moller from constitutional to international human rights

Upload: liga-da-justica-um-blog-de-teoria-politica

Post on 02-Apr-2018

216 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    1/22

    1

    Note:thisisaroughdraft.Dontciteorcirculatewithouttheauthorspermission.

    KaiMller

    FromConstitutionaltoInternationalHumanRights

    I.IntroductionPartofwhatsparksthecurrentphilosophicaldiscussionaboutinternationalhumanrightsis

    amismatchbetweentheirgreatpracticalandtheoreticalimportanceontheonehandand

    whatisperceivedtobeanunderdevelopedgraspoftheirmoralbasisandstructureonthe

    other.Broadlyspeaking,twostrategies,towhichthispaperwilladdathird,arecurrently

    employed inordertothrow lighton internationalhumanrights:1someapproachthemby

    startingfromamoraltheoryofhumanrightsasopposedtospecificallyinternationalhuman

    rights, and then ask to what extent a proper understanding of human rights can help

    illuminate the phenomenon of international human rights.2 Others focus more on the

    internationalsphereofwhichinternationalhumanrightsareapart,tryingtoderiveatheory

    ofinternationalhumanrightsfromtherolethatphenomenonplaysoroughttoplayinthe

    sphereoftherelationsbetweenstates.3Nothingiswrongasamatterofprinciplewiththose

    approaches:afullfledgedtheoryof internationalhumanrightsmustsurelymakesenseof

    both international and human rights; thus,whatwe are ultimately looking for is an

    integratedtheory.Itthereforeseemsplausibletoassumethatonecanapproachtheproject

    ofdevelopingacomprehensivetheoryofinternationalhumanrightsfromdifferentangles,

    just asonemight reach the top of amountain from different sides. In this paper, Iwill

    develop and propose a theory of international human rights, but Iwill choose another,

    previously largely unexplored route, namely one via the philosophy of national

    constitutionalrights.

    Thereare important structural similaritiesbetweenconstitutional rightsand international

    humanrights.Inbothcontexts,compliancewithfundamental(read:constitutional;human)

    rightsis,looselyspeaking,oneoftheimportantyardsticksoflegitimacy,beitinthesenseof

    constitutionallegitimacyorinthesenseoffallingwithinthesphereofastatessovereignty.

    Furthermore,therightsprotectedbynationalconstitutionsandinternationaltreatieslook,

    onthewhole,strikinglysimilar.Thissimilaritydoesnotendonthesurfacebutgoesallthewaydown.Europeanlawyerswhoareacquaintedwithbothnationalconstitutionallawofa

    jurisdictionthatemploysstrongjudicialreviewsuchasGermanyinitsBasicLawandthe

    lawof theEuropeanConventiononHumanRightsknow that thedoctrinal tools, styleof

    reasoning,and theoutcomesproducedbynationalconstitutionalcourtsontheonehand

    and theEuropeanCourtofHumanRightson theotherarevery similar indeed.As iswell

    known,when theUnited Kingdom decided in the late 1990s that itwanted to set up a

    systemof constitutionaljudicial review, itdidnotdesign anew,nationalbillof British

    1SeeAllenBuchanan,TheEgalitarianismofHumanRights,120(2010)Ethics679,68082.2James

    Griffin,

    On

    Human

    Rights

    (OUP

    2008).

    See

    also

    John

    Tasioulas,

    Taking

    Rights

    out

    of

    Human

    Rights,

    120

    (2010)Ethics647.3Raz;Beitz

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    2/22

    2

    rights(althoughthatisaprojectthatcontinuestobeonthetableintherespectivepolitical

    discussions) but instead simply incorporated the European Convention onHuman Rights

    intoUK law;4thuseffectivelyadoptingthetextoftheEuropeanConventiontogetherwith

    theexistingandfuturejurisprudenceoftheEuropeanCourtofHumanRights5aspartofits

    nationalconstitutionallaw.

    Structuralsimilaritiessuchastheonesmentionedaboveaswellashistoricalandsemantic

    links between the concepts of constitutional and international human rights make it

    promising toapproach theprojectofdevelopingacomprehensive theoryof international

    human rights via an understanding of national constitutional rights. This route becomes

    evenmore appealing in light of the fact that in recent years there has been awave of

    scholarship theorising constitutional rights;6 thus, drawing on this work may prevent

    philosophersofinternationalhumanrightsfromhavingtoreinventthewheel.

    Iwillproceedbysettingoutsomestructuralfeaturesofnationalconstitutionalrightsinthe

    nextsection.Thatsectionwillshowthatitismisguidedtobelieve,asmanydo,thatnational

    constitutional rights law rests to a considerable extent on contingencies specific to the

    national communitywhich has adopted them. Theopposite is true: conversations about

    constitutional rightsare,on thewhole,no lessglobal inappeal thanconversationsabout

    international human rights. Furthermore, the section will give an overview of those

    structuralfeaturesofconstitutionalrightswhichinpreviousworkIhavelabelledtheglobal

    model of constitutional rights, and itwill present the basics of a theory of that global

    model, focussing on the questions of the scope of rights (which interests ought to be

    acknowledged as grounding rights?) and their permissible limitations (under what

    conditions is a limitation of a right legitimate?). This will prepare the ground for the

    subsequentsection,whichtakesthestepfromnationalconstitutionalrightstointernational

    human rights. It examines the case for a view held bymany international human rights

    theorists,namely thatwhatever internationalhuman rightsare, theyaremoreminimalist

    thannationalconstitutional rights (call this internationalhuman rightsminimalism).Thus,

    the paper will ask whether there is room to make national constitutional rights more

    minimalist.Myconclusionwillbethatthere isnosuchroom:anysuchattemptwilleither

    introducearbitrariness(because,aswillbeshown,reducingthescopeofinterestsprotected

    asrightswillnecessarily involvethedrawingofmorallyarbitrarythresholds)orwill ignore

    thefactthatconstitutionalrightsarealreadyasminimalistascoherentlypossible(because,

    aswillbecome clear, they setupa reasonableness standardofjustification,and treating

    policieswhichare less than reasonableas legitimate ismorallyunappealing).Thus, there

    exists neither the necessity nor themoral possibility tomake constitutional rightsmore

    minimalist. It follows that the moral structures of national constitutional rights and

    4HumanRightsAct1998.5Section2(1)oftheUKHumanRightsAct1998:Acourtortribunaldeterminingaquestionwhichhasarisenin

    connectionwithaConventionrightmusttakeintoaccountany

    (a)judgment,decision,declarationoradvisoryopinionoftheEuropeanCourtofHumanRights ...whenever

    madeorgiven[...].6SeeinparticularRobertAlexy,ATheoryofConstitutional Rights(OUP2002);MattiasKumm,TheIdeaof

    SocraticContestationandtheRighttoJustification: ThePointofRightsBasedProportionalityReview,(2010)4

    Law&EthicsofHumanRights141;MattiasKumm,PoliticalLiberalismandtheStructureofRights:Onthe

    Placeand

    Limits

    of

    the

    Proportionality

    Requirement,

    in

    Pavlakos

    (ed.),

    Law,

    Rights

    and

    Discourse:

    The

    Legal

    PhilosophyofRobertAlexy(HartPublishing,2007),131;KaiMller,TheGlobalModelofConstitutionalRights

    (OUP2012).

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    3/22

    3

    international human rights are identical. The fourth section will spell out some of the

    implicationsofthisview.

    II.The

    moral

    structure

    of

    national

    constitutional

    rights

    1.Aglobalconversationaboutrights

    Intermsoftheirpossiblereachandappeal,contemporarydiscussionsaboutconstitutional

    rights are global. Thus, it is emphatically not the case that the moral demands of

    constitutional rightsare inextricably linked and intertwinedwithaparticular constitution

    with a particular interpretative history, adopted by a particular political community at a

    particularpointintime.Theinsightthatconstitutionalrightsdiscourseisgovernedmoreby

    freestanding moral discourse about what rights and legitimacy require than by

    considerations relating to thehistoryofadocumentorpeople is,however,still relatively

    young.Asrecentlyas1996,RonaldDworkinpublishedhisbookFreedomsLaw,

    7

    whichisacollection of essays dealing with important US Supreme Court decisions on abortion,

    euthanasia,hate speech andother controversial topics. The subtitleof thisbook is The

    moralreadingoftheAmericanconstitution,whichmakesclearthatDworkinperceivedhis

    bookasacontribution toaspecificallyAmericandiscourse.Today, less than twodecades

    later, an authorwho published a book dealingwith problems as universal as the ones

    discussedbyDworkinandwhorestrictedhim orherselftoonlyoneparticularjurisdiction

    wouldrightlybeaccusedofarbitrarinessinthechoiceofhisorhermaterials.Constitutional

    rightsdiscoursehasgoneglobal.

    Alookatthestructureofconstitutionalrightslawaroundtheworldhelpsexplainhowthis

    could happen. Courts around theworld employ a twostage analysiswhen determining

    whetheranactbyapublicauthorityviolatesconstitutionalrights.Atthefirststage,theyask

    whether the act interferes with (limits, restricts) a right. If so, the second question is

    whether the interference isjustifiable.The test that isalmost globally8employed at this

    secondstage istheproportionalitytest,accordingtowhichan interferencewitharight is

    justifiableifitservesalegitimategoalandisproportionatetothatgoal.Injudicialpractice,

    the first stage has become less and less important, largely as a consequence of rights

    inflation, that is, thephenomenon thatmoreandmore interestsareprotectedas rights.

    Thus, the focus of the analysis has shifted to the second stage, and the proportionality

    principle which dominates that stage has become the by farmost important doctrinal

    principleofconstitutionalrights lawaroundtheworld. Interestingly,nationalconstitutions

    donotgivecourtsanyguidanceastohowtoconducttheproportionalitytest.Constitutions

    normallydonotevenmentionthetermproportionality.Instead,theyusephrasessimilar

    to thatemployedby theCanadianCharterofRightsandFreedoms,which stipulates that

    rightsareguaranteed subjectonly to such reasonable limitsprescribedby lawascanbe

    demonstrablyjustified ina freeanddemocraticsociety.9Thepointofthoserathervague

    7RonaldDworkin,FreedomsLaw:TheMoralReadingoftheAmericanConstitution(OUP1996)8An

    important

    exception

    isthe

    US

    jurisprudence.

    On

    the

    issue

    of

    whether

    the

    US

    Supreme

    Court

    applies

    proportionalityunderadifferentname,seePaulYowell,...SeealsoMller,GlobalModel,...9CanadianCharterofRightsandFreedoms1982,section1.

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    4/22

    4

    phrases is to release judges from interpretative constraints;10 thus, when courts apply

    proportionality analysis, they are not usually bound by textual subtleties, nor are they

    bound by the history of the particular constitution they are interpreting. Rather, they

    engageinfreestandingmoralreasoningaboutwhatrightsrequire,largelyunguidedbythe

    constitutionwhichtheyinterpret.

    2.Theglobalmodelofconstitutionalrights11

    While it is to be expected that different courtswill often come to different conclusions

    whendealingwithaparticular rights issue say, thequestionofwhetherorunderwhat

    conditionshatespeechmaybeprohibited,orwhetherassistedsuicidemustbepermitted

    at a more abstract level, a remarkable consensus about certain structural features of

    constitutionalrightshasemergedinrecentdecades.Ihavelabelledthissetofdoctrinesand

    phenomenatheglobalmodelofconstitutionalrights;inthissectionIwillbrieflyintroduce

    itsmainfeatures,whichwillpavethewayforpresenting,inthefollowingsectionatheoryof

    constitutionalrightswhichfitsandjustifiesthesefeatures.

    Theglobalmodelofconstitutionalrightsisbestintroducedandexplainedbycontrastingit

    withwhat I call the dominant narrative of fundamental rights. The dominant narrative

    holds (1) that rights cover only a limited domain by protecting only certain especially

    important interestsof individuals; (2) that rights imposeexclusivelyorprimarilynegative

    obligationsonthestate;(3)thatrightsoperateonlybetweenacitizenandhisgovernment,

    not between private citizens; and (4) that rights enjoy a special normativeforcewhich

    means that theycanbeoutweighed, ifatall,only inexceptional circumstances.Of these

    features of the dominant narrative, the general acceptance of the second rights as

    imposing negative obligations on the state has already eroded considerably, mainly

    becauseofthegrowingrecognitionofsocialandeconomicrights.12Thethirdlimitationtothe relationshipbetweencitizenandgovernment,whilegenerallyheld tobe true,does

    notnormallyattractmuchattentionby rights theorists.The firstand the fourth special

    importanceandspecialnormativeforcearestillalmostuncontroversial.However,under

    theglobalmodelofconstitutionalrightsallfourelementsofthisnarrativehavebeengiven

    upandoftenalongtimeago.Thedoctrinesanddevelopmentsinconstitutionalrightslaw

    whichhaveledtotheirerosionarerightsinflation,positiveobligationsandsocioeconomic

    rights,horizontaleffect,andbalancingandproportionality.

    a.Rightsinflation

    Constitutional rights are no longer seen as onlyprotecting certain particularly important

    interests. Especially in Europe a development has been observed which is sometimes

    pejorativelycalledrightsinflation13,anamewhichIwilluseinaneutralsenseasdescribing

    thephenomenonthatincreasingly,relativelytrivial interestsareprotectedas(primafacie)

    10KaiMller, Proportionality:Challenging thecritics,10 (2012) International JournalofConstitutional Law

    709at717.11ThissectiondrawsonideasdevelopedingreaterdepthinmybookTheGlobalModelofConstitutionalRights

    (OUP2012).12Foratheoreticalaccountofthisdevelopment,seeFredman,HumanRightsTransformed:PositiveRightsand

    Positive

    Duties(Oxford

    University

    Press,

    2008),

    ch.

    1.

    13Letsas,ATheoryof Interpretation of theEuropeanConventiononHumanRights (OxfordUniversityPress,

    2007),126.

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    5/22

    5

    rights. Themost extreme approach is that of the German Federal Constitutional Court,

    which has explicitly given up any threshold to distinguish a mere interest from a

    constitutionalright.Asearlyas1957itheldthatArticle2(1)oftheBasicLaw,whichprotects

    everyonesrighttofreelydevelophispersonality,istobeinterpretedasarighttofreedom

    ofaction.14TheCourtprovidedvariousdoctrinalreasonsforthisresult, itsmainargument

    beingthatanearlierdraftofArticle2(1)hadread Everyonecandoashepleases (Jeder

    kanntunundlassenwaserwill),andthatthisversionhadbeendroppedonlyforlinguistic

    reasons.15 Itaffirmed this ruling invarious laterdecisions;most famously itdeclared that

    Article2(1)oftheBasicLawincludedtherightstofeedpigeonsinapark16andtogoriding

    inthewoods.17

    Whileotherjurisdictionshavenot,tomyknowledge,adoptedsuchafarreachingapproach

    to the scopeof rights, thephenomenonof rights inflationand thedifficultyof findinga

    principledway todistinguish rights frommere interestshavebeenwidelyobserved. It is

    importanttonotethatthebroadunderstandingofrightsdoesofcoursenotimplythatthe

    stateisprohibitedfrom interferingwiththeright inquestion.Rather,ashasbeenpointedoutabove,thereisanimportantconceptualdistinctionbetweenaninterferencewithanda

    violationofaright:aninterferencewillonlyamounttoaviolationifitcannotbejustifiedat

    thejustificationstage.Thus,thebroadunderstandingofrightsattheprimafaciestagemust

    beseen inconjunctionwiththeproportionalitytestwhichpermitsthe limitationofprima

    facierightswhentheyareoutweighedbyacompetingrightorpublicinterest.

    b.Positiveobligationsandsocioeconomicrights

    Rightsarenolongerregardedasexclusivelyimposingnegativeobligationsonthestate.But

    whilemosttheoristsofrightsonlystartedtoreconsidertheirviewsonthis issuefollowing

    thegrowingacceptanceof socioeconomic rights (particularly their inclusion in theSouthAfricanConstitution),constitutionalrightslawhadgivenuptheviewthatrightsimposeonly

    negative obligations at least since the 1970s when the doctrines of positive duties or

    protectiveobligationsbecameestablished.Theideaisthatthestateisunderadutytotake

    stepstopreventharmtothe interestsprotectedby (otherwisenegative)rights.Thus,the

    statemust,asamatterofconstitutionalrightslaw,putinplaceasystemwhicheffectively

    protectsthepeople fromdangersemanating fromotherprivatepersons,suchascriminal

    activitieswhichthreaten,forexample, life,physicalintegrity,orproperty;and itmustalso

    protect them from dangerswhich do not have a (direct) human cause, such as natural

    disasters.

    Furthermoreandmaybemoreimportantly,thereistheaforementionedtrendtowardsthe

    acknowledgementofsocioeconomicrights,whichobviously imposepositivedutiesonthe

    stateandthusconflictwiththedominantnarrativeaccordingtowhichrightsareconcerned

    onlywithnegativeobligations.Themostwidelydiscussedexampleofthisdevelopment is

    theSouthAfricanConstitution,whichcontainsinitssections26,27and29rightstohousing,

    healthcare,food,water,socialsecurityandeducation.

    14BVerfGE6,32(Elfes).

    15Ibid.,

    36

    37.

    16BVerfGE54,143(PigeonFeeding).

    17BVerfGE80,137(RidingintheWoods).

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    6/22

    6

    c.Horizontaleffect

    Constitutional rights are no longer seen as affecting only the relationship between the

    citizenandthestate;rather,theyapply insomewaybetweenprivatepersonsaswell.For

    example, the constitutional right to privacy may protect a person not only against

    infringements of his privacy by the state, but also against such infringements by hisneighbour,landlord,oremployer.Thedoctrinaltoolwhichachievesthisiscalledhorizontal

    effect of rights,where horizontal as opposed to vertical indicates that rights operate

    betweenprivatepersons.ThefirstcourttoacknowledgehorizontaleffectwastheGerman

    Federal Constitutional Court in its famous Lth decision of 1953.18 From Germany the

    concept travelled to other parts of theworld. It has by now become awellestablished

    featureoftheglobalmodelofconstitutionalrights;one indicatorof itssuccess isthatthe

    newSouthAfrican constitutionexplicitlyendorseshorizontaleffect in section8(2),which

    states in slightlyawkward language: Aprovisionof theBillofRightsbindsanaturalora

    juristicperson if,andtotheextentthat, it isapplicable,taking intoaccountthenatureof

    therightandthenatureofanydutyimposedbytheright.

    d.Balancingandproportionality

    Contrary to thedominantnarrative, it isnot the case that constitutional rights generally

    enjoyaspecialorheightenednormative force in legalpractice.While it istruethatsome

    rightsareabsoluteforexampletherighttofreedomfromtorturemostrightsincluding

    the rights to life, physical integrity, privacy, property, freedom of religion, expression,

    assembly and association can be limited in line with the proportionality test.

    Proportionalityhasbecomethecentraldoctrineofcontemporaryconstitutionalrightslaw,

    andhasbeenacceptedbyvirtuallyeveryconstitutionalcourtinCentralandEasternEurope

    andisincreasinglyemployedinCentralandSouthAmericanjurisdictions.19Accordingtothetestasusedbymostscholarsworkinginthefield,theproportionalitytesthasfourprongs.

    First,apolicy interferingwith the rightmustbe inpursuitofa legitimategoal;second, it

    mustbeasuitablemeansoffurtheringtheachievementofthegoal(suitabilityorrational

    connection); third, itmustbe necessary in that theremust notbe a less restrictive and

    equally effective alternative (necessity); and finally and most importantly, it must not

    imposeadisproportionateburdenon the rightholder (balancingorproportionality in the

    strict sense). Some courts have adopted tests that look slightlydifferenton the surface;

    however,whatall testshave incommon is thatat theircore, there isbalancingexercise

    wheretherightisbalancedagainstthecompetingrightorpublicinterest,whichimpliesthat

    farfromenjoyinganyspecialorelevatedstatusoverpublicinterests,rightsoperateonthesameplaneaspolicyconsiderations.

    3.Theorisingtheglobalmodel:betweenminimalismandmaximalism

    a)Thescopeofrights:endorsingrightsmaximalism

    18BVerfGE7,198(Lth).EnglishtranslationfromthewebsiteoftheUniversityofTexasSchoolofLaw,

    http://www.utexas.edu/law/academics/centers/transnational/work_new/[copyright:

    Basil

    Markesinis].

    19StoneSweetandMathews, ProportionalityBalancingandGlobalConstitutionalism, (20089)47Columbia

    JournalofTransnationalLaw72,112.

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    7/22

    7

    The global model does not endorse the once uncontroversial idea that the point of

    constitutional rights is to limitgovernmentandkeep itoutofour lives: that idea cannot

    makesenseofthedoctrinesofhorizontaleffectandpositiveobligationsandtheincreasing

    acknowledgment of socioeconomic rights. The point of constitutional rights under the

    globalmodelisnottodisablegovernment;ratheritmustbetoenableeverypersontotake

    controlofhisorherlife.Constitutionalrightsprotecttheabilityofpersonstolivetheirlives

    accordingtotheirselfconceptions;thus,theyarebasedonthevalueofpersonalautonomy.

    Forexample,constitutionalrightsprotectapersonsrighttoengageinfreespeech,believe

    inandfollowthepreceptsofherreligion(importantaspectsofpersonalautonomy),control

    herprivatelife(includinghersexualandreproductiveautonomy),tobodilyintegrity(partly

    a precondition for, partly an element of personal autonomy), and so on. This focus on

    autonomynotonlyexplainsthetraditionallyacknowledgedsetofcivilandpoliticalrightsin

    theirnegativedimension,itcanfurtherjustifytheexistenceofhorizontaleffectandpositive

    obligations: from an autonomybased perspective,whatmatters is notwho violates the

    rightbut rather the adequateprotectionof the interest at stake. Finally, the autonomy

    basedapproachmakessenseofsocioeconomicrightssuchastherightstofood,healthcare,oreducation,whichprotectthepreconditionsofautonomy.

    The crucial question for present purposes is the scope of protection offered by

    constitutionalrights:shouldtheycoveranarroworabroadrangeofautonomy interests?

    The first feature of the globalmodel (rights inflation) suggests that an approachwhich

    regards rightsasprotectingallautonomy interestsofaperson including thoseof trivial

    importance,suchasfeedingbirdsorridinginthewoods(tousethosefamousGermancases

    again) sits best with the practice of constitutional rights law. Thus, the picture that

    emerges is that under the globalmodel, all autonomy interests are protected as rights;

    however,this

    protection

    isnot

    absolute

    or

    near

    absolute;

    rather

    itcan

    be

    limited

    as

    long

    as

    thelimitationisproportionate.Isitpossibletomakesenseofthisarguablycounterintuitive

    proposition?Itis indeedpossible,buttodoso,wemustdispenseofadearlyheldviewof

    almostallphilosophers,who insistthatfundamentalrightsprotectonlyanarrowrangeof

    interestswhilehavingaspecialnormativeforcewhichmeansthattheycanrarely,ifever,be

    outweighed by competing considerations. That model is flatly incompatible with the

    practice of constitutional rights law around the world, in particular with the global

    endorsementoftheproportionalityapproach.Instead,Idefendthefollowingaccountofthe

    pointandpurposeofconstitutional rights.Themainentitlement thatapersonhasunder

    the globalmodel is to being treatedwith a certain attitude: an attitude that takes her

    seriouslyasapersonwithalifetolive,andthatwillthereforedenyhertheabilitytoliveher

    lifeinacertainwayonlywhentherearesufficientlystrongreasonsforthis.Appliedtothe

    caseofhobbiessuchasfeedingthebirds,thismeansthatweshouldnotaskwhetherthe

    freedom to feed birds is an aspect of a narrowly defined set of especially important

    interests.Rather,weshouldaskwhetherthestatetreatsapersonsubjecttoitsauthorityin

    awaywhich isjustifiabletoherwhenthestateprohibits,forexample,herparticipationin

    theactivityoffeedingbirds;andthiswillbethecaseonlywhentherearesufficientlystrong

    reasonssupportingtheprohibition.Thus,thepointofconstitutionalrights isnottosingle

    outcertainespeciallyimportantinterestsforheightenedprotection.Rather,itistoshowa

    particularformofrespectforpersonsbyinsistingthateachandeverystatemeasurewhich

    affects a persons ability to live her life according to her selfconceptionmust take her

    autonomyinterestsadequatelyintoaccountinordertobejustifiabletoher.Constitutional

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    8/22

    8

    rightslawinstitutionalisesarighttojustification20,thatis,arighttobeprovidedwithan

    adequatejustification for every state action (and omission) that affects the agent in a

    morallyrelevantway.

    b)Thestructureofjustification:rightsminimalism

    To say thatapersonhasa constitutional right toX,whereX could stand for freedomof

    religion,freedomofexpression,property,etc.,meansnotthatthestatecannot,oratleast

    not normally, limit X. Rather it means that when the state limits X it must provide

    sufficientlystrongreasons forthis: ifthereasonssupportingthe limitationaresufficiently

    strong, then the limitationwill be proportionate and thereforejustified; if they are not

    strongenough,thelimitationwillbedisproportionateandtherightwillhavebeenviolated.

    Thisraisesthequestionofwhatthestandardforsufficientlystrongreasonsisandought

    tobeinthedomainofconstitutionalrights.Twocandidateapproachessuggestthemselves.

    Accordingtothecorrectnessstandard,whenastatelimitsaright,itisjustified indoingso

    onlyifitspolicyisthebestpossiblethecorrectresponsetothesocialproblemathand.

    Bywayof contrast,undera reasonableness standard, the stateacts legitimatelywhen it

    choosesareasonable,asopposedtotheonecorrect,policy.

    As an illustration, let us look at the problem of assisted suicide. Some peoplewho are

    sufferingfroman incurablediseaseandwhodesiretokillthemselveswhentheirsituation

    becomesunbearableknowthatwhentheyreachthatstage,theywillnolongerbyphysically

    strongenoughtoimplementthatplanontheirown,althoughtheycouldstilldoitwithhelp

    fromapartner,friend,orphysician.However, it ispreciselythisassistancewhichinmany,

    though by nomeans all, countries is illegal and punishable. The reason given for such

    policiesisusuallythatallowingassistedsuicidewouldleadtotheriskofabuse,whereweak

    andvulnerablepatientsarebulliedintodeathorevenkilledbyrelativesorcarers.Underthecorrectnessapproach,astatewhichlimitstherighttoassistedsuicidewhichispartofthe

    right toprivate lifeorprivacy isjustified indoing soonlywhere this limitation is,asa

    matter of substance, the best possible policy. Under the reasonableness approach, the

    limitation isjustified if it isat least reasonable (thoughpossiblynot correct).Thus, letus

    stipulatethatabanofassistedsuicideisanexampleofapolicywhichlegislatorscaningood

    faithbelievetobethebestpolicy(ieitisreasonable),butwhichasamatterofmoralfactis

    notthebestpolicy.Underthecorrectnessapproach,weshouldconsiderthispolicyasone

    which violates rights,whereas under a reasonableness approach,we should accept it as

    justified.

    Bothasamatterofthecurrentpracticeofjudicialreviewaroundtheworldandasamatter

    ofphilosophicalattractiveness,thereasonablenessapproachispreferable.Thejustification

    for this is controversial, however.Mattias Kumm points to the existence of reasonable

    disagreement:wheresuchreasonabledisagreementaboutthebestpolicyexists,choosing

    one of the reasonable policies must be legitimate.21 I have argued that the notion of

    reasonabledisagreement,whilerelevant,cannotdoallofthemoralworkandproposedthat

    itistheprincipleofdemocracywhichrequiresthatapolicywhichisreasonable,asopposed

    20Kumm,

    Forst

    21MattiasKumm,TheIdeaofSocraticContestationandtheRighttoJustification: ThePointofRightsBased

    ProportionalityReview,(2010)4Law&EthicsofHumanRights141at16870.

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    9/22

    9

    tocorrect,isregardedasconstitutionallylegitimate.22Ifwerequiredthedemocraticprocess

    tocomeupwiththebestpossiblepolicywheneveritlegislatesinthedomainofrights,this

    would, in lightof thebroad scopeof rightsunder the globalmodel,mean thatoftenor

    indeedpossiblyalwaystheoutcomeofdemocraticdeliberationswouldbepredetermined

    bythemoralrequirementsofrights.Therewouldbenoroomfordemocraticdeliberation

    andgoodfaithdisagreementaboutpolicies;andthismustbe flatly incompatiblewithour

    understanding of democracy as a form of government where the people and their

    representativesdebateand,usually,faceagenuinechoicewithregardtotheproperwayto

    dealwithaparticularsocialproblem.Thus,thevalueofdemocracyrequiresthatweaccept

    areasonablenessstandardasopposedtocorrectnessstandardforassessingthejustifiability

    ofthelimitationofaright.

    This reasonableness standard is reflected in the jurisprudence of national

    constitutional courts. I do not have the space here show this point in depth; so a few

    observationsmust suffice. The Canadian Supreme Court has stated that the legislature

    mustbegivenreasonableroomtomanoeuvre23

    ,aphrasewhosepoint isto indicatethatthe legislature need not find the one right answer to the rights question at stake. The

    German Federal Constitutional Court often uses a negative formulation, stating that the

    proportionality test is satisfied if the interference is notdisproportionateor notoutof

    proportion.24Soratherthanrequiringpositivelythatthepolicybeproportionate,theCourt

    demands negatively that it not be disproportionate; the effect of this is to give the

    necessary leeway to theelectedbranches.Occasionally theCourtuses formulations that

    indicateevenmoreclearlythattheapproachitusesisreallyareasonablenessapproach,for

    examplewhenitstatesthattheremustbearelationship[betweentheseriousnessofthe

    interference and theweightof the reasons supporting the interference] that can stillbe

    consideredas

    reasonable

    25

    .

    c)Theemergingpicture:betweenminimalistandmaximalistapproaches

    The picture which emerges is that national constitutional rights are at the same time

    minimalistandmaximalist: theyaremaximalistwith regard to the rangeof interests that

    theyprotectasrights,andminimalistwithregardtothestandardofjustificationwhichthey

    demandwithregardtotheprotectionofthoseinterests.Whileasaconsequenceofrights

    inflation all autonomy interests, including those of trivial importance, are protected as

    rights,ameasurelimitingarightisjustifiedifsupportedbyareasonable,asopposedtothe

    best possible,justification. The underlying idea here is that every statemeasurewhich

    affects aperson in amorally relevantway inotherwords, every statemeasurewhichaffectsapersonsabilitytolivehislifeaccordingtohisselfconceptiontriggersthedutyof

    justification; and that the standardofjustificationmustbea reasonableness standard in

    order to preserve ameaningful sphereof democratic debate about and choicebetween

    differentreasonablepolicies.

    22KaiMller,TheGlobalModelofConstitutionalRights(OUP2012),118.

    23R.

    v.

    Edwards

    Books

    and

    Art,(1986)

    S.C.R.

    713,

    795.

    24SeeforexampleBVerfGE65,1,54.

    25BVerfGE76,1,51.

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    10/22

    10

    III.FromnationalconstitutionalrightstointernationalhumanrightsWiththeaboveaccountofthemoralstructureofnationalconstitutionalrightsinmind,we

    cannowapproachinternationalhumanrights.Asexplainedintheintroduction,theworking

    hypothesis of this paper is that themoral structure of national constitutional rights and

    internationalhumanrightswillatleastberelated.Thus,thequestiontobeaddressednowiswhatmodifications,ifany,wehavetoapplytothetheoryofnationalconstitutionalrights

    presentedabove inorder tomake ita suitable theoryof internationalhuman rights.My

    conclusionwillbethatweneednomodificationswhatsoever.

    Therearetwoobjectionswhichatheoristof internationalhumanrightscouldhavetothis

    view.Thefirstisthatnationalconstitutionalrights,unlikeinternationalhumanrights,reflect

    andarebasedonnationalidiosyncrasiesandcontingenciesandarethereforenotasuitable

    candidate for a theory of international human rights, which by its very nature must

    transcend such contingencies. However, as I have explained above, constitutional rights

    discourseisjustasglobalasinternationalhumanrightsdiscourse;constitutionsaroundthe

    world containbroadly the same setof rights,and constitutionalcourtsaround theworld

    employ the samedoctrinal tools to interpret them,most importantly theproportionality

    testwhosepointistoenableafreestandingdiscussionofthemoraljustifiabilityofapolicy.

    Theideathatconstitutionalrightsareoroughttobereflectiveofnationalidiosyncrasiesto

    alargeextentissimplywrongandoughttobeabandoned.

    The second andmore promising objection is that constitutional rights aremorallymore

    demanding than international human rights. The idea is that constitutional rights

    incorporate and reflect a comprehensive set of legitimacy conditions for a policy or

    executive decision, whereas international human rights set only minimum standards.

    Correlative to this perceived distance between national constitutional rights andinternationalhuman rights is aperceiveddistancebetween constitutional legitimacy and

    nationalsovereignty:noteverythingthat isconstitutionally illegitimate(read:thatviolates

    constitutionalrights)alsotranscendsthesphereofastatessovereignty(andconflictswith

    internationalhumanrights):mostscholarswouldholdthatthereisroomforpoliciestofall

    withinthesphereofsovereigntywhileatthesametimeviolatingconstitutionalrights.

    Herearetwoimportantviewsfromtheliteraturewhichadoptthisbasicapproach.Thefirst

    talks about the relationship between constitutional and human rights, and the second

    focusesontherelationshipbetweenlegitimateauthorityandnationalsovereignty.InJustice

    forHedgehogs,RonaldDworkinproposesatheoryofbothconstitutional(inhisterminology:

    political)rightsandhumanrights.Hewrites:

    Itseemswidelyagreedthatnotallpoliticalrightsarehumanrights.Peoplewhoallacceptthatgovernment

    mustshowequalconcernforallitsmembersdisagreeaboutwhateconomicsystemthatrequiresButalmost

    noneofthemwouldsuggestthatthemanynationsthatdisagreewithhisopinionareguiltyofhumanrights

    violationsWhynot?Humanrightsarewidelythoughttobespecialand,accordingtomostcommentators

    andtopoliticalpractice,moreimportantandfundamental.26

    The secondquote,by JosephRaz,dealswith the correspondingpointof the relationship

    betweenlegitimateauthorityandnationalsovereignty.Myinteresthereisnotinlegitimate

    authority but in constitutional legitimacy, and I have no space here to explore the

    26RonaldDworkin,JusticeforHedgehogs,???.

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    11/22

    11

    relationshipbetween the two.However,Razsbasic intuition alsoworks, Ibelieve, ifwe

    replacehisreferencetolegitimateauthoritywithconstitutionallegitimacy.

    Wemustnot confuse the limitsof sovereigntywith the limitsof legitimate authority. The sovereigntyof

    states sets limits to the right of others to interfere with their affairs. The notion of sovereignty is the

    counterpart of that of rightful international intervention. The criteria determining the limits of legitimate

    authoritydependon themoralityof theauthoritysactions.However,noteveryactionexceedinga stateslegitimateauthoritycanbeareasonforinterferencebyotherstates,whateverthecircumstances, justasnot

    everymoralwrongdoingbyanindividualcanjustifyinterventionbyotherstostoporpunishit.27

    Thus, according to the widely held view reflected in the above statements, there is a

    distancebetweenconstitutional legitimacyandconstitutionalrightsontheonehand,and

    internationalhuman rightsand statesovereigntyon theother.This is theview that Iwill

    challenge in this section.My strategywillbenegative: Iwill show that, starting from the

    theoryof constitutional rightswhich Ioutlined in theprevious section, there isneithera

    morallycoherentwaytocreatethisdistance,noristhereaneedforit.Itfollowsthatifwe

    wanttoprotecthumanrightsattheinternationallevel,weshouldacceptpreciselythesame

    accountofrightsthatisappropriateatthenationallevel,andthatthemoralboundariesof

    constitutionallegitimacyarethesameasthoseofnationalsovereignty.

    Structurally,therearetwowaystotinkerwiththetheoryofconstitutionalrightspresented

    intheprevioussection inordertomake itmoreminimalist.First,onecouldtrytoreduce

    the range of interests protected as rights. Second, one could focus on the standard of

    justification (the reasonableness standard) andmake this standard looser. Iwill consider

    bothoptionsinturn,concludingthatnoneofthemcanbeimplementedwithoutmakingthe

    resultingaccountofinternationalhumanrightsmorallyunappealing.

    1.Limitingtherangeofinterestsprotectedasrights

    I argued above that under the global model of constitutional rights, all of a persons

    (autonomy) interestsareprotectedas rights.Thus,aperson can, toemploy two famous

    Germancasesagain,successfullyclaimarighttofeedbirdsinaparkortogoriding inthe

    woods. Theunderlying idea of this broad scope of rights is that every state action (and

    omission) which affects a person in a morally relevant way requires justification. To

    translate this right tojustification28 intoa theoryof rights, it isnecessary toprotectall

    autonomy interestsofapersonattheprima faciestage,and toassessthejustifiabilityof

    theirlimitationatthejustificationstage,usingtheproportionalitytest.

    Now,an

    international

    human

    rights

    theorist

    might

    respond

    by

    arguing

    that

    while

    itmay

    be

    appropriatetoprotectsuchabroadscopeofrightsinthecontextofnationalconstitutional

    law, it would be inappropriate to do so at the international level. Thus, the range of

    interests protected as rights ought to be drawnmore narrowly, introducing a threshold

    whichdistinguishesrightsfrommereinterests.

    Forthisideatosucceed,however,itwouldhavetobepossibletoidentifyathresholdwhich

    pointstoaprincipleddistinctionbetweenthoseinterestswhichdoandthosewhichdonot

    attracttheprotectionofrights.Afirstideamightbetodrawthelineinapragmaticway:we

    27Raz,

    Human

    Rights

    Without

    Foundations

    28RainerForst,TheJustificationofHumanRightsandtheBasicRighttoJustification: AReflexiveApproach,

    120(2010)Ethics711.

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    12/22

    12

    could say thatonly interestsof, say, fundamental importanceattract theprotectionof

    internationalhuman rights.But theproblemwithpragmaticapproaches isprecisely their

    pragmatic character, that is, theabsenceofprinciple.A second,morepromising strategy

    would be to consider the existence of a qualitative difference between rights andmere

    interests.Themostpromisingattempt inthisdirectionhasbeenmadebyJamesGriffin in

    hisbookOnHuman

    Rights.Heargues thatthethresholdcanbederived from the ideaof

    personhood:

    Human life is different from the life of other animals.We human beings have a conception of

    ourselvesandofourpastand future.We reflectandassess.We formpicturesofwhatagood life

    would beAndwe try to realise thesepictures. This iswhatwemean by adistinctively human

    existenceAndwevalueourstatusashumanbeingsespeciallyhighly,oftenmorehighlythaneven

    ourhappiness.Thisstatuscentresonourbeingagentsdeliberating,assessing,choosing,andacting

    tomakewhatweseeasagoodlifeforourselves.

    Human rights can then be seen as protections of our human standing or, as I shall put it, our

    personhood.Andonecanbreakdownthenotionofpersonhoodintoclearercomponentsbybreaking

    downthenotionofagency.Tobeanagent, inthefullestsenseofwhichwearecapable,onemust(first)chooseonesownpaththrough lifethat is,notbedominatedorcontrolledbysomeoneor

    somethingelse(call it autonomy).[And](third)othersmustnotforciblystoponefrompursuing

    whatoneseesasaworthwhilelife(callthisliberty).29

    Griffintellsusmoreabouthowdemandingtherighttolibertyis:

    [L]iberty applies to the final stage of agency, namely to the pursuit of ones conception of a

    worthwhile life.Bynomeanseverythingweaimatmatterstothat.Therefore,societywillaccepta

    personsclaimtotheprotectionoflibertyonlyiftheclaimmeetsthematerialconstraintthatwhatis

    atstakeisindeedconceivableasmatteringtowhetherornotwefunctionasnormativeagents.30

    Griffins idea is that personhood functionsboth as thebasisofhuman rights and as alimitation on their scope: only those interests that are important for personhood are

    protected as human rights. However, this account does notwork. Its failure is that the

    personhood approach does not offer a coherentway to delineate interests relevant for

    personhoodfromotherinterests.ForGriffin,personhoodrequiresautonomyandliberty(in

    myterminology,personalautonomy):basically,controloverones life.But itrequiresonly

    thatkindofcontroloveroneslifethatisrequiredbythevalueofpersonhood.Thisleaves

    open the question ofwhat the test is for determiningwhether some instanceof liberty

    (autonomy) isrequiredforpersonhood.Mysuspicion isthat it issimplyimportance.For

    example,Griffinexplainsthatthedomainof liberty is limitedtowhat ismajorenoughto

    count

    as

    part

    of

    the

    pursuit

    of

    a

    worthwhile

    life

    31

    .

    At

    another

    point,

    he

    defends

    a

    human

    righttogaymarriageonthegroundofitscentralitytocharacteristichumanconceptionsof

    aworthwhilelife.32Thus,itseemsthatthethresholdofpersonhoodsimplyrefersbacktoa

    slidingscaleofimportance:aninterestthatismajorenoughorcentralwillacquirethe

    statusofahumanright.Butsuchaslidingscalecannot,asexplainedabove,dothemoral

    work.Thethresholdwouldhavetobebetweennotquitemajorenoughandbarelymajor

    enoughor notquite centraland barely central.Then,underGriffinsmodel,all that

    29JamesGriffin,OnHumanRights(OUP2008)at3233.Griffinssecondpoint,omittedinthequote,isabout

    minimumprovisionofresourcesandcapabilitiesthatittakestobeanagent.30Ibid

    at

    167.

    31Ibidat234(emphasisadded).

    32Ibidat163(emphasisadded).

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    13/22

    13

    separatesaninterestthatisjustbelowfromonethatisjustabovethethresholdisasmall

    difference in terms of importance or centrality. This small difference, however, cannot

    justifythegreatnormativesignificancethatforproponentsofthresholdmodelscomeswith

    oneof thembeinga simple interestand theotherahuman right. Ibelieve that this isa

    generalproblemofthresholdtheoriesthatisnotlimitedtoGriffinsaccount.33Ifthatistrue,

    thentheonlypossibleconclusionisthatthethresholdrequirementshouldbedroppedand

    itshouldbeacknowledgedthatthescopeofinternationalhumanrights,justasthescopeof

    national constitutional rights, extends to everything that is in the interest of apersons

    autonomy.However,thisbeingso,wemustabandontheideathatbyreducingthescopeof

    interestsprotectedasrightswecanmakesenseofthewidespreadintuitionthatthereisa

    distance between themoral demands of national constitutional rights and international

    humanrights.

    2.Loweringthestandardofjustification

    The second structural possibility to construct a distance between national constitutional

    rightsand internationalhumanrights istorelaxthestandardofjustification.Asexplained

    above, under national constitutional rights, a policy limiting a right will be considered

    justified if it is reasonable (asopposed tocorrect).Thismeans that tobeconstitutionally

    legitimate,thelegislaturedoesnothavetofindthebestpossible,oroneright,answerto

    thesocialproblemitaddresses;ratheritactslegitimatelyifitsanswerisreasonable.

    The importance of this point cannot be overstated.Much of the discussion about the

    justifiabilityofjudicial reviewat thenational level restson themistakenassumption that

    whencourts

    adjudicate

    constitutional

    rights,

    they

    thereby

    remove

    the

    choice

    of

    policies

    from the democratically elected legislature.34 This view is however at least an

    overstatement:courtsdonotremovechoiceassuchfromthelegislature;theyremoveonly

    thepossibilitytochooseanunreasonabledisproportionatepolicy.Thechoicebetween

    allpossiblereasonableproportionatepoliciesremainswiththelegislature.Whenacourt

    declaresthatapolicyrespectsconstitutionalrights, itsaysnothingmoreor lessthanthat

    thepolicyunder consideration is reasonable; itdoesnotpassjudgmentonwhether it is

    correct (this is simplynot thecourts task).Conversely,whereacourtdeclaresapolicya

    violationofconstitutionalrights,itdecidesthatthisparticularpolicyisoutsidethescopeof

    reasonablepolicies;butitleavestothelegislaturethetaskofchoosingareasonablepolicy.

    With this clarification inmind, let us turn toDworkins proposal as to how to delineate

    constitutional(political)frominternationalhumanrights:

    Wemust insist that thoughpeopledohaveapolitical right toequal concernand respecton the right

    conception,theyhaveamorefundamental,becausemoreabstract,right.Theyhavearighttobetreatedwith

    theattitudethatthesedebatespresupposeandreflectarighttobetreatedasahumanbeingwhosedignity

    fundamentallymatters.

    Thatmoreabstractrighttherighttoanattitude isthebasichumanright.Governmentmayrespectthat

    basichumanrightevenwhenitfailstoachieveacorrectunderstandingofmoreconcretepoliticalrightsWe

    33 For a similar view, cf. Joseph Raz, Human Rightswithout Foundations, in Samantha Besson and John

    Tasioulas(eds),

    The

    Philosophy

    of

    International

    Law(2010),

    at

    326;

    Dworkin,

    Justice

    for

    Hedgehogs,

    34JeremyWaldron,TheCoreoftheCaseAgainstJudicialReview,(2006)115YaleLawJournal,1346at1386

    1395.

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    14/22

    14

    ask:Canthelawsandpoliciesofaparticularpoliticalcommunitysensiblybeinterpretedasanattempt,evenif

    finallya failedattempt, to respect thedignityof those in itspower?Ormustat leastsomeof its lawsand

    policiesbeunderstoodasarejectionofthoseresponsibilities,towardeitheritssubjectsatlargeorsomegroup

    withinthem?Thelatterlawsorpoliciesviolateahumanright.

    Thetestcannotbesatisfiedsimplybyanationspronouncementofgoodfaith.Itissatisfiedonlywhena

    governmentsoverallbehaviour isdefensibleunderan intelligible,even ifunconvincing,conceptionofwhat

    ourtwoprinciplesofhumandignityrequire.35

    As the above quote shows, Dworkinmust believe that in the domain of constitutional

    (political) rights, legitimacy requires thatgovernmentget it right, i.e. that it find theone

    rightanswertotherightsissueathand.Thiscanbecontrastedwiththedomainofhuman

    rightswhich, according to Dworkin, require only that government act in good faith. As

    Dworkinexplains, thegood faith requirement isnota subjectivebutanobjective test: it

    requires that the respectivepolicybedefensibleunderan intelligible conceptionofwhat

    dignityrequires.Inlightofthis,IbelieveitisfairtoDworkinsintentionstoequateingood

    faithwithreasonable: the functionof thegood faith requirement is toacknowledgea

    sphereofacceptabledisagreementwhileneverthelessrequiringthatthepolicyatstakebe

    objectivelyjustifiable. Thismust in substance amount to a reasonableness standard: an

    unreasonablepolicy isnotdefensibleasenacted ingoodfaithoras intelligible,whereasa

    reasonablepolicyisdefensibleinthisway.

    CanweuseDworkins ideatocreateadistancebetweennationalconstitutionalrightsand

    internationalhumanrightsundertheglobalmodel? Ibelievethatwecannot.Dworkincan

    createthisdistanceinhistheoryonlybecausethestandardofjustificationinhisaccountof

    constitutional(political)rightsiscorrectness.Icannotassessherewhetherthispositionis

    viablewithinDworkinstheoryofrights(Ihavemydoubts).Butontheassumptionthatitis,

    itisindeedastructuralpossibilityforDworkintothenrelaxthecorrectnessstandardwhichhe uses for constitutional rights and adopt a reasonableness (good faith) standard for

    internationalhumanrights.Bywayofcontrast,inthetheoryofconstitutionalrightswhich

    underlies the global model, the standard of review is already only a reasonableness

    standard anyway; therefore any further relaxation of this standard would imply that

    internationalhuman rightshavenoobjection topolicieswhichaffectpeoples rightsand

    whicharenotevenreasonable.Reasonablemeanssomethinglikesupportedbyadequate

    reasons. It is implausible tohold thatapolicywhich limitsapersonshuman rightsand

    which isnot supportedbyadequate reasonsneverthelesscomplieswithhuman rights. In

    otherwords,we cannot go below the threshold of reasonableness, and given that this

    thresholdisalreadyemployedbynationalconstitutionalrights,wecannotcreateadistancebetween national constitutional rights and international human rights by relaxing the

    standardofjustification.

    Theaboveargument isdirectedat the relationshipbetweennationalconstitutional rights

    and international human rights. We can examine the same issue by contrasting

    constitutional legitimacyandnational sovereignty.RememberRazs claim,quotedabove,

    thatthetworefertodifferentstandards,withnationalsovereigntybeingwiderthanwhat

    he calls legitimateauthority,andwhat I call constitutional legitimacy.Why is this so, for

    Raz?

    35RonaldDworkin,JusticeforHedgehogs,3356(emphasisintheoriginal).

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    15/22

    15

    As Isee it,thecorepoint,which istoocomplextobedweltuponhere, isthatmuchofthecontentofthe

    moralprincipleswhichgovernsocial relationsand the structureofsocialorganisation isdeterminedby the

    contingentpracticesofdifferent societies.Hence theprincipleswhich shouldgovern international relations

    cannotjustbeageneralisation oftheprinciplesofjusticewhichgovernanyindividualsociety.Howdoesthis

    bearon the issueof state sovereignty?Directly itestablishes adegreeof variabilitybetween standardsof

    justice and thereby variability in the precise content and scope of rightswhich apply in different political

    societies.Thisspeaksforcaution ingivingoutsidersarightto intervene intheaffairsofotherstates. Italso

    suggeststhedesirabilityofallowingpoliticalsocietiesfreedomfromtoocloseexternalscrutiny,tobefreeto

    developtheirownrightsaffectingpractices.36

    ByRazsownadmission,thisisonlythesketchofanargument.Inwhatfollows,Iwillunpack

    andinterpretthestatement,andIwillagainreplaceRazstermoflegitimateauthoritywith

    constitutional legitimacy; so what follows is the critique of a position which Raz

    presumably holds only partially. There is a close connection between constitutional

    legitimacy and the principles of justice that govern any individual society. But those

    principles of justice will vary from society to society. This is not so because of moral

    relativism (whichRazrightlyrejects),orbecausewhateverprinciplesasocietyhappensto

    acceptmake thoseprinciplesjust.Rather, it isbecauseofwhatRazcallsabenign social

    relativism, according towhich the principles ofjusticewill be sensitive to social facts.

    Applied to the issuehere,certainpracticeswillhavedevelopedwithina society,and the

    principlesofjusticewhichareapplicabletothatsocietywilloratleastmaybesensitiveto

    thosepractices.Henceitisnotpossibletosimplytakeonesocietysprinciplesofjusticeand

    applythemtoanothersocietywithdifferentpracticesandstructures;andgiventheclose

    connection between justice and constitutional legitimacy, it is not possible to equate

    nationalsovereigntywithanygivensocietysstandardsforconstitutionallegitimacy.Inlight

    ofthis,cautionisrequiredwhenassessingquestionsofjusticefromtheoutside,andnotoo

    closeexternalscrutinyshouldbeapplied.

    To illustrate this idea, letus take the exampleof the right to education,which Raz also

    considersinhispaper,albeitinadifferentcontext.LetussaythatincountryA,peoplehave

    amoralrightagainstthestatetobeprovidedwitheducation,butthatincountryB,people

    havenosuchmoral rightbecause,say, thesocialstructuresof thatcountryaresuch that

    people can have a rewarding lifewithout formal instruction, or because in that country

    education isprovidedby the familyorclanand the stateneednotget involved.Thus, in

    countryA,justice requires that thestateprovideeducationand incountryB itdoesnot.

    Thus,aninternationaljudgewhoisacitizenofcountryAandwhoiscalledupontoassess

    thehumanrightssituationincountryBcouldmistakenlybelievethateducationisahuman

    right(based

    on

    her

    experience

    at

    home);

    in

    order

    to

    avoid

    such

    mistakes

    she

    should

    adopt

    anattitudeofcaution,andadditionallysheshouldkeepinmindthefactthatsocietiesneed

    freedomtodeveloptheirownrightsaffectingpractices.

    Thefirstproblemwiththisapproachistheassumedlinkbetweenconstitutionallegitimacy

    andjustice. Constitutional legitimacy is not about securingjustice. Rather, as explained

    above, it is aboutwhether apolicy is supportedby adequate reasons:wemay say, it is

    aboutwhetherapolicyreliesonareasonable,asopposedtotheonecorrect,conceptionof

    justice.Inotherwords,apolicymaybeunjustbutneverthelessconstitutionallylegitimate.

    Thismustbetruebecauseifconstitutionallegitimacyrequiredjustice,thentherewouldbe

    36 Joseph Raz, Human Rights without Foundations, in Samantha Besson and John Tasioulas (eds), The

    PhilosophyofInternationalLaw(2010),...

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    16/22

    16

    noroomfordemocraticdisagreementaboutquestionsofjusticerather,onlyone,namely

    theonejust,policywouldbeconstitutionally legitimate;suchanapproachwouldbeflatly

    incompatible with the value of democracy which requires the people or their

    representativestoengageindiscussionsandcontroversiesaboutandultimatelyholdavote

    on what justice requires. This means that constitutional legitimacy leaves states a

    considerableroomformanoeuvre:allitinsistsonisthatapolicybeareasonableattemptat

    justice. From the point of constitutional legitimacy, states have an enormous leeway in

    working outwhich conception ofjusticeworks best for them, and theymay take their

    structureofsocialrelation,history,andsocialpracticesintoaccountwhendoingso.Thereis

    nomoralneed,nor is there themoralpossibility, tomake this leewayevenwider in the

    contextofnationalsovereigntybecausedoingsowouldimplyawardingthedignifyinglabel

    offalling intothesphereofnationalsovereigntytoapolicywhich isnotonlyunjustbut

    which cannot even be defended as a reasonable attempt atjustice. The pluralism and

    diversitywhichrightlyoughttobecherishedintheinternationalarenamust,tobemorally

    defensible, be a diversity and pluralism of reasonable conceptions ofjustice, not one of

    unreasonableandthereforeunjustifiableones.

    Inlightofthisclarification,letusassessRazstwoargumentsaboutwhysovereigntyiswider

    thanconstitutional legitimacy.Oneofhispoints isthatsocietiesneedfreedomtodevelop

    theirownrightsaffectingpractices,andthattherefore internationalsupervisionoughtnot

    tobe too intrusive.This argument isunconvincing: the freedom todevelopones rights

    affectingpractices issurelyvaluablewhenusedtodeveloprightsrespectingpractices.But

    what if a society uses it to develop rightsviolating practices? Societies do indeed need

    freedom to develop their own practices, but the only freedom they need is to choose

    between different reasonable conceptions of justice, not the freedom to choose

    unreasonableones;

    and,

    as

    pointed

    out

    above,

    policies

    based

    on

    reasonable

    conceptions

    of

    justicedonotviolaterightsandremainwithinthesphereofnationalsovereignty.

    Razs second point is that there are certain difficulties with outsiders assessing the

    requirements ofjustice in a given society. As a preliminary point, these difficulties are

    reduced but do not entirely go away when we replace justice with constitutional

    legitimacy:theyarereducedbecause itwilloftenbeeasier,especially foranoutsider,to

    assesswhether apolicy is reasonable than to assesswhether it is correct;however, the

    problems still persist to an extent because the reasonableness of a policy will still be

    sensitivetolocalcontingenciestosomeextent.

    IbelievethatRazhasavalidpointhere,albeitonewhichleadshimtodrawanunattractiveconclusion.Letustaketheexampleofaninternationaljudge.Itistruethataninternational

    judgecannotsimplyrelyontheconceptionofconstitutionallegitimacyadoptedinhishome

    countryandapply ittothesocietyfromwhichthecaseonhisdeskoriginates.Rather,he

    mustask thequestionofwhetherthepolicyatstake is legitimateunder thestandardsof

    legitimacyofthesocietywhosepolicyitis;andestablishingthismayonoccasionbedifficult

    orevenimpossibleforhim.However,theproperresponsetothisproblemisnottoloosen

    the moral requirements of sovereignty but rather to acknowledge that sometimes an

    outsidersempiricaland/ornormativeknowledgeislimited,andthereforetoshowadegree

    ofdeferencetowardstheoriginaldecisionmaker.

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    17/22

    17

    Dealingwiththiskindofuncertaintyisthedailybusinessofinternationalcourtssuchasthe

    ECtHR,whichhasdevelopedstrategiesanddoctrinestodososatisfactorily. Itsjudgments

    usuallycontain longsectionssettingoutthedomesticcontextoftherights issueatstake;

    this enables the Court to assess whether the policy is justifiable within the respective

    domesticcontext.Furthermoreandmoreimportantly,theCourtsdoctrineofthemarginof

    appreciation acknowledges and provides away of dealingwith the specific institutional

    limitationsunderwhichit,asaninternationalcourt,operates.Theclassicstatementofthe

    marginofappreciationwassetoutinthefamousHandysidecase:

    Byreasonoftheirdirectandcontinuouscontactwiththevitalforcesoftheircountries,Stateauthoritiesarein

    principle inabetterpositionthan the internationaljudge togiveanopinionon [thequestionofwhethera

    restrictionoftherightisnecessary].[...][I]tisforthenationalauthoritiestomaketheinitialassessmentofthe

    realityofthepressingsocialneedimpliedbythenotionof'necessity'inthiscontext.

    Consequently,Article10(2)leavestotheContractingStatesamarginofappreciation.[...]Nevertheless,Article

    10 (2) does not give the Contracting States an unlimited power of appreciation. The Court,which [...] is

    responsibleforensuringtheobservanceofthoseStates'engagements, isempoweredtogivethefinalruling

    onwhethera 'restriction'or 'penalty' is reconcilablewith freedomofexpressionasprotectedbyArticle10.

    ThedomesticmarginofappreciationthusgoeshandinhandwithaEuropeansupervision.(paras48,49)

    ThemarginofappreciationdoctrineenablestheCourttodefertothenationalauthoritiesof

    therespectivememberstate inasituationwhere ithasdoubtsaboutthejustifiabilityofa

    policy but is simultaneously unable to convince itself of its unjustifiability (because of

    epistemicuncertainty).Insuchcases,theCourtwilloftenholdthatthemeasureatstakelies

    withinthemarginofappreciationoftherespectivememberstate. Itshouldbenotedthat

    themarginofappreciationdoctrineisnotonlyoneofthecornerstonesofEuropeanhuman

    rights law,butalsooneofthemostdifficultandcontroversialpartsof it;andtheCourt is

    often rightly accused of taking recourse to it too lightly. So my goal here is not to

    wholeheartedlydefend theCourtsapproach; rather it is tomake themore limitedpointthat there are indeed caseswhere the doctrine is rightly invoked because of epistemic

    uncertainty.

    TogiveanexampleofascenariowhereitisdifficultandmaybeimpossiblefortheCourtto

    establishtherightoutcome,letusconsidertheRefahPartycase.TurkeybannedtheRefah

    PartywhichitconsideredextremistandathreattoTurkishdemocracy,inparticularbecause

    of its rightwing Islamic agenda, which included, among other things, a proposal to

    introduce aspects of Sharia law. In a nutshell, one of the important issues at stakewas

    whetherTurkeywasjustifiedintakingatoughstancetowardsreligious,inparticularIslamic,

    parties,in

    order

    to

    protect

    its

    commitment

    to

    what

    has

    been

    labelled

    militant

    secularism,

    which in turnwas regardedbyTurkeyasacornerstoneofprotecting itsdemocracy from

    beingunderminedandeventually, toput itbluntly, slipping intoan Islamicdictatorship. I

    regardthiscaseasaparadigmexampleofthescenarioRazmusthaveinmind,whereitis

    extremelydifficultifnotimpossibleforanoutsidersuchasaninternationaljudgetodecide

    whetherTurkeysactionofdissolvingtheRefahpartywasjustified,andthereasonforthis

    difficulty lies in the fact thatnormative considerationsabout the legitimacyofbanninga

    politicalpartyareinextricablyboundupwithquestionsrelatingtoTurkeyshistory,culture,

    andpolitics,whichmake itdifficult ifnot impossible foranoutsider to resolve the issue

    satisfactorily. So, to repeat, Raz has a point. But if I am given the task to resolve a

    mathematicalpuzzlewhich istoodifficultforme,theresponsetomypersonalintellectual

    limitations cannot be to relax the standards ofmathematical truth. Similarly,where an

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    18/22

    18

    internationalcourtisunabletodeterminewhetheracountryspolicyreflectsareasonable

    conception of justice, we should not respond by relaxing the moral requirements of

    sovereignty.Rather,weshouldacknowledgethattheproblemofepistemicuncertaintymay

    on occasion lead international courts to defer to the respective national authorities

    problematic and unsatisfactory as this may be , and at the same time insist that

    sovereigntycanbeinvokedonlyinsupportofjustifiable(reasonable)policies.

    3.Conclusion

    Both strategies of creating a distance between national constitutional rights and

    constitutional legitimacy on the one hand and international human rights and national

    sovereigntyontheotherfailed.Totheextentthatconstitutionalrightsaremaximalistin

    characterbyprotectingall(autonomy)interestsasrights,thiscannotbeabandonedwithout

    introducing arbitrariness, and to the extent that constitutional rights areminimalist by

    insisting not on a correctness but only on a reasonableness standard ofjustification, afurtherloweringofthestandardisneithernecessarynorcoherentlypossible.Itfollowsthat

    national constitutional rights and constitutional legitimacy on the one hand and

    international human rights and national sovereignty on the other have the samemoral

    structure.Thenextsectionwillfleshoutsomeoftheimplicationsofthisview.

    IV.Implications1.Analternativeexplanationofinternationalhumanrightsminimalism,anditslimits

    Many scholars believe thatminimalism be it an absoluteminimalism or a relative

    minimalism(minimalismofinternationalhumanrightsinrelationtonationalconstitutional

    law) isbuilt into themoral structureof internationalhuman rights.However, theonly

    defensiblekindofminimalismispragmaticandthereforeexternaltothemoralstructureof

    internationalhumanrights.Therearegoodreasonswhymuchofinternationalhumanrights

    practicefocusesonpreventingparticularlyegregiousviolationsofhumanrights.Butthose

    reasonshavenothing todowith themoral structureof internationalhuman rights; they

    simplyreflectjudgmentsaboutpriorities.

    While it isplausibletodefendsomeformofminimalismonpragmaticgrounds,wewould

    howeverpaintaonesidedpictureofinternationalhumanrightsifwearguedthatallofitis

    oroughttobeminimalistforpragmaticreasons.Pragmaticminimalismcanbejustifiedonly

    to theextent that it ispolitically impossibleorexcessively costly toprotect international

    humanrightscomprehensively. Inotherwords,weshouldworktowardsastateofaffairs

    where international human rights are comprehensively protected, and where it is not

    necessary to limit theirpractical reach to thepreventionofonly theworsthuman rights

    violations. In this sense the theoryof internationalhuman rightsproposedhere ispartly

    aspirational.

    I say partly because there exists already one instance of a legal institutionalisation of

    human rights at the international levelwhichbroadly reflects themodel I advocate: theEuropean Convention onHuman Rights.Approaching thejurisprudence of the European

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    19/22

    19

    CourtofHumanRightswiththeideasofhumanrightsminimalisminmindwouldbefutile:it

    is about as maximalist in character as even the most expansive system of national

    constitutionalrights.First,wecanidentifyrightsinflationinthejurisprudenceoftheECtHR:

    theCourttendstoreadevenrelativelytrivialinterestsintotheConvention,mostofteninto

    Article8(therighttorespectforprivateandfamilylife).Togivejustoneexample,inacase

    involving residents near Heathrow airport complaining about the noise caused by night

    flights, the Court held that Article 8 also covers the right not to be affected by aircraft

    noise37dismissivelydubbedthehumanrighttosleepwell

    38byGeorgeLetsas.Second,

    the Court protects negative aswell as positive obligations in fact, it hasmore or less

    dropped the distinction between the two.39 (It admittedly does not, at least not

    comprehensively, protect socioeconomic rights,whichwere deliberately left out of the

    Convention.) Third, the Court applies the proportionality test and, by and large, has no

    scruplesaboutdeclaringameasureofamember statedisproportionateand therefore in

    violationofhumanrights.Togive,again,justoneexample:theCourtrecentlyruledagainst

    theUnitedKingdom for failing toprotect the rightof an employeeofBritishAirways to

    openlywearasmallcrossduringwork,arguingthatBAs interest inmaintainingacertaincorporateimagewasoutweighedbytheapplicantsrighttomanifestherreligion.

    40Whilea

    comprehensiveanalysisoftheCourtsjurisprudenceisbeyondthescopeofthispaper,itis

    fair to say that its approach to human rights is structurally extremely close to that of

    national constitutional courts. This being so, it cannot be argued that the model of

    internationalhumanrightswhichIproposeinthispapercannotworkinpractice.Itdoes,by

    andlarge,workinpractice,namelyinthememberstatesoftheCouncilofEurope,andnot

    onlydoes itworksomehow;rather,thejurisprudenceoftheCourt incharge iswidelyand

    rightlyregardedastheposterchildofinternationalhumanrightslaw.

    2.Whatsthepointofinternationalhumanrightslaw?

    If,asIargue,themoralstructuresofnationalconstitutionalrightsandinternationalhuman

    rightsareidenticalandifweshouldworktowardsastateofaffairswheretheinternational

    orderprotectsfundamentalrightsaswellassomenationalconstitutionalcourtsalreadydo,

    thenthis leadstothequestionofthepointofthisadditional layerofrightsprotection.At

    firstglance,aninstitutionalisedmechanismfortheprotectionofinternationalhumanrights

    whichreliesonthesamestandardsasnationalconstitutionalcourtsmayseemoddandan

    unnecessarycomplicationandduplicationofresponsibilities.

    Thereis,however,nothingsuspiciousaboutthefactthatunderthemodeladvocatedhere,

    national constitutional courts and international human rights courts apply the same

    standardsofreview.The internationalmechanismsfortheprotectionofhumanrightswill

    only kick inwhen somethinghas gonewrong at thenational level.Thus, ifonewere to

    adoptaminimalistapproach to internationalhuman rights, then the internationalactors

    wouldonlybecomeactiveafterthenational levelhasfailedtodelivereventhisminimum

    standard. Inthemodeladvocatedhere,the internationalactorswould interferewhenthe

    37Hattonv.U.K.

    38Letsas

    39Addexample.

    40Eweidav.U.K.

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    20/22

    20

    respectivenationalconstitutionalcourtmadeamistakeandacceptedapolicyascomplying

    withtherequirementsofconstitutionallegitimacy(whichareidenticaltothoseofnational

    sovereignty)wheninrealityitviolatedthem.Thus,thepointofinternationalhumanrights

    lawistopolicetheboundariesofastatessovereignty.

    A further question is whether there is a moral obligation on states to create legallyinstitutionalisedmechanisms for the protection of international human rights. I believe

    there are, and Iwill focus on twomoral reasons for states to sign up for a system of

    internationalhumanrightsprotection.Thefirstcentresoneachstatesdutytoensureand

    improveitsownlegitimacyinrelationtoitscitizens.41Oneimportantaspectofitslegitimacy

    isitsrespectforitscitizensfundamentalrights.Therearegoodoutcomerelatedreasonsto

    hold that an adequate institutionalisation of fundamental rightswill provide not only a

    national levelof constitutionalprotectionbut includeanadditional international layeras

    well.42First,theinternationallayermaystabiliseacountryslongtermcommitmenttothe

    valuesofdemocracy,theruleof law,andfundamentalrights,andmaymake itharderfor

    forces seeking to undermine or destroy its democratic culture to succeed. In a nationalcontext, the integrity of a constitutional court ismostunder threatwhen the governing

    partiesseek toundermine itswork, forexample through theappointmentofjudgeswho

    support the governments ideology, the tinkeringwithprocedural rules,or constitutional

    amendments.While it is true that international courts, too, operate in an environment

    which involves political pressure (this is clearly visible in the case of the ECtHR which

    suspiciouslyoftenbacktracksfrom itsownjurisprudencewhen facedwithresistance from

    nationalgovernments), itwillbe impossible foranyonenationalgovernmentgoneastray

    and acting in isolation to do serious damage to an international court. Second and

    independently, there is reason to assume that international courtswill sometimes reach

    betteroutcomes

    compared

    to

    national

    constitutional

    courts.

    National

    constitutional

    courts

    and international courts have their respective weaknesses and strengths. Among the

    strengthsofawelldesignednationalconstitutionalcourt isthat itsjudgeswillhavemore

    adequatewaysofacquiringtherelevantempiricalknowledgeonwhichthecorrectoutcome

    oflegalcases,includinghumanrightscases,oftendepends,andthattheywillhaveadeeper

    understanding of the principles of justice applicable to their respective society. An

    internationalcourtwill find itmoredifficulttoaccesstherelevantempiricaldata;and,as

    discussedabove,willalsoonoccasion find itmoredifficult toassess thejustifiabilityofa

    statespracticesfromtheoutside.InthecaseoftheEuropeanCourtofHumanRights,this

    oftenleadstheCourttoadoptarelativelyhighdegreeofdeferencetowardstherespective

    nationalauthorities,whichpotentiallyleadstoanunderprotectionofhumanrights.There

    arehoweveralso importantways inwhichan internationalcourtmaybebetterplacedto

    engageinjudicialreview:thehumanmindoftenleadsustotrustwhatwearefamiliarwith,

    andthereforeinthecaseofanationalconstitutionalcourt,thejudgesintimateknowledge

    oftheirlegalordermayonoccasionprecludeafreshandunbiasedassessmentofthelawat

    stake. Insuchsituations,an internationalcourt,asabodymostlymadeupofjudgesfrom

    41OnastatesobligationtoimproveitsownlegitimacyseeDworkin,ANewPhilosophyforInternationalLaw,

    (2013)Philosophy&PublicAffairs1,17.42Ileaveopenthefurtherquestionofwhetherthereareoutcomeindependentreasons(thatis,reasonswhich

    donot

    rest

    on

    the

    assumed

    ability

    of

    international

    courts

    to

    improve

    the

    overall

    level

    of

    rights

    protection)

    whichnecessitatetheexistenceofarighttoahearingbeforeaninternationalcourt.Forthenationalcontext,

    suchaclaimhasbeenmadebyAlonHarel,...andMattiasKumm,...

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    21/22

    21

    otherjurisdictions,maybemoreadequateand inabetterposition,relativelyspeaking,to

    identifycertainpathologiesofthepoliticsandpoliciesofanationalcommunity.

    The second reason forjoiningan international system for theprotectionofhuman rights

    can be derived from a states obligations to people living in other states and can be

    explained in the followingway.Human rights flow from a fundamental status of humanbeings which they possess simply by virtue of their humanity; wemay call this status

    human dignity. Violations of human dignity are a moral concern for everyone; this

    proposition is thebasisof theview,assumedby thispaper, that thesovereigntydefence

    doesnotholdinthecaseofaviolationofhumanrights:aviolatingstatecannotclaimthat

    itsviolationofhumanrightsisnotthebusinessofotherstates.Thus,everystateisundera

    moralobligationtotakeadequatestepsintheinternationalarenatoensurethatthehuman

    dignityofpeople living inotherstates isrespected.One importantwayofdischargingthis

    moralobligation istoparticipate in internationalsystemsofhuman rightsprotection that

    arelikelytoleadtoanimprovementinhumanrightscomplianceinthosestates.Thus,even

    acountrywhosedemocraticand rightsrespectingculture isofsuchahighquality that intermsofimprovingitslevelofrightsprotectionathomeithasnothingtogainfromjoining

    aninternationalsystemofrightsprotectionwillbeunderamoralobligationtoparticipateif

    by doing so it contributes to amore effective protection of human rights abroad. For

    example,thecurrentdebateintheUnitedKingdomaboutwhetherthecountryshouldleave

    theCouncilofEuropecentresalmostexclusivelyonthequestionofwhattheUKmayget

    outof stayingor leaving,andusuallyneglects the fact thatwhatever theanswer to that

    question may be, the more important consideration relates to the UKs obligation to

    contribute to making the ECHR a success across Europe and improving human rights

    complianceinothermemberstateswithalessimpressivedemocraticandrightsrespecting

    culturethan

    that

    of

    the

    UK.

    Which steps are adequate and therefore morally required will of course be a difficult

    question,andwill crucially involve strategic considerationsas to the likely successof the

    schemeunderconsiderationinimprovinghumanrightscomplianceinthelongrun.Assume

    thatthemeasureunderconsiderationisaregionalhumanrightstreatywhich includesthe

    rightofindividualstopetitionaninternationalcourtwiththefinalauthorityonquestionsof

    interpretation in otherwords, a scheme similar to the ECHR.Where the international

    situation is such that itcanbeexpected that thenewlycreatedcourtwill,on thewhole,

    functionwelland improvethecomplianceoftheparticipatingstateswiththedemandsof

    humandignity,astatewillbeunderanobligationtoparticipate inthisschemeeven if its

    rightssituationathomedoesnotneedimprovementandcanbeconsideredentirelystable

    even in the long run. Itowes thisdutynot to itsowncitizensbut to thepeopleofother

    stateswhose dignity is not currently adequately respected, orwho live in stateswhose

    democraticandrightsrespectingcultureisnotsufficientlymatureandneedsthestabilising

    effectofthistreaty inordertokeepthecountryonadignityrespectingcourse.Bywayof

    contrast,wheretheinternationalsituationissuchthatitcouldbeexpectedthatthetreaty

    under considerationwould not contribute tomore respect for dignity in the respective

    region for example because onewould have to expect thatmany of the participating

    countrieswould send incompetentorcorruptjudges to siton thenewcourt,orbecause

    there is no sufficient prospect of the new courts judgments being obeyed no such

    obligationwould arise. (However, in such a situation, other obligationswould of courseexist,thecrucialquestionbeingwhichstepsare likelyto improvecompliancewithhuman

  • 7/27/2019 Moller From Constitutional to International Human Rights

    22/22

    22

    rights over time.) Thus, importantly,my argument isnot thatwhatever the state of the

    world or the respective region, international human rights courts ought to be set up

    everywhere.Suchcourtsareonlyoneofarangeofpotentialmeasurestostabilisearegions

    respect forhuman rights in the long run,and they shouldonlybeusedwhere there isa

    reasonablechanceofthemsucceedingwiththeirwork.Thatsaid,wheretheconditionsare

    sufficiently favourable, there is an obligation to introduce them, for the reasons given

    above.

    Theaboveargumentclaimsthatstateshaveanobligationtotakeadequatestepstoprotect

    humanrightsinsideaswellasoutsidetheirownborders.Thepointcanbepushedfurther:I

    will claim that the creationof an international courtofhuman rightswill,under certain

    conditions,itselfbeamatterofhumanrights.Theargumenttothiseffectproceedsintwo

    steps and is structurally similar to, though substantively different from, establishing the

    existenceofamoralrightunderRazsinteresttheoryofrights.Razhasfamouslyarguedthat

    a rightexistswhereapersons interestgroundsduties inothers. Ina structurallyparallel

    way, I claim that a person has a right if someone else is under an obligationwhich isgrounded in thatpersons status;and this rightwillbeahuman right if the statusunder

    consideration is the status of human dignity. Thus, a person has a human right to the

    creationofan internationalhumanrightscourt ifstatesareunderanobligationtocreate

    such an institutional protection of human rights and if this obligation flows from that

    personshumandignity.Theobligationtocreateaninternationalhumanrightscourt,where

    itexists, is,asarguedabove,grounded in thestatusofhumandignityofespecially those

    peoplewhosehuman rightsare at riskofnotbeing adequately respected in theirhome

    states in the present or the future. This establishes the possibility of the existence of a

    humanrighttothecreationofaninternationalcourtofhumanrights.

    V.ConclusionThispaperhasdemonstratedthatinternationalhumanrightshavethesamemoralstructure

    as national constitutional rights and, in particular, that the widespread view that

    internationalhumanrightsaremoreminimalistthannationalconstitutionalrightscannotbe

    maintained. As has been shown, international human rights minimalism is neither

    coherently possible, nor is it desirable in the interests of a reasonable pluralism and

    diversityattheinternationallevel.Itfollowsthatminimalismcan,ifatall,onlybejustified

    pragmatically,asanecessarysettingofprioritiesinordertotackleatleastthemosturgent

    human rightsproblems.Butweshouldtry to limittheneed for thispragmatism,and the

    aspirationexpressedbythetheoryofinternationalhumanrightsendorsedhereisthatofa

    worldwhere the same levelof rightsprotection that todayalreadyexistsat thenational

    levelinmanycountriesisalsoendorsedandeffectivelyinstitutionalisedattheinternational

    level.