naïve, resolute or sophisticated? a study of dynamic decision making john d hey luiss, rome, italy...

47
Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università del Piemonte Orientale ESA 2007 World Meeting , 28th June- 1st July 2007

Upload: winfred-marsh

Post on 31-Dec-2015

219 views

Category:

Documents


3 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated?A Study of Dynamic Decision Making

John D HeyLUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK

Gianna LotitoUniversità del Piemonte Orientale

ESA 2007 World Meeting , 28th June-1st July 2007

Page 2: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

The issue

• An important issue in the analysis of dynamic decision making concerns the behaviour of dynamically inconsistent people.

• Do they know that they are dynamically inconsistent, and, if so, what do they do about it?

• One prior issue to be discussed before proceeding:• Do the preferences of the decision maker satisfy

Expected Utility theory or not?• If they do, then the decision maker is not dynamically

inconsistent.• If they don’t, then the possibility of dynamically

inconsistent behaviour arises.

Page 3: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• Two points should be made in this latter case:

1) A non-Expected Utility decision maker may plan to make a particular decision when he or she reaches some decision node, but may prefer to implement another decision when that decision node is actually reached.

2) for a non-Expected Utility decision maker, the way that he or she processes the decision tree may make a difference to the solution adopted:

• choosing the best ex ante strategy might lead to one solution,

• while using backward induction might lead to another.

Page 4: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• Economic theory has identified three possible responses to the dynamic inconsistency question:

• such decision makers act naively (ignoring their inconsistency);

• they act resolutely (imposing their first-period preferences and not letting their inconsistency affect their behaviour);

• they act sophisticatedly (anticipating their inconsistency, optimizing by taking it into account, then letting their inconsistency affect their behaviour).

Page 5: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• We report on an experiment that lets us infer which of these responses describes the behaviour better.

• The experiment allows us not only to observe choices in dynamic decision problems but also to obtain subjects’ evaluations of such problems.

• Combining these two types of data we can• not only estimate the preferences of the

decision makers• but also infer whether they are naïve, resolute

or sophisticated

Page 6: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

Background• The present study builds upon two previous studies,

both concerned with dynamic decision problems.• The first of these is that of Cubitt, Starmer and

Sugden (1998), who considered the issue of behaviour in dynamic decision problems;

• the second study is that of Hey and Paradiso (2006) who considered subjects’ evaluations of decision problems.

• Both studies used the same three decision trees which are representations of a dynamic decision problem identical from a strategic point of view (the set of available ex ante strategies is the same for all trees), but different in the temporal frame.

Page 7: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• Cubitt et al. find that subjects behave differently in the different trees – which violates the hypothesis that the subjects’ preferences are EU, and suggests that temporal frame influences decisions.

• Hey and Paradiso find that the temporal frame has also some effects on the evaluations the subjects make of the problems.

Page 8: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• Our experiment differs from both these previous studies.

• We add an explicit pre-commitment option to the decision problem.

• We also add a fourth tree which helps us in our task of distinguishing between naïve, resolute and sophisticated subjects.

• In addition, we observe not only behaviour but also preferences.

Page 9: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

The design• The experiment used four decision problems, T1, T2, T3 and

T4• Each tree implies a choice between two or more of the

following prospects, defined on set X = (a, b, c, d, e) of consequences where

• a > b > c > d >e = 0 andb= c+1 and d = e+1.

• K = c (that is, the certainty of c)L = (a,e; q, 1-q)M = (c, e; r, 1-r)N = (b, d; r, 1-r)O = (a, e; rq, 1-rq)

• Note that N first-order stochastically dominates M.

Page 10: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

M

O

K

L

O

M

N

O

M

N

Page 11: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• T1 and T2 provide a standard test of EU theory: if a subject’s preferences satisfy EU then the subject should choose M (O) if and only if he or she chooses K (L).

• T3 is the same as tree T2 with the addition of a prior choice: the subject can either proceed to tree T2 or accept gamble N.

• T4 is the static version of T3. In T4 the agent faces a choice among the same prospects M, N and O as in T3, but the temporal order of the decision is reversed: the agent has to choose at the beginning of the decision problem, before any uncertainty is resolved.

Page 12: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

Predictions - behaviour

Expected utility

T1 T2 T3 T4

K is preferred to L, and hence M to O (N dominant over M)

Up

(M)

Up

(K)

Down

(N)

Down

(N)

L is preferred to K, and hence O to M

Down

(O)

Down

(L)

Up, Up

(O)

Up

(O)

Page 13: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

Non-Expected

utility

T1 T2 T3 T4

K is preferred to L, but O to M (common violation)

Down

(O)

Up

(K)

Naive:Up, Down

Resolute:Up, Up (O)

Sophist.:Down (N)

Up

(O)

L is preferred to K, but M to O

Up

(M)

Down

(L)

Naive: Down (N)

Resolute:Down

Sophist.:Down

Down

(N)

Page 14: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

Predictions - bids Expected utility

K is preferred to L, and hence M to O (N dominant over M)

T1=T2 < T3=T4

(N dominates M)

L is preferred to K, and hence O to M

T1 = T2 = T3 = T4

Page 15: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

Predictions - bids Non-Expected utility

K is preferred to L, but O to M (common violation)

Naive: T1=T2= T3=T4

Resolute: T1=T2= T3=T4

Sophisticated: T1=T4>T3>T2

L is preferred to K, but M to O

T1=T2 < T3=T4

(N dominates M)

Page 16: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

The implementation

• In the experiment we used three sets each with four trees, with the following values for the payoffs and probabilities.

• Note that the possible payoff varies from a minimum of £0 to a maximum of £150 (set 2).

Parameter values

Set 1 Set 2 Set 3

a £50 £150 £60

b £31 £51 £41

c £30 £50 £40

d £1 £1 £1

e £0 £0 £0

q 0.8 0.5 0.75

r 0.25 0.1 0.2

Page 17: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• The experiment was conducted at EXEC, University of York

• A total of 50 students, both graduate and undergraduate, took part in the experiment.

• They were given written instructions

• When all participants had finished reading the instructions, a PowerPoint presentation was played at a predetermined speed on their individual screens. After this, they could ask questions. The experiment then started.

Page 18: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• In order to elicit the subjects’ evaluations for the three sets of four trees, we used the second-price sealed-bid auction method, which was implemented as follows.

• Subjects performed the experiment in groups of five. They were sat at individual computer terminals and were not allowed to communicate with each other.

• They individually made bids for each of the three sets of four trees (twelve trees overall) and were given 15 minutes to bid for each set.

Page 19: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• During the bidding period the subjects were allowed to practice playing out the decision trees as much as they wanted in the time allowed.

• It was made clear that the outcomes of the practice did not affect the payments in any way. The number of seconds left for the practice and bidding was shown in the box at the top left-hand side of each decision tree.

• When the bidding time was over, the subjects played out all the twelve problems for real.

Page 20: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• We displayed on each subject’s screen the results of his or her playing out plus the bids of all the 5 subjects in the group for each of the twelve trees.

• Then we invited one of the 5 subjects to select a ball at random from a bag containing 12 balls numbered from 1 to 12.

• This determined the problem on which the auction was held.

• The subject with the highest bid for the problem paid us the bid of the second highest bidder

• As all subjects were given a £20 participation fee, 4 of the 5 members earned £20, while the fifth earned £20 minus the bid of the second highest bidder plus the outcome of the decision problem.

Page 21: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• Both in the instructions and in the presentation it had been emphasised through different examples that the bid for each problem should be equal to the willingness to pay for that decision problem.

• It was emphasised that in case the subject’s bid was the highest for the chosen problem, he or she would end up with the participation fee, minus the second highest bid, plus the outcome.

• This could be less than the participation fee and the subject could end up losing money.

Page 22: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

Descriptive results - behaviourSet 1 Set 2 Set 3

Expected

utility

K preferred to L, and M to O

12 12 15

L preferred to K, and O to M

Total number

19

31

16

28

11

26

Non-Expected utility

K preferred to L, but O to M (common violation)

15 18 18

L preferred to K, but M to O

Total number

4

19

4

22

6

24

Page 23: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

Consistency to theory - behaviourSet 1

Cons total

Set 2

Con total

Set 3

Con Total

Expected

utility

K and M 9 12 8 12 8 15

L and O 11 19

5 16 7 11

Non-Expected

utility

K but O

(common violation)

Naive 1

15

2

1

2

18

4

3

1

18

2

1

Resolute

Sophisticated

L but M 0 4

2 4 2 6

Page 24: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

Consistency to theory - bidsPredicted bids Set 1

Con tot

Set 2

Con tot

Set 3

Con tot

Expected

utility

K and M T1=T2 <T3=T4 4 12

5 12 4 15

L and O T1=T2 =T3=T4 3 19 1 16 3 11

Non-Expected

utility

K but O

(common violation)

Naive

or Resolute

T1=T2 =T3=T4

1

15

0

2

18

1

3

18

0Sophisticated

T1=T4 >T3>T2

L but M T1=T2 <T3=T4 0 4 0 4 2 6

Page 25: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

A formal analysis of the data

• There are two problems with the above description of the data. First, it is partial and does not use all the data from each subject in a systematic fashion.

• Second, it ignores the existence of noise in the subjects’ responses: some of the information that we have obtained from the subjects may be just noise or error.

• To remedy these two problems we provide a systematic analysis which uses all the data from each subject and explicitly incorporates noise into the analysis.

• Our objective is the same, however – to try and infer whether subjects are naïve, resolute or sophisticated.

Page 26: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• We assume that the subjects each have a well-defined preference function and that each is either naïve, resolute or sophisticated.

• For each subject we find the best-fitting preference function and the best-fitting specification (naïve, resolute or sophisticated) to represent the subject’s responses on the experiment.

• The responses are the bids (for the 4 trees in each of the 3 sets) and the decisions (in 4 trees on each of the 3 sets) – a total of 24 observations for each subject.

• We note that the nature of the data is different – for the bids we have a number, while for the decisions we have their choice. The former is essentially a continuous variable while the latter is a discrete variable (taking either 1 of 2 values or 1 of 3 values). The analysis of the two kinds of data has to be different.

Page 27: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• We need to assume a preference functional which could be a non-Expected Utility functional but which could also be Expected Utility.

• We therefore assume that the preference functional is that of Rank Dependent Expected Utility, and we denote the utility function by u(.) and the probability weighting function by w(.).

• The Rank Dependent Expected Utility of a gamble G = (x1, x2,…,xI; p1, p2, …, pI), where the prospects are indexed in order from the worst x1 to the best xI, is given by

Page 28: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• We note that Rank Dependent Expected Utility preferences reduce to Expected Utility preferences when the weighting function is given by w(p)=p.

1 1 12

( ) ( ) [ ( ) ( )] ( ... )I

i i i i Ii

V G u x u x u x w p p p

Page 29: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• To fully characterise the preferences of a subject obeying the Rank Dependent Expected Utility model, we need to know the utility function u(.) and the weighting function w(.).

• We assume particular functional forms for these two functions and estimate the parameters of the functions.

• We assume the CARA and CRRA specifications for the utility function and the Quiggin (1982) and Power specification for the weighting function.

• The Quiggin specification allows for an S-shaped weighting function while the Power specification does not

Page 30: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• Moreover, we need to specify the stochastic structure of the data.

• We assume that, when evaluating any gamble (whether static or dynamic), the subject makes a measurement error.

• More specifically, if u(.) is the utility function of the individual, and u-1(.) its inverse, then we assume that

• the certainty equivalent of any gamble G is given by u-1(V(G)) + e,

• where V(G) is the rank dependent expected utility of the gamble (using equation above) and where e is an error – a measurement error.

Page 31: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• To complete, we need to specify the distribution of e.

• We assume that e has an Extreme Value distribution with parameters 0 and 1/s.

Page 32: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• Thus the cumulative distribution function, F(.) of e is given by:

• The probability density function f(.) is given by

• Mean and variance of e are γ/s and π2/(6s2), respectively

• s is inversely proportional to the standard deviation, and can indicate the precision of the distribution: the larger s, the smaller the standard deviation, the more precise the valuation made by the subject

( ) exp( exp( ))F e es

( ) exp( exp( )) exp( )f e es es s

Page 33: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• We estimate the parameters of the utility function, the parameters of the weighting function and the precision parameter s using maximum likelihood (implemented in GAUSS).

• To do this we need to specify the likelihood of the observations.

• This is different for the decision and for the bids• in essence the likelihood of a decision is the

probability that that decision is taken given the parameters and the stochastic specification; the likelihood of a bid is the probability density at the bid given the parameters and the stochastic specification.

Page 34: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• In order to ensure the robustness of our results we use all four possible combinations:

• CRRA with Power; CRRA with Quiggin; CARA with Power; and CARA with Quiggin

• As will be seen, there are some variations in the results with the different combinations but they are relatively minor.

Page 35: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• We could simply place each subject in a particular category according to the highest value of the maximised log-likelihood, though we feel that that might give a distorted picture, particularly as there are subjects for whom the maximised log-likelihood on the three specifications are very close

• Instead we chose the following methodology• For each subject (on any one utility

function/weighting function combination) we have three maximised log-likelihoods. Let us denote these by ll(n), ll(r) and ll(s) for the naïve, resolute and sophisticated specifications respectively.

Page 36: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• If we adopt a Bayesian interpretation of the results, and if we start with equal priors on the three specifications, then the posterior probabilities of the naïve, resolute and sophisticated specifications being the correct ones are….

• Hence, for example, for Subject 1 on the ‘CRRA plus Power’ combination we have

• ll(s) = -18.02091, ll(n) = -17.30638 and ll(r) = -14.96283• applying formula we have that the posterior probabilities for

the three specifications are • P(s) = 0.0411, P(n) = 0.0840 and P(r) = 0.8749• The resolute specification is almost certainly the correct one,

though the other two specifications have some residual claim

exp( ( ))( ) , ,

exp( ( )) exp( ( )) exp( ( ))

ll iP i i n r s

ll n ll r ll s

Page 37: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• We have applied this analysis to all the subjects for each of the four utility function/weighting function combinations.

• Graphically, we use triangles, and represent the probability of the sophisticated specification being correct on the horizontal axis and the probability of the resolute specification being correct on the vertical axis. The probability of the naïve specification being correct is the residual and is represented by the perpendicular distance from the hypotenuse.

• In each of these triangles subjects are indicated by a number.• The triangles are divided into three areas – the one to the

top being where the resolute specification is most probable, the one to the right being where the sophisticated specification is most probable and the one nearest the origin being where the naïve is most probable.

Page 38: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

CRRA and Power weighting function results

Page 39: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

CRRA and Quiggin weighting function results

Page 40: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

CARA and Power weighting function results

Page 41: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

CARA and Quiggin weighting function results

Page 42: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

The following results are apparent depending upon the particular combination:

Combination

Number in ‘naive most

probable area’

Number in ‘resolute most probable area’

Number in ‘sophisticated most probable

area’

CRRA and Power 15 35 0

CRRA and Quiggin

19 28 3

CARA and Power 23 23 4

CARA and Quiggin

16 30 4

Page 43: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• It is interesting to note that the sophisticated specification performs consistently worse than the other two, that the resolute specification appears to be better for the majority of the subjects though there is some movement between the naïve and the resolute.

• This could be a consequence of the fact that there is very little data that allows us to discriminate between these latter two specifications.

• It is clear from this and the earlier analysis that the resolute and naïve specifications perform particularly well.

Page 44: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

Conclusions• In conducting experiments to try to determine

whether subjects are naïve, resolute or sophisticated, experimenters have a serious difficulty in designing the experiment to observe plans and hence to see whether they are implemented.

• The experiment tries to surmount these difficulties with a unique design in which not only behaviour is observed but also preferences over different representations of the dynamic decision problem are observed.

Page 45: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• Moreover, we have constructed the decision problems in such a way that we can distinguish between naïve decision makers (those who ignore any possible future inconsistencies), resolute decision makers (those who are resolute in implementing their a priori plans) and sophisticated decision makers (who anticipate their future inconsistencies but who are not sufficiently resolute to overcome them).

• We have used the data to infer the type of each subject.

Page 46: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• The picture is somewhat clouded as we do not know ex ante the preference functional of each individual, but we have explored the robustness of our categorisation.

• While the final picture is not totally clear, it seems to be the case that around 58% of our 50 subjects are resolute, 36.5% naïve and just 5.5% sophisticated.

• The large number of resolute subjects and the small number of sophisticated subjects in our experiment surprised us, as we thought ex ante that it would be difficult for subjects to be resolute.

Page 47: Naïve, Resolute or Sophisticated? A Study of Dynamic Decision Making John D Hey LUISS, Rome, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito Università

• The implications for economic theory are significant.

• If we look at models which incorporate dynamically inconsistent behaviour (such as the literature on quasi-hyperbolic discounting in the context of a life-cycle saving model), it will be seen that most of these models assume sophisticated behaviour.

• Our results suggest that this might be descriptively implausible.