neopythagoreanism and negative theology

Upload: jose-manuel-osorio

Post on 02-Jun-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    1/18

    This article was downloaded by: [The University of Manchester]On: 07 July 2011, At: 12:57Publisher: Taylor & FrancisInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House,37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Symbolae OsloensesPublication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

    http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/sosl20

    Neopythagoreanism and negative theologyJohn Whittaker

    a

    aMemorial University of Newfoundland St. John's, Newfoundland, Canada

    Available online: 29 Jun 2010

    To cite this article:John Whittaker (1969): Neopythagoreanism and negative theology, Symbolae Osloenses, 44:1, 109-125

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00397676908590612

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

    This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematicreproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form toanyone is expressly forbidden.

    The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contentswill be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses shouldbe independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims,proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in

    connection with or arising out of the use of this material.

    http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00397676908590612http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/sosl20
  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    2/18

    NEOPYTH GORE NISM ND NEG TIVE

    THEOLOGY

    J O H N W H I T T A K E R

    Memoria l

    UniversityofNewfoundland

    S t.

    J ohn s,

    Newfoundland, Ca nada

    T h e purpose of this paper is to reconsider two suggestions put

    forward by H. A. Wolfson

    1

    regarding Albums' mathematical

    illustration of the

    via negationis

    2

    :

    , , ,

    .

    I twas indicated by E. R. Dodds

    3

    that Albinus' illustration points

    to a Neopythagorean source. Wolfson, however, has

    drawn

    attention

    4

    to the similarity between Albinus' statement and the

    following passagefrom Simplicius' lost commentary on Euclid's

    Elements, preserved in alNairizi's Arabic commentary on the

    Elements: Dixit propterea Sambelichius: Punctum ideo negando

    Euclides

    diffinivit, diminutione superficiel a corpore, et diminu

    tionelinee a superficie, et diminutione puncti a linea. Cum ergo

    1

    I n his pape r Albinus and Plotinus on divine attr ibutes

    (

    HarvardT heological

    Review45 ( 1952) ,

    115 ff.) ; see further his N egative attributes

    in

    h e C hurch

    Fathers

    and the

    G no stic Basilides

    (Harvard Th eological Review50( 1957) ,

    145 ff.), and

    Infinite

    and

    privative judgm ents

    in

    Aristotle, Averroes,

    a n d K a n t (

    Philosophy a nd Phenomenalogkal Research8 (1947) , 173 ff.).

    2

    Didasc.

    10 ,

    p.

    165 H ermann.

    3

    Proclus: T he

    Elements

    of T heology

    (2nd

    ed.

    Oxford,

    1963), 312.

    4

    Albinus

    and

    Plotinus

    on

    divine attr ibute s 118

    f.

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    3/18

    1 1 0 JOHN WHITTAKER

    corpus sit tres habens dimensiones,

    punctus

    necessario nullum

    earum habet, nee habet partem.

    5

    On the basis of this similarity Wolfson argues

    6

    that Albums

    statement is only a fragment of a comment on Euclid s definition

    of a point which, like the passage of Simplicius, tried to explain

    Euclid s

    negative definition of a point

    7

    . This interesting proposal,

    which is supported by Festugire

    8

    , even if correct, would not

    necessarily affect

    the validity of Dodds suggestion, since any

    commentary on Euclid that was available to Albinus is likely

    to have been Neopythagorean in tone and theologically orien-

    tated. However, it must be noted that it in no way necessarily

    followsfrom the

    fact

    that Simplicius, in a commentary on Euclid,

    expressed

    himself in terms which are more or less similar to those

    of Albinus that Albinus was borrowing

    verbatim

    from an already

    existing commentary on theElements.In

    fact,

    Wolfson is assuming

    that Simplicius is

    himself

    here quoting from an earlier com-

    mentary on theElements and that this commentary, or a previous

    commentary of at this point similar content, was available to

    Albinus. Nodoubt Simplicius was heavily indebted to previous

    commentators, but it is rash to suppose that Albinus could not

    have taken his illustration from any other source than a Euclidean

    commentary.

    The

    movement from point to solid figure

    (i.e.,

    the reverse of

    Albinus illustration) was taught by early Pythagoreans

    9

    . We

    meet

    it again, e.g., in Philo

    10

    , in Plutarch

    11

    , in Sextus Empiricus

    12

    ,

    5

    Anaratiiin

    decem

    libros

    priores E lementorum Euclidis comm entant

    ex

    interpretatione

    Gherardi

    C remonensis ,

    ed. M.

    Curtze 1899 ) ,

    p. 2.

    11

    ff.

    6

    Op. cit., 119.

    7

    Wolfson has not explained precisely hisview of therelationship between

    Albinus

    and thepurported

    commentary

    on

    Euclid. However,

    one

    gains

    the impression that Wolfson believes thatthemathematical illustration of

    the

    via

    negationis was Albinus ownadaptation of this supposed Euclidean

    commentary;cf.loc. cit.

    8

    La

    Rvlat ion d Herms Trismgiste,IV

    Le

    Dieu

    Inconnu et la

    Gnose

    (Paris,

    1954) , 314 f.

    9

    C f.

    G. S.

    Kirk

    and

    J .

    E.

    Raven, The

    Presocratic Philosophers

    (Cambridge,

    1957) ,

    253 ff.

    10

    E.g., Deopific.

    49.

    11

    Plat, quaest.

    1001 1002A; cf. n.19 below

    12

    Adv

    math.

    10 281

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    4/18

    NeopythagoreanismandNegative

    Theology

    111

    in Nicomachus

    of

    Gerasa

    13

    ,

    in Alexander Polyhistor's

    account

    reproduced

    by Diogenes Laertius

    14

    , in Hippolytus

    15

    , as well as

    in Theoof Smyrna

    16

    ,Iamblichus

    17

    and the Pythagorean Anon.

    Photii

    18

    .

    That

    Albinus' illustration is directly related to this

    Pythagorean

    conception

    may be surmised from the

    fact

    that

    Plutarch,

    Sextus Empiricus and

    Nicomachus

    all present, in

    Pythagorean

    contexts,

    not only the movement from point to

    solid

    figure but also that from solid figure to point

    19

    . Moreover

    the two movements are already presented in combination by

    1 3

    Introd. arithm.

    2. 6. 4.

    1 4

    8. 25.

    1 5

    Haer.

    4. 51 , PG 16, col. 3119; 6. 23, PG 16, col. 3227.

    1 6

    p. 97 Hiller.

    1 7

    Theolog, arithm.

    p. 84 de Falco.

    1 8

    Phot. cod.249, 439 a.

    1 9

    Plutarch,

    Plat, quaest.

    1001 1002

    ,

    ,

    ,

    '

    ' '

    '

    .

    ,

    ,

    ,

    ( ).

    ,

    ' ,

    .

    Sextus

    Empiricus,

    Adv. math.

    10. 259 ff.

    , '

    .

    '

    ix

    ,

    , a

    ,

    . ,

    '

    ,

    (

    ,

    , , ),

    vat ,

    .

    Cp. Nicomachus,

    Introd. arithm.

    2. 6. 7.

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    5/18

    1 1 2 JOHN WHITTAKER

    Aristotle

    20

    , and, as H. J . Krmer has shown

    21

    , were

    probably

    commonplace in the Old Academy. Thus

    there

    is no

    need

    whatsoever

    to suppose as does Wolfson

    that

    Albinus source

    could only have been a

    commentary

    on Euclid. On the

    other

    hand

    Krmer goes too far in

    supposing that

    Albinus

    mathe-

    matical

    illustration

    was a direct inheritance from the Old Acad-

    emy. Albinus

    does

    not identify the

    ultimate

    source of reality

    with

    as Plato apparently did in his lecture on the

    Good.

    Albinus simply saysthat one can form an impression of the ulti

    mate

    divinity in the same way as one can form an impression of

    th e geometrical point ; he is presenting a mathematical illustra

    tion of the

    via negationis

    but not identifying G od with the One

    conceived

    in mathematical terms. This in itself renders it unlikely

    thatAlbinus' illustration be taken directly from an Old Academic

    source.

    In all probability we have here rather a Middle Platonic

    adaptation of Neopythagorean material which itself in turn built

    upon Early Pythagorean and Old Academic concept ions.

    A consideration of Clement of Alexandria's formulation of the

    mathematical

    illustration of the

    via negationis

    may help to clarify

    this point

    22

    : . . .

    '

    ,

    ,

    ,

    ,

    ,

    ,

    , '

    ,

    ,

    ,

    2 0

    M etaph.

    1016

    b 24 ff.

    ,

    ,

    ,

    ,

    ,

    ' ,

    ,

    ,

    .

    F o r the

    progression

    fromsolidfigure tomathematical unitseefurther

    M etaph. 1028

    b 16 ff.

    (se. the

    Pythagoreans)

    ,

    , ,

    .

    O n

    t h e

    s ee be low.

    2 1

    S e e h i sDer

    Ursprung d er

    Geistmetaphysik ( A m s t e r d a m , 1 9 64 ) ,

    in

    p a r t i c u l a r

    p p . 105 ff.

    2 2

    Strom.

    5.

    1 1 , P G 9 ,

    cols .

    108

    f.

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    6/18

    Neopythagoreanismand Negative

    Theology

    113

    , ,

    '

    / , [

    ,

    , '

    , ,

    ,

    , , ,

    '

    ,

    ...

    , ' , ,

    ,

    .

    T he

    question of the relationship between Clement's statement

    and that of Albinus must first be considered. We have already

    noted

    23

    that Wolfson seems to regard Albinus' illustration as his

    own adaptation of the supposed Euclidean commentary. This

    leads him to

    suggest

    that Clement's statement was borrowed

    directly from Albinus (hespeaks of Clement 'paraphrasing Al

    binus'

    2

    *).

    However, an examination of Clement's accountshows

    that Wolfson must be mistaken.

    There

    are two main reasons why this must be so. (1) Cle

    ment's version introduces the term in place of Albinus'

    and the fact that

    occurs in Celsus

    too

    25

    in

    the same connection

    shows

    that it was a current Middle

    Platonicterm for the procedure in question. (2) Clement includes

    a

    final stage in the negative regression which has no counterpart

    in Albinus:

    , ,

    ' , . (We

    shall deal with this point immediately.) Clearly the presence

    23

    S ee n. 7above.

    24

    'Negative

    attributes

    in theChurch

    Fathers

    and theG nostic Basilides'

    (seen. 1

    above),

    p. 147.

    25

    C f.

    Origen,

    Contra Cels.

    7.

    42 ,

    P G

    11, col . 1481

    ; cf.H.

    J . Krmer,

    op. cit.

    (see

    . 21above), 105 n. 279.Plotinus, like Albinus,

    uses

    theterm

    :

    Em. 6. 7. 36

    .Wolfson's assumption ('Albinus and Plo

    tinusondivineattributes' (see n. 1above),p. 119)that Plotinuswas

    directly

    dependent

    onAlbinus is

    unnecessary.

    Theterm in

    this

    connection

    was commonplace in the

    Middle Platonic

    period;cf.

    the latter half

    ofthis paper.Furthermore,

    there

    is noadequate evidence

    that

    Plotinuswas

    familiar with

    the writings ofAlbinus; cf.Les

    Sources

    dePlotin,

    Entretienssurl AntiquitClassiqueV (Vandoeuvres-Genve,

    I 9 6 0 ) , 4 2 2 .

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    7/18

    11 4 JOHN WHITTAKER

    of

    the term and the more detailed nature of Clement's

    exposition

    indicate that his account is independent of that of

    Albinus. T he probability is rather that both were recounting

    a

    familiar doctrine, that Albinus, true to style, presents this

    doctrine

    in abbreviated form, whereas Clement, also true to

    style, puts forward a more elaborate version.

    T h e

    final stage in Clement's version, to which atten tion has

    just been drawn, contains, I believe, some indication of Neo

    pythagorean influence, and must therefore be considered in

    detail.

    T o this passage Sthlin, in his edition of the

    Stromata

    26

    ,

    cites the following parallels: Aristotle, De anima 409 a 6

    .

    ( =

    )

    . Anal,

    post.

    87 a 36

    ,

    .

    Nicomachus,Introd.

    anthtn.

    2. 6. 3, p. 84. 8 f. Hoche (Sthlin s

    reference, copied by Casey and Friichtel, is incorrect)

    .R . P. C a s e y

    2 7

    notes

    that one should add to Sthlin s list Sextus Empiricus,

    Adv.math.10. 281, and this reference is incorporated into Friich-

    tel s revision of Sthlin s edition

    28

    even though the passage

    in question is not strictly relevant since Sextus omits the vital

    stage of the

    .

    In fact however Sthlin s list is by

    no means complete and the followingadditions

    should

    be made:

    Aristotle,

    Metaph.

    1016 b 29 ff. (cf. ; 20 above);

    Metaph.

    1028

    b

    16 ff. (cf. . 20 above);

    Metaph.

    1084 b 26 f. (

    ); Anal. post. 88 a 33 f. ( . . . al

    ai

    ,

    a l

    )

    ; Alexander of Aphrodisias' account of Plato's

    lectureon the

    Good

    at Simplicius,

    In

    phys.454. 24 = = Aristotle,

    De

    bono fr. 2, p. 115 Ross (

    )

    ; Iamblichus,

    Thiolog. arithm.

    I , p. 1. 4 de F a l c o (

    , );Proclus,In

    Eucl.

    El. 95.

    21 (o

    ); the Pythagorean Anon.

    Photii

    at

    Phot.

    cod.249. 439 a

    (

    ,

    26

    G C S v o l . 1 5 .

    2 7

    H a n a r d T h e o l og ic a l

    R e v i e w 18 1 9 2 5 ) ,

    7 5 . 1 14 .

    2 8

    G C S

    vo l . 5 2 .

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    8/18

    Neopythagoreanismand Negative Theology

    115

    , , ^

    ,

    ,

    '

    ).

    Fromthis mass of evidence the

    following

    emerges. (1) Whether

    or not, as Alexander's accountsuggests,the pertinent conception

    of the relationship between the and the was

    actually presented by Plato in his lecture on the Good, the

    frequency withwhich this conception occurs in Aristotle suggests

    that it might well

    have

    been current in the Old Academy

    29

    .

    (2 ) T he evidence of Nicomachus of G erasa, of Iamblichus and

    of the Pythagorean Anon. Photii, and in particular P roclus'

    statement that the relevant definition of the is Pytha

    gorean clearly indicate that in later antiquity the conception

    in

    question was current first and foremost among Neopytha

    goreans. Consequently the probability is that we are here faced

    no t

    with

    a continuity of Academic tradition but rather

    with

    an

    instance of the Neopythagorean

    revival

    of doctrines current in

    the Early Academy. I f this is the case, then the presence in

    Clement's account of this conception of the

    and the

    may be

    regarded

    as suggestive of Neopythagorean in

    fluence thereon.

    There is a further indication of Neopythagorean influence

    in Maximus of Tyre's brief mention of the

    via negationis

    30

    :

    , , ,

    , '

    , ,

    } '

    , ,

    ,

    .

    T h e

    sequence ,

    , ,

    is

    informative.

    Festugire

    31

    compares

    the

    Hermetic

    Exc.

    Stob.

    6. 19 (III. 39

    N - F )

    3 2

    :

    , ,

    29

    C f. .G a i se r, Piatons ungeschriebene

    L e h r e

    ( S tu t tga r t , 1 9 6 3 ) , 3 5 5 . 64 .

    30

    D iss. 17 . 11 ,

    p.

    6 9 D b n e r .

    31

    O p . c i t . s e e .

    8

    a b o ve ) , 1 15 .

    1.

    32

    Cf. theH ermet ic Exc. Stob.2 . 15

    ( I I I .

    7

    N F )

    and 8. 2. 2

    ( I I I .

    47

    N F ) .

    But see n. 35

    below.

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    9/18

    1 1 6

    JOHN WHITTAKER

    ,and suggests that in the Hermetic version

    is the equivalent of

    in Maximus. I n fact however

    and are not equivalents for the Hermetist and Maximus

    are presenting to us different shortened versions (cf. Maximus

    )of a much longer list of sensible att ribu

    tes which Philo has preserved in a Pythagorean co ntext

    33

    :

    , ,

    ,

    ,

    , , , , .

    If, as is

    suggested

    by the context as well as by the occurrence

    elsewhere of the same list

    34

    , Philo's list is of Neopythagorean

    origin then it seems likely that Maximus' illustration and the

    Hermetic variant

    derive

    from some Neopythagorean source.

    The widespread influence of the list in question may be judged

    not

    only from the above evidence but also from the fact that

    , ,

    occur in combination in theological

    contexts

    in Albinus

    35

    , Justin

    36

    and Origen

    36a

    . Furthermore, it is

    3 3

    De opific. 120.

    3 4

    T h esame list o c c u r s in a Pythagorean c o n t e x t atLydus,De mens. 2. 12,

    p. 35 . 2 ff.

    Wnsch

    and with Anatolius as

    source

    at Iamblichus, Theolog,

    arithm. 7, p. 55. 9 f. de Falco

    (this

    latterreferenceis not

    noticed

    by

    Wnsch

    in

    the case of Lydus nor by Cohn and Wendland in the case of Philo).

    35

    Didasc. 10, p. 164

    Hermann

    ,

    ,

    ,

    ,

    ,

    .

    However, unlike Maximus,

    Justin

    (see . 36 below),

    Clem.

    Alex, (see p. 113 above), and Celsus, who

    criticizes

    the Christians

    for

    attributing , and to G od (cf. Origen,Contra

    Cels.

    6.

    64, PG 11, col.

    1 3 9 6 ) ,

    Albinus does not deny to his first princip le

    but states (loc. cit .) ,

    .

    Politicus

    275 8 f. ( ', ,

    , . . . ) might provide

    Platonic

    authority for Albinus' viewpoint but cf. below on Ph aedr us

    247

    6 f. I t is doubtful whether Celsus in criticizing the Christians had

    the

    N eopythagorean list in m ind. T h e

    combination

    , is

    quite common:

    cf. Aristotle,De

    part.

    an i m . 640 b 32 ff. = D K 68

    , xa ) ;

    Plato, Gorgias465 4, 474 D 4 and 2,Rep.373 6, T heaetetus 163

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    10/18

    Neophagoreanism andNegative Theo logy 117

    perh ps

    just

    possibleth t Clement

    had this

    same

    list in mind

    when

    he

    wrote

    at the

    close

    of the

    passage

    quoted

    above

    , , , , , ,

    ' ,

    7

    .

    But whatever the value of

    these

    slight

    indications of Neo

    pythagorean influence,

    it has been

    adequately demonstrated

    10 ; Aristotle,

    Eth. Nie.

    1118 a 4 andMeteor.372 a 30 ff., cf. further

    Bonitz,

    Index s.v. ;consecutive sections of the

    Planta

    of Aetius are

    labelled and

    (Diels,Doxogr.pp. 312 f.).

    Furthermore,Festugire (op. cit. (see n. 8 above), 226 n. 4) has rightly-

    stressed the influence of Plato,Phaedrus247 6 f.

    x a

    (cf. also, asFestugire (loe.

    c i t . )

    notes, Symp.211 A 5 ff.). The

    Phaedrus

    passage was a

    popular

    Platonic

    commonplace,

    quoted,

    e.g., by Origen (

    Contra Ce ls .

    6. 19, PG 11, col.

    1320) and Clem. Alex. (

    Strom.

    5. 3, PG 9, cols. 32 f.). Festugire (loe.

    c i t . ) is however clearly mistaken in referring to the passage of Albinus

    quotedat theheadof this footnote as aparaphrase ofPhaedrus247 6 f.

    The Phaedrustext was

    indeed,

    as Festugire remarks, frequently para-

    phrased;

    cf. Iamblichus,

    De myst.

    I. 18 (54. 11 ff.), the Hermetic

    Exc.

    Stob.2 A. 15 (II I. 7 N-F) and 8. 2.2 1 1 1 .47 N-F), C.H. 13. 6 ( II . 202.

    14

    ff. N-F.) Nevertheless Albinus is clearly

    drawing

    upon a different

    source.

    36

    Dial,

    Tryph.

    4, PG 6, col. 484

    . . .

    . . .,

    , , , ,

    (cf.

    Philo,

    De

    opific.

    120 ,Iamblichus,

    Theolog,arithm.7, p. 55. 9 de Falco , Lydus,Demens.

    2 . 1 2 ,p.35.4f.W. ).

    3 6 a

    De

    prineip.I. 1. 6, PG 11, col. 125 Non ergo aut corpus aliquod, aut .in

    corpore esse putandus est Deus, sed intellectualis natura simplex, . . .

    Mens vero ut moveatur vel operetur, non indget loco corporeo ( =

    ?),

    eque

    sensibili magnitudine ( = ),vel corporali

    habitu ( = )aut colore ( = ),neque alio ullo prorsus indiget

    horum quae corporis vel materiae propria sunt. Cp. ibid. I . 2. 2, PG

    11 , col. 130 Si ergo semel recte receptum est, unigenitum FiliumDei,

    sapientiam

    eius esse substantialiter subsistentem, nescio si iam ultra eva

    gari sensus noster debeat ad suspicandum, ne forte ipsa ,id

    est substantia eius corporeum aliquid habeat,cum

    omne

    quod corporeum

    est,

    vel

    habitu,

    velcolore,vel

    magnitudine designetur. Ibid. I. 2. 4, PG 11,

    col. 133 Quia hae omnes appellationes ex operibus eius (se. Fil i iDei)

    virtutibus nominatae sunt, et in nulla harum vel levi opinione intelligi

    corporale aliquid potest, quodvel

    magnitudinem

    designare videatur, ve lhabitum,

    ve lcolorent.

    3 7

    Seep.

    113 above.

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    11/18

    11 8 JOHN WHITTAKER

    above that there is no need to regard, as does Wolfson, Albinus'

    mathematical illustration of thevia negationisas an adaptation

    of a Euclidean commentary. However, this is not to deny that

    Albinus and his contemporaries were

    aware

    of the theological

    potentiality of the Elements.Euclidean terminology occurs fre

    quently in combination

    with

    Pythagorean number speculation

    in

    thewritingsof Philo

    38

    ;

    whilst

    Hippolytus

    39

    tells us that the

    Naassenes identified the mustard seed of the N.T . (cf., e.g.,

    Matth.13. 31 f.)withthe indivisible point a striking instance

    of the no doubt Neopythagorean mspired theologicalusageof

    the geometrical conception of a point : . . . ,

    ' ,

    ,

    avcfj . , ,

    ,

    ,

    , , , r o

    .

    T h e

    also occurs in Hippolytus' account of

    Simonian

    gnosticism at Haer. 6. 14, PG 16, col. 3214,whilst

    atHaer.4 .51 , PG 16, col. 3119 Hippolytus refers to the theological

    utilisation of the Pythagorean progression from point to solid

    figure

    andadds

    ,

    , \

    .

    I I

    T h e

    second half of this paper willdealwithWolfsons' discus

    sion of the term . With Albinus, Didasc. 10, p. 165 H.

    ( '

    , ,

    , ' ,

    '

    ' '

    '

    38

    Cf. , e.g., De

    opific.

    49a n d 9 8 ;De

    Decalog.

    24 ff. Ont he phi losoph ica l

    i m p o r t a n c e of th eEu cl ide an defs seeDe congr. end.grat. 14 6 f., and

    C l e m .

    Alex.

    Strom. 6.

    1 1 , P G 9 , c o l . 3 1 2 .

    39

    H a e r

    5. 9,

    P G 16, co l . 3154 .

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    12/18

    Neopythagoreanism and Negative T heology 119

    ' ,

    ,

    , '

    *

    0

    ),and such statements of Plotinus as

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    13/18

    1 2 0 JOHN WHITTAKER

    1 9

    f.)

    .

    I t is not true as Wolfson claims

    44

    that 'in Aristotle, "negation"

    in its strictly

    technical

    sense of a logical negation is contrasted

    with the term "privation".'

    Strictly

    speaking is con

    trasted with an d with as at Cat. l i b

    17 ff.

    ,

    , , rj ,

    .When

    however

    is used to denote a type of

    proposition

    (namely, privative), then it is not contrasted with

    but

    subordinated

    to it. Nor

    does

    the account of

    Alexan

    der ofAphrodisias to which Wolfson refers

    45

    giveany indication

    that he regarded otherwise than as a subdivision of

    16

    :

    ,

    .

    .

    '

    ,

    ,

    '

    (

    ,

    '

    ), '

    . ,

    , , ,

    , . ,

    ,

    .I t may be added that there is no

    specific

    Aristotelianterm

    to cover the typeof

    proposition which

    Wolfson

    has in

    mind,

    i.e., 'the wall is not

    seeing'.

    On the subject of

    it may be

    noted that Aristotle

    seems on occasion to admit the use of

    this

    term simply as an

    equivalent

    of

    .

    At Metaph. 1022 b 22 f. we

    read

    44

    'Albinus and Plotinus on divine attributes', 120.

    45

    Op.

    cit., 120

    N .

    36. 'Negative attributes in the

    Church Fathers

    and the

    Gnost ic

    Basilides', 145 f.

    'Infinite

    and privative judgments in Aristotle,

    Averroes, and

    K a n t ,

    174.

    46

    In

    M e ta p h .

    p. 327. 12 ff. Hayduck.

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    14/18

    Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology 121

    iva ,

    f

    ,

    .

    Ross,ad lac,claims that the

    words

    indicate

    that in this sense is not identical

    with

    negation, since

    there are some attributes 'which cannot be possessed by any

    thing, e.g., (according to Aristotle's doctrine) "actually infinite".'

    Ross's interpretation is difficult to maintain in

    view

    of Metaph.

    1046

    a 31 ff.

    ], .,

    and

    (contra

    Ross,

    loe. cit.) Metaph.

    1055

    b 3 ff.

    ,

    ,

    .The phrase

    vsurely covers both

    is not actually infinite' (which, according to Ross's inter

    pretation, the definition of at Metaph. 1022 b 22 ff.

    was intended to exclude ) and, e.g., 'the

    wall

    is not seeing'.

    I t is noteworthy that whenever Aristotle lists the meanings of

    it is this broad meaning of the term which

    appears

    first. I t may be noted further that in thePriorAnalytics

    occurs frequently as the equivalent of ; cf., e.g., .

    Anal.

    pr.25 a 6.

    Chrysippus, too, who devoted an entire

    work

    to the subject

    of

    and

    whose

    treatment of the subject

    appears

    to

    have

    been more detailed than that of Aristotle, emphasizes the am

    biguity

    of the term

    and admits the priority of the more

    general

    usage

    of the term. After distinguishing and

    he c o n t i n u e s

    1 8

    :

    f

    ,

    ,

    .

    f

    , ,

    ,

    .

    .

    Furthermore,

    it may be doubted whether

    is used,

    as Wolfson

    argues,

    by

    Albinus

    as an equivalent of

    ,

    47

    Cf.

    S V F I I .

    13 (p. 5. 11).

    48

    SVF I I . 177 = Simplicius,inArist.Cat.100 Bas.

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    15/18

    12 2 JOHN WHITTAKER

    whether in the broad Aristotelian sense or the narrower Wolf

    sonian. With reference to Albinus' mathematical illustration

    of the via negationisWolfson readily admits

    49

    , 'The passage as

    it stands would seem to deal not with the manner in which we

    can speak of God, but rather with the method by which we can

    arrive at a conception of G od.' Wolfson seeks to avoid this

    major

    difficulty by claiming that

    50

    'what he (sc. Albinus) means

    to explain is not only how we can form a conception of God

    but also how we can describe God, and, with regard to the latter,

    his explanation is that we can describe God negatively, in the

    same way as Euclid defines a point negatively.' Now it is no

    doubt a corollary to Albinus' statement that we can form a

    conception of God by 'abstracting' from Him, that we can

    describe Him by means of negative statements. But this in no way

    alters the fact that Albinus is here dealing only with the problem

    of forming a conception of God. The corollary remains unstated.

    Moreover, this same

    usage

    of and its cognates

    (i.e.,to describe an act of thought) is already obvious in Aristotle.

    Cf . , e.g.,

    M etap h .

    1061 a 28 ff.

    (

    (

    ,

    ,

    ,

    ,

    ' ' , .)); M etap h . 1029

    a 16 ff. {

    ^ ,

    );

    Metaph.

    1036 b I ff., where Aristotle is dealing with

    th e difficulty of conceiving form without matter, (

    o '

    ).

    I t is evident from the above examples that Aristotle's use of

    th e relevant terms has exercised influence upon the formulations

    of thevianegationiswhich we have been considering. I t is equally

    evident that in Aristotle these terms refer to mental acts rather

    than to negative statements. Plutarch in the

    passage

    quoted

    49

    'Albinusand

    Plotinus

    ondivineattributes',118.

    5 0

    Op. cit., 119.

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    16/18

    Neopythagoreanismand Negative Theology 123

    in

    footnote 19

    (

    )is clearly influenced by Aristotelian terminology.

    The

    use of the

    verbs

    and

    (cf.

    Metaph.

    1061

    a

    28 ff., cited on p. 122 above) in the context of Clement's version

    of the

    via negationis

    (see p. 112 above) corresponds precisely to

    their

    Aristotelian usage. Similarly in the version of Maximus

    of

    Tyre (see p. 115 above)

    can refer only to an act

    of thought (cf.

    . . . ) .

    There

    is thus no good reason to suppose that in Albums the

    phrase

    has anything

    to

    do with negation as such.

    I n

    the

    passage

    in question Albinus is concerned purely with

    the.problem of forming a conception of God. The matter of

    negative statements lies outside the scope of his exposition.

    I n

    the case of Plotinus the situation is perhaps slightly dif

    ferent. At

    Enn.

    6. 7. 36

    (

    ) the term is clearly

    used in the same sense as in Albinus and Plutarch

    51

    . Plotinus

    is referring briefly

    to

    current and familiar methods of conceiving

    the

    deity, and in this context, as we have seen,

    has

    nothing to do with negation

    52

    . I t should also be noted that

    is used frequently by Plotinus in statements dealing

    with the

    vianegationis.

    That what Plotinus had in mind in such

    passages

    was not negation but a mental process of abstraction

    is obvious from the following (Enn.6. 8. 21) : (ofh>y ,

    ,

    ,

    Here the meaning of

    is decided by the contrasted

    verb ;

    this latter

    term, borrowed from mathematics, cannot mean 'assert' and

    consequently

    in the same context cannot mean 'deny'.

    51

    I t is by no means as evident as Wolfson c laims (op. cit ., 119 f.) that

    Enn.

    5. 3. 14 ("

    H

    ,

    r

    ,

    ,

    '

    ,

    , ,

    ,

    , . )is intended as an explanation of .

    Neither this latter term nor any of its cognates appear in the

    passage

    in

    question or in its immediate context.

    5 2

    See pp . 121 f. above.

    53

    See further

    Enn.

    5. 3.17 (

    ) and

    Enn.

    5.5.13 (

    ).

    E m .

    6. 9.. 9

    (

    ) .

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    17/18

    12 4 JOHN WHITTAKER

    However, at Enn. 6. 8. 11 Plotinus writes of the One

    v

    ; ,

    ',

    Here, as the

    participle indicates, Plotinus is dealing with the matter

    of making statements about the One.Brhier translates, Que

    peuventalors vouloir

    dire

    les mots: il lui est arrivpar accident

    d tre

    ainsi? Comment les dire, quand tout ce qui est dit de

    lui n est que ngation? . Though, as Wolfson points

    out

    54

    ,

    eventually came to be used in the sense of negation,

    it is by no means obvious that this was the meaning which

    Plotinus had in mind in the present context. T he combination

    is Aristotelian and in Aristotle denotes not 'by

    negation' but 'by process of abstraction'. Cf.De 432 a 3 ff.

    , ,

    , ' ,

    ,

    55

    . I n

    all

    probability it was the Aristotelian usage that Plotinus had in

    mind in the passage under consideration. Nevertheless it must

    be admitted that the combination . . .

    ,

    though not a precise equivalent of 'negations', is not far removed

    therefrom.

    However, as Wolfson has indicated

    58

    , is certainly

    used in the sense of 'negation' in later literature. I n addition

    to the evidence presented by Wolfson it may be noted that

    Isidore of Seville,

    drawing

    on Marius Victorinus, writes (Etymo

    log.

    2. 29. 9) : Octava species definitionis est, quam Graeci

    ,Latini per privantiam contrarii eius,

    quod definitur, dicunt: 'Bonum est, quod malum non est.

    Iustum est, quod iniustum non est,' et his similia. Hoc autem

    genere definitionis uti debemus, cum contrarium notum est, ut:

    S i bonum est quod prodest cum honstate, id

    quod

    tale non

    est

    malum

    est.

    57

    . Here clearly refers to negation,

    5 4

    A lb inus

    a n d

    P l o t i nus

    o n

    d i vine a t t r i bu tes , 129

    f. , an d

    Nega t i ve a t t r i bu tes

    i n

    t h e

    C h u r c h F a t h e rs

    a n d t h e

    Gn ost ic Bas i l ides ,

    1 4 8

    ff.

    5 5

    Cf. abo

    De

    anim. 42 9 b 18 and431 b 12.

    56

    C f.n. 54above.

    4 7

    T h e r e are further

    instances

    of this type of

    definition

    in a

    passage

    of

    Gregory

    of

    N yssa

    (Deanimaet

    resurrectione,

    PG 46, col. 40) towhich

  • 8/10/2019 Neopythagoreanism and Negative Theology

    18/18

    Neopythagoreanism and NegativeTheology 125

    though not in the narrow Wolfsonian sense. On definition

    see further Boethius, Liber de diffini

    tione,PL 64, cols. 902 and 904 ff.

    Nevertheless, in spite of the fact that

    came to be used

    in the sense of 'negation', we may conclude that it is not the

    case, as Wolfson claims, that Albinus employed the term as an

    equivalent of 'negation' (in whatever sense this term may be

    used),

    and further that it is not likely that Plotinus ever con

    sciously used the term in question to imply negation, even

    though in his day the development

    towards

    the new meaning

    may well have been underway.

    Wolfson refers ('N egative attributes

    in the

    Church Fathers

    and the

    G n o s t i c Basilides', 148) :

    ,

    v ,

    ,

    , ,

    .

    and

    are

    quite

    clearly

    intended

    as

    equivalents.