organ and tissue transplants

Upload: nikola-stojsic

Post on 03-Apr-2018

242 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    1/32

    ORGAN AND TISSUE TRANSPLANTS: SOME ETHICAL

    ISSUES

    Paul Flaman

    (St. Joseph's College, University of Alberta,

    Edmonton, Canada)

    Introduction

    1. Ethical Issues Regarding the Donor

    a) From the Deceased

    b) From Living Persons (Adults, Mentally Disabled,

    Minors)

    c) From Anencephalic Infants

    d) From Human Fetuses

    2. Ethical Issues Regarding the Recipient

    3. Ethical Issues Regarding Allocation of LimitedResources

    a) Criteria for Selection

    b) Using Animals

    c) Artificial Substitutes for Tissues and Organs

    d) High Costs, Universality and Justice

    4. Ethical Issues Regarding Procurement of Organs

    and Tissues

    a) Buying and Selling Human Organs and Tissues

    b) Media Publicity

    c) Types of Consent (Voluntary or Expressed,Family, Presumed, Required Request, Routine

    Inquiry)

    d) Fears, Confusion and the Need for Education

    Conclusion

    Some Cases and Questions For Discussion

    Introduction

    Although the idea of organ transplantation is an

    old one, successful transplantation did not occur

    until the Twentieth Century. When different blood

    types and their respective compatibility or

    incompatibility, as well as a method of preserving

    blood, were discovered, blood transfusions

    became an accepted medical procedure. They

    were widely used during the First World War. Dr.

    Emmerich Ullmann experimented on dogs with

    kidney transplants in the early 1900's. He found

    that the transplanted organ functioned longer, the

    closer the donor and recipient were genetically

    ,

    .

    , , ,

    .

    .

    1900-.

    ,

    .

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    2/32

    related. Human skin grafts were attempted in the

    late 1920's. It was found that they could be

    performed without the problem of rejection

    between identical twins. In the early 1940's Dr.

    Peter Medawar and his team experimented with

    rabbits. They began to understand the immune

    system which exists in higher animals and human

    beings. Antigens, on the surface of cells, enable

    higher organisms to recognize a foreign body. They

    stimulate the production of antibodies which are

    important in fighting infection. This, however, also

    causes the phenomenon of rejection in organ

    transplantations.

    The more similar the tissues' antigens, of donor

    and recipient, the less likely they are to recognize

    each other as alien bodies. Tissue typing and

    matching is based on this. Rejection remains oneof the main causes of failure in organ

    transplantation because it is difficult to find

    completely matching tissues. New drugs (e.g.

    cyclosporine) greatly ease the rejection problem.

    Recipients, except in the case of a transplant

    between identical twins, need to take such drugs

    for the rest of their lives. In the case of a successful

    kidney transplant, however, the costs related to

    the transplant and the required drugs are cheaper

    than the alternative of renal dialysis. The quality of

    life of the recipient is also better.

    Today the transplantation of many organs

    between well-matched human beings is quite

    successful, with the majority of recipients living

    five or more years. Kidney, cornea, bone marrow

    and skin transplants today, for example, are

    considered routine for certain conditions. Heart

    and lung or heart-lung transplants, liver and

    pancreas (or pancreatic islets) transplants are also

    becoming more common. According to Dr. Robert

    White, even a human head transplant (perhaps

    better referred to as a body transplant) may be

    possible. The recipient in this case though would

    resemble a quadriplegic because it would be

    impossible to connect the 100 to 200 million

    severed nerve endings.(Varga, 211-19)

    Experiments continue to be done to try to improve

    the technology and possibilities regarding

    1920-.

    . 1940-

    .

    .

    , ,

    .

    . ,

    ,

    .

    ",

    ,

    .

    .

    ,

    . (. )

    .

    ,

    ,

    .

    , ,

    . .

    ,

    .

    , ,

    , ,

    .

    -

    ( )

    .

    ,

    (

    ) .

    100 200

    (,

    211-19).

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    3/32

    transplantation. For example, research is being

    done regarding human cell cultures, transplants

    from human fetuses, including brain tissue, and

    from animals to human beings. The latter includes

    attempts to genetically design animals with organs

    that are less likely to be rejected by human beings.

    Some animal products (e.g. insulin and pig heart

    valves) are already used regularly. Research also

    continues to be done to improve artificial organs

    and other artificial aids to human functioning.

    Since many people can benefit greatly in terms of

    length and quality of life from organ and tissue

    transplants, the demand usually exceeds the

    supply. The costs related to some organ

    transplants are very high as well. Therefore, many

    questions are raised today regarding how best to

    procure more organs, how to fairly distributelimited resources, and whether all transplants

    should be covered by public funds.

    The ethical and legal issues related to organ and

    tissue procurement and transplantation are often

    discussed in light of such principles as autonomy,

    benevolence, non-maleficence, free and informed

    consent, respecting the dignity, integrity and

    equality of human beings, fairness, and the

    common good. The Judeo-Christian perspective

    affirms the great dignity of each human personcreated in the image of God (cf. Gen 1:26-31). The

    various aspects, parts and functions of a human

    person participate in this dignity. We are also

    social beings who have a responsibility as co-

    creators and stewards of God's creation. "In the

    donation and transplantation of human organs,

    respect is to be given to the rights of the donor,

    the recipient and the common good of

    society."(CHAC, 44)

    . ,

    , ,

    ,

    .

    .

    (.

    ) .

    .

    ,

    .

    , . ,

    ,

    ,

    .

    ,, ,

    ,

    ,

    , .-

    (. 1:26-31). ,

    .

    -

    . "

    ,

    ,

    ." (, 44)

    1. Ethical Issues Regarding the Donor

    a) From the Deceased

    In general it is seen as praiseworthy to will one's

    1.

    )

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    4/32

    body or parts of one's body for the benefit of

    others after one's death. In 1956 Pope Pius XII

    summed up the Catholic view on this:

    A person may will to dispose of his [or her] body

    and to destine it to ends that are useful, morally

    irreproachable and even noble, among them the

    desire to aid the sick and suffering. One may make

    a decision of this nature with respect to his own

    body with full realization of the reverence which is

    due it....this decision should not be condemned

    but positively justified.(quoted from Ashley and

    O'Rourke 1989, 305)

    More recently (1985) the Pontifical Academy of

    Sciences stated:

    Taking into consideration the important advancesmade in surgical techniques and in the means to

    increase tolerance to transplants, this group holds

    that transplants deserve the support of the

    medical profession, of the law, and of people in

    general. The donation of organs should, in all

    circumstances, respect the last will of the donor,

    or the consent of the family present.(MacNeil)

    Such a donation can greatly benefit others and

    cannot harm the donor who is dead. Not to offer

    such a donation can be a sign of indifference tothe welfare of others. To donate, however, is not

    considered obligatory. Transplantation is against

    some people's consciences for religious or other

    reasons.(cf. LRCC, 140-2) Consideration for the

    sensibilities of the survivors may also make some

    people hesitate to sign over their bodies.

    In any case proper respect should always be

    shown human cadavers. Although they are by no

    means on par with a living human body/person,

    they once bore the presence of a living person.

    The probably dying potential donor should be

    provided the usual care that should be given to

    any critically ill or dying person. Because of a

    potential conflict of interest, it is widely agreed

    that the transplant team should be different from

    the team providing care for the potential donor,

    who is not to be "deprived of life or of the

    essential integrity of their bodily functions.... No

    , . 1956,

    :

    *

    +

    ,

    ,

    .

    ,

    .... ,

    (

    ' 1989, 305).

    (1985)

    :

    ,

    , ,

    . ,

    ,

    ,

    . ()

    ,

    .

    .

    , , .

    (. , 140-

    2)

    ..

    .

    /

    ,

    .

    .

    ,

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    5/32

    organs may be removed until the donor's death

    has been authenticated by a competent authority

    other than the recipient's physician or the

    transplant team."(CHAC, 44 and 46) Various parts

    of the human body can often be kept in good

    condition for transplant purposes after the death,

    irreversible cessation of all brain functions, of the

    donor.(Jonsen, 235-7)

    The Catholic Health Association of Canada (CHAC)

    considers transplantations of brain cells

    (presuming irreversible cessation of all brain

    functions of the donor) in order to restore

    functions lost through disease as permissible "as

    long as the unique personal identity and abilities of

    the recipient are not compromised in any

    way."(45)

    The German Bishops' Conference and the Council

    of the German Evangelical Church consider the

    transplant of "reproductive glands" as unethical,

    "since it intervenes in the genetic individuality of

    the human being."(374) This does not seem to

    exclude transplanting all sexual body parts, but the

    gonads. Any child that resulted following an ovaryor testicle transplant would have the dead donor

    and not the living recipient as its biological mother

    or father. This would violate the rights of the child

    (see SCDF 1987, 23-26).

    The case of the body of a pregnant woman in

    Germany, who had been declared brain dead,

    being kept alive with the hopes of the child coming

    to term was recently given some media attention.

    Some criticized this as not giving proper respect to

    the woman. Can not this effort, however, be seen

    as similar in some ways to organ donation and,

    therefore, as commendable? The woman had at

    least implicitly offered her body for the child's sake

    before her fatal accident. Her family also

    requested this.(Associated Press) Cases such as

    this also raise the question of "ordinary" and

    "extraordinary" means of saving life (see below

    under 1.b).

    , "

    ... .

    ,

    "(, 44 46)

    .

    ,

    , (, 235-7).

    ()

    (

    ),

    ",

    ". (45)

    "

    " "

    ",

    . "(374)

    , .

    ,

    . (

    1987, 23-26).

    ,

    ,

    .

    .

    , ,

    , ,

    ? ,

    .

    ()

    ""

    "" (

    1.)..

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    6/32

    The use and possible use of cadavers and

    "neomorts" (brain-dead individuals maintained on

    life support) for a variety of purposes (transplants,

    research, training medical students), perhaps even

    a considerable time after the person's death, has

    provoked ethical and legal debate. Various

    concerns include respect for the dead and their

    wishes, respecting the family's wishes, benefitting

    others and the common good. In light of this,

    anyone considering donating their organs and/or

    body after their death, highly commendable in

    itself, may wish to specify certain limits.(cf. LRCC,

    113-17; Gaylin; and CHAC, 43 and 46)

    "" (

    ) (,

    , ),

    ,

    .

    ,

    , .

    ,

    / ,

    ,

    (. , 113-17,

    , 43 46).

    b) From Living Persons (Adults, Mentally Disabled,

    Minors)

    Transplants between living persons raise thequestion whether it can ever be ethical to mutilate

    one living person to benefit another. Concerning

    this many distinguish between parts of the body

    that can regenerate (e.g. blood and bone marrow)

    and parts that do not regenerate. Regarding the

    latter some are paired (e.g. kidneys, corneas and

    lungs), whereas others are not (e.g. heart). Before

    transplants of organs such as kidneys were

    performed, many Catholic theologians considered

    this unethical between living persons. They

    thought it violated the Principle of Totality whichallowed the sacrifice of one part or function of the

    body to preserve the person's own health or life

    (i.e. a part could be sacrificed for the sake of the

    whole body), but did not allow one person to be

    related to another as a means to an end. When

    such transplants began in the early 1950's ethicists

    gave the problem closer study.

    Gerald Kelly (1956) argued that such donations

    which have as their purpose helping others could

    be justified by the Principle of Fraternal Love or

    Charity provided there was only limited harm to

    the donor. Some ethicists argued this did not

    violate the Principle of Totality provided that

    functional integrity of the body was not destroyed,

    even though there is some loss to anatomical

    (physical) integrity. Donating one of one's kidneys

    could be justified for proportionate reasons, since

    one can function with one healthy kidney. ("Living

    ) (, ,

    )

    .

    (.

    ) .

    (.

    , ),

    (. ).

    ,

    .

    (.

    ),

    .

    1950

    .

    (1956)

    .

    ,

    ()

    .

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    7/32

    kidney donors constituted some 15% of the donor

    pool in Canada in 1989."[LRCC, 20]) Donating one

    of one's functioning eyes, however, can not be

    justified, since one's ability to see (functional

    integrity) would be seriously impaired.

    Basic to medical ethics is the Principle of Free and

    Informed Consent. To be properly informed the

    potential living donor should be given the best

    available knowledge regarding risks to him/herself,

    the likelihood of success/failure of the transplant

    and of any alternatives. In some cases there is

    much pressure to donate (e.g. from family

    members if one is a good match). The courts have

    rightly refused to compel such donations.

    Motivated by charity, which includes a properly

    ordered love for others and oneself, one could

    decide not to offer an organ.(Ashley and O'Rourke1989, 305-8; CHAC, 31 and 34)

    The distinction of ordinary and extraordinary

    means is also applicable to transplants. The

    Catholic Church teaches that one is obliged to use

    ordinary means to preserve life, but not

    extraordinary means, that is, means that are very

    burdensome (very painful, expensive,

    inconvenient, risky, or even very psychologically

    burdensome) or do not offer reasonable hope of

    benefit, or are disproportionate (cf. SCDF 1980,section IV; Ashley and O'Rourke 1986, Ch. 11.5;

    and CHAC, 52-4). Some forms of organ and tissue

    transplant from a living donor, especially those

    involving invasive surgery, involve considerable

    burden to the donor. If means are available that

    do not involve such burdens, such as a matching

    organ from a deceased donor, these are certainly

    to be preferred.

    The above principles would allow in some cases

    such procedures as "transplanting part of the liver

    from a living adult donor into a child recipient,

    whereafter the adult donor's liver regenerates

    within a month and the child's new partial liver

    develops as the child grows"(LRCC, 15), or

    ,

    . ("

    15%

    1989." *, 20+)

    , ,

    ,

    ( )

    .

    .

    / , /

    .

    (.

    ). .

    ,

    ,

    (

    ' 1989 305-8,, , 31 34).

    .

    , , ,

    ( ,, , ,

    )

    , (.

    1980, , ' 1986,

    11.5;. , 52-4).

    ,

    ,

    .

    ,

    ,

    .

    "

    ,

    "

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    8/32

    donating one's heart if one were to simultaneously

    receive a heart and lung transplant (Garrett et al.,

    200).

    A competent adult can give free and informed

    consent to be or not to be a living donor, but an

    incompetent person cannot. Can a guardian

    ethically consent for a legally incompetent person,

    such as a severely mentally disabled adult or a

    minor, to be a living donor? Concerning this issue

    some distinguish, for example, between a young

    child and a mature minor's ability to comprehend

    the implications of donating. Regarding medical

    decisions an incompetent person's guardian is to

    act for their benefit or best interests, and, as far as

    possible, their wishes, if known and reasonable.

    Some think children and the mentally disabled

    should never be living donors. They are simplybeing used with a violation of their bodily integrity,

    risks to their health and life, and no benefit to

    themselves. An argument against their being a

    living donor of an organ such as a kidney, is that an

    alternative such as renal dialysis is often available

    until a suitable deceased donor can be found.

    Others argue that in some cases the psychological

    benefit to the donor (e.g. a child's sibling lives)

    could outweigh the risks (e.g. of donating bone

    marrow).(LRCC, 48-50) The Catholic Health

    Association of Canada (CHAC) says that, "Organ ortissue donation by minors may be permitted in

    certain rare situations."(44)

    Can it be ethical to have another child for

    transplant purposes (e.g. for a bone marrow

    transplant)? Conceiving and having a child for this

    motive alone would involve treating him/her as a

    mere means to another's benefit. This would

    violate the great dignity of a person, created in

    God's image, who should be loved for his/her own

    sake.(cf. CHAC, 45; Garrett et al., 200)

    Concerning the whole issue of living donors, the

    German Bishops' Conference and the Council of

    the German Evangelical Church say:

    ( , 15),

    ( ., 200).

    ,

    .

    ,

    ,

    ? ,

    ,

    .

    , , ,

    , .

    .

    ,

    , .

    ,

    .

    (. ) (. )

    (, 48-50)

    (). , "

    ." (44)

    (.

    )?

    /

    . ,

    ,

    / (. ,

    45;. , 200).

    ,

    "

    :

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    9/32

    ...No one is obliged to donate tissue or an organ;

    therefore no one can be forced to do so. The

    decision to donate one's organs while still alive can

    only be made by the individual concerned

    personally. Not even parents are allowed to decide

    on an organ donation by their child; they are

    allowed to give their consent only for a donation

    of tissue (e.g., donation of bone-marrow). The

    doctor in this case has a special responsibility

    because no one can control whether a donation is

    truly voluntary.

    When a living person donates an organ as a result

    of a personal decision, then the organ's transplant

    is to be carried out with due attention, and post-

    operative medical care of the donors as well as the

    recipients must be provided. Further,consideration must be given so that no problems

    develop in the relationship between the donor and

    the recipients (dependence, excessive gratitude,

    guilt feeling).(375)

    ... ,

    .

    .

    ,

    ( ,

    ).

    ,

    .

    ,

    ,

    ,

    . ,

    (,

    , ). (375)

    c) From Anencephalic Infants

    Anencephalic infants are born with a major portion

    of the brain absent. If born alive they die within a

    few days, although in rare cases some survive for

    weeks or months. They can suck and cry and some

    argue that their degrees of consciousness or

    unconsciousness may vary. According to thewidely accepted criteria of death as irreversible

    cessation of all brain functions, they are living

    human beings/persons. To increase the likelihood

    of procuring viable organs from them, some would

    like to redefine death in terms of partial brain

    death so that they could be considered dead

    (although still breathing spontaneously...), or for

    them to be exempt from the total brain death

    criteria, or to consider them non-persons. Many

    others, however, argue that partial brain death

    criteria are invalid in light of our present

    knowledge and/or such an arbitrary move would

    endanger other classes of living human beings and

    lead many more people to refuse to sign organ

    donor cards. Although extraordinary means of

    prolonging the life of anencephalic infants do not

    need to be used, they should be given the normal

    care of dying persons.(cf. CHAC, 45-6; LRCC, 95-

    106; Garrett et al., 202; Ashley and O'Rourke 1986,

    )

    .

    ,

    . ,

    .

    ,

    / .

    ,

    ,

    (

    ...),

    ,

    -. , ,

    /

    .

    ,

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    10/32

    Ch. 11.2, and 1989, 311-12)

    (. , 45-6, , 95-106;

    , 202...; ' 1986, 11.2,

    1989, 311-12.)

    d) From Human Fetuses

    Is it ethical to transplant brain or other tissues

    from human fetuses to benefit others (e.g. those

    suffering from Parkinson's Disease)? If the fetus

    has died of natural causes, the ethical issues would

    be similar to other transplants from the deceased.

    When the fetus has died or will die as a result of

    procured abortion, however, other ethical issues

    arise. The Catholic Church considers direct

    abortion (the intentional killing of an innocent

    human being) to be gravely immoral. Some argue

    that to use tissues from a fetus killed by abortion

    could be done without approving direct abortion(cf. using tissues or organs from a murder victim).

    Such use, however, could "justify" abortion (i.e. to

    benefit others) for many women who otherwise

    are unsure about having an abortion. A good end

    though does not justify an evil means (see Rm 3:8).

    The timing of the abortion may be influenced as

    well. The widespread usage of electively aborted

    fetuses would establish an "institutional and

    economic bond between abortion centers and

    biomedical science..."(Post, 14; cf. CHAC, 15, re

    unethical cooperation)

    Some argue that transplanting fetal brain tissue

    would require the fetus to be still alive, that is, the

    tissue would not be good for transplant purposes

    after the fetus has experienced total brain

    death.(cf. Duncan, 16-22) Some say that other

    means of treating such diseases as Parkinson's can

    and should be developed.(cf. Dailey)

    Another issue involves consent. Anyone involved

    in procured abortion would not qualify as the

    fetus' guardian since they hardly have his/her best

    interests at heart. The Catholic Health Association

    of Canada (CHAC) concludes that,

    "Transplantations using organs and tissues from

    deliberately aborted fetuses are ethically

    objectionable." (45; cf. SCDF 1987, 16-18)

    )

    (.

    )?

    ,

    .

    ,

    , ,

    .

    (

    ) .

    (.

    ). , ,

    "" (.

    )

    . ,

    ( 3:8).

    , .

    "

    ..."(, 14;. 15,,

    )

    ,

    ,

    . (. , 16-22)

    (. ).

    .

    , /

    .

    () ,

    "

    ."

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    11/32

    (45; 1987, 16-18.)

    2. Ethical Issues Regarding the Recipient

    ...nobody [i.e. no potential recipient] has a claim

    on organs or tissue of any person, living or dead.

    The sick should thus accept the tissue and organs

    freely offered by others as a gift.(German

    Bishops..., 373)

    This position is widely accepted.

    Another moral issue involving the recipient is free

    and informed consent. A competent person who

    could possibly benefit from receiving a transplant

    should be adequately informed regarding the

    expected benefits, risks, burdens and costs of the

    transplant and aftercare, and of other possiblealternatives. So should the guardian(s) of an

    incompetent person. A legally incompetent person

    who can understand some things that are relevant

    to their condition, a proposed transplant, and

    decisions that they are capable of making, should

    be informed of these in an appropriate way.

    Guardians should respect the wishes, if known and

    reasonable, of incompetent persons in their care.

    No unfair influence should be put on someone to

    be a transplant recipient. Potential recipients and

    their families can be tempted to pressure,blackmail or bribe a potential living donor to

    donate or a health care professional to give them a

    privileged position on the waiting list. Such

    practices are unethical because they fail to

    properly respect the freedom of the donor or they

    violate other potential recipients' rights regarding

    access (cf. Garrett et al., 206-7) Recipients should

    also avoid any unethical cooperation in any abuses

    (e.g. the organs or tissues have been procured

    immorally/illegally) that are sometimes associated

    with transplantation.(cf. CHAC, 15 and 31; Ashley

    and O'Rourke 1986, 88 and 90-1; and 4.a below)

    A potential transplant recipient and/or their

    guardian(s) could also consider their decision in

    2.

    ... *. +

    ,

    .

    ( ..., 373).

    .

    .

    ,

    , ,

    . ,

    () .

    , ,

    ,

    . ,

    ,

    .

    .

    ,

    ,

    . ,

    (. .,

    206-7)

    (.

    / )

    (. , 15 31,

    ', 1986 88, 90-1, 4. .)

    /

    ()

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    12/32

    light of ordinary and extraordinary means of

    preserving life (see above, under 1.b). The

    competent adult Jehovah Witness who refuses a

    life-saving blood transfusion, for example, because

    this is against a tenet of their religion, can be

    understood to be refusing means that would be

    "very burdensome" for them. Courts, however,

    sometimes override the decision of natural

    guardians including parents when this is judged

    clearly against the best interests of incompetent

    persons including a child (e.g. to allow a life-saving

    blood transfusion to the child of Jehovah Witness

    parents). This issue is more difficult when the child

    begins to develop his/her own value system, but is

    still considered legally incompetent.(see n. 3

    below under "Some Cases...")

    Proper safety measures should be followed toprotect transplant recipients from receiving AIDS

    and hepatitis viruses, etc.(cf. LRCC, 161; and

    Garrett et al., 200)

    ( ,

    1.).

    , ,

    ,

    " " . ,

    ,

    , (.

    ).

    /

    ,

    ( 3. "

    ...").

    , (. , 161;.

    , 200)

    3. Ethical Issues Regarding Allocation of Limited

    Resources

    a) Criteria for Selection

    Requests or the demand for human organs and

    tissues usually exceed what is available or thesupply. Significant practical and ethical questions

    regarding efficiency and fairness arise as to how

    best to distribute these limited resources. On what

    basis should this person rather than that person be

    chosen to receive a given organ? Who should

    choose? These decisions are serious as they can

    involve who will live and who will die. In section 4

    below we will consider some ways of addressing

    this problem by attempting to increase the supply

    of human organs and tissues. In sections 3.b and c

    we will consider some alternative methods of

    attempting to meet some of the needs in this area.

    In this section, however, we will consider some

    criteria for selecting which potential transplant

    recipient will receive a given human organ or

    tissue.

    A widely used and approved criterion of selection

    is to give priority to those who have great need

    3..

    )

    .

    .

    ,

    ?

    ?

    .

    4

    .

    3.

    . ,

    ,

    .

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    13/32

    and who are expected to benefit greatly. For

    example, it does not make sense to give a limited

    number of available organs to those who will not

    benefit or who are expected to only live marginally

    longer but suffer much with the transplants, when

    others would benefit greatly. While this criterion is

    widely accepted as fair, there is much discussion

    about how to define and assess "benefit". Many

    argue that both expected length of survival and

    the possibilities regarding rehabilitation should be

    considered.

    In spite of the success of transplants, care must be

    taken not only that they extend life biologically,

    but that they also offer the patient a real chancefor a healthy life. The new organs should add new

    years to life, and help to provide a new and better

    life.

    ....as a last resort a choice sometimes has to be

    made between a transplant immediately available

    but with a very small chance of survival, and a long

    term transplant offering a greater possibility of

    healing.(German Bishops..., 374-5)

    With regard to who will likely benefit more fromreceiving a transplant, medical criteria such as

    blood and tissue typing (i.e. who is less likely to

    reject the transplant), and the absence of other

    life-threatening diseases, are used. Other factors

    such as the potential recipient's will to live,

    motivation and ability to follow post-operative

    directions (e.g. taking immunosuppressants), his or

    her family support, and the skill of the transplant

    team can also be relevant to the success of a

    transplant.(Garrett et al., 213-216)

    Potential recipients (i.e. those likely to benefit

    from a transplant) are registered on a "first come,

    first serve" basis. This, or random methods of

    selection (e.g. a lottery) where there is equal

    chance, is fair provided that the need and benefit

    . ,

    ,

    ,

    ,

    .

    ,

    "".

    .

    ,

    ,

    .

    ,

    .

    ....

    ,

    ,

    (

    ..., 374. - 5)

    ,

    (.

    ),

    , .

    ,

    ,

    (.

    -),

    ,

    .

    ( , 213-216.)

    (

    )

    " , "

    . ,

    (. ) ,

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    14/32

    are approximately the same among potential

    recipients.(cf. Varga, 226; and Ashley and

    O'Rourke 1986, 112, and 1989, 308)

    Some argue in favor of using criteria such as social

    worth, and merit or demerit, to select or prioritize

    potential recipients. Concerning "social worth", for

    example, is it fair to give priority to a mother of

    young children over a single person, or to a

    successful doctor over someone who is at present

    unemployed? Concerning merit should a retired

    person who contributed a lot to the community be

    given priority over a young person who has not yet

    proven him or herself? Regarding demerit, for

    example, should someone who previously abused

    alcohol, smoked heavily or ate unhealthily be

    denied a liver, lung or heart transplant?(cf.

    Altman; Moss and Siegler) Many, however,criticize these and other criteria such as ability to

    pay, race, religion, gender, and age, as involving

    unfair discrimination. They are said to violate the

    equal dignity of all human beings. Criteria such as

    "social worth" are also seen by some to be too

    difficult and subjective to apply efficiently and

    reasonably.(cf. CHAC, 30 and 45; Appleton

    International Conference, 6-7; Varga, 226; Garrett

    et al., 216; Childress) Childress argues as well that

    the criteria for selecting recipients should be open

    and subject to public scrutiny.

    (. , 226, ' 1986 112,. ,

    1989, 308)

    ,

    ,

    . "

    ", ,

    ,

    ?

    ? , ,

    ,

    ,

    (. , )

    , ,

    , ? ,

    , , ,

    .

    .

    " ",

    (. , 30 45; , 6-7,

    , 226;.. , 216; )

    .

    b) Using

    Animals

    The shortage of various human parts for transplant

    purposes has in part motivated research in animal

    to human transplants. The use of some animal

    parts such as insulin extracted from animal

    pancreases, catgut as absorbable sutures, and pig

    heart valves, are already "accepted" medical

    treatments. Attempts, however, to transplant a

    baboon's heart to a human infant (Baby Fae) or a

    pig liver to a dying woman, for example, have

    aroused considerable controversy.(see LRCC, 18-

    )

    .

    ,

    , ,

    "" .

    , ,

    ( )

    , ,

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    15/32

    19; n. 4 below under "Some Cases..."; and Siegel)

    Some argue that the present state of transplants

    between species does not justify such experiments

    which so far do not offer hope of therapeutic

    benefit to the human recipients. Defenders of such

    experiments argue that they can be justified if no

    other alternatives are available and for the

    knowledge gained. Some have questioned

    whether such transplants involve irresponsible

    meddling with nature. Various animal rights

    groups have protested the sacrifice of animals

    involved in this and other research, which uses

    them as "mere means" to human welfare.

    Concerning organ transplants from animals to

    human beings research is being done with various

    immunosuppressive agents with the hope of

    finding a combination to overcome the rejection

    problem.(Johnston) Attempts are also being madeto genetically engineer and breed new strains of

    some animals such as pigs so that their organs can

    be transplanted into humans with less risk of

    rejection. If successful, the scientists involved hope

    that this will overcome the large shortage of

    human donor organs.(Reuter; Hanson)

    Widely accepted directives for human

    experimentation call for both adequate

    preliminary animal experimentation to minimize

    the risks to human subjects and that the welfare ofanimals used in research be respected.(e.g.

    Helsinki Declaration of 1975, p. 1771) Pope John

    Paul II in an address to a Congress of the Pontifical

    Academy of Sciences said, "...animals are at the

    service of man and can hence be the object of

    experimentation. Nevertheless, they must be

    treated as creatures of God which are destined to

    serve man's good, but not to be abused by

    him...."(p. 5) The Catholic Health Association of

    Canada (CHAC) stipulates that animals involved in

    research are to be properly respected and such

    research "is to be allowed only when other

    methods involving non-living subjects are no

    longer helpful. When use of such subjects is

    justified, pain relief must be used or suffering

    reduced to a minimum."(60)

    With respect to tissue transplants between

    individuals of different species, Pope Pius XII on

    ( , 18-19, 4

    " .. ... ", )

    .

    .

    .

    ,

    " "

    .

    ().

    ,

    . ,

    (, ).

    (.

    1975, 1771.)

    .

    , "...

    ,

    ,

    , .

    .... "(. 5)

    ()

    ",

    -

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    16/32

    May 14, 1956, spoke of the transplant of a cornea,

    for example, as moral, if possible and warranted.

    He, however, considered the transplant of the

    sexual glands of an animal to a human being as

    immoral. Thomas O'Donnell interprets the

    condemnation of the latter as aimed at transplants

    that would "envision an act of attempted

    generation."(104-7)

    The Sacred Congregation for the Doctrine of the

    Faith excludes, among other things, attempts of

    fertilization between human and animal gametes

    and to gestate human embryos in the uteruses of

    animals as contrary to human dignity. It considers

    genetic interventions that are therapeutic, for

    proportionate reasons, however, as licit.(SCDF

    1987, 15-20; cf. CHAC, 60)

    The Catholic Health Association of Canada (CHAC)

    considers transplants from living animals to

    humans as

    ...permissible as long as these can fulfill an

    essentially beneficial human function in the

    recipient. The human dignity of the recipient is not

    to be compromised in any way and due respect is

    to be paid to the non-human donor in the whole

    transplant procedure.(46)

    .

    ,

    ". (60)

    ,

    , 14.

    1956, ,

    , ,

    . , ,

    . '

    (104-7) "

    ."

    ,

    ,

    .

    , ,

    ( 1987, 15-20;. , 60).

    ()

    ,

    ...

    .

    -

    . (46)

    c) Artificial Substitutes for Tissues and Organs

    The shortage of various human parts for transplant

    purposes has also in part motivated research in

    the development of artificial and synthetic

    substitutes for tissues and organs. There are a

    number of substances that the human body does

    not reject. A number of artificial replacement

    technologies including false teeth, artificial limbs

    and joints, hearing aids, synthetic lenses,

    pacemakers, mechanical and synthetic heart

    valves, genetically engineered insulin and growth

    )

    .

    .

    ,

    , ,

    , ,

    ,

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    17/32

    hormone, and renal dialysis, are already routinely

    used in treatment. Other technologies such as the

    implantable artificial heart are still experimental or

    are used temporarily with the hope of keeping the

    person alive until a suitable human donor organ is

    found.

    Artificial replacement technologies are generally

    very costly to develop. If they prove to be

    successful and are mass produced, their long-term

    costs can be significantly reduced. A number of

    routinely used replacement technologies such as

    long-term renal dialysis, however, remain

    expensive. Some ethical questions concerning such

    costs will be considered in section 3.d below.

    Another issue is that the recipient of some artificial

    parts may need to make certain psychologicaladjustments. Consider, for example, the

    implantable artificial heart (also a heart transplant

    from another animal species) in light of the

    "popular belief that the heart is the center of

    human emotions, the organ of love."(Varga, 239.

    Cf. ibid, 238-41; LRCC, 20-22; and Thomas and

    Waluchow, Case 7:3.)

    The Catholic Health Association of Canada (CHAC)

    states that artificial substitutes for tissues and

    organs are permissible provided they "can fulfill anessentially beneficial human function in the

    recipient" and the "human dignity of the recipient"

    is not compromised in any way.(46)

    , ,

    .

    ,

    .

    .

    ,

    .

    , ,

    .

    3. .

    . , ,

    (

    ) (, 239. "

    ,

    ." . , 238-41, , 20-22,

    , 7:3).

    ()

    "

    " " "

    . ( 46)

    d) High Costs, Universality and Justice

    The development and use of technology related to

    organ and tissue transplants or artificial

    substitutes is expensive. For example, estimates of

    the costs of transplant procedures, without

    complications, "range from $20,000-$30,000 for a

    kidney, $60,000-$80,000 for a heart, and

    $120,000-$150,000 for a liver."(Goddard) With

    complications the costs can be much higher. Such

    costs are beyond the means of many people, if

    they are not covered by public funds, medical

    insurance or charity. The demand for transplants

    has also increased because they have become

    quite effective. For example, the one-year survival

    rate for all transplants is at least 70-80%; and the

    ) ,

    . ,

    ,

    , ()

    " $ 20,000 -

    $ 30,000 , $ 60,000 - - $ 80,000 ,

    $ 120,000 $ 150,000 ." .

    ,

    ,

    .

    ,

    . ,

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    18/32

    five-year survival rate for heart and liver

    transplants is 70% and 70-80%

    respectively.(Goddard)

    Today the issue of whether transplants and other

    expensive medical technologies are cost-effective

    and whether public funds should cover the costs of

    all such procedures for everyone who could

    benefit from them is being discussed a lot. It

    should be noted, however, that the average cost

    per life year gained from a transplant (e.g. kidney)

    can be significantly lower than alternative

    treatments (e.g. hemodialysis). In addition, the

    recipient of a successful transplant often

    contributes much more to the economy through

    work, spending and paying taxes, than if they

    would have died or remained ill.(Goddard)

    Other questions include: Could the large sums of

    money (or some of it) that is spent on developing

    and using transplant technology and artificial

    substitutes be better used to improve the health

    and quality of life of more people if spent in other

    ways (e.g. providing better access to primary

    health care, improving education and preventative

    health programs, improving the environment by

    further reducing pollutants, etc.)? What percent of

    health care dollars should be allotted to transplant

    programs and related research? Broader questionsinclude: What per cent of public funds should be

    spent on the good of health as compared to other

    goods? Should government spending and public

    health services be limited or reduced, or should

    taxes be increased to provide for more people's

    needs and/or wants? To what extent should

    transplant services and organs be supplied to

    people of other countries? There are no easy

    answers to such questions of distributive justice

    which, among other things, can affect who lives

    and who dies. One can also ask how it affects us as

    moral agents if we do not help or save all those we

    can?(cf. Ashley and O'Rourke 1989, 308-10;

    Engelhardt; Garrett et al., 216-19; and Thomas and

    Waluchow, 132-4)

    Parliament through the Canada Health Act (1985)

    has committed Canada to providing "reasonable

    access" to "medically necessary" hospital and

    70-80%,

    70% 70-80% ().

    . , ,

    (. )

    (.

    ). ,

    , ,

    ().

    :

    ( )

    (.

    ,

    ,

    , )?

    ? :

    ?

    ,

    / ?

    ?

    , ,

    .

    ,

    (.

    ' 1989, 308-10, ,

    , 216-19;. ? , 132-4)

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    19/32

    health services on a uniform basis. Reasonable

    access, however, does not mean absolute access.

    The term "medically necessary" is also open to

    interpretation.(LRCC, 124-5)

    The position of the Catholic Health Association of

    Canada (CHAC) is: "Basic health care needs are to

    be considered in the allocation of resources for

    transplantations, especially when it is a question of

    novel procedures involving scarce organs and

    expensive, limited medical facilities."(45) With

    respect to allocating resources in general it calls

    for solidarity with sick persons, careful

    stewardship of God's gifts and "active participation

    in the formulation of policy for the equitable

    distribution of health care funds in society as a

    whole", among other things.(22-24)

    (1985)

    "

    " " "

    .

    , ,

    . " "

    (, 124-

    5).

    () : "

    ,

    , .

    "(45)

    ,

    "

    ", (22-24).

    4. Ethical Issues Regarding Procurement of Organs

    and Tissues

    a) Buying and Selling Human Organs and Tissues

    Some argue in favor of allowing human organs and

    tissues to be bought and sold to increase thesupply and to respect people's autonomy. Others

    argue against such saying that to treat the human

    body and its parts as commodities violates human

    dignity.(cf. LRCC, 56-62; and May, 165-7) Human

    tissues and organs are in fact being sold in some

    places. For example, a French pharmaceutical firm

    buys placentas from 110 Canadian hospitals to

    manufacture vaccines and other blood products

    (Aikenhead), and some living poor people in

    countries such as India sell one of their kidneys for

    $700 or so. In Bombay, for example, there have

    also been some cases of kidnapping where victims

    regain consciousness to find that one of their

    kidneys was removed while they were

    drugged.(Wallace; cf. Rinehart)

    Concerning this whole issue some distinguish

    between human waste products such as placentas,

    body parts that regenerate such as blood, and

    4..

    )

    .

    (. , 56-62, , 165-7)

    .. ,

    110

    (),

    $ 700 . ,

    ,

    ,

    (;. ).

    ,

    ,

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    20/32

    nonregenerative human organs such as kidneys.

    Many distinguish profit making from covering the

    donor's expenses. Paying for organs can constitute

    unjust moral pressure on the donor. It could

    invalidate any free consent or a contract. Some

    also fear that the buying and selling of organs and

    tissues, if it became widespread, would undermine

    the altruism (giving motivated by love) and social

    bonding now associated with transplants. It could

    also lead to organs going to the highest bidder.

    Equity would be violated with ability to pay rather

    than medical need determining the distribution of

    organs. Some others, however, argue that this

    could be controlled by regulating sales, and that

    totally forbidding the buying and selling of human

    tissues and organs would drive the market

    underground. Because of the controversy and

    ethical problems surrounding the buying andselling of human body parts, some say that other

    alternatives should be pursued to increase the

    supply.(cf. LRCC, 78-86; and Garrett et al., 203-4)

    A World Health Organization resolution in 1989

    that was eventually supported by more than 151

    nations in part, "Calls Upon Member States to take

    appropriate measures to prevent the purchase and

    sale of human organs for transplantation..."(LRCC,

    162-3 and 202-3) With respect to blood

    transfusions, Pope Pius XII said, "It iscommendable for the donor to refuse

    recompense: it is not necessarily a fault to accept

    it."(LRCC, 58) Concerning the Christian vision

    which sees human life and the body as "a gift of

    the Creator, which persons cannot dispose of as

    they please", the German Bishops' Conference and

    the Council of the German Evangelical Church say,

    "This does not exclude compensation for the

    expenses incurred by the donation of tissue and

    organs, but it does forbid deriving profit from

    it."(375; cf. Chilean Bishops' Permanent

    Commission, 374). The Catholic Health Association

    of Canada (CHAC) holds that the buying and selling

    of human organs, tissues and blood "contradicts

    the principle of charity which is part of the

    necessary justification for such

    transplantations."(46)

    , ,

    .

    .

    .

    .

    ,

    ,

    ( )

    .

    .

    ,

    . , ,

    ,

    .

    ,

    (.

    , 78-86;. , 203-4).

    1989 151

    , "

    ..." (, 162-3 202-3)

    ,

    , "

    : ."

    (, 58)

    "

    ,

    ", "

    ,"

    ,

    "(375;.

    , 374)..

    ()

    , "

    ." (46)

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    21/32

    b) Media Publicity

    Sometimes an organ or tissue is procured for a

    person by publicizing their need through the

    media. This could bypass the regular transplant

    channels and their selecting recipients for an

    available organ on the basis of greatest need and

    greatest likelihood of benefit, and first come first

    serve (see 3.a above). On the other hand, media

    pleas frequently bring in more volunteers than

    those required for the case being publicized.

    Media publicity also increases public awareness of

    the need for transplants and so in the long run

    should increase the supply of donated tissues and

    organs. Garrett et al. argue that at this stage of

    medical history media publicity for a particular

    case should be tolerated, but in time it should be

    eliminated as much as possible.(212)

    )

    .

    ,

    ( 3.). ,

    .

    . .

    ,

    (212.

    c) Types of Consent (Voluntary or Expressed,

    Family,

    Presumed, Required Request, Routine Inquiry)

    Voluntary or expressed consent involves a person

    making known their free offer to donate one or

    more of their organs and/or bodily tissue, after

    they have died or while alive.(cf. 1.a and b above)

    Concerning cadaver donation, a person canexpress their wishes by some form of advanced

    directives, such as by filling out the Universal

    Donor Card attached to their driver's license. Free

    and informed consent is required when the

    transplant is from a living donor. Previously

    expressed voluntary consent regarding a deceased

    donor is the ideal because it involves an act of love

    and responsible stewardship over one's body. It

    also communicates to others, including one's

    family and health care professionals, one's wishes.

    In the absence of clearly expressed voluntary

    consent, the family or person lawfully responsible

    for the body of the deceased may be approached

    regarding donation. Proper respect involves due

    consideration of the wishes of the deceased and

    their loved ones.

    Many potential organs and tissues for

    transplantation (e.g. of brain-dead accident

    ) (

    , ,

    , ,

    )

    / , (. 1. ).

    ,

    ,

    .

    .

    ,

    .

    , ,

    ,

    .

    ,

    .

    .

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    22/32

    victims) are lost because the person did not

    previously express voluntary consent and their

    families were not approached about donating.

    Because of this and the shortage of organs and

    tissues for transplantation, some have proposed

    other models of consent including presumed,

    required request and routine inquiry, to hopefully

    increase the supply. Although only a minority of

    deceased potential donors have signed donor

    cards, surveys show that most people favor organ

    donation. Some argue that it is ethical to presume

    consent on their behalf, unless the person while

    alive gave clear indications to the contrary, since a

    transplant does not harm the donor after death

    and it can benefit others. France, Belgium and

    some other countries have various forms of

    presumed consent legislation in place. People can

    opt out by registering their intention not to be adonor. Questions concerning this approach

    include: Should minors and the mentally disabled

    be included? To what extent should health care

    professionals check to see if the person has

    expressed a wish not to donate? Can not this be a

    form of exploiting human ignorance and weakness

    (cf. people ignorant that they can opt out or too

    lackadaisical to do so)?

    Required request requires hospitals to develop

    protocols to ensure that families of potentialdonors are actually asked to donate. Routine

    inquiry requires hospitals to develop protocols to

    ensure that families of undeclared potential

    donors have the opportunity to donate - people

    tend to react more positively when offered a

    choice. Some have criticized these approaches as

    not allowing professional discretion. Many health

    professionals are reluctant to approach families

    who have just lost a loved one about

    transplantation. This is considered a major barrier

    to increasing the supply of organs and tissues.

    Most families though do not object to being

    approached. Required request or routine inquiry

    has been widely endorsed in the United States as a

    preferred public policy option when compared to a

    free or regulated market of organ and tissue sales

    or a presumed consent approach. It is seen as

    more respectful of altruism, familial sentiments

    and religious interests. It can also help the

    (.

    )

    .

    ,

    , ,

    ,

    .

    ,

    .

    ,

    ,

    . ,

    .

    .

    :

    ?

    ?

    (.

    )?

    .

    -

    , .

    .

    ,

    .

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    23/32

    bereavement process by making something

    positive come out of the death. Some significant

    increases in organ and tissue donation have been

    recorded where this policy is in place. A few

    jurisdictions also allow presumed consent

    following required inquiry if the family did not

    object.

    The Law Reform Commission of Canada

    recommends maintaining and strengthening the

    present express consent model in Canada with

    hospitals implementing routine-inquiry protocols.

    These, however, are to recognize professional

    discretion not to ask in cases where this would

    clearly be inappropriate.(LRCC, 39-46, 145-39, and

    176-82; cf. Varga, 221-2; Garrett et al., 210-11;

    Ashley and O'Rourke 1989, 310; and May, 167-8)

    d) Fears, Confusion and the Need for Education

    There is a need for education of the general public

    and many health care professionals concerning the

    whole area of organ and tissue transplants. Many

    people are not well informed of the needs, the

    shortage of organs and tissues, and the great

    potential benefit of many people for transplants.

    Many have unfounded fears or reservations or are

    confused about some of the issues of being adonor. In a recent United States survey, "the two

    most common reasons given for not permitting

    organ donation were (1) they might do something

    to me before I am really dead; (2) doctors might

    hasten my death."(LRCC, note 226) This shows

    ignorance of standard policy and procedure

    concerning transplants. These include strict criteria

    for determining total brain death and the

    separation of the ill or dying patient's health care

    team and the transplant team.

    Although surveys show that most people think

    transplantation is a good thing, only a minority

    sign an organ donor card. Why? First of all, many

    are not fully aware of the advantages of this type

    of voluntary expressed consent.(see section 4.c

    above) Some people may be unwilling to think

    about their own mortality, an inevitable fact, or be

    superstitious. For example, they may mistakenly

    .

    .

    .

    ,

    .

    .

    ,

    .

    ,

    .

    .

    , ,

    (, 39-46, 145-39, 176-82 , , 221-

    2;... , 210-11, ' 1989

    310, , 167-8)

    ) ,

    .

    ,

    ,

    .

    . ,

    " ,

    (1)

    ,

    (2) ." (,

    226 )

    .

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    24/32

    think that signing a donor card will increase their

    chance of a fatal accident. Some may have

    concerns about the mutilation of their body.

    Organs and tissues, however, are carefully

    removed and incisions are closed, so that it will

    not be apparent to anyone viewing the body that

    organs or tissues have been donated.(HOPE, 3)

    Also,

    Some people wonder what will happen to their

    bodies if at death they donate an organ. The truth

    is that every earthly body decays. Therefore, the

    alternative is between an organ decomposing or

    serving to keep an other human being alive. We

    Christians believe, as St Paul tells us, that our

    corruptible body will be transformed into a

    spiritual body for the glory of God (cf. 1 Cor 15:35-

    53)(Chilean Bishops' Permanent Conference, 375)

    Some people may also not realize that they can

    specify limits on an organ donor form regarding

    the use of their body (e.g. which organs they may

    or may not wish to donate). People should be

    encouraged to consider organ and tissue donation

    as a "legacy of love", as an incarnate form of

    "CHARITY AFTER DEATH."(Wolak, 18)

    Health care professionals also need to be educated

    about the meaning of organ and tissuedonation.(CHAC, 43) Some have unfounded

    reservations about approaching individuals or

    families to consider organ and tissue donation. It is

    important that some members of the health care

    team be trained in approaching potential donors

    and their families in a sensitive way. They need to

    be able to provide the necessary personal and

    social support regarding the grieving process.(cf.

    Batten) Some health care professionals also need

    to learn that properly respecting the dead human

    body is a requirement of our humanness. Along

    these lines some medical schools offer services of

    remembrance and gratitude before and after

    dissecting human cadavers.(Lynch, 1018) Care

    needs to be taken, too, regarding the language

    one uses about the dead. For example, "harvesting

    the dead" connotes "taking" and is repugnant,

    whereas "donation" connotes "giving" and is

    dignified.(cf. Belk) In order to increase the

    .

    ,

    .

    ? ,

    ( 4. )

    , ,

    .. ,

    .

    . , ,

    , ,

    (, 3).

    ,

    , .

    .

    ,

    .

    , ,

    , (. 1

    15:35-53) (

    , 375)

    (.

    ).

    " ",

    " ."

    (, 18)

    (, 43)

    ..

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    25/32

    potential for transplants, some health care

    professionals have a special responsibility with

    regard to raising the general level of consciousness

    of the needs. This should be done in a way that

    always properly respects patients' rights of

    confidentiality and that does not detract from

    communicating other pressing health care issues.

    "The public is entitled to be accurately informed

    about the medical progress and implications of

    transplantation."(CHAC, 47; cf. German Bishops...,

    376)

    .

    (. )

    ..

    (,

    1018) , ,

    .. ,

    " " "" ,

    "" ""

    (. )

    .,

    .

    . "

    ." (, 47;

    . ..., 376)

    Conclusion

    A number of the many ethical issues concerningorgan and tissue transplants have been treated in

    this paper. These issues concern the donor, the

    recipient, the allocation of limited resources, and

    the means of procuring organs and tissues.

    Although there have been some abuses in this

    field, and there are some areas of controversy, I

    would like to conclude with a positive note.

    Organ donation, carried out under proper

    conditions, is a beautiful and modern expression of

    Christian charity: it gives dignity to the person who

    in death becomes a life-support for another; it

    shows noble concern for the respect of the life of

    others; and it implies a sense of communion with

    humanity. The Gospel proclaims that there is no

    greater love than to give one's life for another (cf.

    Jn 15:13). Jesus welcomes the good done to

    another as though it were done to himself (cf.

    Matt 25).(Chilean Bishops' Permanent

    . ,

    , ,

    .

    ,

    ,

    .

    ,

    ,

    :

    ,

    ,

    .

    (. 15:13).

    (.

    25) ( ,

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    26/32

    Commission, 375) 375).

    Some Cases and Questions For Discussion

    1. Don and Dan are identical twins. After Don

    suffers kidney failure, Dan is requested by his

    brother's wife to donate one of his healthy kidneys

    to Don. Does Dan have any obligation to surrender

    one of his healthy kidneys to his brother? Under

    what condition would you defend Dan's decision

    not to surrender his kidney.(From Ashley and

    O'Rourke 1986, 172)

    2. Is it ethical for a living person with two good

    eyes to donate an eye to enable a blind person to

    see?

    3. Sally was 15 years old and had been a practisingJehovah Witness for several years. She lived with

    her sister Jane, who was 18 years old and an

    atheist, and mother, who had been a Jehovah

    Witness but who renounced this following a legal

    separation with her husband. Sally had only seen

    her father, who was a devout Jehovah Witness, a

    few times since the separation. Sally was involved

    in a bad car accident and before lapsing into a

    coma was heard to say repeatedly, "I don't want to

    die. Please help me." The doctor said Sally would

    die without surgery which required a bloodtransfusion. The surgery had a 90% success rate,

    with a 5% chance of paraplegia and another 5%

    chance of death. Sally's mother insisted that the

    operation with a blood transfusion take place to

    save her life. Her father strongly objected that this

    would violate a sacred principle of Sally, an

    avowed Jehovah Witness. Jane pointed out that

    Sally was a minor and questioned whether her

    commitment to the blood transfusion principle

    could have been fully informed and voluntary. Her

    parents were her legal guardians. The doctor went

    before a judge to seek a resolution. If you were the

    judge, what would be your decision?(condensed

    from Thomas and Waluchow, 150-4)

    4. Baby Fae was born with a severe heart defect

    which would cause her death within a few weeks.

    Her parents were poor and in a country without

    universal medical insurance. Loma Linda Hospital

    1. .

    ,

    .

    ?

    ( ' 1986,

    172).

    2.

    ?

    3.. 15 .

    , 18

    , , ,

    .

    ,

    , .

    ,

    "

    .".

    . 90% ,

    5% 5%

    .

    .

    ,

    .

    .

    .

    . ,

    ( ,

    150-4)?

    4..

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    27/32

    offered to cover the costs of transplanting a heart

    from a baboon. The parents signed an elaborate

    consent form which was never released. The

    doctors did not consider the possibility of a human

    donor, thinking the hopes of finding one were

    almost nonexistent. It seems that they also did not

    seriously consider a new form of corrective

    surgery for this type of heart defect with a 40

    percent survival rate after several years. Baby Fae

    was reported in serious but stable condition for

    two weeks following the operation, but died a

    week later, apparently of complications related to

    rejecting the baboon heart. Did the doctors act in

    an ethical manner? Under what conditions, if any,

    would a transplant of this nature be

    acceptable?(cf. Ashley and O'Rourke 1986, 117;

    and Thomas and Waluchow, 119-24)

    5. Should public funds cover the related costs of

    transplants for all people who can benefit from

    them? Should taxes be increased to fund more

    publicity of the need and so increase the supply of

    organs and tissues for transplants, and to pay for

    more transplants, so that more people can live

    longer and healthier?

    6. Mrs. Simpatico, a nurse, had cared for Joseph,

    who was 30 years old, a few weeks before he died.

    The hospital has a policy requiring nurses to askthe families of all dead patients for organ

    donations. Both she and the family are very upset

    about the death. She believes Joseph's young wife

    and three children need comfort and not decisions

    at this moment, so she does not ask for the organ

    donation, even though the hospital has a long

    waiting list. When the nursing supervisor discovers

    this omission, she reprimands Mrs. Simpatico and

    warns her: "One more incident like that and you

    will be fired." Is the hospital's policy good? Was it

    right for Mrs. Simpatico to make an exception in

    this case?(adapted from Garrett et al., 221)

    7. Two men on the same service are awaiting a

    cornea transplant because of chemical burns on

    their eyes. One is an alcoholic street person with

    other serious health problems. The other is a

    prominent lawyer with a wife and three children. A

    donor's eye becomes available, and by coincidence

    .

    .

    .

    .

    ,

    .

    40

    .

    ,

    ,

    .

    ?

    , ,

    (. ', 1986, 117,

    , 119-24)?

    5..

    ?

    ,

    , ?

    6.. , ,

    , 30 ,

    .

    .

    .

    ,

    ,

    , .

    ,

    :

    "

    ." ?

    (

    , 221.)?

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    28/32

    both men's cornea match the donor's. The

    physician decides on the basis of "first come, first

    served" and transplants the cornea to the

    alcoholic. Is it ethical to do this when the alcoholic

    has more serious health problems? Is there a

    relevance to the patients' social

    positions?(adapted from Garrett et al., 221)

    8. Anissa is 17 years old when it is discovered she

    has leukemia. Her primary hope for survival rests

    on a bone marrow transplant, but there are no

    likely donors for her unusual genetic

    characteristics. Her parents decide to have

    another child in the hope that the infant will

    provide a tissue match (a 25% chance). Is it

    ethically right to conceive a child for the purpose

    of generating tissue for transplantation? If the

    infant is a tissue match, is it right for the parents todecide for the infant?(adapted from Garrett et al.,

    222)

    9. In your opinion why do comparatively few

    people sign the Universal Donor Card on their

    driver's license?(adapted from Ashley and

    O'Rourke 1986, 210)

    10. After Ben, a 10 year old boy, is declared brain

    dead in Alberta Children's Hospital, Dr. Mitchell

    asks Ben's parents if they have considered organdonation. They consent because they think it is a

    good way to deal with their grief and what Ben

    would have wanted. As a result a few other

    children are living normal lives: Kirsten of

    Edmonton received Ben's heart; Stuart of Airdrie

    and Amy of Calgary each received one of Ben's

    kidneys; Johnny of Pittsburgh received Ben's liver;

    and Steven of Lethbridge received Ben's cornea.

    (This case is presented in the video, "Have You

    Considered Organ Donation?"[1991, 11 minutes],

    the Human Organ Procurement and Exchange

    Program [HOPE], University of Alberta Hospitals.)

    7..

    .

    .

    .

    ,

    .

    " , "

    .

    ?

    (

    , 221.)?

    8. 17

    . ,

    .

    ,

    (25% ).

    ?

    ,

    ( , 222.)?

    9. ,

    ( ' 1986, 210)?

    10. , 10- ,

    ,

    -

    . ,

    .

    :

    ,

    ,

    ,

    . (

    , "

    ?" *1991, 11 +,

    *+,

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    29/32

    .)

    References:

    Aikenhead, Sherri (1993). "Sale of Human Placentas to French Pharmaceutical Firm Questioned" and

    "Hospitals Should Inform Mothers if Placentas Traded - Commissioner," The Edmonton Journal, 3 Mar.

    1993, A14, and 4 Mar. 1993, A11, respectively.

    Altman, Lawrence K., M.D.(1990). "Should Alcoholics get new Livers?", The Edmonton Journal, 15 Apr.

    1990, E6.

    Appleton International Conference (1992), "Developing Guidelines to Forgo Life-prolonging Medical

    Treatment," The Bioethics Bulletin, University of Alberta, Edmonton, Jan. 1993, 2-7.

    Ashley, Benedict M., OP; and Kevin D. O'Rourke, OP (1986). Ethics of Health Care. St. Louis: Catholic

    Health Association of the United States.

    __________ (1989). Health Care Ethics, Third Edition. St. Louis: Catholic Health Association of the United

    States.

    Associated Press, "Brain-dead woman suffers miscarriage," The Edmonton Journal, 17 Nov. 1992.

    Batten, Helen Levine (1990). "The Social Construction of Altruism in Organ Donation," Ch. 8 in Organ

    Donation and Transplantation: Psychological and Behavioral Factors, ed. by James Shanteau and Richard

    Jackson Harris. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.

    Belk, Russell W. (1990). "Me and Thee Versus Mine and Thine: How Perceptions of the Body Influence

    Organ Donation and Transplantation," Ch. 12 in Organ Donation and Transplantation: Psychological and

    Behavioral Factors, ed. by James Shanteau and Richard Jackson Harris. Washington, DC: American

    Psychological Association.

    Cefalo, Robert C.; and H. Tristam Engelhardt, Jr. (1993). "The Use of Fetal and Anencephalic Tissue for

    Transplantation," Eike-Henner Kluge, ed., Readings in Biomedical Ethics: A Canadian Focus. Scarborough:

    Prentice Hall Canada Inc., 367-78.

    CFRN Television (1987). "A Second Chance" (Video, 50 minutes). Available from HOPE, University of

    Alberta Hospitals, Edmonton.

    [CHAC] Catholic Health Association of Canada (1991). Health Care Ethics Guide. Ottawa. References are

    by page number.

    Childress, James (1978). "Rationing of Medical Treatment," Encyclopedia of Bioethics. New York: The

    Free Press, 1414-19.

    Chilean Bishops' Permanent Commission (1991). "On Organ Transplants," Catholic International, 15-30

    April 1991, 374-5.

    Dailey, Thomas G. (1993). "Fetal Tissue Transplants: Some Ethical Questions." Edmonton: St. Joseph's

    College Catholic Bioethics Centre, Jan. 1993.

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    30/32

    Duncan, Glenn E. (1992). "Grim Harvest," The Catholic World Report, Aug. 1992, 16-22.

    Engelhardt, H. Tristram (1987). "Allocating Scarce Medical Resources and the Availability of Organ

    Transplantation: Some Moral Presuppositions," Thomas A. Shannon, ed. Bioethics, Third Edition.

    Mahwah: Paulist Press, 565-79.

    Garrett, Thomas M.; Harold W. Baillie; and Rosellen M. Garrett (1993). Health Care Ethics: Principles and

    Problems. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall, Ch. 9.

    Gaylin, Willard, M.D. (1987). "Harvesting the Dead," in Bioethics, Third Edition, ed. by Thomas A.

    Shannon. Mahwah: Paulist Press, 553-63.

    German Bishops' Conference and the Council of the German Evangelical Church (1988). "Christians and

    the Ethics of Organ Transplants," Catholic International, 15-30 April 1991, 373-6.

    Goddard, Hans (1992). "No Easy Way to Figure Costs of Transplants," The Medical Post, 7 July 1992, 43.

    Hanson, Mark J. (1992). "A Pig in a Poke," Hastings Center Report, Nov.-Dec. 1992, 2.

    Helsinki Declaration of 1975, Encyclopedia of Bioethics, Vol. 1V. New York: The Free Press, 1978, pp.

    1771-3.

    [HOPE] Human Organ Procurement and Exchange Program (1993). Organ & Tissue Donation (pamphlet).

    Edmonton: University of Alberta Hospitals.

    John Paul II, Pope (1982). "Biological Experiments Should Contribute to the Well-Being of Mankind,"

    L'Osservatore Romano, English weekly ed., 8 Nov. 1982, pp. 4-5.

    Johnston, Cameron (1993). "Transplanting Animal Organs Into Humans Could Soon Become a Reality in

    Canada," The Medical Post, 5 Jan. 1993.

    Jonsen, Albert R. (1989). "Ethical Issues in Organ Transplantation," Ch. 9 in Medical Ethics, ed. by Robert

    M. Veatch. Boston: Jones and Bartlett Publishers, 229-52.

    [LRCC] Law Reform Commission of Canada (1992). Procurement and Transfer of Human Tissues and

    Organs, Working Paper 66. Ottawa: Canada Communication Group - Publishing.

    Lynch, A. (1990). "Respect for the Dead Human Body: A Question of Body, Mind, Spirit, Psyche,"

    Transplantation Proceedings, Vol. 22, No. 3 (June), 1990, pp. 1016-18.

    MacNeil, Archbishop Joseph N. (1986), excerpt in "Your Religion and Organ Donation" (pamphlet).

    Edmonton: Lions Eye Bank.

    May, William E. (1977). Human Existence, Medicine and Ethics. Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, Ch. 7.

    Moss, Alvin H.; and Mark Siegler (1993). "Should Alcoholics Compete Equally for Liver Transplantation?",

    Eike-Henner Kluge, ed., Readings in Biomedical Ethics: A Canadian Focus. Scarborough: Prentice Hall

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    31/32

    Canada Inc., 85-94.

    O'Donnell, Thomas J., S.J. (1976). Medicine and Christian Morality. New York: Alba House.

    Post, Stephen G. (1991). "Fetal Tissue Transplant: The Right to Question Progress," America, 12 Jan.

    1991, 14-16.

    Reuter (1993). "Pigs Born with Human Genes," The Edmonton Journal, 12 Mar. 1993.

    Rinehart, Dianne (1993). "Sold for Organs, Risk to Kids Grows," The Edmonton Journal, 22 Jun. 1993,

    B14.

    [SCDF] Sacred Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith (1980). Declaration on Euthanasia. Battleford,

    Sask.: Marian Press.

    __________ (1987). Instruction on Respect for Human Life in its Origin and on the Dignity of

    Procreation. Boston: St. Paul Editions.

    Siegel, Lee (1992). "Use of Pig Liver Defended," The Press Democrat, 14 Oct. 1992, B4.

    Thomas, John E.; and Wilfrid J. Waluchow (1990). Well and Good: Case Studies in Biomedical Ethics,

    Revised Edition. Peterborough: Broadview Press.

    Varga, Andrew C. (1984). The Main Issues in Bioethics, Revised Edition. Ramsey: Paulist Press, Chs. 11

    and 12.

    Wallace, Charles P. (1992). "Trafficking on Kidney Street: The Rich get Healthier from Trade in Human

    Organs," Science and Medicine, 13 Sept. 1992.

    Wolak, Richard, OMI (1990). "Donate Your Organs: Charity After Death: Everyone Should Plan to be an

    Organ Donor," Our Family, July/August 1990, 15-18.

    Suggested Reading/Viewing:

    Ashley, Benedict M., OP; and Kevin D. O'Rourke, OP (1989), Health Care Ethics. St. Louis: Catholic Health

    Association of the United States, especially re ethical methodologies, norms of Christian decision in

    bioethics, and organ transplantation.

    Catholic Health Association of Canada (1991). Health Care Ethics Guide. Ottawa, especially pp. 42-47.

    Human Organ Procurement and Exchange Program [HOPE] (1991). "Have You Considered Organ

    Donation" (Video, 11 minutes). Edmonton: University of Alberta Hospitals. HOPE also has available other

    relevant videos and up-to-date educational literature.

    Law Reform Commission of Canada (1992). Procurement and Transfer of Human Tissues and Organs,

    Working Paper 66. Ottawa: Canada Communication Group - Publishing.

    Thomas, John E.; and Wilfrid J. Waluchow (1990). Well and Good: Case Studies in Biomedical Ethics,

  • 7/28/2019 Organ and Tissue Transplants

    32/32

    Revised Edition. Peterborough: Broadview Press, Cases 7:1, 7:3, 8:4, 9:1, 10:1, 10:2, and 12:6.

    Author's (Paul Flaman's) Home Page