philosophy and logic the process of correct reasoning

81
Philosop hy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Upload: dayna-marsh

Post on 18-Jan-2018

231 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

What is a “word”???

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Philosophy

and

LogicThe Process of

Correct Reasoning

Page 2: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Logic is the art & science ofcorrect reasoning

Analysis

Clarification

Evaluation

Words

Statements

Arguments

of

Page 3: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

What is a “word”???

Page 4: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Statements: anOFFICIAL definition

A statement (also known as a “proposition”) is a verbal expression* that is either true or false and that may therefore be either affirmed or denied.

*A verbal expression is an expression in words, either spoken or written.

Page 5: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Problem: Are statements(propositions) really verbal expressions?

Can’t I believe, for example, that “it is raining” without

saying or writing it?

Page 6: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

In other words,

can a

“propositional mental state” (i.e., a belief)

be considered a “statement” (in a sense)???

Page 7: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Another problem

There may be various verbal expressions of the same statement or proposition.

“It is raining.”

“Es regnet.”

“Il pleut.”

“Esta lloviendo.”

Page 8: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Still another problem

• Must a statement or proposition be either true or false? • What about “The

present King of France is bald” & “This sentence is false”???

Page 9: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

“The present King of France

is bald.”• If there is no present King of France, how

can it be true that he is bald?• But is it false that he is bald? In that case, it

would be true that he is “haired.” But how can that be since there is no King of France at present?

Page 10: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Louie the Bald

• “The present King of France is bald” is a sentence and therefore a verbal expression.

• Is it a statement?

• If so, then some statements are (APPARENTLY) neither true nor false.

Page 11: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

However, . . .

Page 12: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

the great 20th century philosopher, Bertrand Russell

(1872-1970), thought that “The present King of France is bald”

and “The present King of France is not bald” should be interpreted as follows:

Page 13: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

1. “There is a present King of

France, and he is bald.”

2. “There is a present King of

France, and he is not bald.”

According to Russell, both of thesestatements are false.

Page 14: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

P & Q

T T T

T F F

F F T

F F F

Page 15: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Is it possible that “The present King of France is

bald” is NOT a statement?

What do you think and why?

And how about . . . .

Page 16: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

“This sentence is false” ? ? ?

Page 17: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

If “This sentence is false” is true . . . .

• then it is false (because it truly states that it is false); and

• if it is false, then it’s true (again because it truly states that it is false).

• Is the sentence both true and false at the same time??? How can that be???

Page 18: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Very Hard Extra Credit Assignment:

Is the set of all sets that are not members of themselves

a member of itselfor not???

Page 19: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

What follows if it is?

And what follows if it isn’t?

Page 20: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Sets that are and sets that aren’t members of themselves:

• Most sets are NOT members of them-selves.

• E.g., the set of all cats is not a cat; the set of all tables is not a table; the set of all human beings is not a human being; & so on.

• But there ARE sets that ARE members of themselves.

• E.g., the set of all countable things is a countable thing; the set of all conceivable things is a conceive-able thing; & so on.

Page 21: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

But, once again,

is the set of all sets that are not members of themselves a

member of itself or not???

Page 22: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Well, anyway . . . .

let’s move on.

Page 23: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

For most or all PRACTICAL purposes, we can assume that a STATEMENT is a verbal expression that is EITHER TRUE OR FALSE and that may therefore be either affirmed or denied.

Now,

Page 24: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

having discussed words and statements,

let’s talk about ARGUMENTS.

The OFFICIAL DEFINITION of an ARGUMENT is as follows:

Page 25: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

An ARGUMENT is• a group, series, or set of STATEMENTS• in which one of the statements, known as

the CONCLUSION,• is claimed by the arguer to follow logically

(by way of INFERENCE) from the other statements in the argument,

• which are known as PREMISES• (and which the arguer claims to be TRUE).

Page 26: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

All arguments have the same basic structure or format:

1. Premise

2. Premise

3. Premise

4. Conclusion

Factual Claim (premises are true)

Inference

Inferential Claim - that the truth of the conclusion follows logically (by way of inference) from the ASSUMED truth of the premises

Page 27: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Factual Claim & Inferential Claim

• The factual claim in an argument is the claim, made by the arguer, that all of the premises in the argument are true (as opposed to false or unconvinc-ing).

• The inferential claim in an argument is the claim, made by the arguer, that the conclusion of the argument follows logically from its premises, assuming that the premises are true.

Page 28: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

How to (1) analyze and (2) evaluate an argument

Page 29: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

First, we need to find an argument to analyze and evaluate.

Page 30: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Suppose someone were to argue something really silly, like

Page 31: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

“All bats have two heads because all bats are kangaroos, and all kangaroos have two heads.”

Page 32: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

The argument must be subjected to a 6-step analysis & evaluation.

Step 1. Identify the conclusion.

Step 2. Identify the premises.

Step 3. Set the argument up in “standard form.”

These three steps constitute an “argument analysis.” An “argument evaluation” consists of the next three steps, which are:

Page 33: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Step 4. Evaluate the factual claim. Are the premises true, false, or unconvincing?

Step 5. Evaluate the inferential claim. Does the conclusion follow logically from the premises (assuming that they are true)?

Step 6. Evaluate the argument as a whole. Is it sound or unsound?

Page 34: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Let’s apply the six-step method to our sample argument about

kangaroos and bats.(1) All bats have two heads

because

(2) all bats are kangaroos

and

(3) all kangaroos have two heads.

Step 1. What’s the conclusion?

Page 35: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Step 1:Can you see that

the conclusion of the argument is

“All bats have two heads”

Page 36: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

and that the premises are

Step 2:

“All bats are kangaroos”

and

“All kangaroos have two heads”?

Page 37: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Step 3:

Thus, the logical (or “standard”) form of the

argument is

1. All kangaroos have two heads.

2. All bats are kangaroos.

3. All bats have two heads.

Page 38: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Or to put it more abstractly,

1. All K is T.

2. All B is K.

3. All B is T.

Page 39: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Two-

headed

things

Kangaroos

Bats

and even more

abstractly,

Page 40: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

We have now

• (1) identified the conclusion of the argument,• (2) identified the premises of the argument,

• and• (3) represented the argument in STANDARD FORM.

That is what is meant by an ARGUMENT ANALYSIS.

Page 41: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Now we need an

ARGUMENT EVALUATION.

Is the argument successful (“sound”)?

Page 42: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

For the argument to be “sound,”

the premises of the argument must be true (as opposed to false or unconvincing)

andthe conclusion of the argument must follow

logically from the premises (assuming that they are true).

Page 43: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Step 4: Are the premises of the argument true, or false, or unconvincing?

Premise 1: Is it true or are you convinced that “all kangaroos have two heads”?

Premise 2: Is it true or are you convinced that “all bats are kangaroos”?

Page 44: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

This step is easy (in this case).

It is obvious to anyone in her (or his)

right mind that both premises in

this argument are FALSE.

Page 45: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Another point about Step 4:

We need to explain WHY we think the premises are true, false, or unconvincing.

Page 46: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Step 5: But what about the INFERENCE (or INFERENTIAL

CLAIM) in this argument?

• Does the conclusion follow logically from the premises (assuming that they are true)?

• In other words,– IF all kangaroos were two-headed, and– IF all bats were kangaroos,– would it follow logically that all bats have two

heads?

Page 47: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

It would, wouldn’t it?

The inference (reasoning) in the argument is “good.” The conclusion does follow logically from the premises (on the assumption that the premises are true, which is an assumption we always make at Step 5).

Page 48: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Step 6: Is the argument as a whole “sound”?

Well, at Step 5 we saw that the inference (reasoning) in the argument

is good, but at Step 4

we found that both premises in the argument are false.

Page 49: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

For an argument to be sound,

all of its premises must be true (i.e., the “factual claim” in the argument must be justified) (Step 4),

and the inference in the argument must be good (i.e., the “inferential claim” in the argument must be justified) (Step 5).

Page 50: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

The argument we have been considering is UNSOUND because, although it contains good reasoning, at least one of its premises is not true.

Page 51: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

For an argument to be sound as opposed to unsound,

• both the factual claim and the inferential claim in the argument must be justified.

• If the factual claim is not justified (i.e., if at least one premise is false or unconvincing), then the argument is unsound.

• If the inferential claim is not justified (i.e., if the conclusion does not follow logically from the premises, assuming that they are true), then the argument is unsound.

Page 52: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

And, of course,

if NEITHER the factual claim NOR the inferential claim is justified (i.e., if the

argument fails on both counts),

then the argument is unsound.

Page 53: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Let’s now apply the six-step method of argument analysis and evaluation to a few simple (and unrealistic) arguments, beginning with this one:

All cats are animals, and all tigers are cats. Therefore, all tigers must be animals.

The argument contains three statements, right? Which one of them is the conclusion (Step 1)?

Page 54: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

All cats are animals, and all tigers are cats. Therefore, all tigers must be animals.

Step 2: What are the premises of this argument?

Step 3: What is the logical (“standard”) form of the argument? (See next slide)

Page 55: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

1. All cats are animals.

2. All tigers are cats.

3. All tigers must be (are) animals.

This is it, right?

Page 56: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Argument Evaluation

1. All cats are animals.

2. All tigers are cats.

3. All tigers are animals.

Step 4: Is the factual claim justified? That is, are both premises true (as opposed to false or unconvincing)?

Page 57: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Step 5: Does the conclusion follow logically from the premises?

1. All cats are animals.

2. All tigers are cats.

3. All tigers are animals.

That is, if all cats are animals, and if all tigers are cats, does it follow that all tigers are animals?

Page 58: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

If all cats are animals,

Animals

Page 59: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

and if all tigers are cats,

TigersCats

Animals

it looks like all tigers must be animals, right?

Page 60: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Step 6: Is the argument as a whole sound or unsound?

That is, are the factual claim and the inferential claim both justified? Are the premises true (Step 4), and does the conclusion follow logically from the premises (assuming that they are true) (Step 5)?

1. All cats are animals.

2. All tigers are cats.

3. All tigers are animals.

Page 61: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

What about the following argument?

Tigers must be cats because all cats are animals and all tigers are also animals.

Class Participation Exercise:

Write a six-step analysis & evaluationof this argument.

Page 62: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Here’s the STANDARD FORM of the argument:

1. All cats are animals.

2. All tigers are animals.

3. All tigers are cats.

Page 63: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

A possible misconceptionat Step 6

To prove that an argument is unsound is not to prove that its

conclusion is false.

Page 64: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Enthymemes,i.e., incompletely expressed arguments

Page 65: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Deductive vs. nondeductive (“inductive”) arguments

A deductive argument is one that contains a deductive inferential

claim.

A nondeductive (“inductive”) argument is one that contains a nondeductive inferential claim.

Page 66: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Deductive vs. nondeductive inferential claims

• A deductive inferential claim is the claim, made by the arguer, that the truth of the conclusion follows with the force of absolute logical necessity from the assumed truth of the premises.

• A nondeductive inferential claim . . . .

Page 67: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

. . . is the claim, made by the arguer, that the truth of the conclusion follows with some significant degree of probability from the assumed truth of the premises.

Page 68: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Deductive inferential claims are either “valid” or “invalid.”

Nondeductive inferential claims are either “strong” or

“weak.”

Page 69: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

A deductive inferential claim (or

argument) is validwhen the truth of its conclusion

follows necessarily from the assumed truth of its premises.

1. If Polly is a cat, then Polly is an animal.2. Polly is a cat.3. Polly is an animal.

is valid.

Page 70: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

A deductive inferential claim (or argument) is invalid

when the truth of its conclusion DOES NOT follow necessarily from the assumed

truth of its premises.1. If Polly is a cat, then Polly is an animal.

2. Polly is an animal.

3. Polly is a cat. is invalid.

Page 71: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

A nondeductive inferential claim

(or argument) is strong

when the truth of its conclusion follows with some significant degree of probability from the assumed truth of its premises.

Page 72: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

1. Millions of crows have been observed.

2. All of them have been black.

3. All crows are black (probably).

is strong.

Page 73: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

A nondeductive inferential claim

(or argument) is weakwhen the truth of its conclusion

DOES NOT follow with any significant degree of probability

from the assumed truth of its premises.

Page 74: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

1. The great majority of college

professors are politically liberal.

2. Patricia Quinn is a college

professor.

3. Patricia Quinn is (probably)

politically liberal. is weak.

Page 75: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Necessary & Contingent Statements

Page 76: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Statements (e.g., premises in an argument) are either true or false.

• However, some statements are necessarily true or false,

• while others are contingently true or false.• Thus, there is a distinction between

necessary and contingent statements (or propositions).

Page 77: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Necessary statements

• Necessarily true -- formal and informal tautologies

• Necessarily false -- formal and informal contradictions (re: the law of non-contradiction)

• A priori verification & falsification (i.e., verification or falsification by logical analysis alone (no empirical appeal)

Page 78: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Tautologies & contradictions

The negation of a tautology is a contradiction, and the negation of a

contradiction is a tautology.

Page 79: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Contingent statements

• Neither necessarily true (tautology) nor necessarily false (contradiction)

• True under some conditions; false under others

• A posteriori verification & falsification (i.e., verification or falsification on empirical grounds -- not by logical analysis alone -- & verification/falsification not always possible)

Page 80: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

Tautologies, contradictions, & contingent statements

The negation of a tautology is a contradiction; the negation of a

contradiction is a tautology; and the negation of a contingent statement is

neither a tautology nor a contradiction, but another contingent

statement.

Page 81: Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning

To Be

Continued . . . .