j. doyne farmer john geanakoplos

63
Hyperbolic Discounting is time consistent: Discounting the far future with uncertain discount rates 2009 1 J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Upload: graiden-hogan

Post on 02-Jan-2016

39 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Hyperbolic Discounting is time consistent: Discounting the far future with uncertain discount rates 2009. J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos. The Environment. How much should we do today to make the environment better in 200 years or 500 years? How to trade off the present vs the future? - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Hyperbolic Discounting is time consistent: Discounting the far future with uncertain

discount rates2009

•1

J. Doyne FarmerJohn Geanakoplos

Page 2: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

The Environment

• How much should we do today to make the environment better in 200 years or 500 years?

• How to trade off the present vs the future?• Economists all seem to agree we should

exponentially discount the future at some rate.

• Conservatives say 3% per year. Nordhaus.• Liberals say 0.5% per year (Stern report).

•2

Page 3: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Discounting the future• How does one compare something today with something

tomorrow?• How do we value something for current generations in

comparison with future generations?• Ramsay (1928): For consumption stream (x0,x1,x2,…)

• U(x) = u(x0) + D(1)u(x1) + D(2)u(x2) + … • Ramsay argued for D(t) = 1

– To discount later generations in favor of earlier ones is “ethically indefensible and arises merely from the weakness of the imagination”

– … it is “a polite expression for rapacity and the conquest of reason by passion” (Harrod, 1948)

– Reinterpret as consumption stream by same agent; get discounting.

•3

Page 4: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Reasons for Discounting

• Impatience: Fisher, Shakespeare• Probability of Death: Rae• Failure of imagination: Bohm-Bawerk

•4

Page 5: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Exponential discounting

• Standard approach in neoclassical economics is exponential discounting (Samuelson).

• = 1/(1+r0)τ

• Analogous to present value with constant bank interest rate r.– At time you would have– Discount for time is therefore

•5

D e r

er 1

money now

money latere r

er 1

Page 6: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Value of far future under exponential discounting?

• Under exponential discounting with realistic interest rates, the far future is not worth much

• E.g., with interest rate of 6%, 100 years out the discount factor is 0.0025.

• This is used by some economists to argue that we should put very little effort into coping with phenomena such as global warming that create problems in the far future.

•6

Page 7: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Copenhagen Consensus(eight leading economists, four Nobel prize winners)

•7

QuickTime™ and aTIFF (Uncompressed) decompressor

are needed to see this picture.Concerning global warming:“If we use a large discount rate, they will be judged to be small effects” (Robert Mendolson, criticizing an analysis by Cline using 1.5% discounting)

Bjorn Lomborg

Page 8: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Discounting of far future is very sensitive to the interest rate

•8

interest rate 10% 5% 1%discount factor 5 x 10-5 7 x 10-3 0.37

100 years into the future:

So how to pick the discount rate?

Page 9: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Market interest rates• We can see what the market interest rates are.• At the moment they are the lowest ever. • 1% per year for under a year, rising to 3% per year or so

in 10 years. Seems to stay thereafter.• But don’t have interest rates for beyond 30 years in

heavily traded markets. Most bonds of 30 year maturity or less.

• Some English consols. Also old railroad bonds. Trade for very low interest rates. Curiosity?

• Must make up rates beyond 30 years.

•9

Page 10: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Hyperbolic discounting

• Early D(t) goes down exponentially, but for large t, D(t) goes down slowly.

• D(t+1)/D(t) → 1.• The most commonly used functional form

with this property is

•10

D(t) (1t)

•α = 1, β = ½

•D(t) ≈ 1/√t

Page 11: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

•11

StrotzLaibsonLoewensteinAinslieAinslie-Hernnstein

Animals and Real People Are

Hyperbolic Discounters

Page 12: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

E.g. Thaler experiment

• How much money would you need in the future in lieu of $15 today?

•12

time amount discount interest rate

month $20 D(1) =15

200.751 345%

year $50 D(12) 15

500.9012 120%

10 years $100 D(120) 15

1000.98120 19%

• Fits hyperbolic model with β = 1/2

Page 13: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Rabin Story

• Girl asked to clean her room today vs tomorrow. Much rather do it tomorrow.

• When asked to clean her room in 365 days or 366 days, it doesn’t matter to her. The ratio of what she would pay today to get out of doing it in 365 days to getting out of it in 366 days is barely bigger than 1.

•13

Page 14: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Iroquois constitution

• Gayanashagowa -- Great Law of Peace --constitution of the Haudenosaunee

• In every deliberation we must consider the impact on the 7th generation … even if it requires having skin as thick as the bark of a pine.

•14

Page 15: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Even animals use hyperbolic discounting

•15

QuickTime™ and aTIFF (Uncompressed) decompressor

are needed to see this picture.

Widely viewed as “irrational”, or at least “behavioral”.

Page 16: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Is hyperbolic discounting time consistent?

• Clearly agents could not be Samuelson discounters.

• If D(t)/D(t+1) goes down, is that time consistent behavior?

•16

Page 17: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Hyperbolic discounting seems irrational

• Only way for D(t+1)/D(t) → 1 seems to be if people think in the future they will become more patient.

• Or in future will become less likely to die in one year.

• Or will develop better imagination about the future as they get older.

• All implausible.

•17

Page 18: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Hyperbolic discounting is irrational

• If world is certain• People do not think they will grow more

patient, or less likely to die, etc

•18

Page 19: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Rabin Story

• Girl asked to clean her room today vs tomorrow. Much rather do it tomorrow.

• When asked today to clean her room in 365 days or 366 days, it doesn’t matter to her.

• But if asked today whether she thinks in 365 days if she is asked to clean her room it will matter whether it is then or the next day, she will say it likely will matter

• Sounds time inconsistent, and Rabin and most others agree. They exult in the irrationality.

• But public policy should be rational!

•19

Page 20: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Solution: One Period Discount is Random!

• Future interest rates are not known today for sure.• People don’t know how urgent their one period

impatience will be.• Death probabilities vary.• An entire industry on Wall Street built to analyze

values when future interest rates unknown.• How does this help if future interest rates on

average are at least as high as today?

•20

Page 21: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Geometric Random Walk Interest Rate Model

• Called Black-Derman-Toy model• (Ho-Lee model same but with random walk)• Workhorse of finance.• Analyzed to death for t < 30 years• But not for large t

•21

Page 22: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

•22

.5

.5

.5

.5

.5

.5

v = volatility

Page 23: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

•23

Page 24: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

D(t) = how much would you pay today for $1 for sure at time t

• Clearly discount factor D(t) must depend on what market expects future one period discounts to be; otherwise there would be arbitrage opportunities.

• Two wrong answers! • D(τ)=e-E₀[r₀]e-E₀[r₁]...e-E₀[rτ-1] < e-r₀τ

• D(τ)=E₀[e-r₀]E₀[e-r₁]...E₀[e-r(τ-1)] ≈ K(1/2)τ

• Both wrong answers lead to more discounting!

•24

Page 25: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

D(t) = how much would you pay today for $1 for sure at time t

• Suppose common knowledge that at any time t, can always make bet at even odds that interest rate will go up or down.

• Then correct answer by no-arbitrage must be average product of one period discounts over all paths to period t.

• D(τ)=E₀[e-r₀e-r₁...e-r(τ-1)]•25

Page 26: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

•26

.5

.5

.5

.5

.5

.5

v = volatility

Page 27: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Theorem

• In geometric random walk, the discount factor D(τ) goes down exponentially at first, at rate faster than r0, but converges to

• D(τ) = Kτ-1/2 as τ → ∞. So hyperbolic discounting is rational.

• D(t+1)/D(t) ≈ √(t+1)/√t• Length of time before entering hyperbolic region is

shorter if vol is higher.• Here K is a constant, or maybe a slowly varying

function like 1/log. Logt/ √t is tiny.•27

Page 28: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

r0=4%, v = 50%

•28Farmer and Geanakoplos

Page 29: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Comparison of discount factors x 100 (15% annual volatility, 4% initial rate)

•29

year rnd. wlk. constant20 46.2 45.660 12.5 9.5

100 5.1 2.0500 0.80 2 x 10-7

1000 0.50 4 x 10-16

Page 30: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Fits Thaler data

•30

Page 31: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Why is this true?

• Think of one period discount as coming from one year death probability.

• Hazard probability follows random walk.• Conditional on living for 100 years, likely were

following path with very low one year death rates. If one year death probs got bad, you would already be dead.

• Hence conditional probability of living one more year after making it to 100 is very high.

• Familiar idea in economics.•31

Page 32: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Where does 1/√t come from?

•32

2n

n≈ 22nK/√n

Proportion of 22n possibilities is about K/√n ≈ K/√tt = 2n

Page 33: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Idea of Proof

• Consider the case where volatility v = ∞.• Then have three kinds of paths:• Good paths: Those in which from time 1

onward remain strictly below median.• Mediocre paths: Those in which from time 1

onward hit median but remain below median.• Bad paths: Those in which at some date go

above median. These contribute zero to value

•33

Page 34: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

•34

r0

Good Path: starts down and never hits r0

0

-1

-3

Page 35: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

•35

r0

Another Good Path: same number of ups as downs

0

Page 36: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Good paths• Might as well start all paths at -1 at time 1, and

go for T-1 periods = 2n.• End up at -1 or -3 or -5 etc.• So can count total number of good paths by

adding number that end at -1 plus number that end at -3 plus number that end at -5 etc.

• Total paths that start at -1 and end at -1 have right proportion 1/√T. But need to subtract out non-good paths that start and end at -1, and add good paths that end at -3 plus -5 etc.

•36

Page 37: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

•37

r0

Bad Path

Page 38: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

•38

r0

Reflection Principle

Page 39: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Reflection Principle for paths end -1

• Number of non-good paths that start at -1 and hit or cross 0 and end at -1 is equal to all paths that start at +1 and end at -1.

• But that is equal to number of all paths that start at -1 and end at -3.

• Hence number of good paths that start at -1 and end at -1 is equal to the number of all paths that start at -1 and end at -1 minus the number of all paths that start at -1 and end at -3.

•39

Page 40: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Reflection Principle for paths end -3

• Number of non-good paths that start at -1 and hit or cross 0 and end at -3 is equal to all paths that start at +1 and end at -3.

• But that is equal to number of all paths that start at -1 and end at -5.

• Hence number of good paths that start at -1 and end at -3 is equal to the number of all paths that start at -1 and end at -3 minus the number of all paths that start at -1 and end at -5.

•40

Page 41: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Number of good paths equals

• All paths that end at -1 minus all paths that end at -3

• Plus• All paths that end at -3 minus all paths that

end at -5• Plus etc

• Equals all paths that end at -1.•41

Page 42: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

End of Proof for v = ∞

• So all good paths has right proportion of all paths.

• Must count total number of mediocre paths that hit 0 but do not cross zero.

• Same technique can be used to show that is exactly equal to number of paths that never hit 0. These paths all get discounted.

• In fact can compute how many paths get discounted k times, for each k.

•42

Page 43: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Proof for v < ∞

• Key idea is that when interest rate goes down exponentially, discount rate goes up doubly exponentially. So after logT periods of going down, discount factor is essentially 1.

• D = 1/(1+r0(e-v)(1/v)logT)= 1/(1+r0/T)

• Even if one period discount factor is D from then on until T, get virtually no discounting

• DT = (1/(1+r0/T))T = e-r0

•43

Page 44: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

•44

r0

Strip: Everything Below is Good Path

(1/v)logT

Good path starting here

Period TPeriod 0

Page 45: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Proof for v < ∞

• Let N = logT + 1. Note N/√T ≈ 0.• So probability that path starting at 0 goes first to -1 is

½.• For T large probability that path exits strip is ≈ 1.• Then probability the path exits at bottom of strip

before exiting at top is 1/N by gambler’s ruin theorem.• Once out at bottom fraction of good paths that never

enter strip again is at least 1/√T.• So get D(t) ≥ 1/2N√T times discounting while in strip.

•45

Page 46: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Discounting While in Strip

• Actually spend pretty long in strip before exiting at bottom. If visited every line equally while in strip before exiting at bottom, then too much discounting.

• But can show spend most of time while in strip before exiting at bottom near middle of strip, where discount factor already near 1.

•46

Page 47: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Discounting While in Strip• Let Π(i) = i/N = prob of exiting at N starting at i.• Let E(i,k) = expected number of times you hit k

starting at i before exiting, with i≤ k ≤ N.• Clearly E(i,N) = Π(i).• Π(i) = E(i,k)(1/2)(1/(N-k)) if i < k < N• E(i,k) = 2 Π(i)(N-k)• Let W(i,k) = expected hits of k that also exit at N.• W(1,k) = (k/N)E(1,k) = 2k(N-k)/N2

• W(1,k)N = 2k(N-k)/N = expected number of hits of k starting at 1 conditional on exiting at N

•47

Page 48: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Generalizatios

• Asymptotic Behavior of Stochastic Discount Rate

• Geanakoplos-Sudderth-Zeitouni• Instead of binary, let v be any bounded

random variable with zero mean and positive variance. Then

• 1/√t-o(1) < D(t) < 1/√t+o(1)

•48

Page 49: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

End

•49

Page 50: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Utility today and in the future over certain prizes

•50

Page 51: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

•51

Page 52: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Conclusion from certainty and time consistency

Discount factor Ds(τ) must be the productof one-period discounts Ds+i(1).

•52

Page 53: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Certainty, time consistency and strict stationarity

• Exponential discounting is time consistent and strictly stationary, I.e. rs+τ = r is constant independent of t.

• Samuelson exponential discounting is the only time consistent, strictly stationary discounting function under certainty.

•53

Page 54: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Give up strict stationarity

• But then must have Ds(1) declining with time s.

• This is implausible because death hazard is increasing not decreasing with age. People do not get more patient with age; more likely they undertake fewer long term projects. That is point of Rabin story.

• So it would seem that hyperbolic discounting is incompatible with time consistency, i.e. incompatible with rationality.

• But it is compatible with time consistency if we give up certainty as well.

•54

Page 55: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

The discount is not constant• Urgencies vary• Hazards vary• Interest rates vary• The future is uncertain, and uncertainties are typically correlated in

time.• Under these circumstances, on average hyperbolic discounting is

time consistent -- each step uses exponential discounting, but at varying rates. Result is not exponential!

•55

Page 56: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Key uncertainty

• One period discount Ds+τ(1) is not known at s

• So utility of x depends not just on time s that one considers x, but also the psychological one-period discount rate r at that time, Us,r(x).

• Can rehabilitate weak stationarity by requiring that if x is constant, then utility should depend on r but not on s.

• Can also assume that given r, r one period later is likely to be at least as high, so that on average people get more impatient

•56

Page 57: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

time consistency with certainty to time consistency with

uncertainty

•57

Page 58: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Discounting certain payoffs with uncertain discount rates

• As long as the payoffs are certain, even if they depend on time, it makes sense to compare consumption today vs consumption at a fixed time in the future. Let us call the resulting certainty discount factors Ds(τ).

• Time consistency requires • Ds(τ) = average[exp(Σi=0

τ-1-rs+i)

• Familiar theorem from interest rate models•58

Page 59: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Weitzman example• Suppose interest rate has probability ½ of being high R per period

forever after, and probability ½ of being low r per period forever after.

• Then Ds(τ) converges to 1/2e-rτ as τ → ∞.

• This is known as convexity if finance. Comes from autocorrelation of interest rates.

• Weitzman argued that for long horizons like environment, should think of very low interest rates.

•59

Page 60: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Discount factors in geometric random walk

• Where N(τ) = 2τ-1.

• When payoffs xs are certain functions of time

•60

Page 61: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Theoretical explanation

• Consider high volatility limit• Discount rate tree has a “cliff”: 0 or 1• Discount rate is fraction of paths that do not

cross the cliff.• Random walk with barrier crossing• Scales as • Implies non-integrability!

•61

t 1/ 2

Page 62: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

Who is the better economist?

•62

QuickTime™ and aTIFF (Uncompressed) decompressor

are needed to see this picture.

pigeon

QuickTime™ and aTIFF (Uncompressed) decompressor

are needed to see this picture.

12 economists in Copenhagen consensus

Page 63: J. Doyne Farmer John Geanakoplos

r0={.5, 1,100}%, v = 100%

•63