myopia and anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of...

57
Myopia and Anchoring * George-Marios Angeletos Zhen Huo September 26, 2018 Abstract We consider a stationary setting featuring forward-looking behavior, strategic complementarity, and incomplete information. We obtain an observational equivalence result that recasts the ag- gregate dynamics of this setting as that of a representative-agent model featuring two distortions: myopia, as in models with imperfect foresight; and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome, as in models with habit persistence and adjustment costs. We further show that the as-if distortions are larger when the general-equilibrium feedback, or the strategic complementarity, is stronger. These results offer a fresh perspective on the observable implications of informational frictions; build a useful bridge to the DSGE literature; and help reduce an uncomfortable gap be- tween the prevailing structural interpretations of the macroeconomic time series and the related microeconomic evidence. Finally, an empirical evaluation is offered in the context of inflation, wherein it is shown how our results can rationalize existing estimates of the Hybrid NKPC while also matching survey evidence on expectations. * We thank Alexander Kohlhas and Luigi Iovino for discussing our paper in, respectively, the 2018 Cambridge/INET conference and the 2018 Hydra/CEPR workshop. We also acknowledge useful comments from Jaroslav Borovicka, Simon Gilchrist, Jennifer La’O, Stephen Morris, Mikkel Plagborg-Moller and seminar participants at the aforementioned confer- ences, Columbia, NYU, CUHK, the 2018 Duke Macro Jamboree, the 2018 Barcelona GSE Summer Forum EGF Group, the SED 2018, the 2018 NBER Summer Institute Impulse and Propagation Mechanisms Group and Macro Perspectives Group. MIT and NBER; [email protected]. Yale University; [email protected].

Upload: vuliem

Post on 07-May-2019

216 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

MyopiaandAnchoring*

George-MariosAngeletos† ZhenHuo‡

September26, 2018

Abstract

Weconsiderastationarysettingfeaturingforward-lookingbehavior, strategiccomplementarity,

andincompleteinformation. Weobtainanobservationalequivalenceresultthatrecaststheag-

gregatedynamicsofthissettingasthatofarepresentative-agentmodelfeaturingtwodistortions:

myopia, asinmodelswithimperfectforesight; andanchoringofthecurrentoutcometothepast

outcome, asinmodelswithhabitpersistenceandadjustmentcosts. Wefurthershowthattheas-if

distortionsarelargerwhenthegeneral-equilibriumfeedback, orthestrategiccomplementarity, is

stronger. Theseresultsofferafreshperspectiveontheobservableimplicationsofinformational

frictions; buildausefulbridgetotheDSGE literature; andhelpreduceanuncomfortablegapbe-

tweentheprevailingstructuralinterpretationsofthemacroeconomictimeseriesandtherelated

microeconomicevidence. Finally, anempiricalevaluationisofferedinthecontextofinflation,

whereinitisshownhowourresultscanrationalizeexistingestimatesoftheHybridNKPC while

alsomatchingsurveyevidenceonexpectations.

*WethankAlexanderKohlhasandLuigi Iovino fordiscussingourpaper in, respectively, the2018Cambridge/INET

conferenceandthe2018Hydra/CEPR workshop. WealsoacknowledgeusefulcommentsfromJaroslavBorovicka, Simon

Gilchrist, JenniferLa’O,StephenMorris, MikkelPlagborg-Mollerandseminarparticipantsattheaforementionedconfer-

ences, Columbia, NYU,CUHK,the2018DukeMacroJamboree, the2018BarcelonaGSE SummerForumEGF Group, the

SED 2018, the2018NBER SummerInstituteImpulseandPropagationMechanismsGroupandMacroPerspectivesGroup.†MIT andNBER;[email protected].‡YaleUniversity; [email protected].

Page 2: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

1 Introduction

Forward-lookingbehaviorandequilibriumfeedbacksarecentral toourunderstandingofbusiness

cycles, asset-pricefluctuations, industrydynamics, andmore. Inthispaper, weopenanewwindow

intotheinterplayofthesefeatureswitharealisticfrictionintheamountofknowledgeagentshave

aboutthefundamentalsandaboutoneanother’sbeliefsandactions.

Wefirstestablishanobservationalequivalencebetweenarational-expectationssettingfeaturing

suchaninformationalfrictionandabehavioralvariantfeaturingtwodistortions:

• myopia, orextradiscountingoffutureoutcomes; and

• anchoringofcurrentoutcomestopastoutcomes, orbackward-lookingbehavior.

Wefurthershowthattheas-ifdistortionsarelargerwhenthegeneral-equilibrium(GE) feedback, or

thestrategiccomplementarity, isstronger, andelaborateontheunderlyingtheoreticalprinciples. We

finallybuildusefulconnectionstomultiplestrandsoftheliterature, addressadisturbingdisconnect

betweentheprevailingstructuralinterpretationsofthemacroeconomictimeseriesandtherelated

microeconomicevidence, andofferanempiricalevaluationinthecontextofinflation.

Framework. Westudyadynamicsettinginwhichtheoptimalaction(orbestresponse)ineach

perioddependspositivelyontheexpecteddiscountedpresentvaluesofanexogenousfundamental,

denotedby ξt, andtheaverageaction, denotedby at. Intheabsenceoftheinformationalfriction,

thissettingreducestoarepresentative-agentmodel, inwhich at obeysthefollowinglawofmotion:

at = φξt + δEt [at+1] , (1)

where φ > 0, δ ∈ (0, 1], and Et[·] denotestherationalexpectationoftherepresentativeagent.Condition(1)neststheEulerconditionoftherepresentativeconsumer, whichcorrespondstoag-

gregatedemand(ortheDynamicIS curve)intheNewKeynesianmodel, aswellastheNewKeynesian

PhilipsCurve(NKPC),whichdescribesaggregatesupply. Alternatively, thisconditioncanbereadas

anasset-pricingequation, with ξt standingfortheasset’sdividendand at foritsprice. Theseexamples

indicatethebroaderapplicabilityoftheresultswedevelopinthispaper.1

Wedepartfromtherepresentative-agentbenchmarkbyallowinginformationtobeincomplete

(i.e., noisyandheterogeneous). Thiscanbetheproductofeitherdispersedprivateinformation(Lucas,

1972; MorrisandShin, 2002)or rational inattention (Sims, 2003). Eitherway, thekey is thatwe

accommodate, notonly first-order uncertainty(imperfectknowledgeoftheunderlyingfundamental),

butalso higher-order uncertainty(uncertaintyaboutthebeliefsandactionsofothers). Thatis, welet

agentsfacerealisticdoubtsabouttheawareness, attentiveness, orresponsivenessof others.

1ApplicationsnotexploredheremayincludedynamicBertrandcompetitionandmarketswithnetworkexternalities.

1

Page 3: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Mainresult. Underappropriateassumptions, theincomplete-informationeconomyisshownto

beobservationallyequivalenttoavariant, complete-information, representative-agenteconomyin

whichcondition(1)ismodifiedasfollows:

at = φξt + δωfEt [at+1] + ωbat−1 (2)

forsome ωf < 1 and ωb > 0. Thefirstmodification(ωf < 1)representsmyopiatowardsthefuture, the

second(ωb > 0)anchorsthecurrentoutcometothepastoutcome. Theonedullstheforward-looking

behavior, theotheraddsabackward-lookingelement. Furthermore, bothdistortionsareshownto

increasewiththestrengthoftheGE feedback, orthedegreeofthestrategiccomplementarity.2

Theexactformofthisresultreliesonstrongassumptionsaboutthestochasticprocessfor ξt and

theinformationstructure. Itneverthelessstylizesafewmoregeneralinsights, whoserobustnesswe

documentinSection 7 underaflexiblespecificationofthestochasticityandtheinformation.

Onekeyinsight, whichbuildson AngeletosandLian (2018), explainthemyopia. Recallthat, in

oursetting, behaviordependscriticallyonexpectationsofthe future actionsofothers—e.g., current

aggregatespendingdependsonexpectationsoffutureaggregatespending, currentassetpricesdepend

onexpectationsoffutureassetprices, etc. Inequilibrium, suchexpectationsarepinneddownbythe

currentbeliefsof the futurebeliefsofothers. Because suchhigher-orderbeliefs tend tovary less

thanthecorrespondingfirst-orderbeliefs inresponsetoanyinnovationin ξt, it is as if theagents

discountthefutureoutcomesmoreheavilythaninthefrictionless, representative-agentbenchmark.

Furthermore, becausethedependenceofequilibriumbehavioronhigher-orderbeliefsincreaseswith

theGE feedback, orthestrategiccomplementarity, thiskindofmyopiaalsoincreaseswithit.3

Another key insight, which builds on Woodford (2003), Morris and Shin (2006) and Nimark

(2008), regardstheroleplayedbylearning. Learninginducesextrapersistenceinthebeliefsofthe

fundamentalandofthefutureoutcomes. Furthermore, thispersistenceisstrongerinthelatterbeliefs

thanintheformer, reflectingthesmallerdependenceofhigher-orderbeliefsonrecentinformation.

Thisexplainswhythecurrentoutcomeappearstobeanchoredtothepastoutcomeataratethat, like

ourformofmyopia, increaseswiththestrengthoftheGE feedback, orthestrategiccomplementarity.

Weaddtotheliterature, notonlybyblendingtheseinsightsandofferingafewmore, butalsoby

operationalizingthemintermsofourobservational-equivalenceresult, whichisnew. Alsonewisthe

analysisinSection 7. Thisallowsforaflexiblespecificationofthestochasticityandthehigher-order

2SuchGE feedbacksareoften“hidden”behindthekindofrepresentative-agentequilibriumconditionshereinstylizedbycondition(1). TheyincludetheKeynesianincome-spendingmultiplierinthecontextoftheDynamicIS curve, thedynamicstrategiccomplementarityinthefirms’price-settingdecisionsinthecontextoftheNKPC,andthepositivefeedbackfromexpectationsoffuturetradestocurrenttradesinthecontextofassetpricing.

3Tobeprecise, ourobservational-equivalence resultconfounds theaforementionedeffectwithanadditionaleffect,whichisthatthefirst-orderbeliefsofthefundamentalalsomovelessthaninthefrictionlessbenchmark. AsexplainedinSection 7, thiseffectisnotstrictlyneeded: higher-orderuncertaintyisalonesufficientforthedocumentedformofmyopia.However, thetwoeffectsmaynaturallycometogetherinapplicationsandonlycomplementeachother.

2

Page 4: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

beliefdynamics, whilealsocuttingtheGordianknotofcomplexsignal-extractionproblems, soasto

developasharpunderstandingoftheprinciplesthatunderlyourobservational-equivalenceresult.

Together, these resultsoffera freshperspectiveon theaggregate implicationsof informational

frictions. Theyallowustodrawanumberofusefulconnectionstotheliterature. Andtheyfacilitate

our empirical exercise in the context of inflation. Weelaborateon these applied aspects of our

contributionbelow.

DSGE. Baselinemacroeconomicmodelsemphasizeforward-lookingbehaviorbuthavehardtime

capturingasalientfeatureoftheaggregatetimeseries: inflation, consumptionandinvestmentalike

appeartorespondsluggishlytotheunderlyinginnovations, asifthereisastrongbackward-looking

component in their lawsofmotion. Toaddress thischallengeandprovideasuccessfulstructural

interpretationofthedata, theDSGE literaturehassacrificedonthemicro-foundations.

Forinstance, tomatchtheinflationdynamics, theliteraturehasfollowed GaliandGertler (1999)

and Christiano, Eichenbaum, andEvans (2005)inreplacingthestandardNKPC withtheso-called

HybridNKPC,abackward-lookingvariantthatfindsnosupportintherelatedmenu-costliterature

(AlvarezandLippi, 2014; GolosovandLucas Jr, 2007; NakamuraandSteinsson, 2013). Similarly, to

matchtheaggregateinvestmentdynamics, theliteraturehasemployedaformofadjustmentcostthat

isincompatiblewithbothstandardQ theory(Hayashi, 1982)andtheliteraturethatstudiesinvestment

atthemicrolevel(Bachmann, Caballero, andEngel, 2013; CaballeroandEngel, 1999).

Ourobservational-equivalenceresultoffersthesharpestpossibleillustrationofhowinformational

frictionscanprovideaplausiblemicro-foundationfortheDSGE add-ons: accommodatingincom-

pleteinformationisakintoaddinghabitpersistenceinconsumption, adjustmentcostsininvestment,

andabackward-lookingelementintheNKPC.Atthesametime, ourresultindicatesthattheas-if

distortionsmaybeendogenoustoGE feedbackmechanismsandtherebyalsotopoliciesthatregulate

thesuchmechanisms.4

MicrovsMacro. TheGE feedbackisactive, andhigher-orderbeliefsarerelevant, onlywhen

agentsrespondtoaggregateshocks. Itfollowsthatthedocumentedformsofmyopiaandanchoring

mayloomlargeatthemacroleveleveniftheyappeartobesmallinmicrodata. Thisprovidesasimple,

unifiedexplanationtowhythemacroeconomicestimatesofboththehabitpersistenceinconsumption

andtheadjustmentcostsininvestmentaremuchhighertheirmicroeconomiccounterparts(Havranek,

Rusnak, andSokolova, 2017; GrothandKhan, 2010; Zorn, 2018); whythepersistenceofinflation

ishigherintheaggregatetimeseriesthanindisaggregateddata(Altissimoet al., 2010); andperhaps

evenwhythemomentuminassetpricesismorepronouncedatthestock-marketlevelthanatthe

individual-stocklevel(JungandShiller, 2005).

4Eearlierworkssuchas Sims (2003), MankiwandReis (2002, 2007), MackowiakandWiederholt (2009, 2015), andNimark (2008)share the idea that informational frictionscansubstitute for theDSGE add-ons, butdonotcontainourobservational-equivalenceresultandourinsightsaboutGE effectsandthemicro-to-macrogap, whichwediscussnext.

3

Page 5: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

BoundedRationality. Theformofmyopia, orimperfectforesight, documentedhereisrationalized

byaninformationalfriction, asin AngeletosandLian (2018). Similarformsofimperfectforesight

areobtainedin Garcıa-SchmidtandWoodford (2018)and FarhiandWerning (2017)byreplacing

rationalexpectationswithLevel-kThinking, andin Gabaix (2017)byintroducingabeliefbiascalled

“cognitivediscounting.” Theseworks, however, donotallowtheimperfectiontodiminishwiththe

accumulationofinformationovertimeand, asaresult, donotproducethesecondkeyfeatureof

ourapproach, theanchoringof thecurrentoutcometotheprevious-periodoutcome. Intermsof

condition(2), theyeffectivelylet ωf < 1 butrestrict ωb = 0. Bycontrast, thedataappeartodemand

both ωf < 1 and ωb > 0.5 Thisfavorsofourapproachovertheaforementionedalternatives, butalso

invitestheconsiderationofvariantsthat combine incompleteinformationwithboundedrationality.

AsexplainedinSection 7, suchvariantsmayintensifythedocumenteddistortions.

ApplicationtoInflation. Ourcontributioniscompletedwithanempricalexerciseinthecontext

of inflation. We revisit themicro-foundationsof theNKPC,adding incomplete information. We

assumeamodestdegreeofprice stickiness, one in linewith textbookparameterizationsand the

relatedmicroeconomicevidence. Wenextshowthatourresultshelprationalizeexistingestimatesof

theHybridNKPC,suchasthosefoundin GaliandGertler (1999)and Gali, Gertler, andLopez-Salido

(2005). Wefinallyshowthat this isachievedwithaninformational frictionthat also matchesthe

evidenceoninflationexpectationsprovidedby CoibionandGorodnichenko (2015).

Here, it isusefultoclarifythefollowingpoint. Bymeasuringthepredictabilityof theaverage

forecasterrorinsurveys, CoibionandGorodnichenko (2015)providedakeyempiricalmomentthat

helpsgaugetheleveloftheinformationalfriction. Yet, bytreatinginflationasanexogenousstochas-

ticprocess, thisworkcouldnotpossiblyquantifytheequilibriumimpactofthisfrictionontheactual

inflationdynamics. Ourpaperfillsthisgapbysolvingthefixedpointbetweeninflationexpectations

andactualinflation, byconnectingtheaforementionedempiricalmomenttoitstheoreticalcounter-

part, andbyevaluatingtheimpliedbiteontheequilibriumoutcomes.

Layout. Therestofthepaperisorganizedasfollows. Section 2 expandsontherelatedliterature.

Section 3 introducesourframework. Section 4 developstheobservational-equivalenceresult. Sec-

tion 5 illustratestheapplicabilityofthisresultanddiscusseditsvalue-added. Section 6 containsour

quantitativeexerciseinthecontextofinflation. Section 7 illustratestherobustnessoftheinsightsun-

derlyingourobservational-equivalenceresult. Section 8 concludes. TheAppendicescontainproofs

andafewadditionalresults.5Whiletheliteratureontheforward-guidancepuzzle(Del Negro, Giannoni, andPatterson, 2015; McKay, Nakamura,

andSteinsson, 2016; AngeletosandLian, 2018; FarhiandWerning, 2017)hasfocusedongettingextradiscounting, theDSGE andSVARsliteratureshavelongpointedouttheneedofastrongbackward-lookingcomponent. Furthermore, theavailableevidenceonexpectations(e.g., CoibionandGorodnichenko, 2012, 2015; Coibion, Gorodnichenko, andKumar,2015)suggests, notonlythattheaverageforecastsoffutureoutcomesrespondlittleonimpacttoaggregateshocks, butalsothattheyadjustmoreandmorewiththepassageoftime. Thefirstpropertymapsto ωf < 1, thesecondto ωb > 0.

4

Page 6: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

2 RelatedLiterature

Asalreadynoted, ourpaperbuildsheavilyontheexistingliteratureoninformationalfrictions, most

notablyon MorrisandShin (2002, 2006), Woodford (2003), Nimark (2008), and AngeletosandLian

(2018); see AngeletosandLian (2016)forareviewandadditionalreferences. Ourmaincontributions

vis-a-visthisliteratureare: (i)theobservational-equivalenceresultanditsapplications; (ii)thebridges

ithelpsbuildtothreeotherstrandsoftheliterature, namelyonDSGE,onmicro-to-macro, andon

bounded-rationality; (iii) theempiricalexercise in thecontextof inflation; and(iv) theanalysis in

Section 7, whichusesanunconventionalyetflexiblespecificationoftheinformationstructuresoas

toovercomethefamiliardifficultiesinthecharacterizationofthehigher-orderbeliefdynamicsand

shedamplelightonthebroaderunderlyingprinciples.

Onthemethodologicalfront, ourpaperbuildson HuoandTakayama (2015). Inparticular, we

utilizethemethodsofthatpaperinordertosolveexplicitlyfortherational-expectationsequilibrium

under our baseline specification. We then translate theobtained equilibrium in the formof our

observational-equivalenceresultandstudyitscomparativestaticswithrespecttothestrengthofGE

feedbackandotherparameters. Whatisnewhereisthesecondstep, whichisintegraltoourapplied

contribution, andtheanalysisinSection 7, whichfollowsadifferentmethodologicalroute.

Ontheappliedfront, ourpaperismostcloselyrelatedto Nimark (2008). Thispaperisthefirst

tostudyanincomplete-informationversionoftheNKPC.Itsharesouremphasisonforward-looking

beliefsandtheinsightthatincompleteinformationcanrationalizeabackward-lookingcomponent

in the inflationdynamics. It doesnot, however, contain eitherour analytical results or the tight

connectionwedrawbetweentheestimatesoftheHybridNKPC (GaliandGertler, 1999)andthe

evidenceoninflationexpectations(CoibionandGorodnichenko, 2012, 2015).6

MackowiakandWiederholt (2009)arguethatrationalinattentioncanreconcilepricerigidityat

themacrolevelwithpriceflexibilityatthemicrolevel.7 Althoughthismessagesoundssimilarto

oursregardingthegapbetweenmicroandmacro, themechanismisdifferent. Inthatwork, thegap

isexplainedbytheagentspayinglessattentionto, orotherwisefacinggreaterfirst-orderuncertainty

about, aggregateshocksrelativetoidiosyncraticshocks. Inourpaper, instead, thegapisattributedto

GE effectsandhigher-orderuncertainty; itisthereforepresent evenif theleveloffirst-orderuncertainty

about, ortheattentionto, thetwokindsofshocksisthesame. Thetwomechanismsarenevertheless

complementaryandnaturallycometogetherinapplications.6Thesepointsdistinguishmorebroadlyourcontributionfromalargerliterature, including MankiwandReis (2002), Reis

(2006), Kiley (2007), Melosi (2016), and Matejka (2016), thatstudiesprice-settinginthepresenceofinformationalfrictions.A fewotherpapersdirectlyreplacetherepresentativeagent’sinflationexpectationswiththeaverageforecastofinflationinsurveydatawhenestimatingthestandardNKPC;asnotedin Mavroeidis, Plagborg-Møller, andStock (2014), thisapproachlackssatisfactorymicro-foundationsandisindeedinconsistentwithouranalysis.

7Relatedly, Zorn (2018)arguesthatrationalinattentioncanhelpexplainwhysectoralinvestmentrespondssluggishlytoaggregateshocksbutnottosectorspecificshocks, and Carrollet al. (2018)arguethatinformationalfrictionscanreconcilethemicroandmacroestimatesofconsumptionhabit.

5

Page 7: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Bordaloet al. (2018)and KohlhasandWalther (2018a,b)arguethattheexpectationsdatapainta

morevariedpicturethantheonecontainedinourpaperandintheaforementionedliterature: while

averageforecaststendtounder-reacttoaggregateshocks, individualforecaststendtoover-reactto

idiosyncraticnews, suggestingeitheraparticulardeparturefromrationalexpectations(Bordaloet al.,

2018)oramoreelaborateinformationalfriction(KohlhasandWalther, 2018a,b). Theinterplayof

theseideaswiththemechanismswestudyisanimportantquestion, beyondthescopeofthispaper.

Nevertheless, themost relevant fact forourpurposes is theunder-reactionofaverage forecasts to

aggregateshocks, whichisconsistentwithourtheory.

TherelationofourpapertotheliteratureonLevel-kThinkinghasalreadybeencommentedon

andisfurtherdiscussedinthelastpartofSection 5. Relatedisalsotheliteratureonadaptivelearning

(Sargent, 1993; EvansandHonkapohja, 2012; MarcetandNicolini, 2003). Thisliteratureallowsfor

theanchoringofcurrentoutcomestopastoutcomes; see, inparticular, Carvalhoet al. (2017)foran

applicationinthecontextofinflation. Theanchoringfoundinourpaperhasthreedistinctqualities:

itisconsistentwithrationalexpectations; itistiedtothestrengthoftheGE feedback; anditisdirectly

comparabletothatfoundintheDSGE literature.

3 TheAbstractFramework

Inthissectionwesetupourframework, reviewthefrictionless, complete-informationbenchmarkwe

departfrom, andillustratetheinteractionofforward-lookingbehaviorandhigher-orderbeliefs.

Setup. Timeisdiscrete, indexedby t ∈ 0, 1, ..., andthereisacontinuumofplayers, indexed

by i ∈ [0, 1]. Ineachperiod t, eachagent i choosesanaction ait ∈ R. Wedenotethecorresponding

averageactionby at. Wenextspecifythebestresponseofplayer i inperiod t asfollows:

ait = Eit [φξt + βait+1 + γat+1] (3)

where ξt istheexogenousfundamental, Eit[·] istherational-expectationoperatorconditionalontheperiod-t informationofplayer i, and (φ, β, γ) areparameters, with φ > 0, β, γ ∈ [0, 1), and β+γ < 1.

Condition(3)specifiesbestresponsesinrecursiveform. Toseemoreclearlyhowcurrentbehavior

dependsonexpectationsoftheentirefuturepathsofthefundamentalandoftheaverageaction, we

iteratethisconditionforwardandreachthefollowingextensive-formrepresentation:

ai,t =

∞∑k=0

βkEi,t [φξt+k] + γ

∞∑k=0

βkEi,t [at+k+1] , (4)

Aggregatingtheaboveconditionacrossagents, wethenalsoobtainthefollowingequilibriumrestric-

6

Page 8: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

tionbetweenoutcomesandexpectations:

at = φ

∞∑k=0

βkEt [ξt+k] + γ

∞∑k=0

βkEt [at+k+1] , (5)

where Et[.] denotestheaverageexpectationinthecross-sectionofthepopulation.8

Thelastconditionisuseful, notonlybecauseitfacilitatesthecharacterizationoftheaggregate

outcomeasafunctionoffirst-andhigher-orderbeliefs(seebelow), butalsobecauseithelpsnest

applicationsinwhichadirectanaloguetotheindividual-levelbest-responsecondition(3)isunavail-

able, asincaseswhere at correspondstothepricedeterminedinaWalrasianmarket. Finally, either

oftheseconditionsmakesclearthatthescalars β and γ parameterizetwodistinctaspectsofforward-

lookingbehavior. Ontheonehand, β determinestheextenttowhichanindividualdiscountsthe

futurevaluesofeithertheexogenousfundamentalortheendogenousoutcome. Ontheotherhand, γ

regulatestheextenttowhichanindividualconditionshiscurrentbehavioronherexpectationsofthe

futureactionsof others. Inapplications, thiskindofdynamicstrategiccomplementaritycorresponds

toGE effectssuchasthepositivefeedbackfromexpectationsoffutureinflationtocurrentinflation,

orthatfromexpectationsoffutureaggregatespendingtocurrentaggregatespending.

Frictionless, Representative-AgentBenchmark. Suppose, momentarily, thatinformationiscom-

plete, bywhichwemeanthatallagentssharethesameinformationandthereforefacenouncertainty

aboutoneanother’sbeliefs. Inthiscase, wecanreplace Et[·] incondition(5)withtheexpectationofarepresentativeagent, thatis, theexpectationconditionalonthecommoninformation. Regardless

ofhownoisythatcommoninformationmightbe, wecanthenusetheLawofIteratedExpectations

toreducecondition(5)tothefollowing, representative-agent, Euler-likecondition:

at = Et[φξt + δat+1], (6)

where Et[·] denotestheexpectationoftherepresentativeagentand δ ≡ β + γ ∈ (0, 1).

Itisthenimmediatetoseethatthecomplete-informationversionofourframeworkneststhetwo

buildingblocksoftheNewKeynesianmodel: theNKPC isnestedwith at standingforinflationand

ξt fortherealmarginalcostortheoutputgap; andtheDynamicIS Cure(thatis, theEulercondition

8Thebest-responsebehaviorassumedabove is similar to thatassumed in AngeletosandLian (2018). Butwhereasthatpaperconsidersanon-stationarysettingwhere ξt isfixedatzero inall t = T , for somefixed T ≥ 1, ourpaperaccommodatesastationarysettinginwhich ξt variesinall t and, inaddition, thereisgraduallearningovertime. Thesefeaturesareessentialforourobservational-equivalenceresult, aswellasfortheappliedlessonswedrawinthispaper. Ourframeworkalsoresemblesthebeauty-contestgamesconsideredby, interalia, MorrisandShin (2002), Woodford (2003),AngeletosandPavan (2007), BergemannandMorris (2013), and HuoandPedroni (2017). Becausebehavioris not forward-lookinginthesesettings, therelevanthigher-orderbeliefsarethoseregardingthe concurrent beliefsofothers. Bycontrast,therelevanthigher-orderbeliefsinoursettingarethoseregardingthe future beliefsofothers. Theimplicationsofthissubtledifferencearediscussedasweproceed; theyincludethedependenceofthedocumentedformofmyopiaonthepersistenceofthefundamentalandontheanticipationofthefuturelearningofothers.

7

Page 9: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

oftherepresentativeconsumer)isnestedwith at standingforconsumptionand ξt fortherealinterest

rate. Alternatively, condition(6)canrepresentanasset-pricingequationwith at standingfortheasset

priceand ξt forthenext-perioddividend.

Byiteratingcondition(6), wecanobtainthecomplete-informationoutcomeasfollows:

at = φ∞∑k=0

δkEt[ξt+k]. (7)

Thisstylizeshow, intheaforementionedapplicationsandbeyond, outcomesarepinneddownbyfirst-

orderbeliefsoffundamentals. Asforextensionsoftheseapplicationsthataddincompleteinformation,

wewilllatershowhowsuchextensionscanindeedbenestedincondition(5).

IncompleteInformationandHigher-OrderBeliefs. Onceinformationisincomplete, condition

(7)ceasestoholdand, instead, theaggregateoutcomehingesonacertainkindofforward-looking,

higher-orderbeliefs. Lateron, appropriateassumptionsabouttheinformationstructurewillpermit

anexplicitcharacterizationofthesebeliefs. Fornow, weexplainhowtheaggregateoutcomecanbe

expressedasafunctionofthesebeliefs regardless oftheinformationstructure.

Toillustrate, let β = 0 < γ,9 whichmeansthattheequilibriumoutcomesatisfies

at = φEt [ξt] + γEt [at+1] . (8)

Iteratingthisconditiononcegives

at = φEt [ξt] + γφEt

[Et+1 [ξt+1]

]+ γ2Et

[Et+1 [at+2]

],

fromwhichitisevidentthattheequilibriumoutcomedependsonaparticularkindofforward-looking,

second-orderbeliefs, namelythecurrentbeliefsofthenext-periodbeliefsofthenext-periodfunda-

mentalandthenext-periodoutcome(seesecondandthirdtermintheabovecondition, respectively).

Byiteratingcondition(8)againandagain, wecanultimatelyexpresstheequilibriumoutcomeasa

functionofaninfinitehierarchyofbeliefsaboutthecurrentandfuturevaluesofthefundamental:

at = φ

∞∑h=0

γhFh+1t [ξt+h] (9)

where, foranyrandomvariable X, Fht [X] isdefinedrecursivelyby

F1t [X] ≡ Et [X] and Fh

t [X] ≡ Et

[Fh−1t+1 [X]

]∀h ≥ 2.

9Thiscaseistoonarrowfortheapplicationsofinterest, butitisusefulbecauseofitsrelativesimplicity.

8

Page 10: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Considernextthemoregeneralcaseinwhichboth γ > 0 and β > 0. Inthiscase, whichisrelevant

fortheapplicationsofinterest, theclassofhigher-orderbeliefsthatdrivetheequilibriumoutcomeis

muchricherthantheonedescribedabove. Toseethis, let φ1−ρβ = 1 (thisiscompletelyinnocuous)

andrewritecondition(8)asfollows:

at = Et [ξt] + γ

∞∑k=1

βk−1Et [at+k]

Applyingthisconditiontoperiod t+ k, forany k ≥ 1, andtakingtheexpectationsasofperiod t, we

obtainthefollowingrepresentationoftheperiod-t beliefsofthefutureoutcomes:

Et[at+k] = Et

[Et+k [ξt+k]

]+ γ

∞∑j=1

βj−1Et

[Et+k [at+k+j ]

]Combiningandrearranging, wereachthefollowingcharacterizationoftheperiod-t outcome:

at = Et [ξt] + γ

∞∑k=1

βkEt

[Et+k [ξt+k]

]+ γ2

∞∑k=1

βk−1∞∑j=1

βj−1Et

[Et+k [at+k+j ]

]Therelevantsecond-orderbeliefsarethereforethoseregardingthebeliefsofothers, notonlyinthe

nextperiod, butalsoin all futureperiods, namely Et[Et+k[ξt+k]] forevery k ≥ 1.

Asweiteratethisargumentagainandagain, thesetofhigher-orderbeliefsthatemergegetsricher

andricher. Inparticular, fixa t andpickany k ≥ 2, any h ∈ 2, ..., k, andany t1, t2, ...th suchthatt = t1 < t2 < ... < th = t + k. Then, theperiod-t outcomedependsonallofthefollowingtypesof

forward-lookinghigher-orderbeliefs:

Et1 [Et2 [· · · [Eth [ξt+k] · · · ]].

Forany t andany k ≥ 2, thereare k − 1 typesofsecond-orderbeliefs, plus (k − 1)× (k − 2)/2 types

ofthird-orderbeliefs, plus (k − 1)× (k − 2)× (k − 3) /6 typesoffourth-orderbeliefs, andsoon.

What’snext. Theabovederivationsindicatethepotentialcomplexityofdynamic, incomplete-

informationmodels. Anintegralpartofourcontributionisthebypassingofthiscomplexityandthe

developmentofsharpanalyticalresults. Thisisachievedbyfollowingtwodifferent, butcomplemen-

tary, paths. InSections 4-6, weemployasomewhatrigidspecificationofthefundamentalprocess

andtheinformationstructuresoastofacilitateourobservation-equivalenceresultanditsvariousap-

plications. InSection 7, wethenuseamoreflexiblespecificationbutalsocuttheGordianknotof

complexsignal-extractionproblemssoastoshedfurtherlightontheunderlyingprinciplesandtheir

robustness; thissacrificestheeleganceofourobservational-equivalenceresultbutnotitsessence.

9

Page 11: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

4 TheEquivalenceResult

Inthissectionwedevelopourobservation-equivalenceresult. Theprinciplesunderlyingthisresult

arebestunderstoodbystudying thepropertiesofhigher-orderbeliefs, whichwedo inSection 7.

Here, webypassesthisstepand, instead, characterizedirectlytherational-expectationsfixedpoint.

Thisservesalsothegoalofclarifyingthefollowingbasicpoint. Eventhoughtheanalystmayfind

itinsightfultounderstandtherational-expectationsequilibriumintermsofhigher-orderbeliefs, the

agentsintheeconomyneednotthemselvesengageinhigher-orderreasoning. Instead, inthetradition

ofMuthandLucas, itsufficesthattheyhaveinmindthecorrectstatisticalmodelofthefundamental,

ξt, andtheaggregateoutcome, at. Whatismore, thisstaticalmodelcanberelativelysimpledespite

thecomplexityoftheunderlyinghigher-orderbeliefdynamics.

4.1 Specification

Wehenceforthmaketwoassumptions. First, weletthefundamental ξt followanAR(1)process:

ξt = ρξt−1 + ηt =1

1− ρLηt, (10)

where ηt ∼ N (0, 1) istheperiod-t innovation, L isthelagoperator, and ρ ∈ (0, 1) parameterizes

thepersistenceofthefundamental. Second, weassumethatplayer i receivesanewprivatesignalin

eachperiod t, givenby

xit = ξt + uit, uit ∼ N (0, σ2) (11)

where σ ≥ 0 parameterizestheinformationalfriction(thelevelofnoise). Theplayer’sinformationin

period t isthehistoryofsignalsuptothatperiod.

Theseassumptionsarerestrictive. Theyruleout, interalia, endogenoussignalssuchasprices. The

mainjustificationforthemisthattheyguaranteetheexactvalidityofourobservational-equivalence

result. Thisresultmayneverthelessserveasagoodproxyoftheequilibriumeveninextensionsthat

allowforendogenoussignals; weillustratethisinAppendixC.Furthermore, thepresenceofidiosyn-

craticnoiseintheavailableinformationcanbemotivatedasthebyproductofrationalinattention,

subjecttothecaveatthatwedonotstudytheproblemoffindingtheoptimalsignal.

Allinall, weviewourbaselinespecificationasausefulandempiricallyplausibleperturbation

ofthecomplete-informationbenchmark. Thisbenchmark, whichishereinnestedbysetting σ = 0,

imposes, notonlythateveryagentknowsthecurrentvalueof ξt, butalsothatsheisconfidentthat

everyotheragentsharesthesamebeliefswithhimabouttheentirefuturepathofboth ξt and at. By

contrast, setting σ > 0 letsagentsface, notonlyuncertaintyabouttheunderlyingaggregateshocks,

butalsodoubtsabouttheattentiveness, awareness, andresponsivenessofothers.

10

Page 12: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

4.2 SolvingtheRational-ExpectationsFixedPoint

Considerfirstthefrictionlessbenchmark(σ = 0), inwhichcasetheoutcomeispinneddownbyfirst-

orderbeliefs, asincondition(7). ThankstotheAR(1)specificationassumedabove, Et[ξt+k] = ρkξt, for

all t, k ≥ 0. Wethusreachthefollowingresult, whichstatesthatthecomplete-informationoutcome

followsthesameAR(1)processasthefundamental, rescaledbythefactor φ1−ρδ .

Proposition 1. Inthefrictionlessbenchmark (σ = 0), theequilibriumoutcomeisgivenby

at = a∗t ≡φ

1− ρδξt =

φ

1− ρδ

1

1− ρLηt. (12)

Considernextthecaseinwhichinformationisincomplete(σ > 0). Asalreadyexplained, the

outcome is thena functionofan infinitenumberofhigher-orderbeliefs. Despite thesimplifying

assumptionsmadehere, thedynamicstructureofthesebeliefsisquitecomplex. Indeed, usingthe

Kalmanfilter, wecanreadilyshowthattherelevantfirst-orderbelief, Et[ξt], followsanAR(2)process:

Et[ξt] =

(1− λ

ρ

)(1

1− λL

)ξt =

(1− λ

ρ

)(1

1− λL

)(1

1− ρL

)ηt, (13)

where λ = ρ(1−G) and G istheKalmangain. Itthenfollowsthattherelevantsecond-orderbelief,

Et[Et+1[ξt+1]], followsanARMA(3,1). Andbyinduction, wecanalsoshowthat, forany h ≥ 1, the

relevant h-thorderbelief, Et[Et+1[...Et+h[ξt+h]], followsanARMA(h+ 1, h− 1).

Inshort, beliefsofhigherorderexhibitincreasinglycomplexdynamicsandthestatespaceneeded

to track theentirebeliefhierarchy is infinite. Yet, asanticipated in thebegginingof this section,

thiscomplexityis not inheritedbytherational-expectationsfixedpoint. Themethodsof Huoand

Takayama (2015)guaranteethat, insofarasthefundamentalandthesignalsfollowfiniteARMA pro-

cesses, thefixedpointweareinterestedinisalsoafiniteARMA process. Undertheassumptions

madehere, thisismerelyanAR(2)process, whoseexactformischaracterizedbelow.

Proposition 2. Theequilibriumexists, isuniqueandissuchthattheaggregateoutcomeobeysthe

followinglawofmotion:

at =

(1− ϑ

ρ

)(1

1− ϑL

)a∗t , (14)

where a∗t isthefrictionlesscounterpart, obtainedinProposition 1, andwhere ϑ isascalarthatsatisfies

ϑ ∈ (0, ρ) andthatisgivenbythereciprocalofthelargestrootofthefollowingcubic:

C(z) ≡ −z3 +(ρ+

1

ρ+

1

ρσ2+ β

)z2 −

(1 + β

(ρ+

1

ρ

)+β + γ

ρσ2

)z + β,

Condition(14)expressestheincomplete-informationdynamicsasasimpletransformationofthe

complete-informationcounterpart. Thistransformationisindexedbythescalar ϑ, whichplaysadual

11

Page 13: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

role: relativetothefrictionlessbenchmark(whichishereinnestedby ϑ = 0), ahigher ϑ meansboth

asmallerimpacteffect, capturedbythefactor 1− ϑρ incondition(14), andamoresluggishbuildup

overtime, capturedbythelagterm ϑL.

Todevelopsomeintuitionfortheresult, considermomentarilythespecialcaseinwhich γ = 0.

Byshuttingdownthestrategiccomplementarity, thiscaseisolatestheroleoffirst-orderuncertainty.

Usingcondition(5)alongwith γ = 0 (andhence δ ≡ β + γ = β)andthefactthat Et[ξt+k] = ρkEt[ξt]

forall k ≥ 0, weinferthattheaggregateoutcomeisgivenby

at = φ∞∑k=0

βkEt[ξt+k] =φ

1− δρEt[ξt]. (15)

This is thesameas thecomplete-informationoutcome, modulo the replacementof ξt, theactual

fundamental, with Et[ξt], theaveragefirst-orderforecastofit. AndsincethelatterfollowstheAR(2)

processgivenincondition(13), weinferthatProposition 2 holdswith ϑ = λ when γ = 0.

Whathappenswhen γ > 0? Inthiscase, higher-orderbeliefsbecomerelevant. Asalreadynoted,

suchbeliefs followARMA processesofever increasingorder. Andyet, theequilibriumoutcome

continuestofollowanAR(2)process, asinthecasewith γ = 0. Thisisthe“magic”oftherational-

expectationsfixedpoint. Butwhereas ϑ equaled λ inthatcase, itisnowstrictlyhigherthan λ.10 That

is, theequilibriumdynamicsexhibitslessamplitudeandmorepersistence, notonlyrelativetothe

complete-informationcounterpart, butalsorelativetothefirst-orderbeliefofthefundamental.

Thispropertyreflectsthefactthathigher-orderbeliefsthemselvesdisplaylessamplitudeandmore

persistencethanfirst-orderbeliefs. InSection 7, wemakethislogicclear, andelaborateonitsrobust-

ness, byworkingwithamoreflexiblespecificationofthefundamentalprocessandtheinformation

structure. Thebottomlineisthatthemorestringentspecificationassumedhereguaranteesthatthe

equilibriuminheritsthekeyqualitativepropertiesofhigherbeliefswithout, however, inheritingtheir

complexity. Thisinturnfacilitatesourobservational-equivalenceresult, whichwepresentnext.

4.3 TheEquivalenceResult

Letusmomentarilyput aside the economyunder considerationand, instead, consider a variant,

representative-agenteconomyinwhichtheaggregateEulercondition(6)ismodifiedasfollows:

at = φξt + δωfEt [at+1] + ωbat−1 (16)

forsome ωf < 1 and ωb > 0. Theoriginalrepresentative-agenteconomyisnestedwith ωf = 1 and

ωb = 0. Relativetothisbenchmark, alower ωf representsahigherdiscountingofthefuture, orless

10Thefactthat ϑ > λmaynotbeobviousfromlookingatProposition 2, butfollowsfromthepropertythat ϑ isincreasingin γ, whichisestablishedasapartoftheproofofProposition 4.

12

Page 14: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

forward-lookingbehavior; ahigher ωb representsagreateranchoringofthecurrentoutcometothe

pastoutcome, ormorebackward-lookingbehavior.

Condition(16)neststheEulerconditionofarepresentativeconsumerwhoexhibitshabit; avariant

oftheQ theorythathastherepresentativefirmfaceacostforadjustingitsrateofinvestmentrather

thanacostforadjustingitscapitalstock; andtheso-calledHybridNKPC.Withthelatterexamplein

mind, wehenceforthrefertotheeconomydescribedaboveasthe“hybrideconomy.”

ItiseasytoverifythattheequilibriumoutcomeofthiseconomyisgivenbyanAR(2)process,

whosecoefficients (ζ0, ζ1) arefunctionsof (ωf , ωb) and (φ, δ, ρ). Incomparison, theequilibriumout-

comeinourincomplete-informationeconomyisanAR(2)processwithcoefficientsdeterminedasin

Proposition 2. MatchingthecoefficientsofthetwoAR(2)processes, andcharacterizingthemapping

fromthelattertotheformer, wereachthefollowingresult.

Proposition 3 (ObservationalEquivalence). Fix (φ, β, γ, ρ). Forany σ > 0 intheincomplete-information

economy, thereexistsauniquepair (ωf , ωb) inthehybrideconomy, with ωf < 1 and ωb > 0, such

that the twoeconomiesgenerate thesame jointdynamics for the fundamentaland theaggregate

outcome. Furthermore, ahigher σ mapstoalower ωf andahigher ωb.

Thisproposition, whichis themainresultofourpaper, allowsonetorecast theinformational

frictionasthecombinationoftwobehavioraldistortions: extradiscountingofthefuture, ormyopia,

intheformof ωf < 1; andbackward-lookingbehavior, oranchoringofthecurrentoutcometopast

outcome, intheformof ωb > 0.Wecomplimentthisresultwiththefollowing, whichstudiesthecom-

parativestaticsoftheas-ifdistortionswithrespecttotheGE effect, orthestrategiccomplementarity.

Proposition 4 (GE). A strongerGE feedback (higher γ) mapstobothgreatermyopia(lower ωf )and

greateranchoring(higher ωb)inthehybridmodel.

WeexpandontheapplicabilityandtheusefulnessoftheseresultsinSections 5 and 6. Before

that, wenextexplainthebroaderprinciples thatunderly them. Wetherebyalsoexplainwhywe

prefertheperspectivedevelopedaboveoverthecharacterizationprovidedinProposition 2: whereas

thelatterdependscriticallyonthedetailsoftheassumedspecificationforfundamentalprocessand

theinformationstructure, theinsightsencapsulatedbyPropositions 3 and 4 aremoregeneral.

4.4 UnderlyingPrinciples

Tounderstandwhatdrives ωf < 1, itsufficestoabstract fromlearningand, instead, focusonthe

effectsoffirst-andhigher-orderuncertainty. Asevidentfromconditions(4)and(5), theoptimalbe-

haviorinoursettingispinneddownbytwoforward-lookingobjects: theexpectedpresentdiscounted

valueoftheexogenousfundamental, andtheexpectedpresentdiscountedvalueoftheendogenous

outcome. Whenaninnovationoccursinthefundamental, bothoftheseobjectsmove, butlessso

13

Page 15: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

underincompleteinformationthanundercompleteinformation. First-orderuncertaintyarreststhe

movementoftheformer. Higher-orderuncertaintyarreststhemovementofthelatter, indeedatan

evengreaterdegreethanthatcharacterizingtheformer. Botheffectscausetheeconomytorespond

less tonewsabout the future that in the frictionlessbenchmark, explaining thedocumentedform

ofmyopia. Andbecausetherelevanceofthesecondeffect(i.e., thatregardinghigher-orderbeliefs)

increaseswiththestrengthoftheGE feedback, thismyopiaalsoincreaseswithit.

Tounderstandwhatdrives ωb > 0, ontheotherhand, itisnecessarytoallowforlearning. The

arrivalofnewinformationastimepassesinducesextrapersistenceinthebeliefsofthefundamental

andofthefutureoutcomesrelativetothepersistenceintheunderlyingfundamental. Furthermore,

thispersistenceinhigher-orderbeliefsisstrongerthanthatinfirst-orderbeliefs, reflectingthesmaller

dependenceofhigher-orderbeliefsonrecentinformation. Thisexplainswhythecurrentoutcome

appearstobeanchoredtothepastoutcomeataratethat, likeourformofmyopia, increaseswiththe

strengthoftheGE feedback.

TheseinsightsaremadecrystalclearinSection 7 withthehelpofaflexiblespecificationthat, not

onlyillustratestherobustnessoftheseinsights, butalsodisentanglestheleveloffirst-andhigher-order

uncertaintyfromthespeedoflearning. Bycontrast, suchadisentanglingisnotpossibleunderthe

morerigidspecificationconsideredhere, because σ, asingleparameter, regulates both thespeedof

learningandtheleveloffirst-andhigher-orderuncertainty.

Theanalysis inSection 7 also reveals that learning shapes theequilibriumbehavior, notonly

inthemannerdescribedabove, butalsoinanother, moresubtle, manner: throughtheanticipation

thatotheragentswill learnin thefuture. Thisanticipatoryeffectmattersonlybecauseagentsare

forward-lookingandisthereforeabsentinstaticbeautycontests.

Theforward-lookingnatureoftheproblemunderconsiderationalsoexplainswhy ϑ, theequi-

libriumpersistenceoftheaggregateoutcome, isincreasingin ρ, theexogenouspersistenceofthe

fundamental. Holding σ constant, anincreasein ρ raisesthehorizonofthe“newscomponent”of

anygiveninnovationinthefundamental: thehigher ρ is, themoreinformationanysuchinnovation

containsabout, notonlyaboutthefundamental, butalsoabouttheequilibriumoutcomefurtherinto

thefuture. Butrecallthatforecastingtheequilibriumoutcomefurtherandfurtherintothefuturein-

volvesbeliefsofhigherandhigherorder. Itfollowsthatanincreasein ρ raisestherelativeimportance

ofhigher-orderuncertainty, inthesamewayasanincreaseinthedegreeofstrategiccomplementarity.

TheseinsightscannotbeunderstoodbymerelyinspectingtheAR(2)solutionobtainedinPropo-

sition 2. Thisunderscoreshowourcontributionhingeson thecombinationof theobservational-

equivalenceresultpresentedaboveandthemoreelaborateanalysisoffered inSection 7. For the

appliedpurposesofthenexttwosections, however, onecansidestepthatanalysis, trustthesummary

ofinsightsprovidedabove, andrelyontheobservational-equivalenceresultalone.

14

Page 16: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

4.5 TestableRestrictions

AlthoughProposition 3 guaranteesthatanincomplete-informationeconomycanalwaysbemapped

toahybrideconomy, theconverseisnottrue: ahybrideconomycanbereplicatedbyanincomplete-

informationeconomyonlywhen ωf and ωb satisfyacertainrestriction.

Proposition 5. Theequilibriumdynamicsofahybrideconomycanbereplicatedbythatofanincomplete-

informationeconomyforsome σ > 0 ifandonlyif ωb > 0 and

ωf = 1− 1

δρ2ωb. (17)

Furthermore, foranypair (ωb, ωf ) thatsatisfiestheaboverestriction, thereexistsaunique σ > 0 such

thatthetwoeconomiesareobservationallyequivalent.

Thisresultoffersasimpletestforourtheory. Supposethatoneusesatimesseriesof ξt and at to

estimate ρ, thepersistenceofthefundamental, andthepair (ωf , ωb), whichgovernsthelawofmotion

(16)oftheoutcome. Supposefurtherthatoneknows β and γ, andhencealso δ, fromindependent

sources. Onecanthentestwhethercondition(17)issatisfied. Ifitdoes, thenandonlythenthedata

iscompatiblewithourtheory.

Additionaltestablepredictions, oroveridentifyingrestrictions, canbeobtainedbylookingatthe

forecastsoffutureoutcomes. Let ϵkt ≡ at+k−Et [at+k] betherealizedaverage k-periodaheadforecast

error. Aslongasinformationisincomplete, ϵkt isseriallycorrelated. Andbecausethemagnitudeof

theserialcorrelationdependson σ, thisprovidesuswithanadditionalrestrictionthatcanbeusedto

identify σ and/ortotestthemodel. WeputtheseideasatworkinSection 6.

5 ImplicationsandDiscussion

TheDSGE literaturethatfollows Christiano, Eichenbaum, andEvans (2005)and SmetsandWouters

(2007)hasaddedthreedistinctbackward-lookingelementstothekeyforward-lookingequationsof

baselinemacroeconomicmodels: habitpersistenceinconsumption, adjustmentcoststoinvestment,

andautomaticpast-priceindexation. Thesemodificationsarecrucialforthisliterature’scapacityto

offerasuccessfulstructuralinterpretationofthemacroeconomictimesseries,11 butlackindependent

empiricalsupport. Theyarealsoinconsistentwiththemodelsemployedinstrandsoftheliterature

thataimatunderstanding themicroeconomicdata.12 All inall, thesekindsofbackward-looking

elementsareconsideredascrudeproxiesforother, unspecifiedmechanisms.11Notonlydotheyallowthetheorytomatchthesluggishnessinthedynamicresponsesofconsumption, investment,

andinflationtoavarietyofidentifiedshocks, butalsohelpfixthecomovementpropertiesoftheNewKeynesianmodel.12Forinstance, althoughtheinflationdynamicsimpliedbythestandardNKPC arebroadlyconsistent—qualitativelyifnot

quantitatively—withmenu-costmodels(AlvarezandLippi, 2014; GolosovandLucas Jr, 2007; NakamuraandSteinsson,2013), suchmodelsdonotproducethekindofbackward-lookingbehaviorimpliedbytheHybridNKPC.Similarly, the

15

Page 17: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Priorworkhasalreadypushed the idea that informational frictionscanbesuchamechanism

(Sims, 2003; Woodford, 2003; MankiwandReis, 2002, 2007; MackowiakandWiederholt, 2009,

2015; Nimark, 2008). Ouranalysisaddstothislineofworkinfourways:

1. Itoffersthesharpest, uptodate, illustrationoftheaforementionedidea.

2. Ithighlights that thebackward-lookingelements featuredin theDSGE literaturemaybeen-

dogenous, notonlytotheleveloftheinformationalfriction, butalsotoGE mechanisms—and

therebyalsotomarketstructuresandpoliciesthatregulatethestrengthofsuchGE mechanisms.

Forinstance, afiscal-policyreformthatalleviatesliquidityconstraintsandreducestheincome-

spendingmultipliermayalsoreducetheas-ifhabitandmyopiaintheconsumptiondynamics.

3. It helps reduce adiscomforting gapbetween themacroeconomic and themicroeconomics

estimatesoftheseelements, apointwediscussnext.

4. Itblendsthesebackward-lookingDSGE elementswithaformofimperfectforesight.

5. Itclarifieshowanemergingliteratureonboundedrationalityrelatestoourapproachandthe

relatedliteratureoninformationalfrictions.

6. ItfacilitatesthequantitativeevaluationweconductinSection 6.

Inthesequel, weelaborateoneachoneoftheseaspectsofourcontribution, startingwithasketchof

howourresultscanbeappliedtoaggregatedemandintheNewKeynesianmodel.

5.1 Applications

InthetextbookNewKeynesianmodel, whichabstractsfrominvestment, aggregatedemandisgiven

bytheEulerconditionoftherepresentativeconsumer:13

ct = −rt + Et [ct+1] , (18)

where ct isaggregateconsumptioninperiod t, rt istherealinterestratebetweenperiod t and t+ 1,

and Et istherationalexpectationconditionalonperiod-t information.

Asshownin AngeletosandLian (2018), anincomplete-informationextensionofcondition(18)is

givenbythefollowing:

ct = −∞∑k=0

θkEt[rt+k] + (1− θ)

∞∑k=1

θk−1Et[ct+k]. (19)

formofinvestmentadjustmentcostassumedintheDSGE literatureisatoddswiththeliteraturethatstudiesinvestmentattheplantorfirmlevel(Bachmann, Caballero, andEngel, 2013; Bloomet al., 2018; CaballeroandEngel, 1999).

13Throughout, weworkwiththelog-linearizedmodel: allvariablesareinlog-deviationsfromsteadystate.

16

Page 18: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

where Et stand for theaverageexpectationof theconsumers, and θ ∈ (0, 1) for their subjective

discountfactor. Tounderstandwherethisconditioncomesfrom, considerthetextbookversionof

PermanentIncomeHypothesis. Thisgivesconsumptionasafunctionoftheexpectedpresentdis-

countedvalueofincome. Extendingthissoastoaccommodatevariationintherealinterestrateand

heterogeneityininformation, andusingthefactthataggregateincomeequalsaggregateconsumption

inequilibrium, resultstocondition(19).

Thisconditionrecaststheaggregate-demandblockoftheNewKeynesianmodelasadynamic

gameamongtheconsumers. Thisgameisnestedinourabstractframeworkbymapping rt and ct to

ξt and at, respectively, andbyletting

φ = −1, β = θ, and γ = 1− θ.

ThefollowingresultisthenanimmediatecorollaryofPropositions 3 and 4, providedofcoursethat

wemaintaintheassumptionsintroducedinthebeginningofSection 4.14

Corollary 1. Wheninformationisincomplete, thereexistscalars ωf < 1 and ωb > 0 suchthatthe

equilibriumprocessforaggregateconsumptionsolvesthefollowingequation:

ct = −rt + ωfEt[ct+1] + ωbct−1 (20)

Furthermore, alower θ, whichmeansastrongerincome-spendingmultiplier, mapstobothalower

ωf andahigher ωb.

Itisthereforeasiftheeconomyispopulatedbyarepresentativeagentwhoseconsumptionex-

hibitshabitpersistence, ofthekindassumedin Christiano, Eichenbaum, andEvans (2005)and Smets

andWouters (2007). Thereare, though, twosubtledifferences. First, whereasthetruehabitmodel

imposes ωf + ωb = 1, ourmodelimplies ωf + ωb < ρ < 1. Thismeansthattheoverallmovement

inconsumptionissmaller, reflectingthemyopiaproducedbyincompleteinformation. Second, and

perhapsmostimportantly, thecoefficients ωf and ωb dependscriticallyon θ, becausethisparameter

governsthestrengthoftherelevantGE feedback, namelytheKeynesianincome-spendingmultiplier.

Itisuseful not tointerpret θ literally, asthesubjectivediscountfactor. Forinstance, wecanreadily

extendtheanalysistoaperpetual-youth, overlapping-generationsmodelalongthelinesof Del Negro,

Giannoni, andPatterson (2015)and, underappropriateassumptions, replicatetheresultsreported

abovewith θ replacedby χθ, where χ isthesurvivalprobability. Thelattercaninturnbethought14OnlineAppendixC of AngeletosandLian (2018)developsa“discounted”Eulerequationthatresemblescondition

(19), butalsodiffersfromitintwocrucialrespects. First, itimposes ωb = 0, rulingoutthehabit-likeelement. Second, itonlydescribestheparticularpathofconsumptiontriggeredbyaonce-and-for-allshiftintheexpectationsoftherealinterestratethatwillprevailatasingle, andfixed, futuredate. Bycontrast, ourresultdescribestheentirestochasticprocessofconsumptioninastationarysettingwithrecurrentshocks. ThesamepointsdistinguishthediscountedNKPC foundinthatpaperfromtheversionoftheHybridNKPC wedeveloplateron, inSection 6.

17

Page 19: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

ofasameasureofthelengthofplanninghorizons, eitherinthesenseofexpectedlifespansorinthe

sensedescribedin Woodford (2018). Alternatively, asin FarhiandWerning (2017), 1 − χ canserve

asaproxyfortheprobabilityofbindingliquidityconstraints. Forourpurposes, thekeyobservation

isthat, evenifsuchfeatureshappentobeirrelevantundercompleteinformationduetooffsetting

PE andGE effects,15 theycanbecrucialunderincompleteinformationbecausetheydeterminethe

strengthoftherelevantGE effectandtheconsequentimportanceofhigher-orderuncertainty.

Thisinturnbuildsabridgetoagrowingtheoreticalandempiricalliteraturethatstudiesthede-

terminantsofaggregatedemandandoftheKeynesianmultiplierinsettingsthatallowforincomplete

marketsandrichheterogeneity.16 Inthelightofourresults, theinteractionofthesefeatureswithin-

formationalfrictionscanperhapsrationalizebothsignificantmyopiavis-a-visthefutureandastrong,

habit-like, backward-lookingforceintheaggregateconsumptiondynamics. Thedependenceofthese

distortionsonpoliciesthatregulatethestrengthoftheKeynesianmultiplier, suchasfiscalreformsthat

alleviateliquidityconstraints, isanotherimplicationofouranalysisthatwarrantsfurtherinvestigation.

Intheabove, wefocusedonconsumption. InAppendixB,weturntoinvestment. Wetakea

modelthatfeaturesaconventionalformofadjustmentcoststocapital, asin Hayashi (1982)and Abel

andBlanchard (1983), andshowhowtheintroductionofincompleteinformationtothismodelcan

makeinvestmentbehave asif theadjustmentcosttakesthemoreexoticformassumedintheDSGE

literature. AndinSection 6, weshowhowtheHybridNKPC canbeobtainedbyaugmentingthe

standardNKPC withincompleteinformation. Together, theseapplicationsexplainhowouranalysis

connectstoeachofthethreebuildingblocksofthemodernmacroeconomicframework.17 Finally,

intheConclusionandAppendixC,wediscussanapplicationtoassetpricing.

5.2 Micro-vsMacro-levelDistortions

AsmentionedintheIntroduction, themacroeconomicestimatesofthehabitinconsumptionandof

theadjustmentcostsininvestmentaremuchlargerthanthecorrespondingmicroeconomicestimates;

see Havranek, Rusnak, andSokolova (2017)forameta-analysisofmultiplestudiesinthecontextof

consumptionhabit, and GrothandKhan (2010)and Zorn (2018)forinvestment. Ourresultsalsooffer

asimpleresolutiontothisdisconnect.

Toillustrate, considertheapplicationtoconsumptionstudiedaboveandallowforidiosyncratic

incomeorpreference shocks. Suppose further thateachconsumerhasperfectknowledgeofher

idiosyncraticshocks, whilemaintainingtheinformationalfrictionregardingtherealinterestrate(the

aggregatefundamental)andaggregatespending(theaggregateoutcome). Inthiscontext, Corollary 1

15Inthepresentcontext, thisoffsettingisevidentthepropertythatthesumofthecoefficients γ and β (whichparameterize,respectively, thePE andtheGE effects)isinvariantto θ and χ.

16E.g., Auclert (2017), KaplanandViolante (2014), Kaplan, Moll, andViolante (2016), and Werning (2015).17Theseapplicationstreateachblockinisolationofeachother. Accommodatingtheirinteractionmaybreaktheexact

observationalequivalence, but, asinthecaseofricherinformationstructures, neednotupsetthekeyinsights.

18

Page 20: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

continuestohold: thedynamicsofaggregateconsumptionexhibithabit-likebehavior. Atthesame

time, theresponseof individualconsumptiontoidiosyncraticshocksexhibitnosuchbehavior. It

followsthataneconometricianmayestimateapositivehabitatthemacrolevel(i.e., intheresponse

ofaggregateoutcomestoaggregateshocks)alongwithazerohabitatthemicrolevel(i.e., inthe

responseofindividualoutcomestoidiosyncraticshocks).

In thecasejustdescribed, theabsenceofhabit-likebehaviorat themicrolevelhingesonthe

assumptionthatagentsobserveperfectlytheiridiosyncraticshocks. Relaxingthisassumption—for

example, lettingagentsberationallyinattentivetobothaggregateandidiosyncraticshocks—allows

themicroresponsestodisplayasimilarformofanchoringasthemacroresponses. Yet, thedistortion

islikelytoremainmorepronouncedatthemacrolevelthanatthemicroonefortworeasons, the

onehighlightedin MackowiakandWiederholt (2009)andtheonehighlightedhere.

Insofarasthefrictionistheproductofcostlyinformationacquisitionorrationalinattention, itis

naturaltoexpectthatthetypicalagentwillcollectrelativemoreinformationabout, orallocaterela-

tivelymorecognitivecapacityto, idiosyncraticshocks, simplybecausesuchshocksaremorevolatile

andthereishigherreturninreducinguncertaintyaboutthem. Thisisthemechanismarticulatedin

MackowiakandWiederholt (2009)andboilsdowntohavinglessfirst-orderuncertaintyaboutid-

iosyncraticthanaggregateshocks. Butevenifthefirst-orderuncertaintyaboutthetwokindofshocks

werethesame, thedistortionatthemacrolevelwouldremainlargerinsofarastherearepositiveGE

feedbackeffects, suchastheKeynesianincome-spendingmultiplierorthedynamicstrategiccom-

plementarityinprice-settingdecisionsofthefirms. Inshort, themechanismidentifiedinourpaper

andtheoneidentifiedintheaforementionedworkcomplementeachothertowardsgeneratingmore

pronounceddistortionsatthemacrolevelthanatthemicrolevel.18

5.3 ImperfectForesightandBoundedRationality

Asalreadynoted, theideathatincompleteinformationcanrationalizeacertainkindofmyopiawas

firstputforwardin AngeletosandLian (2018). Butwhereasthatpaperfocusedonanon-stationary

environmentfeaturingasingle, once-and-for-allanticipatedchangeinthevalueofthefundamentalat

somepredeterminedfuturedate(aparticulartypeof“MIT shock”), ouranalysisconsidersastationary

settingwithrecurringshocks. Thisstepiscrucialforthedevelopmentandtheapplicabilityofour

observational-equivalenceresult. Furthermore, byaccommodatinglearningovertime, ouranalysis

blendsthemyopiawiththebackward-lookingelementsoughtafterbytheDSGE literature.

Thelastpointalsohelpsdistinguishourcontributionfromthoseof Gabaix (2017)and Farhiand

Werning (2017). Theseworksdepart fromrationalexpectations inamanner thathelpscapturea

similarformofimperfectforesightasours. Theformerachievesthisbyassumingthattheperceived18WeverifyalltheseintuitionsinAppendixD withavariantthatletsbothaggregateandidiosyncraticshocksbeobserved

withnoise. Thequantitativepotentialofthisparticularidea, however, isleftopenforfutureresearch.

19

Page 21: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

lawofmotionofalltherelevanteconomicvariablesexhibitlessamplitudeandlesspersistencethan

thetrueone(anassumptioncalled“cognitivediscounting”), thelatterbylettingagentshavelimited

depthofreasoninginthesenseofLevel-kThinking.19 Theseworksdonot, however, provideatheory

ofwhythecurrentoutcomemaybeanchoredtothepastoutcome, orwhytheequilibriumdynamics

mayexhibitmomentum. Intermsofourobservational-equivalenceresult, theyaccommodate ωf < 1

butrestrict ωb = 0. Itfollowsthatanelementarytestabledifferencebetweenincompleteinformation

andthesealternativesiswhether ωb ispositiveorzero.20

Fromthisperspective, theverdict seems tobeclear. First, themacroeconomicdatademands

ωb > 0, whichispreciselythereasonwhytheDSGE literaturedepartedfrombaseline, forward-looking

macroeconomicmodelsbyaddinghabitpersistenceinconsumption, adjustmentcoststoinvestment,

etc. Second, andperhapsmoretellingly, theavailableevidenceonexpectationsalsodemands ωb > 0:

asshownin, interalia, CoibionandGorodnichenko (2012, 2015), Coibion, Gorodnichenko, and

Kumar (2015)and VellekoopandWiederholt (2017), theaverageforecasterrorsexhibitpositiveserial

autocorrelation, bothunconditionallyandconditionalonidentifiedshocks. Finally, theexercisewe

conductinthenextsectionsuggeststhat, atleastinthecontextofinflation, thetwokindsofempirical

regularities—thebackward-lookingforceinoutcomesandthemomentuminbeliefs—aremutually

consistent, notonlyqualitatively, butalsoquantitatively.

Notwithstandingthesepoints, afruitfuldirectionforfutureresearchisperhapsonethatcombines

incomplete informationwithbounded rationality. Weexplore twosuchextensions in theendof

Section 7. Thefirstrelaxestheassumptionthatagentscananticipate, as it isrational, thatothers

willlearninthefuture.21 ThesecondmergesourapproachwithLevel-kThinking.22 Bothofthese

extensionspreservetheessenceofourresults, butalsointensifythedocumentedmyopia. Another

interestingdirectionforfutureresearchmaybeonethataugmentsourworkwiththekindofbelief

extrapolationstudiedin Bordaloet al. (2018)and KohlhasandWalther (2018a,b).

6 ApplicationtotheNKPC

In this section, we study theapplicationofour theory to theaggregate-supplyblockof theNew

Keynesianmodel, thatis, theNKPC.Thisapplicationisshowntomatch jointly existingestimatesof

19Thisfollowstheleadof Garcıa-SchmidtandWoodford (2018), whosesolutionconcept(“reflectiveequilibrium”)isessentiallythesameasLevel-kThinking. Seealso IovinoandSergeyev (2017)foranother, topicalapplication.

20Tobemoreprecise, itmaybepossibletoreconcilethesealternativeswith ωb > 0 byassumingthattheotherwisearbitrary“defaultpoints”intheseworksareincreasingfunctionsofthepastoutcome. Butthisbegsthequestionofwhythedefaultpointsoughttodisplaysuchapositivedependence. Ourapproachoffersasimpleanswer: iftheeffectivedefaultpointistheaverageBayesianbeliefconditionalonhistoricalinformation, itnaturallyexhibitssuchapositivedependence.

21Wefindthis“behavioral”varianttobeplausiblebecauseitimposeslessontheknowledgeandthecognitivecapabilitiesofagents. Inaddition, thisvariantservesausefulpedagogicalpurposebyclarifyingtheroleplayedbytheinteractionoflearningandforward-lookingbehavior.

22WethankAlexanderKohlhasforsuggestingustoexploresuchavariant.

20

Page 22: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

theHybridNKPC (GaliandGertler, 1999; Gali, Gertler, andLopez-Salido, 2005)andindependent

evidenceoninflationexpectations(CoibionandGorodnichenko, 2015). Furthermore, theimplied

quantitativebiteoftheinformationalfrictionontheinflationdynamicsisnon-trivial.

SetupandMappingtoAbstractFramework. Apartfortheintroductionofincompleteinformation,

themicro-foundationsarethesameasinfamiliartextbooktreatmentsoftheNKPC (e.g., Galí, 2008).

Thereisacontinuumoffirms, eachproducingadifferentiatedcommodity. Firmssetpricesoptimally,

but canadjust themonly infrequently. Eachperiod, afirmhas theoption to reset itspricewith

probability 1 − θ, where θ ∈ (0, 1); otherwise, itisstuckattheprevious-periodprice. Technologyis

linear, sothattherealmarginalcostofafirmisinvarianttoitsproductionlevel.

Regardlessofhowinformationthefirmhas, theoptimalresetpricesolvesthefollowingproblem:

P ∗it = argmax

Pit

∞∑k=0

(δθ)kEit

Qt|t+k

(PitYit+k|t − Pt+kΨt+kYi,t+k|t

)

subjecttothedemandequation, Yit+k =(

PitPt+k

)−ϵYt+k,whereQt|t+k isthestochasticdiscountfactor

between t and t+ k, Yt+k and Pt+k are, respectively, aggregateincomeandtheaggregatepricelevel

inperiod t+ k, Pit isthefirm’sprice, assetinperiod t, Yi,t+k|t isthefirm’squantityinperiod t+ k,

conditionalonnothavingchangedthepricesince t, andΨt+k istherealmarginalcostinperiod t+k.

Takingthefirst-orderconditionandlog-linearizingaroundasteadystatewithnoshocksandzero

inflation, wegetthefollowingcharacterizationoftheoptimalrestprice:

p∗it = (1− δθ)∞∑k=0

(δθ)kEit[ψt+k + pt+k]. (21)

Thisconditionmeansthattheoptimalresetpriceofafirmisaweightedaverageofherbeliefofthe

currentandfuturenominalmarginalcosts. Wenextmakethesimplifyingassumptionthatthefirms

observethatcurrentpricelevelbutdonotextractinformationfromit.23 Thispermitsustorestate

condition(21)as

p∗it − pt−1 = (1− δθ)

∞∑k=0

(δθ)kEit[ψt+k + πt+k], (22)

Sinceonlyafraction 1 − θ ofthefirmsadjusttheirpriceseachperiod, thepricelevelinperiod t is

23Asin VivesandYang (2017), thisassumptioncanbeinterpretedasaformofinattentionorboundedrationality. Itcanalsobemotivatedonempiricalgrounds: inthedata, inflationcontainslittlestatisticalinformationaboutcurrentandfuturerealmarginalcosts. Inanyevent, thisassumptionsharpenstheexpositionbutisnotessential. AsshowninAppendixC,ourobservational-equivalenceresultcanbeagoodapproximationofthetrueequilibriuminsettingsthatallowagentstoextractinformationfromcurrentorpastaggregateoutcomes.

21

Page 23: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

givenby pt = (1− θ)∫p∗itdi+ θpt−1. Bythesametoken, inflationisgivenby

πt ≡ pt − pt−1 = (1− θ)

∫(p∗it − pt−1) .

Combiningthiswithcondition(22)andrearranging, wearriveatthefollowingexpressionforinflation:

πt =(1− δθ)(1− θ)

θ

∞∑k=0

(δθ)kEt [ψt+k] + δ(1− θ)

∞∑k=0

(δθ)kEt [πt+k+1] . (23)

Wheninformationiscomplete, wecanreplace Et[·] with Et[·], theexpectationoperatorcondi-tional thecommon informationset. Wecan thenuse theLawof IteratedExpectations to reduce

condition(23)tothefollowing:

πt = κψt + δEt[πt+1], (24)

where κ ≡ (1−δθ)(1−θ)θ . ThisthestandardNKPC.

When, instead, informationisincomplete, theaboveconditionnomoreholds. Instead, inflation

mustbeunderstoodasasolutiontoadynamicgameofthetypestudiedinSections 3 and 4. This

gameisnestedinourframeworkbymapping ψt and πt to ξt and at, respectively, andbyletting

φ = κ β = δθ and γ = δ(1− θ).

ThefollowingisthenanimmediateapplicationofPropositions 3 and 4, providedofcoursethatwe

maintaintheassumptionsintroducedinSection 4.

Proposition 6. (i)Thereexist ωf < 1 and ωb > 0 suchthat, wheninformationis incomplete, the

equilibriumprocessforinflationsolvesthefollowingequation:

πt = κψt + ωfδEt[πt+1] + ωbπt−1 (25)

(ii)Foranygivenlevelofnoise, increasingthedegreeofpriceflexibility(i.e., reducing θ)results

toalower ωf andahigher ωb.

Part(i)establishesthat, wheninformationisincomplete, itis asif inflationisgovernedbyavariant

oftheNKPC thatintroducesmyopia, intheformof ωf < 1, alongwithabackward-lookingcompo-

nent, intheformof ωb > 0. ThisissimilartotheHybridNKPC consideredin, interalia, Galiand

Gertler (1999), Christiano, Eichenbaum, andEvans (2005)and SmetsandWouters (2007).

Part(ii)addsthefollowinginterestinglesson. Wheninformationiscomplete, higherpriceflexibil-

itycontributesmerelytoasteeperNKPC,thatis, toahigher κ incondition(24). Thisisgenerallybad

fortheempiricallyfitoftheNewKeynesianmodel, whichinturnexplainswhytheliteraturehastried

22

Page 24: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

hardtojustifyadegreeofpricestickinessattheaggregatelevelthatishigherthantheonethatappears

totopresentatthemicro-economiclevelunderthelensofmenu-costmodels. Butonceinformation

isincomplete, amoderatedegreeofpriceflexibilitycanbegoodinthesensethatitcontributesto

moresluggishnessintheinflationdynamicsbyreinforcingtheroleofhigher-orderuncertainty. This

pointhelpsexplainwhyourquantitativeimplementationreconcilessalientfeaturesoftheinflation

dynamicswitharelativelymodestdegreeofpricestickiness.

Testing theTheory. TheHybridNKPC estimatedin GaliandGertler (1999)and Gali, Gertler,

andLopez-Salido (2005), issimilar to theoneseen in (25). Thereare, however, twodifferences.

First, ourtheoryrestrictsthepair (ωf , ωb) inthewaydescribedinProposition 5, whereasunrestricted

estimationsoftheHybridNKPC allowtheseparameterstobefree. Andsecond, ourtheorytiesthe

pair (ωf , ωb) tothedynamicsofinflationforecasts. Wenowusetheserestrictionstotestourtheory.

MatchingEstimatesoftheHybridNKPC. Gali, Gertler, andLopez-Salido (2005)synthesizethe

literatureontheestimationoftheHybridNKPC andprovideafewestimatesofthepair(ωf , ωb). A

quicktestofourtheoryiswhethertheseestimatessatisfytherestrictioninProposition 5.

Thispropositiongivesthelocusofthepairs (ωf , ωb) thatarecompatiblewithourtheoryforsome

levelofnoise. Toconstructthislocus, andtobeabletoidentify σ byinvertingtheprovidedestimates

of (ωf , ωb), weneedtospecify δ, θ, and ρ. Weset δ = 0.99, θ = 0.6, and ρ = 0.95. Thevalueof θ

correspondstoamodestdegreeofpricestickiness, broadlyinlinewithtextbookcalibrationsofthe

NewKeynesianmodelandwiththemicrodata. Thevalueof ρ isobtainedbyestimatinganAR(1)

processonthelaborshare, astandardempiricalproxyfortherealmarginalcost. Thelocusimplied

underthisparameterizationofourmodelisthenrepresentedbythesolidredlineinFigure 1.

0.4 0.45 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.750.15

0.2

0.25

0.3

0.35

0.4

0.45

0.5

0.55

0.6

Figure 1: TestingtheTheory

Gali, Gertler, andLopez-Salido (2005)providethreebaselineestimatesof (ωf , ωb). Theseesti-

matesandtheirconfidenceregionsarerepresentedbythebluecrossesandthesurroundingdisks

23

Page 25: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

inFigure 1. A priori, thereisnoreasontoexpectthattheestimatesobtainedin Gali, Gertler, and

Lopez-Salido (2005)shouldfallon, orcloseto, thelocusimpliedbyourtheory. Andyet, asevident

inthefigure, that’spreciselythecase. Inotherwords, ourmodelmatchestheexistingestimateson

theHybridNKPC andallowsonetorationalizethemastheproductofinformationalfrictions.

MatchingSurveyEvidenceonInformationalFrictions. Althoughthetheorypassestheaforemen-

tioned test, it isnotclearat thispointwhether this successhingesonanempirically implausible

magnitudefortheinformationalfriction. Wenowaddressthisquestion, andimposethetheorytoan

additionaltest, byexaminingwhethertheinformationalfrictionrequiredinordertorationalizethe

existingestimatesof ωf and ωb isconsistentwithsurveyevidenceonexpectations.

Tothisgoal, weutilizethefindingsof CoibionandGorodnichenko (2015). Thatpaperusesdataon

inflationforecastsfromtheSurveyofProfessionalForecasterstomeasureakeymomentthatcanhelp

gaugethemagnitudeoftheinformationalfriction. Thebasicideaisthatthefrictionshouldmanifest

itselfinthepredictabilityoftheaverageforecasterrors. Inparticular, CoibionandGorodnichenko

(2015)runthefollowingregression:

πt+k − Et[πt+k] = K(Et[πt+k]− Et−1[πt+k]

)+ vt+k,t (26)

Withcompleteinformation, K iszero, becausethecurrentforecastcorrectionisindependentofpast

information. Bycontrast, wheninformationisincomplete, averageforecastsadjustsluggishlytowards

thetruth, implyingthatpastinnovationsinforecastspredictfutureforecastcorrections, thatis,K > 0.

Furthermore, K islargerthelargerthenoiseandtheslowerthespeedoflearning.

CoibionandGorodnichenko (2015) illustrate this logicwithanexample inwhich inflation is

followsanexogenousAR(1)processand K isadirecttransformationofthelevelofnoise. Clearly,

thisnotthecasehere. Becauseactualinflationandforecastsofinflationarejointlydeterminedin

equilibrium, theregressioncoefficientK impliedbyourtheoryismorecomplicatedthanthatintheir

exampleandis indeedendogenoustotheGE interactionamongthefirms. Nevertheless, wecan

usethetheorytocharacterize K asafunctionof σ andof (δ, θ, ρ). Withthelatterfixedintheway

describedearlier, thisgivesusamappingfromthe90%confidenceintervalofK providedin Coibion

andGorodnichenko (2015)toanintervalfor σ inourmodel. Thatis, wehaveaconfidenceinterval

fortheinformationalfrictionitself. Forany σ inthisinterval, wecanthencomputethepair (ωf , ωb)

predictedbyourtheory.

Wecanthusmaptheevidencereportedin CoibionandGorodnichenko (2015)toasegmentof

the (ωf , ωb) locusweobtainedearlieron. ThissegmentisidentifiedbytheredcrossesinFigure 1 and

givesthepairsof (ωf , ωb) thatareconsistentwiththeconfidenceintervalfor K providedin Coibion

andGorodnichenko (2015). Itisthenevidentfromthefigurethatourmodelcanpassjointlythetest

24

Page 26: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Figure 2: ImpulseResponseFunctionofInflation

ofmatchingthatevidenceandthetestofmatchingtheexistingestimatesoftheHybridNKPC.24

QuantitativeBite. Thequantitativeimplicationsoftheexerciseconductedabovearefurtheril-

lustratedinFigure 2. Thisfigurecomparestheimpulseresponsefunctionof inflationunderthree

scenarios. Thesolidblacklinecorrespondstofrictionlessbenchmark, withperfectinformation. The

dashedbluelinecorrespondstothefrictionalcase, withaninformationalfrictionthatmatchesthe

baselineestimationof CoibionandGorodnichenko (2015). Thedottedredlineisexplainedlater.

Asevidentbycomparing thedashedblue line to the solidblackone, thequantitativebiteof

theinformational frictionissignificant: theimpacteffectoninflationisabout60%lowerthanits

complete-informationcounterpart, andthepeakoftheinflationresponseisattained5quartersafter

impactratherthanonimpact. Thisissuggestiveofhowinformationalfrictionsmayhelpreconcile

quantitativemacroeconomicmodels, whichcanaccount for thebusinesscycleonlybyassuming

significantsluggishnessintheinflationdynamics, withrealisticmenu-costmodels, whichappearto

beunabletoproducesuchsluggishness.25

Let us now explain the dotted red line in the figure. Using condition (23), the incomplete-

informationinflationdynamicscanbedecomposedintotwocomponents: thebeliefofthepresent

discountedvalueof realmarginal costs, φ∑∞

k=0 βkEt[ψt+k]; and thebelief of of thepresentdis-

24Tobeprecise, theabovestatementistruefortwoofthethreebaselineestimatesprovidedin Gali, Gertler, andLopez-Salido (2005). Butthesehappentobetheestimatesassociatedwiththesmallest ωf andthelargest ωb. Thisisgoodnewsforthequantitativesignificanceofourtheory: onceourtheoryisdisciplinedbythesurveyevidence, itrationalizessignificantlevelsofbothmyopiaandanchoring.

25See, forexample, GolosovandLucas Jr (2007), Midrigan (2011), AlvarezandLippi (2014), and NakamuraandSteinsson(2013). AlthoughdifferentspecificationscanrationalizeadegreeofpricerigidityeithermuchsmallerthanoralmostaslargeastheonepredictedbythestandardNKPC,thisliteraturehasnotproducedthekindofhump-shapedinflationdynamicsthattheDSGE literaturehascapturedwiththeHybridNKPC.

25

Page 27: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

countedvalueofinflation, γ∑∞

k=0 βkEt[πt+k+1]. Thesamedecompositioncanalsobeappliedwhen

agentshaveperfectinformation:

π∗t = φ∞∑k=0

βkEt [ψt+k|ψt] + γ∞∑k=0

βkEt

[π∗t+k+1|ψt

], (27)

A naturalquestioniswhichcomponentcontributesmoretotheanchoringofinflationaswemove

fromthecompletetoincompleteinformation.

Toanswerthisquestion, wedefinethefollowingauxiliaryvariable:

πt = φ

∞∑k=0

βkEt [ψt+k] + γ

∞∑k=0

βkEt

[π∗t+k+1|ψt

]. (28)

Thedifferencebetween π∗t and πt measurestheimportanceofbeliefsaboutrealmarginalcosts, and

thedifferencebetween πt and πt measurestheimportanceofbeliefsaboutinflation. Thedottedred

lineinFigure 2 correspondsto πt. Clearly, mostofthedifferencebetweencompleteandincomplete

informationisduetheanchoringofbeliefsaboutfutureinflation. Thesebeliefsaretiedwithhigher-

orderbeliefs, whichdisplaylessresponsivenessandmoreinertiathanthefirst-orderbeliefs.

7 Robustness: IncompleteInformationasMyopiaandAnchoring

Earlier onewe claimed that, although our observational-equivalence result depends on stringent

assumptionsabouttheprocessofthefundamentalandtheavailablesignals, itencapsulatesafew

broaderinsights, whichinturnjustifytheperspectiveputforwardinourpaper. Inthissection, we

substantiatethisclaimbyclarifyingtheseinsightsandbyelaboratingontheirrobustness.

Setup. Wehenceforthletthefundamental ξt followaflexible, possiblyinfinite-order, MA process:

ξt =

∞∑k=0

ρkηt−k, (29)

wherethesequence ρk∞k=0 isnon-negativeandsquaresummable. Clearly, theAR(1)processas-

sumedearlieronisnestedasaspecialcasewhere ρk = ρk forall k ≥ 0. Thepresentspecification

allowsforricher, possiblyhump-shaped, dynamicsinthefundamental, aswellasfor“newsshocks,”

thatis, forinnovationsthatshiftthefundamentalonlyafteradelay.

Next, forevery i and t, welettheincrementalinformationreceivedbyagent i inperiod t begiven

bytheseries xi,t,t−k∞k=0, where

xi,t,t−k = ηt−k + ϵi,t,t−k ∀k,

26

Page 28: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

where ϵi,t,t−k ∼ N (0, (τk)−2) isi.i.d. across i and t, uncorrelatedacross k, andorthogonaltothepast,

current, andfutureinnovationsinthefundamental, andwherethesequence τk∞k=0 isnon-negative

andnon-decreasing. Inplainwords, whereasourbaselinespecificationhas theagentsobservea

signalabout ξt ineachperiod, thenewspecificationletsthemobserveaseriesofsignalsaboutthe

entirehistoryoftheunderlyinginnovations.

Thisspecificationissimilartoourbaselineinthatitallowsformoreinformationtobeaccumulated

astimepasses. Itdiffers, however, intworespects. First, it“orthogonalizes”theinformationstructure

inthesensethat, forevery t, every k, andevery k′ = k, thesignalsreceivedatorpriortodate t about

theshock ηt−k areindependentofthesignalsreceivedabouttheshock ηt−k′ . Second, itallowsfor

moreflexiblelearningdynamicsinthesensethattheprecision τk doesnothavetobeflatin k: the

qualityoftheincrementalinformationreceivedinanygivenperiodaboutapastshockmayeither

increaseordecreasewiththelagsincetheshockhasoccurred.

Thefirstpropertyisessentialfortractability. Thepertinentliteraturehasstruggledtosolvefor, or

accuratelyapproximate, thecomplexfixedpointbetweentheequilibriumdynamicsandtheKalman

filteringthatobtainsindynamicmodelswithincompleteinformation, especiallyinthepresenceof

endogenoussignals; see, forexample, Nimark (2017). Byadoptingtheaforementionedorthogonal-

ization, wecuttheGordianknotandfacilitateaclosed-formsolutionoftheentiredynamicstructure

ofthehigher-orderbeliefsandoftheequilibriumoutcome. Thesecondpropertythenpermitsus, not

onlytoaccommodateamoreflexiblelearningdynamics, butalsotodisentanglethespeedoflearning

fromlevelofnoise—adisentanglingthatwasnotpossibleinSection 4 becauseasingleparameter,

σ, controledbothobjectsatonce.

DynamicsofHigher-OrderBeliefs. Theinformationregarding ηt−k thatanagenthasaccumulated

upto, andincluding, period t canberepresentedbyasufficientstatistic, givenby

xki,t =

k∑j=0

τjπkxi,t−j,t−k

where πk ≡∑k

j=0 τj . Thatis, thesufficientstatisticisconstructedbytakingaweightedaverageof

alltheavailablesignals, withtheweightofeachsignalbeingproportionaltoitsprecision; andthe

precisionofthestatisticisthesumoftheprecisionsofthesignals. Letting λk ≡ πk

σ−2η +πk

, wehavethat

Eit[ηt−k] = λkxki,t, whichinturnimplies Et[ηt−k] = λkηt−k andtherefore

Et [ξt] = Et

[ ∞∑k=0

ρkηt−k

]=

∞∑k=0

f1,kηt−k, with f1,k = λkρk. (30)

Thesequence F1 ≡ f1,k∞k=0 = λkρk∞k=0 identifiestheIRF oftheaveragefirst-orderforecastto

aninnovation. Bycomparison, theIRF ofthefundamentalitselfisgivenbythesequence ρk∞k=0 . It

27

Page 29: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

followsthattherelationofthetwoIRFsispinneddownbythesequence λk∞k=0, whichdescribes

thedynamicsoflearning. Inparticular, thesmaller λ0 is(i.e., thelessprecisetheinitialinformation

is), thelargertheinitialinitialgapbetweenthetwoIRFs(i.e., alargertheinitialforecasterror). And

theslower λk increaseswith k (i.e., theslowerthelearningovertime), thelongerittakesforthatgap

(andtheaverageforecast)todisappear.

Thesepropertiesareintuitiveandaresharedbythespecificationstudiedintherestofthepaper.

IntheinformationstructurespecifiedinSection 4, theinitialprecisionistiedwiththesubsequent

speedoflearning. Bycontrast, thepresentspecificationdisentanglesthetwo. Asshownnext, italso

allowsforasimplecharacterizationoftheIRFsofthehigher-orderbeliefs, whichiswhatweareafter.

Considerfirsttheforward-lookinghigher-orderbeliefs. Applyingcondition(30)toperiod t + 1

andtakingtheperiod-t averageexpectation, weget

F2t [ξt+1] ≡ Et

[Et+1 [ξt+1]

]= Et

[ ∞∑k=0

λkρkηt+1−k

]=

∞∑k=0

λkλk+1ρk+1ηt−k

Noticehere, agentsinperiod t understandthatinperiod t+1 theaverageforecastwillbeimproved,

andthisiswhy λk+1 showsupintheexpression. Byinduction, forall h ≥ 2, the h-thorder, forward-

lookingbeliefisgivenby

Fht [ξt+h−1] =

∞∑k=0

fh,kηt−k, with fh,k = λkλk+1...λk+h−1ρk+h−1. (31)

Theincreasingcomponentsintheproduct λkλk+1...λk+h−1 seenabovecapturetheanticipationof

learning. Werevisitthispointattheendofthissection.

Thesetofsequences Fh = fh,k∞k=0, for h ≥ 2, providesacompletecharacterizationoftheIRFs

oftherelevant, forward-looking, higher-orderbeliefs. Notethat ∂E[ ξt+h|ηt−k]∂ηt−k

= ρk+h−1. Itfollowsthat

theratio fh,kρk+h−1

measurestheeffectofaninnovationontherelevant h-thorderbeliefrelativetoits

effectonthefundamental. Wheninformationiscomplete, thisratioisidentically 1 forall k and h.

When, instead, informationisincomplete, thisratioisgivenby

fh,kρk+h−1

= λkλk+1...λk+h−1.

Thefollowingresultisthusimmediate.

Proposition 7. Considertheratio fh,kρk+h−1

, whichmeasurestheeffectatlag k ofaninnovationonthe

h-thorderforward-lookingbeliefrelativetoitseffectonthefundamental.

(i)Forall k andall h, thisratioisstrictlybetween0and1.

(ii)Forany k, thisisdecreasingin h.

28

Page 30: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

(iii)Forany h, thisratioisincreasingin k.

(iv)As k → ∞, thisratioconvergesto 1 forany h ≥ 2 ifandonlyifitconvergesfor h = 1, and

thisinturnistrueifandonlyif λk → 1.

Thesepropertiesshedlightonthedynamicstructureofhigher-orderbeliefs. Part(i)statesthat, for

anybelieforder h andanylag k, theimpactofashockonthe h-thorderbeliefislowerthanthaton

thefundamentalitself. Part(ii)statesthathigher-orderbeliefsmovelessthanlower-orderbeliefsboth

onimpactandatanylag. Part(iii)statesthatthatthegapbetweenthebeliefofanyorderandthe

fundamentaldecreasesasthelagincreases; thiscapturestheeffectoflearning. Part(iv)statesthat,

regardlessof h, thegapvanishesinthelimitas k → ∞ ifandonlyif λk → 1, thatis, ifandonlyifthe

learningisboundedawayfromzero.

MyopiaandAnchoring. Toseehowthesepropertiesdrivetheequilibriumbehavior, wehence-

forthrestrict β = 0 andnormalize φ = 1. Asnotedearlier, thelawofmotionfortheequilibriumout-

comeisthengivenby at = Et[ξt] + γEt[at+1], whichinturnimpliesthat at =∑∞

h=1 γh−1Fh

t [ξt+h−1] .

Fromtheprecedingcharacterizationofthehigher-orderbeliefs Fht [ξt+h−1], itfollowsthat

at =

∞∑k=0

gkηt−k, with gk =

∞∑h=1

γh−1fh,k =

∞∑h=1

γh−1λkλk+1...λk+h−1ρk+h−1

. (32)

ThismakesclearhowtheIRF oftheequilibriumoutcomeisconnectedtotheIRFsofthefirst-and

higher-orderbeliefs. Importantly, thehigher γ is, themorethedynamicsoftheequilibriumoutcome

tracksthedynamicshigher-orderbeliefsrelativetothedynamicsoflower-orderbeliefs. Ontheother

hand, whenthegrowthrateoftheIRF ofthefundamental ρk+1

ρkishigher, italsoincreasestherelative

importanceofhigher-orderbeliefs. Thisargumentisparticularlyclearwhenconsideringtheinitial

response g0 andsetting ρk = ρk (ξt followsanAR(1)process)

g0 =

∞∑h=1

(γρ)h−1λ0λ1 . . . λh−1.

Here, γ and ρ playasimilarrole. ThisanalysisfurtherillustratesthepointmadeinSection 4.3.

Wearenowreadytoexplainourresultregardingmyopia. Forthispurpose, itisbesttoabstract

fromlearningandfocusonhowthemerepresenceofhigher-orderuncertaintyaffectsthebeliefsabout

thefuture. Intheabsenceoflearning, λk = λ forall k andforsome λ ∈ (0, 1). Theaforementioned

formulafortheIRF coefficientsthenreducestothefollowing:

gk =

∞∑h=1

(γλ)h−1ρk+h−1

λ.

Clearly, this thesame IRF as thatofacomplete-information, representative-economyeconomyin

29

Page 31: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

whichtheequilibriumdynamicssatisfy

at = ξ′t + γ′Et[at+1], (33)

where ξ′t ≡ λξt and γ′ ≡ γλ. Itisthereforeasifthefundamentalislessvolatileand, inaddition, the

agentsarelessforward-looking. Thefirsteffectstemsfromfirst-orderuncertainty: itispresentsimply

becausetheforecastofthefundamentalmovelessthanone-to-onewiththetruefundamental. The

secondeffectoriginatesinhigher-orderuncertainty: itispresentbecausetheforecastsoftheactions

ofothersmove even lessthantheforecastofthefundamental.

Thisisthecruxoftheforward-lookingcomponentofourobservational-equivalenceresult(thatis,

theoneregardingmyopia). Noteinparticularthattheextradiscountingofthefutureremainspresent

even ifwhen if control for the impactof the informational frictiononfirst-orderbeliefs. Indeed,

replacing ξ′t with ξt intheaboveshutsdowntheeffectoffirst-orderuncertainty. Andyet, theextra

discountingsurvives, reflectingtheroleofhigher-orderuncertainty. Thiscomplementstherelated

pointswemakeinSection 4.4 and 5.2.

Sofar, weshedlightonthesourceofmyopia, whileshuttingdowntheroleoflearning. Wenext

elaborateontherobustnessoftheaboveinsightstothepresenceoflearningand, mostimportantly,

onhowthepresenceoflearninganditsinteractionwithhigher-orderuncertaintydrivethebackward-

lookingcomponentofourobservational-equivalenceresult.

Tothisgoal, andasabenchmarkforcomparison, weconsideravarianteconomyinwhichall

agentssharethesamesubjectivebeliefabout ξt, thisbeliefhappenstocoincidewiththeaverage

first-orderbeliefintheoriginaleconomy, andthesefactsarecommonknowledge. Theequilibrium

outcomeinthiseconomyisproportionaltothesubjectivebeliefof ξt andisgivenby

at =∞∑k=0

gkηt−k, with gk =∞∑h=1

γh−1λkρk+h−1.

Thisresemblesthecomplete-informationbenchmarkinthattheoutcomeispineddownbythefirst-

orderbeliefof ξt, butallowsthisbelieftoadjustsluggishlytotheunderlyinginnovationsin ξt.

Byconstruction, thevarianteconomypreservestheeffectsoflearningonfirst-orderbeliefsbut

shutsdowntheinteractionoflearningwithhigher-orderuncertainty. Itfollowsthatthecomparison

ofthiseconomywiththeoriginaleconomyrevealstheroleofthisinteraction.

Proposition 8. Let gk and gk denotetheImpulseResponseFunctionoftheequilibriumoutcome

inthetwoeconomiesdescribedabove.

(i) 0 < gk < gk forall k ≥ 0

(ii)If ρkρk−1

≥ ρk+1

ρkand ρk > 0 forall k > 0, then gk+1

gk>

gk+1

gkforall k ≥ 0

30

Page 32: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Considerproperty(i), inparticularthepropertythat gk < gk. Thispropertymeansthatourecon-

omyexhibitsauniformlysmallerdynamicresponsefortheequilibriumoutcomethantheaforemen-

tionedeconomy, inwhichhigher-orderuncertaintyisshutdown. Butnotethatthetwoeconomies

sharethefollowinglawofmotion:

at = φEt[ξt] + γEt[at+1]. (34)

Furthermore, the twoeconomies share the samedynamic response for Et[ξt]. It follows that the

responsefor at inoureconomyissmallerthanthatofthevarianteconomybecause, andonlybecause,

theresponseof Et[at+1] isalsosmallerinoureconomy. Thisverifiesthatthepreciseroleofhigher-

orderuncertaintyistoarresttheresponseoftheexpectationsofthefutureoutcome(thefutureactions

ofothers)beyondandabovehowmuchthefirst-orderuncertainty(theunobservabilityof ξt)arrests

theresponseoftheexpectationsofthefuturefundamental.

A complementarywayofseeingthispointistonotethat gk satisfiesthefollowingrecursion:

gk = f1,k + λkγgk+1. (35)

Thefirsttermintheright-handsideofthisrecursioncorrespondstotheaverageexpectationofthe

futurefundamental. Thesecondtermcorrespondstheaverageexpectationofthefutureoutcome(the

actionsofothers). Theroleoffirst-orderuncertaintyiscapturedbythefactthat f1,k islowerthan

ρk. Theroleofhigher-orderuncertaintyiscapturedbythepresenceof λk inthesecondterm: itis

asifthediscountfactor γ hasbeenreplacedbyadiscountfactorequalto λkγ, whichisstrictlyless

than γ. Thisrepresentsageneralizationoftheformofmyopiaseenincondition(33). There, learning

wasshutdown, sothatthat λk andtheextradiscountingofthefuturewereinvariantinthehorizon k.

Here, theadditionaldiscountingvarieswiththehorizonbecauseoftheanticipationoffuturelearning

(namely, theknowledgethat λk willincreasewith k).

Considernextproperty(ii), namelythepropertythat

gk+1

gk>gk+1

gk

Thispropertyhelpsexplainthebackward-lookingcomponentofourobservational-equivalenceresult

(thatis, theoneregardinganchoring).

Tostartwith, considerthevarianteconomy, inwhichhigher-orderuncertaintyisshutdown. The

impactofashock k + 1 periodsfromnowrelativetoitsimpact k periodsfromnowisgivenby

gk+1

gk=λk+1

λk

∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h+1∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h>

∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h+1∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h.

31

Page 33: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Theinequalitycapturestheeffectoflearningonfirst-orderbeliefs. Hadinformationbeingperfect,

wewouldhavehad gk+1

gk=

∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h+1∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h; now, weinsteadhave gk+1

gk>

∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h+1∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h. Thismeans

that, inthevarianteconomy, theimpactoftheshockontheequilibriumoutcomecanbuildforce

overtimebecause, andonlybecause, learningallowsforagradualbuildupinfirst-orderbeliefs.26

Considernowoureconomy, inwhichhigher-orderuncertaintyispresent. Wenowhave

gk+1

gk>gk+1

gk

Thismeansthathigher-orderuncertaintyamplifiesthebuild-upeffectoflearning: astimepasses, the

impactoftheshockontheequilibriumoutcomebuildsforcemorerapidlyinoureconomythanin

thevarianteconomy. Butsincetheimpactisalwayslowerinoureconomy,27 thismeansthattheIRF

oftheequilibriumoutcomeislikelytodisplayamorepronouncedhumpshapeinoureconomythan

inthevarianteconomy. Indeed, thefollowingisadirectlycorollaryoftheaboveproperty.

Corollary 2. Supposethatthevarianteconomydisplaysahump-shapedresponse, namely gk is

singlepeakedat k = kb forsome kb ≥ 1. Then, theequilibriumoutcomealsodisplaysahump-shaped

response, namely gk isalsosinglepeakedat k = kg. Furthermore, thepeakof theequilibrium

responseisafterthepeakofthevarianteconomy: kg ≥ kb necessarily, and kg > kb foranopenset

of λk sequences.

Tointerpretthisresult, thinkmomentarilyof k asacontinuousvariableand, similarly, thinkof λk,

gk, and gk asdifferentiablefunctionsof k. If gk ishump-shapedwithapeakat k = kb > 0, itmustbe

that gk isweaklyincreasingpriorto kb andlocallyflatat kb. Butsincewehaveprovedthatthegrowth

rateof gk isstrictlyhigherthanthatof gk, thismeansthat gk attainsitsmaximumatapoint kg thatis

strictlyabove kb. Intheresultstatedabove, thelogicisthesame. Theonlytwististhat, because k is

discrete, wemusteitherrelax kg > kb to kg ≥ kb orputrestrictionson λk soastoguaranteethatkg ≥ kb + 1.

Summingup, learningbyitselfcontributestowardsagradualbuildupoftheimpactofanygiven

shockontheequilibriumoutcome; butitsinteractionwithhigher-orderuncertaintymakesthisbuild

upevenmorepronounced. Itispreciselythesepropertiesthatareencapsulatedinthebackward-

lookingcomponentofourobservationalequivalenceresult: thecoefficient ωb, whichcapturesthe

endogenousbuildupintheequilibriumdynamics, ispositivebecauseoflearninganditishigherthe

highertheimportanceofhigher-orderuncertainty.

TwoFormsofBoundedRationality. Wenowshedlightontwoadditionalpoints, whichwere

26Thisiseasiesttoseewhen ρk = 1 (i.e., thefundamentalfollowsarandomwalk), forthen gk+1 isnecessarilyhigherthan gk forall k. IntheAR(1)casewhere ρk = ρk with ρ < 1, gk+1 canbeeitherhigherorlowerthan gk, dependingonthebalancebetweentwoopposingforces: thebuild-upeffectoflearningandthemean-reversioninthefundamental.

27Recall, thisisbyproperty(i)ofProposition 8.

32

Page 34: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

anticipatedearlieron: theroleplayedbytheanticipationthatotherswilllearninthefuture; andthe

possibleinteractionofincompleteinformationwithLevel-kThinking.

Toillustratethefirstpoint, weconsiderabehavioralvariantwhereagentsfailtoanticipatethat

otherswilllearninthefuture. Tosimplify, wealsoset β = 0. Recallfromequation(31), whenagents

arerational, theforwardhigher-orderbeliefsare

Fht [ξt+h−1] =

∞∑k=0

λkλk+1...λk+h−1ρk+h−1ηt−k.

In thevarianteconomy, byshuttingdown theanticipationof learning, thenatureofhigher-order

beliefschanges, as Eit

[Et+k [ξt+q]

]= Eit

[Et [ξt+q]

]for k, q ≥ 0, andthecounterpartof Fh

t [ξt+h−1]

becomes

Eht [ξt+h−1] ≡ Et

[Et[. . .Et [[ξt+h−1] . . .]

]=

∞∑k=0

λhkρt+h−1ηt−k.

Learningimplies λk+1 > λk, andtheanticipationoflearningimplies λkλk+1...λk+h−1 > λhk . Asa

result, higher-orderbeliefsinthebehavioralvariantunderconsiderationvary less thanthoseunder

rationalexpectations. Bythesametoken, theaggregateoutcomeinthiseconomy, whichisgiven

at =

∞∑h=1

γh−1Eht [ξt+h−1] ,

behavesasifthemyopiaandanchoringarestrongerthanintherational-expectationscounterpart. In

linewiththeseobservations, itcanbeshownthat, ifwegobacktoourbaselinespecificationand

imposethatagentsfailtoanticipatethatotherswilllearninthefuture, Proposition 3 continuesto

holdwiththefollowingmodification: ωf issmallerand ωb ishigher.

Toillustratethesecondpoint, weconsideravariantthatletsagentshavelimiteddepthofreasoning

inthesenseofLevel-kThinking. Withlevel-0thinking, agentsbelievethattheaggregateoutcomeis

fixedatzeroforall t, butstillformrationalbeliefsaboutthefundamental. Therefore, a0it = Eit[ξt],

andtheimpliedaggregateoutcomeforlevel-0thinkingis a0t = Et[ξt].

Withlevel-1thinking, agent i’sactionchangesto

a1it = Eit[ξt] + γEit[a0t+1] = Eit[ξt] + γEit

[Et+1[ξt+1]

],

wherethesecond-orderhigher-orderbeliefshowsup. Byinduction, thelevel-k outcomeisgivenby

akt =k+1∑h=1

γh−1Fht [ξt+h−1] .

33

Page 35: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Inanutshell, Level-kThinkingsimplytruncatesthehierarchyofbeliefsatanexogenouslyspecified,

finiteorder.

Comparedwiththerational-expectationseconomythathasbeenthefocusofouranalysis, the

GE feedbackeffectsinbothoftheaforementionedtwovariantsareattenuated, andtheresultingas-

ifmyopiaisstrengthened. Furthermore, byselectingthedepthofthinking, wecanmakesurethat

thesecondvariantproducesasimilardegreeofmyopiaasthefirstone.28 Thatsaid, thesourceof

theadditionalmyopiaisdifferent. Inthefirst, therelevantforward-lookinghigher-orderbeliefshave

beenreplacedbymyopiccounterparts, whichmoveless. Inthesecond, theright, forward-looking

higher-orderbeliefsarestillatwork, buttheyhavebeentruncatedatafinitepoint.

8 Conclusion

Weshowedhowtheaccommodationofincompleteinformation, higher-orderuncertaintyandlearn-

inginforward-looking, general-equilibriummodelsisakintotheintroductionoftwobehavioraldis-

tortions: myopia, orextradiscountingofthefuture; andbackward-lookingbehavior, oranchoringof

currentoutcomestopastoutcomes. Weformalizedthisperspectivewiththehelpofanobservational-

equivalenceresult, whichrestedonstrongassumptions, butalsoelaboratedontherobustnessofthe

underlyinginsightsandtheofferedperspective.

Ourobservational-equivalenceresultwasinstrumental, notonlyfortheformalizationoftheabove

perspective, butalsoforthefollowingadditional, appliedpurposes:

1. Itillustratedhowincompleteinformationcan, notonlyofferasubstituteforthemoreadhoc

backward-lookingfeaturesoftheDSGE literature, butalsohelpresolvethegapbetweenthe

macroeconomicandmicroeconomicestimatesofsuchfeatures.

2. Itblendthesebackward-lookingfeatureswithaformofimperfectforesight.

3. IthighlightedhowbothoftheseelementsmaybeendogenoustoGE mechanismsandthereby

alsotomarketstructuresandpoliciesthatregulatethem.

4. Itfacilitatedtheempiricalevaluationofourtheoryinthecontextofinflationdynamics.

5. Itletusrelateourapproachandtheexistingliteratureoninformationalfrictionstoanemerging

literatureonboundedrationality.

Althoughourpaperwas focusedonmacroeconomicapplications, ourresultsand insightsare

relevantmorebroadly. Weconcludethepaperbyillustratingthisinthecontextofassetpricing.

28Thisfollowsdirectlyfromthefactthatimpactofeffectofaninnovationinthefirstvariantisboundedbetweenthoseofthelevel-0 andthelevel-∞ outcomeinthesecondvariant.

34

Page 36: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

InAppendix C,we take a settingwith dispersed information and overlapping generations of

traders, along the linesof Singleton (1987). We then show, under appropriateassumptions, that

thissettingcanbenestedinourframeworkandcanthusgiverisetothefollowingequilibriumasset-

pricingcondition:

pt = Et[dt+1] + ωfδEt[pt+1] + ωbpt−1,

where pt istheasset’sprice, dt isitsdividend, Et[·] isthefull-information, rational-expectationsop-

erator, δ isthestandarddiscountfactor, and (ωf , ωb) areourfamiliarcoefficients.

Theaboveoffersasharpillustrationofhowincompleteinformationcanrationalizemomentum

andpredictabilityinassetprices (ωb > 0), inlinewith Kasa, Walker, andWhiteman (2014). Butitalso

highlightsthepossibilityofexcessivediscountingofnewsaboutfuturefundamentals (ωf < 1). This

inturnhintstoapossiblefragilityofthepredictionsoftheliteraturethatemphasizeslong-termrisks

totheaccommodationofhigher-orderuncertainty. Finally, ourinsightaboutthedependenceofthe

as-ifdistortionsonstrategiccomplementarityandGE feedbacksaddsanewangletotheSamuelson

dictum(JungandShiller, 2005): totheextentthatthepositivefeedbackinassettradingisstrongerat

thestock-marketlevelthanattheindividual-stocklevelbecauseoffire-saleexternalitiesandliquidity

blackholes, our resultsmayhelpexplainwhyasset-priceanomaliesaremorepronouncedat the

formerlevelthanatthelatter.

35

Page 37: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

References

Abel, Andrew B.andOlivier J.Blanchard.1983. “AnIntertemporalModelofSavingandInvestment.”

Econometrica 51 (3):675–692. 5.1, 8

Allen, Franklin, StephenMorris, andHyun SongShin.2006. “BeautyContestsandIteratedExpecta-

tionsinAssetMarkets.” ReviewoffinancialStudies 19 (3):719–752. 8

Altissimo, Filippo, LaurentBilke, AndrewLevin, ThomasMatha, andBenoitMojon.2010. “Sectoral

andAggregateInflationDynamicsintheEuroArea.” JournaloftheEuropeanEconomicAssociation

4 (2-3):585–593. 1

Alvarez, FernandoandFrancescoLippi.2014. “PriceSettingwithMenuCostforMultiproductFirms.”

Econometrica 82 (1):89–135. 1, 12, 25

Angeletos, George-MariosandChenLian.2016. “IncompleteInformationinMacroeconomics: Ac-

commodatingFrictionsinCoordination.” HandbookofMacroeconomics 2:1065–1240. 2

———.2018. “ForwardGuidancewithoutCommonKnowledge.” American EconomicReview

108 (9):2477–2512. 1, 5, 2, 8, 5.1, 14, 5.3

Angeletos, George-MariosandAlessandroPavan.2007. “EfficientUseof InformationandSocial

ValueofInformation.” Econometrica 75 (4):1103–1142. 8

Auclert, Adrien.2017. “MonetaryPolicyandtheRedistributionChannel.” NBER WorkingPaperNo.

23451 . 16

Bachmann, Rüdiger, Ricardo J.Caballero, andEduardoM.R. A.Engel.2013. “Aggregate Impli-

cationsofLumpyInvestment: NewEvidenceandaDSGE Model.” AmericanEconomicJournal:

Macroeconomics 5 (4):29–67. 1, 12, 8

Bergemann, DirkandStephenMorris.2013. “RobustPredictionsinGameswithIncompleteInfor-

mation.” Econometrica 81 (4):1251–1308. 8

Bloom, Nicholas, MaxFloetotto, NirJaimovich, ItaySaporta-Eksten, andStephen J.Terry.2018. “Re-

allyUncertainBusinessCycles.” Econometrica forthcoming. 12

Bordalo, Pedro, NicolaGennaioli, YueranMa, andAndreiShleifer.2018. “Over-reactioninMacroe-

conomicExpectations.” NBER WorkingPaperNo.24932 . 2, 5.3

Caballero, Ricardo J.andEduardoM.R. A.Engel.1999. “ExplainingInvestmentDynamicsinU.S.

Manufacturing: A Generalized(S,s)Approach.” Econometrica 67 (4):783–826. 1, 12, 8

36

Page 38: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Carroll, Christopher D., EdmundCrawley, JiriSlacalek, KiichiTokuoka, andMatthew N.White.2018.

“StickyExpectations andConsumptionDynamics.” WorkingPaper24377, NationalBureauof

EconomicResearch. 7

Carvalho, Carlos, StefanoEusepi, EmanuelMoench, andBrucePreston.2017. “AnchoredInflation

Expectations.”. 2

Christiano, Lawrence J,MartinEichenbaum, andCharles L Evans.2005. “NominalRigiditiesandthe

DynamicEffectsofaShocktoMonetaryPolicy.” JournalofPoliticalEconomy 113 (1):1–45. 1, 5,

5.1, 6, 8

Coibion, OlivierandYuriyGorodnichenko.2012. “WhatCanSurveyForecastsTellUsaboutInfor-

mationRigidities?” JournalofPoliticalEconomy 120 (1):116–159. 5, 2, 5.3

———.2015. “InformationRigidityandtheExpectationsFormationProcess: A SimpleFramework

andNewFacts.” AmericanEconomicReview 105 (8):2644–78. 1, 5, 2, 5.3, 6, 6, 6, 6

Coibion, Olivier, YuriyGorodnichenko, andSatenKumar.2015. “HowDoFirmsFormTheirExpec-

tations? NewSurveyEvidence.” NBER WorkingPaperSeries . 5, 5.3

Del Negro, Marco, Marc P Giannoni, andChristinaPatterson.2015. “TheForwardGuidancePuzzle.”

FRB ofNewYorkmimeo . 5, 5.1

Evans, George W andSeppoHonkapohja.2012. Learningandexpectations inmacroeconomics.

PrincetonUniversityPress. 2

Farhi, EmmanuelandIvánWerning.2017. “MonetaryPolicy, BoundedRationality, andIncomplete

Markets.” NBER WorkingPaperNo.23281 . 1, 5, 5.1, 5.3

Gabaix, Xavier.2017. “A BehavioralNewKeynesianModel.” Harvardmimeo . 1, 5.3

Galí, Jordi.2008. MonetaryPolicy, Inflation, andtheBusinessCycle: AnIntroductiontotheNew

KeynesianFrameworkandItsApplicationsSecondedition. PrincetonUniversityPress. 6

Gali, JordiandMarkGertler.1999. “Inflationdynamics: A structuraleconometricanalysis.” Journal

ofMonetaryEconomics 44 (2):195–222. 1, 2, 6, 6

Gali, Jordi, MarkGertler, andJ DavidLopez-Salido.2005. “Robustnessoftheestimatesofthehybrid

NewKeynesianPhillipscurve.” JournalofMonetaryEconomics 52 (6):1107–1118. 1, 6, 6, 6, 24

Garcıa-Schmidt, MarianaandMichaelWoodford.2018. “AreLowInterestRatesDeflationary? A

ParadoxofPerfect-ForesightAnalysis.” AmericanEconomicReview forthcoming. 1, 19

37

Page 39: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Golosov, MikhailandRobert E Lucas Jr.2007. “MenuCostsandPhillipsCurves.” JournalofPolitical

Economy 115 (2):171–199. 1, 12, 25

Groth, CharlotaandHashmatKhan.2010. “InvestmentAdjustmentCosts: AnEmpiricalAssessment.”

JournalofMoney, CreditandBanking 42 (8):1469–1494. 1, 5.2

Havranek, Tomas, MarekRusnak, andAnnaSokolova.2017. “HabitFormationinConsumption: A

Meta-Analysis.” EuropeanEconomicReview 95:142–167. 1, 5.2

Hayashi, Fumio.1982. “Tobin’sMarginalqandAverageq: A NeoclassicalInterpretation.” Econo-

metrica 50 (1):213–224. 1, 5.1, 8

Huo, ZhenandMarcelo ZouainPedroni.2017. “InfiniteHigherOrderBeliefsandFirstOrderBeliefs:

AnEquivalnceResultInfiniteHigherOrderBeliefsandFirstOrderBeliefs: AnEquivalnceResult.”

miméo, YaleUniversity/UniversityofAmsterdam. 8

Huo, ZhenandNaokiTakayama.2015. “RationalExpectationsModelswithHigherOrderBeliefs.”

Yalemimeo . 2, 4.2, 31

Iovino, LuigiandDmitriySergeyev.2017. “QuantitativeEasingwithoutRationalExpectations.” Work

inprogress . 19

Jung, JeemanandRobert J.Shiller.2005. “Samuelson’sDictumandtheStockMarket.” Economic

Inquiry 43 (2):221–228. 1, 8, 8

Kaplan, Greg, BenjaminMoll, andGiovanni L Violante. 2016. “Monetary PolicyAccording to

HANK.” NBER WorkingPaperNo.21897 . 16

Kaplan, GregandGiovanni L.Violante. 2014. “A Modelof theConsumptionResponse toFiscal

StimulusPayments.” Econometrica 82 (4):1199–1239. 16

Kasa, Kenneth, Todd B.Walker, andCharles H.Whiteman.2014. “HeterogeneousBeliefsandTests

ofPresentValueModels.” TheReviewofEconomicStudies 81 (3):1137–1163. 8, 8

Khan, AubhikandJulia K.Thomas.2008. “IdiosyncraticShocksandtheRoleofNonconvexitiesin

PlantandAggregateInvestmentDynamics.” Econometrica 76 (2):395–436. 8

Kiley, Michael T.2007. “A QuantitativeComparisonofSticky-PriceandSticky-InformationModels

ofPriceSetting.” JournalofMoney, CreditandBanking 39 (s1):101–125. 6

Kohlhas, AlexandreandAnsgarWalther.2018a. “AsymmetricAttention.” IIES miméo . 2, 5.3

———.2018b. “SparseExpectations: A UnifiedExplanationofForecastData.” IIES miméo . 2, 5.3

38

Page 40: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Lucas, RobertE. Jr.1972. “ExpectationsandtheNeutralityofMoney.” JournalofEconomicTheory

4 (2):103–124. 1

Mackowiak, BartoszandMirkoWiederholt.2009. “OptimalStickyPricesunderRationalInattention.”

AmericanEconomicReview 99 (3):769–803. 4, 2, 5, 5.2, 8

———.2015. “BusinessCycleDynamicsunderRationalInattention.” ReviewofEconomicStudies

82 (4):1502–1532. 4, 5

Mankiw, N. GregoryandRicardoReis.2002. “StickyInformationversusStickyPrices: A Proposalto

ReplacetheNewKeynesianPhillipsCurve.” QuarterlyJournalofEconomics 117 (4):1295–1328.

4, 6, 5

Mankiw, N GregoryandRicardoReis.2007. “Stickyinformationingeneralequilibrium.” Journalof

theEuropeanEconomicAssociation 5 (2-3):603–613. 4, 5

Marcet, AlbertandJuan P Nicolini.2003. “Recurrenthyperinflationsandlearning.” AmericanEco-

nomicReview 93 (5):1476–1498. 2

Matejka, Filip.2016. “RationallyInattentiveSeller: SalesandDiscretePricing.” ReviewofEconomic

Studies 83 (3):1125–1155. 6

Mavroeidis, Sophocles, Mikkel Plagborg-Møller, and James H Stock. 2014. “Empirical evidence

oninflationexpectations in theNewKeynesianPhillipsCurve.” JournalofEconomicLiterature

52 (1):124–88. 6

McKay, Alisdair, EmiNakamura, andJónSteinsson.2016. “ThePowerofForwardGuidanceRevis-

ited.” AmericanEconomicReview 106 (10):3133–3158. 5

Melosi, Leonardo.2016. “Signallingeffectsofmonetarypolicy.” TheReviewofEconomicStudies

84 (2):853–884. 6

Midrigan, Virgiliu.2011. “MenuCosts, MultiproductFirms, andAggregateFluctuations.” Economet-

rica 79 (4):1139–1180. 25

Morris, StephenandHyun SongShin.2002. “SocialValueofPublicInformation.” AmericanEconomic

Review 92 (5):1521–1534. 1, 2, 8

———.2006. “InertiaofForward-lookingExpectations.” TheAmericanEconomicReview :152–157.

1, 2

Nakamura, EmiandJónSteinsson.2013. “PriceRigidity: MicroeconomicEvidenceandMacroeco-

nomicImplications.” AnnualReviewofEconomics 5 (1):133–163. 1, 12, 25

39

Page 41: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Nimark, Kristoffer.2008. “DynamicPricingandImperfectCommonKnowledge.” JournalofMonetary

Economics 55 (2):365–382. 1, 4, 2, 5

———.2017. “DynamicHigherOrderExpectations.” CornellUniveristymimeo . 7, 8, 31

Reis, Ricardo.2006. “Inattentiveproducers.” TheReviewofEconomicStudies 73 (3):793–821. 6

Sargent, Thomas J.1993. Boundedrationalityinmacroeconomics. OxfordUniversityPress. 2

Sims, Christopher A.2003. “ImplicationsofRationalInattention.” JournalofMonetaryEconomics

50 (3):665–690. 1, 4, 5

Singleton, Kenneth J.1987. “AssetPricesinaTime-seriesModelwithDisparatelyInformed, Com-

petitiveTraders.” In NewApproachestoMonetaryEconomics, editedbyWilliam A.Barnettand

Kenneth J.Singleton.CambridgeUniversityPress, 249–272. 8, 8

Smets, FrankandRafaelWouters.2007. “ShocksandFrictionsinUS BusinessCycles: A Bayesian

DSGE Approach.” AmericanEconomicReview 97 (3):586–606. 5, 5.1, 6, 8

Vellekoop, NathanaelandMirkoWiederholt.2017. “InflationExpectationsandChoicesofHouse-

holds.” GoetheUniversityFrankfurtmimeo . 5.3

Vives, XavierandLiyanYang.2017. “CostlyInterpretationofAssetPrices.” mimeo, IESE/University

ofToronto. 23

Werning, Iván.2015. “IncompleteMarketsandAggregateDemand.” NBERWorkingPaperNo.21448

. 16

Woodford, Michael.2003. “ImperfectCommonKnowledgeand theEffectsofMonetaryPolicy.”

Knowledge, Information, andExpectationsinModernMacroeconomics: InHonorofEdmundS.

Phelps . 1, 2, 8, 5

———.2018. “MonetaryPolicyAnalysisWhenPlanningHorizonsAreFinite.” In NBER Macroeco-

nomicsAnnual2018, Volume33.UniversityofChicagoPress. 5.1

Zorn, Peter.2018. “InvestmentunderRationalInattention: EvidencefromUS SectoralData.” miméo,

UniversityofMunich. 1, 7, 5.2

40

Page 42: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

AppendixA:Proofs

ProofofProposition 1. Followsdirectlyfromtheanalysisinthemaintext.

ProofofProposition 2. Supposethattheagent’sequilibriumpolicyfunctionisgivenby

ait = h(L)xit

forsomelagpolynomial h(L). Theaggregateoutcomecanthenbeexpressedasfollows:

at = h(L)ξt =h(L)

1− ρLηt.

Inthesequel, weverifythattheaboveguessiscorrectandcharacterize h(L).

First, welookforthefundamentalrepresentationofthesignals. Define τη = σ−2η and τu = σ−2

asthereciprocalsofthevariancesof, respectively, theinnovationinthefundamentalandthenoise

inthesignal. (Inthemaintext, wehavenormalized ση = 1.) Thesignalprocesscanberewrittenas

xit = M(L)

[ηt

uit

], with M(L) =

[τ− 1

11−ρL τ

− 12

u

].

Let B(L) denotethefundamentalrepresentationofthesignalprocess. Bydefinition, B(L) needsto

beaninvertibleprocessanditneedstosatisfythefollowingrequirement

B(L)B(L−1) = M(L)M′(L−1) =τ−1η + τ−1

u (1− ρL)(L− ρ)

(1− ρL)(L− ρ), (36)

whichleadsto

B(L) = τ− 1

2u

√ρ

λ

1− λL

1− ρL,

where λ istheinsiderootofthenumeratorinequation(36)

λ =1

2

ρ+ 1

ρ

(1 +

τuτη

)−

√(ρ+

1

ρ

(1 +

τuτη

))2

− 4

.Next, wecharacterizethebeliefsof ξt, ai,t+1, and at+1, thatis, thebeliefsthatshowupinthe

best-responseconditionoftheagent. Theforecastofarandomvariable

ft = A(L)

[ηt

uit

]

41

Page 43: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

canbeobtainedbyusingtheWiener-Hopfpredictionformula:

Eit[ft] =[A(L)M′(L−1)B(L−1)−1

]+B(L)−1xit.

Considertheforecastofthefundamental. Notethat

ξt =[τ− 1

11−ρL 0

] [ ηtuit

],

fromwhichitfollowsthat

Eit[ξt] = G1(L)xit, G1(L) ≡λ

ρ

τuτη

1

1− ρλ

1

1− λL.

Considertheforecastofthefutureownandaverageactions. Usingtheguessthat ait+1 = h(L)xi,t+1

and at+1 = h(L)ξt+1, wehave

at+1 =[τ− 1

h(L)L(1−ρL) 0

] [ ηtuit

], ait+1 − at+1 =

[0 τ

− 12

u h(L)

] [ ηtuit

],

andtheforecastsare

Eit [at+1] = G2(L)xit, G2(L) ≡λ

ρ

τuτη

(h(L)

(1− λL)(L− λ)− h(λ)(1− ρL)

(1− ρλ)(L− λ)(1− λL)

),

Eit [ait+1 − at+1] = G3(L)xit, G3(L) ≡λ

ρ

(h(L)(L− ρ)

L(L− λ)− h(λ)(λ− ρ)

λ(L− λ)− ρ

λ

h(0)

L

)1− ρL

1− λL

Now, turntothefixedpointproblemthatcharacterizestheequilibrium:

ait = Eit[φξt + βait+1 + γat+1]

Usingourguess, wecanreplacetheleft-handsidewith h(L)xit. Usingtheresultsderivedabove,

ontheotherhand, wecanreplacetheright-handsidewith [G1(L) + (β + γ)G2(L) + βG3(L)]xit. It

followsthatourguessiscorrectifandonlyif

h(L) = G1(L) + (β + γ)G2(L) + βG3(L)

42

Page 44: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Equivalently, weneedtofindananalyticfunction h(z) thatsolves

h(z) = φλ

ρ

τuτη

1

1− ρλ

1

1− λz+

+ (β + γ)λ

ρ

τuτη

(h(z)

(1− λz)(z − λ)− h(λ)(1− ρz)

(1− ρλ)(z − λ)(1− λz)

)+ β

λ

ρ

(h(z)(z − ρ)

z(z − λ)− h(λ)(λ− ρ)

λ(z − λ)− ρ

λ

h(0)

z

)1− ρz

1− λz,

whichcanbetransformedas

C(z)h(z) = d(z;h(λ), h(0))

where

C(z) ≡ z(1− λz)(z − λ)− λ

ρ

β(z − ρ)(1− ρz) + (β + γ)

τuτηz

d(z;h(λ), h(0)) ≡ φ

λ

ρ

τuτη

1

1− ρλz(z − λ)− 1

ρ

(τuτη

λ(β + γ)

1− ρλ+ β(λ− ρ)

)z(1− ρz)h(λ)

− β(z − λ)(1− ρz)h(0)

Notethat C(z) isacubicequationandthereforecontainswiththreeroots. Wewillverifylaterthat

therearetwoinsiderootsandoneoutsideroot. Tomakesurethat h(z) isananalyticfunction, we

choose h(0) and h(λ) sothatthetworootsof d(z;h(λ), h(0)) arethesameasthetwoinsiderootsof

C(z). Thispinsdowntheconstants h(0), h(λ), andthereforethepolicyfunction h(L)

h(L) =

(1− ϑ

ρ

1− ρδ

1

1− ϑL,

where ϑ−1 istherootof C(z) outsidetheunitcircle.

NowweverifythatC(z) hastwoinsiderootsandoneoutsideroot. NotethatC(z) canberewritten

as

C(z) = λ

− z3 +

(ρ+

1

ρ+

1

ρ

τuτη

+ β

)z2 −

(1 + β

(ρ+

1

ρ

)+β + γ

ρ

τuτη

)z + β

.

Withtheassumptionthat β > 0, γ > 0, and β+γ < 1, itisstraightforwardtoverifythatthefollowing

43

Page 45: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

propertieshold:

C(0) = β > 0

C(λ) = −λγ 1ρ

τuτη

< 0

C(1) =τu(1− β − γ)

τηρ+ (1− β)

(1

ρ+ ρ− 2

)> 0

Therefore, thethreerootsareallreal, twoofthemarebetween0and1, andthethirdone ϑ−1 islarger

than1.

Finally, toshowthat ϑ islessthan ρ, itissufficienttoshowthat

C

(1

ρ

)=τu(1− ρβ − ργ)

τηρ3> 0.

Since C(ϑ−1) = 0, ithastobethat ϑ−1 islargerthan ρ−1, or ϑ < ρ.

ProofofProposition 3. Theequilibriumoutcomeinthehybrideconomyisgivenbythefollowing

AR(2)process:

at =ζ0

1− ζ1Lξt

where

ζ1 =1

2ωfδ

(1−

√1− 4δωfωb

)and ζ0 =

φζ1ωb − ρωfδζ1

(37)

and δ ≡ β + γ. Thesolutiontotheincomplete-informationeconomyis

at =

(1− ϑ

ρ

)(φ

1− ρδ

)(1

1− ϑLξt

),

Tomatchthehybridmodel, weneed

ζ1 = ϑ and ζ0 =

(1− ϑ

ρ

1− ρδ. (38)

Combining(37)and(38), andsolvingforthecoefficientsof ωf and ωb, weinferthatthetwoeconomies

generatethesamedynamicsifandonlyifthefollowingtwoconditionshold:

ωf =δρ2 − ϑ

δ(ρ2 − ϑ2)(39)

ωb =ϑ(1− δϑ)ρ2

ρ2 − ϑ2(40)

44

Page 46: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Since δ ≡ β + γ andsince ϑ isa functionof theprimitiveparameters (σ, ρ, β, γ), theabove two

conditionsgivethecoefficients ωf and ωb asasfunctionsoftheprimitiveparameters, too.

Itisimmediatetocheckthat ωf < 1 and ωb > 0 if ϑ ∈ (0, ρ), whichinturnisnecessarilytruefor

any σ > 0; andthat ωf = 1 and ωb = 0 if ϑ = ρ, whichinturnisthecaseifandonlyif σ = 0. The

proofofthecomparativestaticsintermsof σ iscontainedintheproofofProposition 4.

ProofofProposition 4. Wefirstshowthat ωf isdecreasingin ϑ and ωb isincreasingin ϑ. Thiscan

beverifiedasfollows

∂ωf

∂ϑ=

−δ(ρ2 + ϑ2) + 2δ2ρ2ϑ

(δ(ρ2 − ϑ2))2<

−δ(ρ2 + ϑ) + 2δρϑ

(δ(ρ2 − ϑ2))2=

−δ(ρ− ϑ)2

(δ(ρ2 − ϑ2))2< 0

∂ωb

∂ϑ=ρ2(ρ2 + ϑ2 − 2δϑρ2)

(ρ2 − ϑ2)2>ρ2(ρ2 + ϑ2 − 2ϑρ)

(ρ2 − ϑ2)2=

ρ+ ϑ

)2

> 0

Nowitissufficienttoshowthat ϑ isincreasingin γ. Notethat

C

(1

ρ

)=τu(1− ρβ − ργ)

τηρ3> 0 and C

(1

λ

)= −τu

τη

γβ

ρλ2< 0

Bythecontinuityof C(z), itmustbethecasethat C(z) admitsarootbetween 1ρ and 1

λ . Recallfrom

theproofofProposition 2, ϑ−1 istheonlyoutsideroot, anditfollowsthat λ < ϑ < ρ. Italsoimplies

that C(z) isdecreasingin z intheneighborhoodof z = ϑ−1, apropertythatweuseinthesequelto

characterizecomparativestaticsof ϑ.

Next, usingthedefinitionof C(z), namely

C(z) ≡ −z3 +(ρ+

1

ρ+

1

ρ

τuτη

+ β

)z2 −

(1 + β

(ρ+

1

ρ

)+β + γ

ρ

τuτη

)z + β,

takingitsderivativewithrespectto γ, andevaluatingthatderivativeat z = ϑ−1, weget

∂C(ϑ−1)

∂γ= − τu

ρτη< 0

Combiningthiswiththeearlierobservationthat ∂C(ϑ−1)∂z < 0, andusingtheImplicitFunctionTheo-

rem, weinferthat ϑ isanincreasingfunctionof γ.

Similarly, takingderivativewithrespectto τu, wehave

∂C(ϑ−1)

∂τu=

1

ρτηϑ−1(ϑ−1 − β − γ) >

1

ρτηϑ−1(1− β − γ) > 0.

Since σ =√τu, ϑ isalsoincreasingin σ.

45

Page 47: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

ProofofProposition 5. Thehybridandtheincomplete-informationeconomiesgeneratethesame

dynamicsifandonlyifconditions(39)and(40)hold. Using(40), wecanrewrite(39)asfollows:

ωf = Ω(ωb; δ, ρ) ≡ 1− 1

δρ2ωb. (41)

Furthermore, any (β, γ, ρ), theequilibriumoftheincomplete-informationeconomygivesaninvertible

mappingfrom σ ∈ (0,∞) to ϑ ∈ (0, ρ), whereascondition(40)givesaninvertiblemappingfrom

ϑ ∈ (0, ρ) to ωb ∈ (0,∞). Itfollowsthatthereexistsa σ ∈ (0,∞) suchthattheequilibriumdynamics

oftheincomplete-informationeconomyreplicatesthatofthehybrideconomyifandonlyifthepair

(ωb, ωf ) satisfiescondition(41)alongwith ωb ∈ (0,∞). Finally, theleveloftheinformationalfriction

thatachievesthisreplicationisobtainedbyinvertingcondition(40)toobtain ϑ, andtherebyalso σ,

asanimplicitfunctionof ωb.

ProofofProposition 8. First, letusprove gk < gk. Recallthat gk isgivenby

gk =

∞∑h=0

γhλkλk+1...λk+hρk+h

Clearly,

0 < gk <

∞∑h=0

γhλkρk+h = gk,

whichprovesthefirstproperty. If limk→∞ λk = 1 and∑∞

h=0 γhρk+h existsforall k, thenitfollows

that

limk→∞

gkgk

=limk→∞

∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h

limk→∞∑∞

h=0 γhρk+h

= 1.

Next, letusprovethat gk+1

gk>

gk+1

gk. Bydefinition,

gk+1

gk=λk+1

λk

∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h+1∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h

gk+1

gk=λk+1

λk

∑∞h=0 γ

hλk+2...λk+h+1ρk+h+1∑∞h=0 γ

hλk+1...λk+hρk+h

Since λk isstrictlyincreasingand ρk > 0, wehave

gk+1

gk

/gk+1

gk>

∑∞h=0 γ

hλk+1...λk+hρk+h+1∑∞h=0 γ

hλk+1...λk+hρk+h

/∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h+1∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h

Itremainstoshowthatthetermontheright-handsideisgreaterthan1. Toproceed, westartwith

46

Page 48: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

thefollowingobservation. If θ1 ≥ θ2 > 0, and y2y1+y2

≥ x2x1+x2

, then

x1θ1 + x2θ2x1 + x2

≥ y1θ1 + y2θ2y1 + y2

Notethat ∑∞h=0 γ

hλk+1...λk+hρk+h+1∑∞h=0 γ

hλk+1...λk+hρk+h=ρk+1

ρk

1 + γλk+1ρk+2

ρk+1+ γ2λk+1λk+2

ρk+3

ρk+1+ . . .

1 + γλk+1ρk+1

ρk+ γ2λk+1λk+2

ρk+2

ρk+ . . .

and ∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h+1∑∞h=0 γ

hρk+h=ρk+1

ρk

1 + γρk+2

ρk+1+ γ2

ρk+3

ρk+1+ . . .

1 + γρk+1

ρk+ γ2

ρk+2

ρk+ . . .

Basedontheobservation, wewillshowthat

1 + γλk+1ρk+2

ρk+1+ γ2λk+1λk+2

ρk+3

ρk+1+ . . .

1 + γλk+1ρk+1

ρk+ γ2λk+1λk+2

ρk+2

ρk+ . . .

≥1 + γ

ρk+2

ρk+1+ γ2

ρk+3

ρk+1+ . . .

1 + γρk+1

ρk+ γ2

ρk+2

ρk+ . . .

byinduction. Wefirstestablishthefollowing

1 + γλk+1ρk+2

ρk+1

1 + γλk+1ρk+1

ρk

≥1 + γ

ρk+2

ρk+1

1 + γρk+1

ρk

This inequality isobtainedby labeling θ1 = 1, θ2 =ρkρk+2

ρ2k+1, x1 = y1 = 1, x2 = γλk+1

ρk+1

ρk, and

y2 = γρk+1

ρk. Byassumption, ρkρk+2

ρ2k+1≤ 1. Meanwhile,

x2x1 + x2

=γλk+1

ρk+1

ρk

1 + γλk+1ρk+1

ρk

≤γλk+1

ρk+1

ρk

λk+1 + γλk+1ρk+1

ρk

=y2

y1 + y2

Nowsupposethat

1 + γλk+1ρk+2

ρk+1+ . . .+ γn−1λk+1 . . . λk+n−1

ρk+n

ρk+1

1 + γλk+1ρk+1

ρk+ . . .+ γn−1λk+1 . . . λk+n−1

ρk+n−1

ρk

≥1 + γ

ρk+2

ρk+1+ . . .+ γn−1 ρk+n

ρk+1

1 + γρk+1

ρk+ . . .+ γn−1 ρk+n−1

ρk

Wewanttoshow

1 + γλk+1ρk+2

ρk+1+ . . .+ γn−1λk+1 . . . λk+n−1

ρk+n

ρk+1+ γnλk+1 . . . λk+n

ρk+n+1

ρk+1

1 + γλk+1ρk+1

ρk+ . . .+ γn−1λk+1 . . . λk+n−1

ρk+n−1

ρk+ γnλk+1 . . . λk+n

ρk+n

ρk

≥1 + γ

ρk+2

ρk+1+ . . .+ γn−1 ρk+n

ρk+1+ γn

ρk+n+1

ρk+1

1 + γρk+1

ρk+ . . .+ γn−1 ρk+n−1

ρk+ γn

ρk+n

ρk

47

Page 49: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Let θ1 =1+γ

ρk+2ρk+1

+...+γn−1 ρk+nρk+1

1+γρk+1ρk

+...+γn−1ρk+n−1

ρk

, θ2 =ρkρk+n+1

ρk+1ρk+n, x1 = 1+γλk+1

ρk+1

ρk+. . .+γn−1λk+1 . . . λk+n−1

ρk+n−1

ρk,

x2 = γnλk+1 . . . λk+nρk+n

ρk, y1 = 1 + γ

ρk+1

ρk+ . . .+ γn−1 ρk+n−1

ρk, y2 = γn

ρk+n

ρk. Wehave

1 + γλk+1ρk+2

ρk+1+ . . .+ γn−1λk+1 . . . λk+n−1

ρk+n

ρk+1+ γnλk+1 . . . λk+n

ρk+n+1

ρk+1

1 + γλk+1ρk+1

ρk+ . . .+ γn−1λk+1 . . . λk+n−1

ρk+n−1

ρk+ γnλk+1 . . . λk+n

ρk+n

ρk

=

x11+γλk+1

ρk+2ρk+1

+...+γn−1λk+1...λk+n−1ρk+nρk+1

1+γλk+1ρk+1ρk

+...+γn−1λk+1...λk+n−1ρk+n−1

ρk

+ x2θ2

x1 + x2

≥x1θ1 + x2θ2x1 + x2

and

1 + γρk+2

ρk+1+ . . .+ γn−1 ρk+n

ρk+1+ γn

ρk+n+1

ρk+1

1 + γρk+1

ρk+ . . .+ γn−1 ρk+n−1

ρk+ γn

ρk+n

ρk

=y1θ1 + y2θ2y1 + y2

Itremainstoshowthat θ1 ≥ θ2 and x2x1+x2

≤ y2y1+y2

. Notethat

θ1θ2

=1 + γ

ρk+1

ρk

ρk+2ρkρ2k+1

+ . . .+ γn−1 ρk+n−1

ρk

ρk+nρkρk+1ρk+n−1

θ2 + γρk+1

ρkθ2 + . . .+ γn−1 ρk+n−1

ρkθ2

Byassumption, θ2 < 1 and θ2 ≤ ρkρk+i+1

ρk+1ρk+iwhen i ≤ n, whichleadsto θ1 ≥ θ2. Alsonotethat

x2x1 + x2

=γnλk+1 . . . λk+n

ρk+n

ρk

1 + γλk+1ρk+1

ρk+ . . .+ γn−1λk+1 . . . λk+n−1

ρk+n−1

ρk+ γnλk+1 . . . λk+n

ρk+n

ρk

≤γnλk+1 . . . λk+n

ρk+n

ρk

λk+1 . . . λk+n + γλk+1 . . . λk+nρk+1

ρk+ . . .+ γn−1λk+1 . . . λk+n

ρk+n−1

ρk+ γnλk+1 . . . λk+n

ρk+n

ρk

=y2

y1 + y2

Thiscompletestheproofthat gk+1

gk>

gk+1

gk.

AppendixB:Investment

A longtraditioninmacroeconomicsthatgoesbackto Hayashi (1982)and AbelandBlanchard (1983)

hasstudiedrepresentative-agentmodelsinwhichthefirmsfaceacostinadjustingtheircapitalstock.

48

Page 50: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Inthisliterature, theadjustmentcostisspecifiedasfollows:

Costt = Φ

(It

Kt−1

)(42)

where It denotestherateofinvestment, Kt−1 denotesthecapitalstockinheritedfromtheprevious

period, and Φ isaconvexfunction. Thisspecificationgivesthelevelof investmentasadecreas-

ingfunctionofTobin’sQ.Italsogeneratesaggregateinvestmentresponsesthatarebroadlyinline

withthosepredictedbymorerealistic, heterogeneous-agentmodelsthataccountforthedynamicsof

investmentatthefirmorplantlevel(CaballeroandEngel, 1999; Bachmann, Caballero, andEngel,

2013; KhanandThomas, 2008).29

Bycontrast, theDSGE literaturethatfollows Christiano, Eichenbaum, andEvans (2005)and Smets

andWouters (2007)assumesthatthefirmsfaceacostinadjusting, nottheircapitalstock, butrather

theirrateofinvestment. Thatis, thisliteraturespecifiestheadjustmentcostasfollows:

Costt = Ψ

(ItIt−1

)(43)

AswiththeHybridNKPC,thisspecificationwasadoptedbecauseitallowsthetheorytogenerate

sluggishaggregateinvestmentresponsestomonetaryandothershocks. Butithasnoobviousanalogue

intheliteraturethataccountsforthedynamicsofinvestmentatthefirmorplantlevel.

Inthesequel, wesetupamodelofaggregateinvestmentwithtwokeyfeatures: first, theadjust-

mentcosttakestheformseenincondition(42); andsecond, theinvestmentsofdifferentfirmsare

strategiccomplementsbecauseofanaggregatedemandexternality. Wethenaugmentthismodelwith

incompleteinformationandshowthatitbecomesobservationallyequivalenttoamodelinwhichthe

adjustmentcosttakestheformseenincondition(43). Thisillustrateshowincompleteinformation

canmergethegapbetweenthedifferentstrandsoftheliteratureandhelpreconcilethedominant

DSGE practicewiththerelevantmicroeconomicevidenceoninvestment.

Letusfillinthedetails. WeconsideranAK modelwithcoststoadjustingthecapitalstock. There

is a continuumofmonopolistic competitivefirms, indexedby i andproducingdifferent varieties

of intermediate investmentgoods. Thefinal investmentgood isaCES aggregatorof intermediate

investmentgoods. Letting Xit denote the investmentgoodproducedbyfirm i, wehave that the

aggregateinvestmentisgivenby

It =

[∫X

σ−1σ

it

] σσ−1

.

29Theseworksdifferontheimportancetheyattributetoheterogeneity, lumpiness, andnon-linearities, butappeartosharethepredictionthattheimpulseresponseofaggregateinvestmentispeakedonimpact. Theythereforedonotprovideamicro-foundationofthekindofsluggishinvestmentdynamicsfeaturedintheDSGE literature.

49

Page 51: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Andletting Qit denotethepricefacedbyfirm i, wehavethattheinvestmentpriceindexisgivenby

Qt =

[∫Q1−σ

it

] 11−σ

.

A representativefinalgoodsproducerhasperfect informationandpurchases investmentgoods to

maximizeitsdiscountedprofit

maxKt,It

∞∑t=0

χtE0

[exp(ξt)AKt −QtIt − Φ

(ItKt

)Kt

],

subjectto

Kt+1 = Kt + It.

Here, thefundamentalshock, ξt, isanexogenousproductivityshocktothefinalgoodsproduction,

and Φ(

ItKt

)Kt represents thequadraticcapital-adjustmentcost. Thefollowingfunctional formis

assumed:

Φ

(ItKt

)=

1

(ItKt

)2

.

Let Zt ≡ ItKt

denotetheinvestment-to-capitalratio. Onabalancedgrowthpath, thisratioandthe

pricefortheinvestmentgoodsremainconstant, i.e., Zt = Z and Qt = Q. Thelog-linearizedversion

ofthefinalgoodsproducer’soptimalconditionaroundthebalancedgrowthpathcanbewrittenas

Qqt + ψZzt = χEt

[Aξt+1 +Qqt+1 + ψZ(1 + Z)zt+1

]. (44)

Whentheproducersoftheintermediateinvestmentgoodschoosetheirproductionscale, theymay

notobservetheunderlyingfundamental ξt perfectly. Asaresult, theyhavetomaketheirdecision

basedontheirexpectationsaboutfundamentalsandothers’decisions. Letting

maxXit

Eit [QitXit − cXit] ,

subjectto

Qit =

(Xit

It

)− 1σ

Qt.

Define Zit ≡ XitKt

asthefirm-specificinvestment-to-capitalratio, andthelog-linearizedversionofthe

optimalchoiceof Xit is

zit = Eit [zt + σqt] .

50

Page 52: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

Insteadystate, theprice Q simplyequalsthemarkupovermarginalcost c,

Q =σ

σ − 1c,

andtheinvestment-to-capitalratio Z solvesthequadraticequation

Q+ ψZ =χ

(A+Q+ ψZ + ψZ2 − 1

2ψZ2

).

FrictionlessBenchmark. Ifallintermediatefirmsobserve ξt perfectly, thenwehave

zit = zt + σqt

Aggregationimpliesthat zit = zt and qt = 0. Itfollowsthat zt obeysthefollowingEulercondition:

zt = φξt + δEt [zt+1]

where

φ =ρχA

ψZand δ = χ(1 + Z).

IncompleteInformation. Supposenowthatfirmsreceiveanoisysignalaboutthefundamental ξtasinSection 3. Here, wemakethesamesimplifyingassumptionasintheNKPC application. We

assumethatfirmsobservecurrent zt, butprecludethemfromextractinginformationfromit. Together

withthepricingequation(44), theaggregateinvestmentdynamicsfollow

zt =ρχA

ψZ

∞∑k=0

χkEt[ξt+k] + χZ

∞∑k=0

χkEt[zt+k+1]

Theinvestmentdynamicscanbeunderstoodasthesolutiontothedynamicbeautyconteststudiedin

Section 3 byletting

φ =ρχA

ψZ, β = χ, and γ = χZ.

Thefollowingisthenimmediate.

Proposition 9. Wheninformationisincomplete, thereexist ωf < 1 and ωb > 0 suchthattheequilib-

riumprocessforinvestmentsolvesthefollowingequation:

zt = φξt + ωfδEt[zt+1] + ωbzt−1

Finally, it straightforward toshowthat theaboveequation isof thesame typeas theone that

governsinvestmentinacomplete-informationmodelwheretheadjustmentcostis intermsofthe

51

Page 53: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

investmentrate, namelyamodelinwhichthefinalgoodproducer’sproblemismodifiedasfollows:

maxKt,It

∞∑t=0

χtE0

[exp(ξt)AKt −QtIt −Ψ

(It

It−1

)It

]

where It istheaggregateinvestment.

AppendixC:AssetPrices

Consideralog-linearizedversionofthestandardasset-pricingconditioninaninfinitehorizon, representative-

agentmodel:

pt = Et[dt+1] + δEt[pt+1],

where pt isthepriceoftheassetinperiod t, dt+1 isitsdividendinthenextperiod, Et istheexpec-

tationoftherepresentativeagent, and δ ishisdiscountfactor. Iteratingtheaboveconditiongivesthe

equilibriumpriceastheexpectedpresentdiscountedvalueofthefuturedividends.

Byassumingarepresentativeagent, theaboveconditionconcealstheimportanceofhigher-order

beliefs. A numberofworkshavesoughttounearththatrolebyconsideringvariantswithheteroge-

neouslyinformed, short-termtraders, inthetraditionof Singleton (1987); see, forexample, Allen,

Morris, andShin (2006), Kasa, Walker, andWhiteman (2014), and Nimark (2017). Wecancapture

theseworksinoursettingbymodifyingtheequilibriumpricingconditionasfollows:

pt = Et[dt+1] + δEt[pt+1] + ϵt,

where Et isthe average expectationofthetradersinperiod t and ϵt isani.i.dshockinterpretedas

thepriceeffectofnoisytraders. Thekeyideaembeddedintheaboveconditionisthat, aslongasthe

tradershavedifferentinformationandtherearelimitstoarbitrage, assetmarketsarelikelytobehave

like(dynamic)beautycontests.

Letusnowassumethat thedividendisgivenby dt+1 = ξt + ut+1, where ξt followsanAR(1)

processand ut+1 isi.i.d. overtime, andthattheinformationofthetypicaltradercanberepresented

bya seriesofprivate signalsas incondition (11).30 Applyingour results, andusing the fact that

ξt = Et[dt+1], wethenhavethatthecomponentoftheequilibriumassetpricethatisdrivenby ξt30Here, weareabstractingfromthecomplicationsoftheendogenousrevelationofinformationandwethinkofthesignals

in(11)asconvenientproxiesforalltheinformationofthetypicaltrader. Onecanalsointerpretthisasasettinginwhichthedividendisobservable(andhencesoistheprice, whichismeasurableinthedividend)andtheassumedsignalsaretherepresentationofaformofrationalinattention. Lastbutnotleast, wehaveverifiedthatthesolutionwithendogenousinformationcanbeapproximatedverywellbythesolutionobtainedwithexogenousinformation.

52

Page 54: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

obeysthefollowinglawofmotion, forsome ωf < 1 and ωb > 0:

pt = Et[dt+1] + ωfδEt[pt+1] + ωbpt−1,

where Et[·] isthefully-information, rationalexpectations. Wethushavethatassetpricescandisplay

bothmyopia, intheformof ωf < 1, andmomentum, orpredictability, intheformof ωb > 0.

Kasa, Walker, andWhiteman (2014)havealreadyemphasizedhowincompleteinformationand

higher-orderuncertaintycanhelpexplainmomentumandpredictabilityinassetprices. Ourresult

offersasharpillustrationofthisinsightandblendsitwiththeinsightregardingmyopia. Inthepresent

context, thelatterinsightseemstochallengetheasset-priceliteraturethatemphasizeslong-runrisks:

newsaboutthelong-runfundamentalsmaybeheavilydiscountedwhenthereishigher-orderuncer-

tainty. Finally, ourresultsuggeststhatbothkindsofdistortionsarelikelytobegreateratthelevelof

theentirestockmarketthanatthelevelofthestockofaparticularfirminsofarasfinancialfrictions

andGE effectscausethetradestobestrategiccomplementsatthemacroleveleveniftheyarestrate-

gicsubstitutesatthemicrolevel, whichinturnmayhelprationalizeSamuelson’sdictum(Jungand

Shiller, 2005).

Weleavetheexplorationofthese—admittedlyspeculative—ideasopenforfutureresearch. We

concludethisappendixbyillustratinghowourobservational-equivalenceresult, whichreliesonas-

sumingawaytheendogenousrevelationofinformationthroughtheequilibriumprice, canbeseen

asanapproximationofthedynamicsthatobtainwhenthisassumptionisrelaxed.

Allowinglearningfrompricesaddsmorerealism, buttypicallyrulesoutananalyticcharacteriza-

tionoftheequilibrium.31 Suppose, inparticular, thatthetradersinoursettingcanperfectlyobserve

thecurrentpriceaswellasthelast-perioddividend. Inthiscase, theequilibriumpricingdynamics

doesnotadmitafinitestate-spacerepresentation. Toillustrate, set δ = 0.98, ρ = 0.95, σu = 2, and

σϵ = σν = 5, andapproximatetheequilibriumdynamicswithanMA(100)process. Thesolidbluein

Figure 3 givestheresultingIRF oftheequilibriumpricetoaninnovationin ξt. Thedashedredline

isobtainedbytakingourhybrideconomy, whichassumesawaythelearningfromeitherthepriceor

thepastdividend, andrecalibratingtheleveloftheidiosyncraticnoisesothattheimpliedIRF isclose

aspossibletotheoneobtainedintheeconomyinwhichsuchlearningisallowed. Asevidentinthe

figure, thehybrideconomydoesaverygoodjobinreplicatingthedynamicsofthelattereconomy.

Wehaveverifiedthatthissimilarityextendstoawiderangeofvaluesfortheparametersofthe

assumedsetting. Thissimilaritymay, ofcourse, bebrokenbyassumingamorecomplexstochastic

processfor thefundamentalandamoreconvolutedlearningdynamics. However, theanalysisof

Section 7 togetherwiththeexamplepresentedhereillustratewhyouranalysiscanbethoughtofasa

31See Nimark (2017)and HuoandTakayama (2015)foramoredetaileddiscussion.

53

Page 55: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

0 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 164

6

8

10

12

14

16

Figure 3: ImpulseResponseFunctionofAssetPrice

convenientproxyofsettingswithendogenousinformationaggregation.

AppendixD:VariantwithIdiosyncraticShocks

Inthisappendix, weextendtheanalysistoasettingthatfeaturesbothaggregateandidiosyncratic

shocks. Thisservestoillustratehowourtheoryoffersanaturalexplanationofwhysignificantlevelsof

as-ifmyopiaandanchoringcanbepresentatthemacroeconomiclevel(i.e., intheresponsetoaggre-

gateshocks)eveniftheyareabsentatthemicroeconomiclevel(i.e., intheresponsetoidiosyncratic

shocks), whichcomplementsthediscussioninSection 5 .

Toaccommodateidiosyncraticshocks, weextendthemodelsothattheoptimalbehaviorofagent

i obeysthefollowingequation:

ait = Eit[φξit + βait+1 + γat+1]

where

ξit = ξt + ζit

andwhere ζit isapurelyidiosyncraticshock. WeletthelatterfollowasimilarAR(1)processasthe

aggregateshock: ζit = ρζit−1 + ϵit, where ϵit isi.i.d. acrossboth i and t.32

Wethenspecifytheinformationstructureasfollows. First, weleteachagentobservethesame

signal xit abouttheaggregateshock ξt asinourbaselinemodel. Second, weleteachagentobserve

32Therestrictionthatthetwokindsofshockshavethesamepersistenceisonlyforexpositionalsimplicity.

54

Page 56: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

thefollowingsignalabouttheidiosyncraticshock ζit :

zit = ζit + vit,

where vit isindependentof ζit, of ξt, andof xit.

Becausethesignalsareindependent, theupdatingofthebeliefsabouttheidiosyncraticandthe

aggregateshocksarealsoindependent. Let 1− λρ betheKalmangainintheforecastsoftheaggregate

fundamental, thatis,

Eit[ξt] = λEit−1[ξt] +

(1− λ

ρ

)xit

Next, let 1− λρ betheKalmangainintheforecastsoftheidiosyncraticfundamental, thatis,

Eit[ζit] = λEit−1[ζit] +

(1− λ

ρ

)zit

ItisstraightforwardtoextendtheresultsofSection 4.2 tothecurrentspecification. Itcanthusbe

shownthattheequilibriumactionisgivenbythefollowing:

ait =

(1− λ

ρ

1− ρβ

1

1− λLζit +

(1− ϑ

ρ

1− ρδ

1

1− ϑLξt + uit

where ϑ isdeterminedinthesamemannerasinourbaselinemodelandwhere uit isaresidualthat

isorthogonaltoboth ζit and ξt andthatcapturesthecombinedeffectofalltheidiosyncraticnoisesin

theinformationofagent i. Finally, itisstraightforwardtocheckthat ϑ = λ when γ = 0; ϑ > λ when

γ > 0; andthegapbetween ϑ and λ increaseswiththestrengthoftheGE effect, asmeasuredwith γ.

Incomparison, thefull-informationequilibriumactionisgivenby

a∗it =φ

1− ρβζit +

κ

1− ρδξt.

Itfollowsthat, relativetothefull-informationbenchmark, thedistortionsofthemicro-andthemacro-

levelIRFsaregivenby, respectively,(1− λ

ρ

)1

1− λLand

(1− ϑ

ρ

)1

1− ϑL.

Themacro-leveldistortionsisthereforehigherthanitsmicro-levelcounterpartifandonlyif ϑ > λ.

Following MackowiakandWiederholt (2009), itisnaturaltoassumethat λ islowerthan λ, be-

causethetypicalagentislikelytoallocatemoreattentiontoidiosyncraticshocksthantoaggregate

shocks. Thisguaranteesalowerdistortionatthemicrolevelthanatthemacrolevelevenifweabstract

55

Page 57: Myopia and Anchoring - lse.ac.uk · myopia,as in models with imperfect foresight;and anchoring of the current outcome to the past outcome,as in models with habit persistence and adjustment

fromGE interactions(whichamountstosetting γ = 0, orabstractingfromrolehigher-orderuncer-

tainty). Butoncesuchinteractionsaretakenintoaccount, wehavethat ϑ remainshigherthan λ even

if λ = λ. Inshort, themacro-levelresponsecandisplayabiggerdistortion, notonlybecauseofthe

mechanismidentifiedintheaforecitedpaper, butalsobecauseoftheroleofhigher-orderuncertainty

identifiedhere.

56