introduction - mathematical association of america

24
1 The Instructor's Important Role in Supporting Mathematical Arguments in a K-5 Mathematics Specialist Program Joy Whitenack Laurie Cavey Aimee Ellington Virginia Commonwealth University James Madison University Virginia Commonwealth University [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Introduction Researchers have provided many examples of what it means to teach mathematics using an inquiry approach. This body of work addresses how student learning can be positively influenced when they have opportunities to explain and justify ideas, listen to others’ explanations, ask clarifying questions when they do not understand classmates’ ideas, represent their ideas using self-invented methods, engage in challenging problem solving activities, and so on (e.g., Ball & Bass, 2003; Cobb, Wood, Yackel, 1992; Hiebert et al., 1997; Lampert, 1990; Rasmussen & Marrongelle, 2006; Whitenack & Knipping, 2002; Yackel & Cobb, 1997). Further, these reports often highlight the fact that although teachers continue to facilitate discussions, the nature of these discussions is markedly different from those that take place in traditional mathematics classrooms. Teachers in inquiry classrooms ask different types of questions and highlight students’ contributions for different purposes (Ball, 1993; Ball & Bass, 2003; Yackel & Cobb, 1997). Additionally, teachers in these types of classrooms take great care choosing representations, using students’ ideas as starting points for advancing these discussions or capitalizing on ideas that underpin their students’ strategies and methods. Often in these types of classrooms, the teacher must be sensitive to students’ incomplete ideas and more informal methods and make decisions about how to use those ideas as the basis for exploring more formal ideas or practices that fit with the mathematical practices in the broader community (Ball, 1993; Ball & Bass, 2003; Yackel, 2002). Yackel (2002) has continued to address the role of explanation and justification in her more recent work. She and her colleagues have provided new insights into how teachers (elementary

Upload: others

Post on 01-Apr-2022

3 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

1

The Instructor's Important Role in Supporting Mathematical Arguments in a K-5 Mathematics Specialist Program

Joy Whitenack Laurie Cavey Aimee Ellington Virginia Commonwealth University James Madison University Virginia Commonwealth University [email protected] [email protected] [email protected]

Introduction

Researchers have provided many examples of what it means to teach mathematics using an

inquiry approach. This body of work addresses how student learning can be positively influenced

when they have opportunities to explain and justify ideas, listen to others’ explanations, ask clarifying

questions when they do not understand classmates’ ideas, represent their ideas using self-invented

methods, engage in challenging problem solving activities, and so on (e.g., Ball & Bass, 2003; Cobb,

Wood, Yackel, 1992; Hiebert et al., 1997; Lampert, 1990; Rasmussen & Marrongelle, 2006;

Whitenack & Knipping, 2002; Yackel & Cobb, 1997). Further, these reports often highlight the fact

that although teachers continue to facilitate discussions, the nature of these discussions is markedly

different from those that take place in traditional mathematics classrooms. Teachers in inquiry

classrooms ask different types of questions and highlight students’ contributions for different

purposes (Ball, 1993; Ball & Bass, 2003; Yackel & Cobb, 1997). Additionally, teachers in these

types of classrooms take great care choosing representations, using students’ ideas as starting points

for advancing these discussions or capitalizing on ideas that underpin their students’ strategies and

methods. Often in these types of classrooms, the teacher must be sensitive to students’ incomplete

ideas and more informal methods and make decisions about how to use those ideas as the basis for

exploring more formal ideas or practices that fit with the mathematical practices in the broader

community (Ball, 1993; Ball & Bass, 2003; Yackel, 2002).

Yackel (2002) has continued to address the role of explanation and justification in her more

recent work. She and her colleagues have provided new insights into how teachers (elementary

2

school teachers and university instructors) support the development of mathematical arguments

during whole class discussions (e.g., Stephan & Rasmussen , 2002; Whitenack & Knipping, 2002).

Yackel, for instance, analyzed part of a university differential equations lesson to illustrate how a

university instructor and his students established the plausibility of arguments about predator-prey

problems. She argued that in this university classroom, the instructor focused discussions on

“developing and supporting arguments for claims that were put forth but not on making claims per se”

(p. 427). Once a claim was made, the instructor redirected the conversation so that students could

explain and justify ideas. In fact, it was normative for the instructor and students to engage in these

types of whole class discussions as they established plausible arguments. The instructor’s role was

important because he could direct the discussion so that students had opportunities to support claims

using their understandings of the mathematical ideas at hand.

In our discussion we, too, address the instructor’s role by highlighting one university course

instructor’s proactive role in establishing and maintaining normative practices for making

mathematical arguments. Here, we make a case for how teachers’ explanations and justifications in

two different mathematics courses in a K-5 Mathematics Specialist program contributed in part to the

mathematical arguments that were established during whole class discussions. To accomplish our

task, we use examples from one lesson in an Algebra and Functions course and one lesson in a

Rational Number and Proportional Reasoning course that are core courses in this endorsement

program.

Following Yackel (2002), we use Krummheuer’s (1995) ethnography of argumentation as an

interpretive framework to reconstruct mathematical arguments in these two lessons. We use examples

from the algebra lesson to illustrate how the instructor facilitated a discussion in which he coordinated

two ensuing arguments. We use examples from the rational number lesson to illustrate how

Krummheuer’s framework can be used to hypothesize how the instructor could use a substantial

3

argument as a starting point for engaging the teachers in proof making. By providing these two

different types of analyses, we illustrate how this interpretive lens might be used to explicate the types

of possible learning opportunities that occurred as teachers engaged in whole class discussions. We

also illustrate the utility of conducting these types of analyses.

Theoretical Considerations

Krummheuer argues that by coordinating constructs associated with argumentation with

ethnomethodology and interactionism, the researcher can understand the structure of an argument as

well as how it is constituted and reconstituted by the participants during an ensuing whole class

discussion. Argumentation as it unfolds in the classroom then is a social phenomenon; it has all the

features that are usually ascribed to classroom discussions and other normative practices associated

with face-to-face interactions. As Krummheuer (1995) states,

Because of the emergent nature of social interaction, argumentations are usually accomplished by several participants. Such a case is called a collective argumentation…In addition, the development of a (collective) argumentation does not need to proceed in a harmonious way. Disputes in parts of an argumentation might arise that could lead to corrections, modifications, retractions, and replacements…The result of this process can be reconstructed and is called an argument. (p. 232)

So argumentation can be used as a way to describe ordinary classroom activity (Krummheuer, 1995).

When part or an entire whole class discussion is reconstructed, in this way, we can develop a scheme

of sorts that structures key parts of the discussion or argument that unfolded.

The model for an argument is comprised of four components: conclusion, data, warrant, and

backing. These components comprise an argumentation, of which the conclusion, data and warrant

make up the core of the argument (Krummheuer, 1995). In addition, in some cases, the

argumentation must be reconstructed if, for instance, the data is invalid or is doubted by one’s

classmates. In this case, the participant must provide different data to support her conclusion. By

way of contrast, if a classmate agrees with the conclusion but does not directly see the relationship

between the data and the conclusion, the participant may be asked to provide additional information

4

that warrants and/or provides backing to support her claims. In the second case, the participant need

not develop a new conclusion-data pairing, but instead, she is obliged to provide evidence to support

the conclusion that further clarifies the warrant. The result of this argumentative process is a

mathematical argument that is socially constructed by the participants. As Krummheuer notes, a

mathematical argument is the result of an argumentation. At times, an argument is part of a complex

argumentation. Arguments can be embedded in other argumentations. This last point is particularly

relevant to our discussion. One of our aims is to understand how the instructor facilitated a discussion

in which several arguments surface and become part of a complex argument.

Another feature of Krummheuer’s (1995) and Toulmin’s (1969) theory relates to that of

distinguishing among different types of arguments. Typically when one makes a mathematical

argument, we are inclined to consider whether this argument aligns with the rules of logic that are

often used to describe the work of mathematicians or those engaging in proof making. Krummheuer,

following Toulmin, suggests that one need not characterize (or evaluate) an argument using the rules

of deduction. For Krummheuer, an argumentation is socially accomplished as each participant tries to

adjust his intentions to the contributions made by others. As a participant explains or justifies his

ideas, the “meaning of the premise increases or changes” (p. 236). To distinguish this type of

argument from the more traditional view of arguments, Toulmin and Krummheuer suggest that

arguments can be either analytic or substantial. Analytic arguments are those that are made using the

rule of deductive reasoning. Substantial arguments, by way of contrast, are arguments that are not

held to tautological requirements. Contributions of this kind would not likely be part of an analytic

argument, but could lead to a substantive argument. This said, outlining a substantive argument has

merit in its own right. One can reconstruct an argument, and in doing so, develop a better

understanding of the particular mathematical practices that emerge during whole class discussions

(Stephan & Rasmussen, 2002).

5

So how might an interactionist perspective fit within this theory of argumentation? Here we

draw on several recent works that have made use of a coordinated framework. In Yackel’s (2002)

retrospective analysis across teaching experiments, she draws on Krummheuer’s (1995) work to

extend normative practices to provide insight into the elementary teacher’s and university instructor’s

roles in supporting the evolution of mathematical arguments. With regard to argumentation, we

specifically focus our analysis around the instructor’s role in facilitating and guiding the discussions

as teachers explain and justify claims that they make. Like Yackel (2002), the focus of our discussion

is around the process by which claims are substantiated rather than the process of developing or

constituting a viable claim. Additionally, we draw on Yackel’s ideas about when and for what

purposes that teacher might contribute to an ensuing argumentation. In particular, does the instructor

offer contributions in the form of warrants or backings when the teachers make omissions? Are there

other situations in which the instructor might be obliged to make contributions?

We also draw on the work of Stephan and Rasmussen (2002) to further clarify the extent to

which these ensuing argumentations become taken as shared. Stephan and Rasmussen offer two

conditions that signal whether or not an argument is in fact agreed upon by the participants. They

state,

We contend that mathematical ideas become taken-as-shared when either (1) the backings and/or warrants for an argumentation no longer appear in students’ explanations and therefore the mathematical idea expressed in the core of the argument stands as self-evident, or (2) any of the four parts of an argument (data, warrant, claim, backing) shift position (i.e., function) within subsequent arguments and are unchallenged. (p. 462)

So if the participants, as in our case, teachers and the instructor do not challenge supports for a data-

conclusion pairing, we might infer that they have reached a consensus about the idea under

consideration. Additionally, if part of an argument is used for a subsequent argument, we can also

presume that the participants have established a shared understanding about an idea.

6

Our hope is that as we conduct these analyses, we contribute to the continuing conversation

about what might be possible when mathematics instruction aligns with reform efforts in the

university mathematics classroom. Additionally, we offer an account of how the instructor might

facilitate discourse that takes seriously teachers’ important role in making mathematical arguments.

Methodological Considerations

Our examples are taken from two different whole class discussions, one in an algebra course

and one in a rational number and proportional reasoning course. These two courses are part of a 3-

year graduate degree program designed to prepare teachers to become K-5 Mathematics Specialists.

The rational number and proportional reasoning course is the third course in the sequence; the algebra

course is the fifth and final mathematics course in the program.

Course participants entered the program with a range of experiences. Some had several years

of teaching experience whereas others had taught fifteen or more years. About one-third of the

participants were already serving in some type of leadership role in their school buildings. The

instructor who led both of these two whole class discussions, Instructor, is a research mathematician

who has been actively involved in providing professional development opportunities for teachers for

over 20 years. The courses were the second and the third courses for which he had served as the

primary instructor in the mathematics specialist program for the same cohort of teachers. As such,

over time, he and the teachers had established a rapport in which they had mutual respect for one

another.

Instructor regularly used the teachers’ contributions to facilitate discussions. He encouraged

teachers to represent their ideas, even if their ideas were partially complete as they supported claims

or if they were not certain of the correctness of their answer. As teachers did so, Instructor, for his

part, highlighted ideas, asked clarifying questions, and so on. As a consequence, Instructor and the

teachers together established that teachers’ ideas were particularly valued. More generally, using

7

constructs related to argumentation, by engaging in these types of discussions, teachers developed

arguments as they provided warrants and backings to support the claims that they made. Instructor,

for his part, also played an important role in what and how contributions were highlighted or used to

support the teachers’ claim. So norms for engaging in argumentation were the result of Instructor’s

and the teachers’ mutually orienting interactions during discussions (cf. Yackel, 2002).

The classroom data is taken from classroom data corpus that includes observation notes of the

lessons, videotape recordings of small group and whole class discussions, digital recordings of

participant interviews and small group discussions, digital photos of participants’ work during whole

class discussions and participants’ individual work. As we observed these and other lessons, we

noted if we needed to revisit particular lessons during our analysis process. We began our analysis

process by conducting a preliminary analysis of each lesson. As we did so we realized that we needed

to transcribe these two lessons to conduct a more thorough microanalysis of the entire lesson.

To conduct microanalyses, we first viewed the videotape and the transcription of the small group and

whole class discussions. As we watched the videotaped lesson, we identified the mathematical ideas

that surfaced and clarified each of the participant’s contributions. We then re-watched the lessons and

coded the participants’ contributions using argumentation constructs (data, conclusion, warrants and

backings).

Using Ethnography of Argumentation to Analyze Whole Class Discussions

We first use the framework to reconstruct two arguments that emerged in the algebra course

and how Instructor facilitated claims, warrants and backings that were simultaneously established as

evidential supports in both arguments. As we present our analysis from the algebra course, we will

also highlight when Instructor offered warrants or backings, and for what purposes (cf. Yackel, 2002).

Secondly, we use the framework use an example from the rational number course to illustrate how the

instructor might use a substantial argument to as an opportunity to introduce teachers to formal proof

8

making. In particular, we hypothesize how Instructor and the teachers might have developed a more

general argument for the density property of the rational numbers.

The Algebra Lesson

To illustrate how we might use this interpretive lens, we reconstruct part of a whole-class

discussion as the participants discussed the following task: Explain what happens to [r + s + (1/s)]

as s increases from some very small positive number (e.g., 0.001) to some very large positive number

(e.g., 1,000) (Schifter, et al., 2008). Previously Instructor and the teachers had made arguments for

why r/s decreased as s increased as well as why 1/s approached 0 as s increased. We refer to the

former as Argument 1 and the latter as Argument 2.

As the discussion continued participants established yet a third argument, Argument 3.

Previously, Teacher B and Teacher C provided the conclusion and data pairing for this new argument:

r + s + 1/s increased because 1/s approached 0. Neither gave specific examples to support this claim,

however Teacher C stated that she had developed a table of values that became larger as she

substituted larger values for s. After Teacher C gave her explanation, Instructor provided specific

pieces of data when he asked the whole class what would happen if s changed from 10 to 11 and then

from 987 to 988. Teachers explained that the values would increase. So at this point in the

discussion, Instructor and the teachers developed the claim and several pieces of data that supported

the claim for Argument 3.

Immediately following this interchange, Ms. Satterfield, one of the case study participants,

made a statement that might be interpreted as a challenge to the conclusion for Argument 3. She

stated that she thought that r + s + 1/s actually decreased, that is, for larger values of s, r + s + 1/s

approached r + s. We enter the discussion as Ms. Satterfield continued to explain her ideas. (Note:

Ms. Satterfield is Ms. S.)

9

Ms. S: Well maybe I’m confused because I looked at it like as s increases, even though you are adding more with s you know that 1/s is going to approach 0 so that the expression itself is going to approach r + s. So it’s not going to continue to increase; I put it is going to decrease—approach r + s. You know I guess I was thinking about it differently than just the value increases or decreases. Does that make sense?

At this point, Ms. Satterfield provided a different explanation for what happened to the values of r + s

+ 1/s. She in fact actually stated a different conclusion-data pairing—as r + s + 1/s increased it

approached r + s because 1/s approached 0. How might Instructor address Ms. Satterfield’s ideas?

Would he interpret her ideas as a challenge to Argument 3, or as a new argument, and so on? As the

discussion continued, notice how he incorporated her ideas into the ensuing argument.

Instructor: Why don’t you draw it? Ms. S: I don’t think I can draw it, is the problem.

Teacher: Sure you can. Ms. S: I don’t know what I would draw.

Instructor: Well, how about we let r be 2? Ms. S: Okay.

Instructor: Why did I say 2? I just picked a number, that’s all…You can’t draw it if you don’t know what the numbers are so let’s let r be some…They said it had to be positive, so let it be 2.

Ms. S: Okay.

As we see, Instructor asked Ms. Satterfield to make a drawing to support her ideas. When she stated

that she was not sure how to make a drawing, Instructor assured her that she could do so and

suggested how she might begin—by letting r be 2. His suggestion about fixing r was important; it

made it possible for Ms. Satterfield to generate supports in this case, a table of values for r + s + 1/s.

As Instructor asked Ms. Satterfield to provide supports in the form of possible warrants, it is

not clear at this juncture whether her table of values supported her new claim or the current claim for

Argument 3. As we continue with our analysis, it will be important to determine how Instructor

draws on Ms. Satterfield’s ideas to support either or both claims.

10

We return to the discussion after Ms. Satterfield had derived these two values. We re-enter the

discussion as she commented that the values decreased for smaller and smaller positive values of s.

Ms. S: See I’m saying that once you get to these really large numbers that 1/s isn’t …I mean I guess maybe I’m saying it’s increasing but to me, I guess, okay, I see what I’m saying. We are kind of saying the same thing now. Where I said it decreases to approach r +s (covers 1/s with her hand), rather than saying it increases…

Notice that once Ms. Satterfield provided two different values for s, she realized that the table

of values supported the claim that r + s + 1/s increases for larger and larger values of s. At the same

time, she continued to argue that the values could be used to show that r + s + 1/s approached r + s.

So, in a sense, Ms. Satterfield provided an explanation that might serve as support for Argument 3 and

her new claim.

It remains to be seen if Ms. Satterfield’s new claim, what we will tentatively call, Argument 4,

will become a mathematical argument for to r + s + 1/s. To better understand if Argument 4 is

established as yet another argument for r + s + 1/s, we return to the ensuing discussion. As the

discussion proceeded, Ms. Satterfield inserted a few more values and then referred to the table of

values as she continued to explain her ideas. We reenter the discussion as she and another teacher,

Teacher E refer to the table as they restate the claim for Argument 4.

Ms. S: (Calculates .01 and .001 for s.) So to me, I guess…I guess I didn’t look at it like now it’s decreasing and then it’s going to increase (moves her hand over the values in the chart). I looked at it like it’s going to decrease until it gets to the point where essentially the answer is going to be r + s (draws a box around 2 + 1,000 and 1,002 and r + s on the chart paper) and then if you keep going the more and more. Even though it may be increasing, it’s really just approaching whatever the value of r plus s is.

Teacher E: But it doesn’t really get to r + s because of the extra small piece, 1/s. Ms. S: Yes.

Here Ms. Satterfield referred to the table of values to explain how she had thought about r + s + 1/s.

She not only argued that this expression increased for larger values of s, but also she argued what

value it approximately increased to, r + s. The fact that she highlighted this idea when she drew a box

11

around specific values provides further support for this interpretation. Teacher E also contributed in

part to this discussion. So at this juncture, Ms. Satterfield’s table of values also served as data for

Argument 4.

As the discussion continued, note how Instructor addressed the teachers’ new ideas.

Instructor: So the expression does keep increasing right? As s gets bigger, the whole expression, what happens to it?

Ms. S: Yeah, well yeah… Teacher F: It increases if s is greater than 1.

Instructor: Yeah, we’re talking about bigger than 1 still, right? When s is bigger than 1, okay as s gets bigger the whole expression keeps getting bigger. But you are saying something about the way it is getting bigger, is changing.

As the discussion proceeded Instructor continued to refer to the table as providing support for

Argument 3. His question, “So the expression does keep increasing, right?” is evidence of this fact.

After making this statement, he too indicated how the table of values also related to her new claim.

He did so by explaining to the class that Ms. Satterfield also provided supportive evidence for the

“way it is getting bigger is changing.” So at this point in the discussion, Instructor and several

teachers provided data for Argument 4. Following this line of analysis, then Teacher E’s early

comment, “But it doesn’t really get to r + s because of the extra small piece, 1/s.” provided additional

support for that further clarifies why the function can only approach r + s. As a consequence we

interpret her comment to serve as a warrant for this new data-conclusion pairing. At the same time,

Instructor and Ms. Satterfield also explained how the table of values supported Argument 3.

So what was Instructor’s role during this part of the discussion? How did he facilitate the

discussion about both claims? From above we note that he was able to highlight ideas that might

serve as data or warrants for both arguments by pointing out how Ms. Satterfield’s ideas were related

to the different mathematical ideas. He also supported her as she constructed the table of values.

First he suggested a way to begin to construct the table of values. Secondly, as the table of values was

constructed, he asked specific questions about values in the table that might highlight ideas that could

12

be used to support both claims. By doing so, he could support Ms. Satterfield’s argument about

convergence and at the same time continue to facilitate a discussion about Argument 3.

To summarize briefly what has happened up to this point, we refer you to Figures 1 and 2. As

Argument 3 emerged, Ms. Satterfield offered yet a fourth argument. Instructor’s role during this part

of the discussion was that of asking teachers to provide examples that further supported the claim

about what happens to r + s + 1/s as s increases. As he made suggestions for what value to assign r,

he helped to launch a discussion in which teachers offered support for Argument 3 as well as

Argument 4. So his role was that of making explicit teachers’ ideas so that these ideas might serve as

evidential support for the claims that they made. Note in the diagram that we have also inserted

Argument 2 as data for Argument 3. Elsewhere we have explained that Argument 3 is a complex

argument, that is Argument 1 is nested inside of Argument 2 and is data for Argument 3 (Whitenack,

Ellington & Cavey, 2009).

As Instructor continued to facilitate this part of the whole class discussion, Teacher E

constructed a graph that provided additional information to support her and Ms. Satterfield’s ideas for

both arguments. By doing so, Teacher E and Instructor provided explanations that might function as

argumentative supports, in this case warrants and backings, for both Argument 3 and Argument 4.

Interestingly, as this discussion proceeded, Teacher E’s backings in Argument 3 were augmented to

that of warrants in Argument 4. So, her graph of the expression supported Ms. Satterfield’s table of

values but in different ways in both arguments. In Figure 1 and Figure 2, we insert these

contributions as warrants or backings to further build the scheme for both arguments. Whereas the

initial claims and data are different, notice that Ms. Satterfield’s and Teacher E’s explanations

supported both arguments.

13

Figure 1 Schematic Representation for Argument 3

On account of

Because

So

Since

Whether you add a large value or a small value, the expression is increasing.

Teacher D’s Warrant

Conclusion

As s increases starting at one whole then the value [r + s + 1/s] increases but as s decreases from 1 the value goes up, also increases.

I substituted values for r & s and made a table of them. Teacher C’s Data

Data

Teachers: The values are going down. [Referring to the 1st three rows of Ms. Satterfield’s table to the right.]

Teachers’ Data

Instructor & Teacher B’s Data

Instructor: For the part where s is bigger than 1, if s goes from 10 to 11 what happens to r + s + 1/s? How much does it increase by?

Teacher B: One?

Instructor: About 1? Why not exactly 1?

Teacher B: Because of the fraction.

Instructor: Because you have that 1/10 thing.

Instructor: If s went from 987 to 988 what would happen to the expression?

Teacher B: About 1 again.

Instructor: Increase about 1 except that tiny little part.

Ms. Satterfield’s Warrant

Instructor: How about we let r be 2?

Now it’s decreasing and then it’s going to increase.

[Motioning down the table of values listed above] The same change occurs just over a smaller space for s values between 0 and 1 compared to s values in the larger space between 1 and 1000.

Look at a tenth [points to (0.1, 12.01)] and ten [points to (10, 12.1)].

Teacher E’s Backings

14

Figure 2. Schematic Representation for Argument 4

It starts getting flatter because it involves 1/s and those values start to get really small.

The curve eventually goes straight or gets close to the line r + s. Teacher E’s Warrants

It doesn’t just increase, it decreases until it approaches this [points to 2 + 1000 in the table presented above].

Ms. Satterfield’s Warrant

It [r + s + 1/s] stops getting bigger in a big way. Ms. Smith’s Backing

[Adds the coordinates (0.001, 1002.01) and (1000, 1002.01) to the graph above.] The same change happens this way [motioning up and down in the area between x = 0 & x = 1] but it takes larger space in this direction to get there [motioning from the point (1, 4) to the right along the x-axis]. Teacher E’s Backings

On account of

Because

So

Since

Argument 2

Data

It never gets [to the value of r + s] because there is always a little extra.

Teacher F’s Data

Ms. Satterfield’s Data

Instructor: How about we let r be 2?

Ms. Satterfield: Because 1/s approaches 0

The expression itself [r + s + 1/s] is going to decrease to approach r + s.

Conclusion

15

The Rational Number Lesson

For our second example, we use part of a whole class discussion in which teachers shared their

methods for finding rational numbers between 1/11 and 1/10. Here we briefly outline strategies that

two small groups shared. (See Whitenack, Cavey, & Ellington (2009) for a full description.)

Group 1’s method. Previously Teacher G from Group 1 explained that 95/1000 and 99/1000

(or 0.095 and 0.099) were two rational numbers between 1/11 and 1/10. She and her group members

explained that 0.095 (or 19/220) made sense because they had used a similar method (converting the

fractions decimal form) to show that 21/220 was a rational number between 1/10 and 1/9—one of

their homework problems. After Teacher G explained, Instructor made a more general statement

about their ideas:

There’s lots of rational numbers between 1/11 and 1/10, and the one you found was 95/1000, and I didn’t say whether or not I would care if it was in lowest form, but you felt better about making it be that way. I think [rewriting the fraction as] two-hundredths gives you a little more sense of it, yeah?

As he redescribed their ideas, he also restated a claim that might serve as a claim for this potential

argument, what we will call Argument 5.

As the discussion continued, several groups offered explanations that also supported this

claim. As they did so, they provided several different sets of warrants for data that supported this

more general claim—there are an infinite number of rational numbers between 1/11 and 1/10. In the

rest of this section, as we briefly outline the ensuing argument, we illustrate how this substantial

argument for the density property was collectively established.

After Teacher G explained her group’s ideas, Ms. Sneider, without prompting, stated that she

could find other decimals (rational numbers) between these two numbers. As she did so, she too

provided supports for Argument 5. We enter the discussion as she explains her ideas:

Ms. Sneider: Now I am just looking at the 0 in the 1000th place in .0909? And now so the decimal between is .095 so it went from 0 to 5… You could also just have a 1 there, or a 2 or 3 or 4.

16

Group 1: Yes, there are an infinite number! Ms. Sneider: …91/1000, 92/1000, 93/1000, 96/1000, 97/1000

Instructor: Yes. Ms. Sneider: But it also helps me to think of whole numbers. Say if I’m looking at the 9 and

the 0 in the 100ths and 1000th s place, I think of 90, and another 90, then 91, 92, 93…

Group 1: Yes. Ms. Sneider: I think of that just for a split second to get…to solidify my thinking.

Here Ms. Sneider built on Group 1’s claim by providing further support, in this case in the form of

warrants, for Argument 5. It is as if she indicated that not only did their explanation make sense, but

also she could find other rational numbers that satisfied this claim by simply manipulating the 1000ths

digit. In fact, as her comment suggests, she could make a similar argument for finding other three-

digit decimals, in this case .091, .092, .093 and .094, that were between .0909 repeating and 0.10.

Applying Krummuheur’s (1995) scheme, we can state this new data-conclusion pairing as

follows: There are an infinite number of rational numbers between 1/11 and 1/10 because.0909

repeating < .091 < .095 and .0909 repeating < .092 < .095. Ms. Sneider’s comments related to the

fraction equivalents for 3-digit decimals between 1/11 and 1/10 are also data that support the

conclusion. In addition, we can place her comment about whole numbers inside the scheme. Recall

that she explained how she thought of these decimals in much of the same way that she thought about

whole numbers. These comments seem to support why she could find the next larger or smaller

rational number. For this reason, her second comment served as a warrant for the data-conclusion

pairing.

We now return to the ensuing discussion as another group, Group 2 explained their method for

finding numbers between two rational numbers. As they presented their strategy, they used an open

numberline to illustrate how they simplified a complex rational number. Instructor, too, played an

17

important role during this discussion as he highlighted aspects of their thinking by referring to how

one could use fraction strips to illustrate their strategy.

Group 2’s method. Group 2 first explained that they converted 1/11 and 1/10 to the equivalent

fractions, 10/110 and 11/110. They then commented that they were not sure how to proceed once

they had these equivalences. We rejoin the discussion as Instructor, in response to Group 2’s

comment, directed a question to the whole class about using fraction strips to represent 10/110 and

11/110:

Instructor: (To Group 2) Before you go any further there…(To the whole class) if you have one of these fraction strips, how many pieces would fold it up into now?

Participants: 110. Instructor: 110 pieces. Can you go from actually folding 8 or folding 12, to actually

thinking in your mind [about making] 110 folds? I’m not that good. But I kind of think it’s as if I had folded 12 times. It’s the same idea [here]. So it’s folded into 110 little pieces.

As the discussion continued, Group 2 provided additional information about these equivalences.

Group 2: 10 ½ /110 was the rational number we found, but this expression does not make sense in its current form.

As the discussion continued, Group 2 then explained how they resolved this issue of working with

complex rational numbers as they spoke with one of the visiting instructors, Instructor 2:

Group 2: Instructor 2 visited our group and discussed this issue with us. He asked us to think about how we could represent 10 ½ /110 if we folded fraction strips. (Draws a number line and marked 10/110 and 11/110 on the number line and marks off the distance halfway between these two numbers to show where 10½ /110 was located on this number line.) So we folded the paper again and found another name for 10 ½ /110—21/220! (Records that they multiplied both fractional parts by 2 to derive 21/220.)

In the above discussion, as Group 2 explained how they found another rational number between 1/11

and 1/10 using a common denominator strategy, they provided new pieces of data that supported the

conclusion, 1/11 = 10/110, 1/10 = 11/110, and 10 ½ /110 = 21/220. To convince the class that 10 ½

/110 was between the two given numbers, they used an open number line to draw the interval between

1/11 and 1/10 and marked the halfway point in this interval where 10 ½ /110 was located. As they did

18

so, they provided additional information about 10 ½ /110, precisely where it was located between

these two rational numbers. For this reason, their drawing served as a warrant because it provided

information about the position of 10 1/2 /110—it was halfway between the two given numbers. Their

explanation for how they derived 21/220, by imagining folding the fraction strip, was also a warrant

because it further explained why 21/220 (or 10 ½ /110) was halfway between 1/11 and 1/10.

As the discussion continued, Instructor asked Group 2 to explain their answer, 21/220.

Instructor: Wait one second. You folded it in half… Group 2: (Paraphrased.) We have 220 parts instead of 110 parts.

Instructor: 220 pieces, right? So you folded it one more time, every one of those 110 pieces is gonna be in half. And that would be how many?

Here as Instructor prompted Group 2 to further explain their strategy, they gave additional

information about the 220—by repeatedly halving (or making half-folds), they could partition the

strips into 220 instead of 110 equal parts. Instructor, too, offered additional information as he

referred to folding (or imagining folding) the fraction strip. As he did so, he explained what happened

when one folded an interval that was already divided into 110 parts. If each of these pieces were

folded again, one would partition the unit interval into 220 pieces. So at this point, he, too, offered

additional information that supported the warrant that Group 2 had provided. As such, both Group 2

and Instructor provided backings for the warrants.

In retrospect, we can see how the argumentation established by Group 2 and Instructor

provides additional data for the claim—there are an infinite number of rational numbers between 1/11

and 1/10. In this case, it one repeatedly makes half-folds using a fraction strip, one will find more and

more numbers between 1/11 and 1/10. Although neither Instructor nor the teachers explicitly

indicated such, at this point in the discussion, the teachers along with Instructor have give several

explanations for finding rational numbers between 1/11 and 1/10. Put another way, they have

provided additional data and warrants (Ms. Sneider) that provide support for the general claim.

19

The discussion continued as other groups offered different methods for how they found

rational numbers between 1/11 and 1/10. (See Figure 3, on the next page, for a general outline of the

scheme for this argument.) Here we have illustrated only the first two groups’ explanations to

highlight the types of strategies that teachers developed. At the same time we have provided an

analysis using constructs associated with argumentation to illustrate how these arguments were

collectively accomplished. As we developed the argument, we did not imply that either the

participants or Instructor intended to develop this more general argument for a specific case of the

Real Numbers. Instead, using our interpretive lens, we have illustrated how Instructor and the

teachers collectively engaged in a discussion that we then recast as an ensuing argument. As we have

done so, we have highlighted the important but different roles that Instructor and the participants

played as they engaged in this argumentation.

20

Figure 3. Schematic Representation for the Rational Number Argument

I can choose a decimal between any two decimals.

I can find a fraction between any two fractions using the same numerator strategy.

I can find a fraction between any two fractions using the same denominator strategy.

I can find a fraction between any two fractions by comparing the difference using benchmarks.

There are an infinite number of fractions between 1/11 and 1/10.

data data data data

Because

Since

Since Since Since

On account of On account

of

On account of

On account of

warrant

warrant

warrant warrant

backing

backing backing

backing

So

21

From Substantial to Analytic Arguments

Although of the teachers’ strategies may not have been explicitly tied to the more general

claim, it is certainly possible that some of the teachers made these types of connections.

Retrospectively, it seems that it would have been feasible for Instructor to connect teachers’

explanations to the more general claim, if that had been his instructional intent. As a result, we

wonder, “How might Instructor have used the resulting substantial argumentation to facilitate a

discussion so that teachers could verify the more general claim?” In other words, “How might

Instructor use the substantial argumentation to establish an analytic argument for the general claim?”

Krummheuer (1995) indicated that a substantial argumentation becomes analytic when “the

whole information of the conclusion is already included in the backing” (p. 244). However, he also

cautioned about using ethnography of argumentation to make comparisons with some analytic ideal.

This is not what we are attempting to do. Rather, we are merely observing that the analysis of the

rational number and probability class discussion has allowed us to see something bigger than what

happened during the lesson. As a result, we wonder what Instructor might do if verifying the general

claim were actually his instructional goal.

For example, Instructor might decide to build off of any one of the groups’ explanations (and

strategies) to develop activities in which teachers explored proof making. Because of space

limitations, we will only highlight one hypothetical scenario. Suppose, for instance, Instructor posed

a task using Group 2’s common denominator strategy during a subsequent lesson. Let’s assume that

he challenged teachers to use Group 2’s strategy to find other rational numbers between 1/11 and

1/10. After they work in small groups to find others, he could reconvene the teachers for a whole

class discussion so that they could share the different numbers that they had found. As they did so, he

could record their ideas in the following table (see Table 1).

22

Table 1. Instructor makes a table of rational numbers that the teachers generated with each half-fold.

Number of half-folds Easy to identify rational numbers between

111 and

110

1 21/220 2 41/440, 42/440, 43/440 3 …

After filling in the table, Instructor might ask participants if they saw a pattern in the table.

The discussion might proceed as Instructor recorded the pattern in a new table (see Table 2).

Table 2. Instructor makes a record to count the number of rational numbers between each interval.

Number of half-folds Number of new rational numbers 1 1 2 2 3 4 4 8 5 ?

At this point, Instructor and the teachers might discuss how they could continue to insert new

values into Table 2 indefinitely. As such, Table 2 could serve as a record of infinitely many rational

numbers that could be identified between 1/11 and 1/10. So as they engaged in this type of

discussion, they would make a proof for the general claim using this specific case. Moreover, they

may also have the opportunity to count the number of rational numbers and even make a

generalization about the number of rational numbers for the nth row of the table. In Krummheuer’s

(1995) terms, Table 2 would thus serve as a backing that contained (and supported) warrants and the

conclusion for Argument 5, that is, it would become analytic.

Final Comments

The purpose of our discussion has been to better understand one instructor’s role in supporting

argumentation in a masters’ course for K-5 mathematics specialists. As we have done so, we have

also identified the kind of mathematical ideas and the possible learning opportunities that might have

23

surfaced during each lesson. As we have illustrated, teachers participated in different but important

ways as they engaged in these whole class discussions. Instructor was able to support teachers in

different ways as they explained their ideas. As he did so, he made it possible for teachers to

contribute to the discussion when and however they could. And when teachers offered more

sophisticated ideas, he was able to capitalize on their contributions so that others might have

opportunities to understand these ideas. So Instructor’s role during the discussion was particularly

important.

From a methodological standpoint, we have illustrated how one might use ethnography of

argumentation as an interpretive framework to understand the instructor’s role in supporting

mathematical arguments in different ways. In the first example, we used our lens to highlight the

complex ways in which the instructor might coordinate two (or more) arguments almost seamlessly

during the discussion. In our second example, we highlight how substantial arguments might be used

to provide opportunities for teachers to engage in formal proof making. As we did so, we illustrated

the utility of using ethnography of argumentation to help us better understand how participants can

collectively establish ways to reason mathematically that is couched in their understandings of the

ideas at hand.

By carefully examining Instructor’s role, we develop a deeper appreciation for the range of

decisions that instructors might make to support unfolding mathematical arguments. Instructor

listened to and supported the teachers’ ideas. At the same time he aligned their ideas with those that

fit with the mathematical practices of the mathematical community at large. By carefully balancing

these sometimes competing agendas (Ball, 1993), he and the teachers were able to contribute in part

to the rich ideas and the possible learning opportunities that may have surfaced during the lesson.

24

Acknowledgements The research reported in this paper is funded by the National Science Foundation, Grant No. EHR-0412324. The opinions expressed here are those of the authors and do not reflect the opinions of the funding institution.

References

Ball, D. L. (1993). With an eye on the mathematical horizon: Dilemmas of teaching elementary school mathematics. Elementary School Journal, 93(4), 373-397

Ball, D. L., & Bass, H. (2003). Making mathematics reasonable in school. In J. Kilpatrick, W. G. Martin, & D. Schifter (Eds.), A Research Companion to Principals and Standards for School Mathematics (pp. 27 – 44). Reston, VA: National Council of Teachers of Mathematics.

Cavey, L. O., Whitenack, J. W., & Lovin, L. (2007). Investigating teachers’ mathematics teaching and understanding: A case for coordinating perspectives. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 64(1), 19-43.

Cobb, P., Yackel, E., Wood, T. (1992). A constructivist alternative to the representational view of mind in mathematics education. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 23(1), 2-33.

Hiebert, Carpenter, T. P, Fennema, E., Fuson, K, Human, P., Murray, H., Olivier, A., and Wearne, D. (1997). Making mathematics problematic: A rejoinder to Prawat and Smith. Educational Researcher, 26, 24-26.

Krummheuer, G. (1995). The ethnography of argumentation. In P. Cobb & H. Bauersfeld (Eds.), The emergence of mathematical meaning: Interaction in classroom cultures (pp. 229-269). Hillsdale, NJ: Earlbaum.Lampert.

Lampert, M. (1990). When the problem is not the question and the answer is not the solution: Mathematical knowing and teaching. in the not the problem and the solution in not the answer. American Educational Research Journal, 27, 29-63.

Rasmussen, C., & Marrongelle, K. (2006). Pedagogical content tools: Integrating student reasoning and mathematics, Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 37, 388-420.

Stephan, M. & Rasmussen, C. (2002). Classroom mathematical practices in differential equations. Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 21, 459-490.

Schifter, D., Bastable, V., Russell, S. J., Monk, S., Kazemi, E., Fraley, C., & Stimpson, V. (2008). Developing mathematical ideas: Facilitator’s guide for reasoning algebraically about operations, Parsippany, NJ: Pearson Learning Group.

Toulmin, S. (1969). The Uses of Argument. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. Whitenack, J. W., Cavey, L. O., & Ellington, A. J. (2009). Argumentation and the role of proof

making in the preparation of K-5 mathematics specialists. Manuscript submitted for publication.

Whitenack, J. W., & Knipping, N. (2002). Argumentation, instructional design theory and students’ mathematical learning: A case for coordinating interpretive lenses. Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 21, 441-457.

Yackel, E., Cobb, P. (1996). Sociomathematical norms, argumentation, and autonomy in mathematics. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 27(4), 458-477.

Yackel, E. (2002). What we can learn from analyzing the teacher’s role in collective argumentation. Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 21(4), 423-440.