1 =AnB.

To obtain (1) from the result of Gale and Stewart, let A = fU, B = go, where f,g are continuous, and for any finite sequence x = (n,, . . ., nQ) of positive integers, denote by Q(x) the set of all co E& Q with x as initial segment, and by R(x), S(x) the closures of fQ(x), gg(x), respectively.

We associate with each y E Y a game G(y) with two players, a and A3, played as follows. The players alternately choose positive integers, a choosing first, each choice made with complete information about previous choices. A play

T = (ml,nl,m2,n2, ... )

will be called a win for a (in G(y)) if there is a positive integer k for which y C R (ml, ... X mO) y (Z S(n,, . ., nk); a win for /3 if there is a positive integer k for which y C S(n,, ..., nk-1), y X R(ml, . . ., M,O), and a draw if for every positive integer k,

y C R(ml, ..., nMk) and y C S(n,, ..., nk).

Informally, a is trying to produce an X = (mi, M2, . . . ) with f(w) = y, and A is trying to produce an co = (n,, n2, ... ) with g(c) = y. The first player to fail drastically, in the sense of producing a finite sequence x for which y is not even in the closure of the image of the set of w consistent with x, loses. If neither ever fails drastically, so that, as is easily checked, both succeed, the game is a draw.

Denote by A, the set of y such that a can force a draw or better in G(y), and by B, the set of y such that A can force a draw or better in G(y). Then A,,Bl have the properties asserted in (1). We sketch the proof.

First, A, is analytic. For the set D of all pairs (y,o) such that 4 is a strategy for a that forces at least a draw in G(y) is a Borel set, and Al is its projection on Y. Similarly, B, is analytic.

Second, A, v A, for if y C A, there is an w = (Mi,M2, ...) with f(w) = y. So a, by playing Mi,12, ..., never drastically fails, so secures at least a draw. Similarly, B, D B.

Third, A, U B, = Y, for the set Q of plays r that win for a in G(y) is open, so

1836

This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 11:46:34 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 3: Infinite Games and Analytic Sets

VoL. 58, 1967 MATHEMATICS: D. BLACKWELL 1837

that, according to the Gale-Stewart theorem, either a can force ir E Q, so that y C A1, or 0 can force ir - Q?, so that y C B1.

Finally, A1 f B1 = A n B, for if y C A1 f B1, either player can force a draw or better in G(y). If both do this, the resulting play

7 = (mi,ni, m2,n2, . .)

is a draw. Then

y = f(ml,m2, ... ) = g(n1,n2, ... ), so that y C AfnB. * Research sponsored by the U.S. Air Force Office of Scientific Research, Office of Aerospace

Research, under AFOSR grant 1312-67. 1 Addison, J. W., "Separation principles in the hierarchies of classical and effective descriptive

set theory," Fund. Math., 46, 123-135 (1958). 2 Gale, D., and F. M. Stewart, "Infinite games with perfect information," Ann. Math. Studies,

28, 245-266 (1953). 3 Kuratowski, K., "Sur les th6or4mes de s6paration dans la theorie des ensembles," Fund. Math.,

26, 183-191 (1936).

This content downloaded from 169.229.32.137 on Thu, 8 May 2014 11:46:34 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions