psychology o fwar

Upload: intan

Post on 01-Jun-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    1/13

    The New Psychology of War and PeacePsychology and Deterrence. by Robert Jervis; Richard Ned Lebow; Janice Gross Stein;Patrick M. Morgan; Jack L. SnyderReview by: James G. BlightInternational Security, Vol. 11, No. 3 (Winter, 1986-1987), pp. 175-186Published by: The MIT PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2538890.

    Accessed: 18/09/2012 11:50

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    The MIT Pressis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access toInternational Security.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=mitpresshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2538890?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2538890?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=mitpress
  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    2/13

  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    3/13

    International

    ecurity

    176

    The authors of Psychologynd

    Deterrencettempt o provide both a suitable

    framework or, nd historical xamples of,foreign olicymakers

    who let their

    hopes and fearsrun away with their ational udgment,

    many of whom

    were,

    like the Melians, ruined as a result.

    The

    impetus for writing his book may

    be

    put

    in two propositions: first,

    the psychological principles, which

    were well known to Thucydides, redis-

    covered by Freud, appropriated by contemporary ognitive science, and

    accepted by most educated people everywhere,

    eem to

    have almost

    totally

    eluded the grasp of the architects f political and military eterrence.Theo-

    ristsof deterrence re regarded by

    the

    authors

    of this volume as psycholog-

    ically nnocent n the extreme. Second, as RichardNed Lebow says, deter-

    rence remains the principle [sic] intellectual

    and policy bulwark against

    nuclear holocaust (p. 204). Thus, Lebow and his co-authors

    believe

    that

    attempts

    to

    deter nuclear

    war-to avoid the

    ultimatecatastrophe-are very

    deeply

    misinformed

    sychologically,

    o much

    so,

    in

    fact,

    hat

    presentpolicies

    of deterrencemay help toproduce thenuclear war they re designed tohelp

    avoid.

    Their

    sworn

    enemy,therefore,

    s

    not

    deterrence,

    ut

    deterrence

    heory,

    which they

    believe

    is based on

    a

    specious, pre-Freudian

    and, by implication,

    pre-Thucydidean)rational-actor sychologythat

    simplydoes not conform o

    the

    thinking

    and

    behavior

    of actual

    foreign policymakers.

    Psychology

    nd

    Deterrences at its core an argument

    that

    holds that the classical theory of

    deterrence ughtto

    be

    regarded

    as

    psychologically

    efuted nd thatwe must

    look

    in

    new, more psychologically

    nformeddirectionsfora safer approach

    to

    deterrence, specially

    nuclear

    deterrence.

    Beforeconfrontinghe argumentsof the revolutionaries,however, let us

    remind

    ourselves briefly

    f two of

    the

    central enets

    of

    the

    old

    regime,both

    of which are denied

    categorically y

    the

    authors

    of

    this

    volume.

    According

    to

    Thomas Schelling whom

    the authors of

    this volume

    regard

    as

    by

    far the

    most

    mportant xpositor

    of deterrence

    heory),

    deterrence is

    not concerned

    withthe

    efficientpplication f force

    but

    with the

    exploitationfpotentialorce.

    2

    This is uncontroversial

    but

    important:

    deterrence s

    alleged

    to

    be

    mainly

    about

    preventing

    war.

    Second, according

    to

    Schelling,

    the

    theory

    of deter-

    renceholds

    thathuman behavior s

    interdependent,

    he actions of adversaries

    being both cause and effect f one another's behavior. As Schelling says,

    Deterrence .. involves

    confronting

    . .

    [an

    adversary]

    with

    evidence that

    2.

    Thomas C.

    Schelling,

    The

    Strategy f ConflictCambridge,

    Mass.:

    Harvard

    University ress,

    1960), p. 5.

  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    4/13

    New

    Psychologyf

    Warand

    Peace

    177

    our behavior will be

    determinedby his behavior. 3These and related

    prop-

    ositions, which together

    have

    exertedenormous influence n the

    continuing

    debates about U.S. foreign olicy, re put forward y Schelling n the

    manner

    of

    general aws, according to which

    it s

    considered egitimate nd

    instructive

    to deduce completelyhypothetical onflicts etween disembodied,

    adversar-

    ial, international actors, who signal their ommitments redibly nd audi-

    bly to one another and who are deterred from ttackingonly because the

    net gain calculated to be derived

    fromnot attacking s greater.

    One of the

    defining haracteristics

    f

    genius

    is

    the

    capacity

    to

    shape

    not

    merely

    the content

    of debate,

    but

    to

    determine the

    terms,

    parameters,

    or

    contourswithin

    which debate takes

    place.

    This

    is

    certainly

    rue of

    Schelling,

    who

    in

    1960 admitted, for

    example,

    that the

    psychological study

    of

    conflict

    is a legitimateenterprisebut

    then promptlydeclared

    it

    out of

    bounds for

    serious

    students of

    international

    onflict.

    He

    decreed

    a

    main

    dividing

    ine

    ... between those that treatconflict s a pathological state and seek its

    causes

    and

    treatment,

    nd those that

    take

    conflict

    or

    granted

    and

    study

    the

    behavior

    associated

    with

    it. 4 n

    other

    words, according

    to

    Schelling,

    there

    ought

    to

    be a

    great

    divide between

    clinical

    and

    academic

    psychology,

    n the

    one

    hand,

    and

    the

    strategy

    f international onflict-of deterrence-on the

    other. That this

    great

    divide

    has

    been

    respected,

    even revered

    by

    students

    of international

    elations,

    no one can

    doubt. But the

    authors of

    Psychology

    and

    Deterrencery,

    n

    effect, o

    ignore Schelling's

    canonical

    dichotomy lto-

    gether

    and

    to

    begin

    to

    carve

    out

    a third

    way:

    a

    psychologically

    nformed

    approach to thepreventionof international onflict, hybridization hathas

    heretofore eemed all but impossible

    due

    to the hegemony of

    Schelling's

    great

    divide.

    Psychology

    s to be

    brought

    out of its closet and into

    contact

    with

    cases of successful

    and failed

    deterrence,

    ases

    that the

    old

    paradigm

    is

    held to

    be

    incapable ofexplaining. By openly acknowledging nd

    allowing

    forwhat

    theyregard

    as

    the

    ubiquitous irrationality

    f

    foreign olicy

    decision-

    making,

    the

    revolutionaries

    eek to

    construct more

    rational nd

    empirically

    robust theoryof

    deterrence.

    Robert

    Jervis

    eads off

    with

    two

    chapterscontaining

    wide

    array

    of

    briefly

    described

    cases, which

    he

    interprets

    n the

    light

    of some

    selected findings

    from ognitive psychology.

    His

    subject

    is

    bias

    in

    the

    perception

    of

    threats,

    and he

    divides

    the

    psychological

    domain of

    interest nto

    two

    types:

    unmo-

    3.

    Ibid., p. 13.

    4.

    Ibid., p.

    18.

  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    5/13

    Internationalecurity 178

    tivated

    bias, which occurs as

    a

    function f predispositions, timulus

    overload,

    and

    selective attention;

    nd

    motivated

    bias,

    in

    which inference

    s used as

    a

    defense mechanism, that is, as protectionagainst knowledge of risk

    and

    danger. As

    an

    example of unmotivatedbias

    or

    a shortcut to

    rationality p.

    23), Jervis ites nattention o

    base rates an

    idea derived

    from sychologists

    Amos Tversky nd Dan Kahneman).5Thatis, policymakers ften

    mistakenly

    estimate probabilitiesbecause they pay insufficientttention o

    the

    overall

    frequency f events, attending

    nstead only

    to the

    vividness

    of

    some

    referent

    case.

    For instance,

    the overreliance on the Munich

    Analogy

    and the re-

    sulting overestimationof

    threat s a

    function,Jervisbelieves,

    of

    failing

    to

    come

    to

    grips

    with the extreme

    rarity

    f leaders

    who

    are

    as

    deceitful,

    pow-

    erful,

    and

    aggressive as Hitler

    (p. 24). As

    an

    example

    of

    motivatedbias,

    Jervis ites the specious Japanese reasoning that ed to thebombingof Pearl

    Harbor. They believed, rather

    ncredibly ccording to Jervis,

    hat afterthe

    bombing,

    the United

    States would simply

    withdraw

    from

    he Pacific

    p. 26),

    a conclusion Jervisbelieves was motivated by a powerfulneed to avoid

    confronting

    he

    objectively

    more

    likely event,

    which

    was

    all-out

    war

    with

    the United

    States.

    The

    antidote

    to both

    sorts

    of bias

    and thus to erroneous

    threat

    perception and

    increased risk

    of

    the failure f deterrence s said to be

    the

    acquisition of

    a

    finer-grained

    nderstanding

    of one another's

    beliefs,

    perceptions,and values, a task that

    Jervis ully cknowledges

    is easier

    said

    than

    done

    (p. 33).

    If

    the value of

    this book resides very argely

    n

    itsargument

    for

    psycho-

    logically more empirical approach to deterrence,then the two case

    study

    chapters by JaniceGross Stein (on the October War of 1973) and one by

    Richard

    Ned Lebow (on

    the

    Falklands

    War

    of1982)must

    be

    regarded

    as,

    in

    important espects, the heart and

    soul of

    the

    volume. For

    it

    is

    in

    the

    thick

    texture f

    such

    extended case

    analyses

    that one

    must try o

    determine

    the

    nature, significance, nd extent

    of psychological bias, and theirrelation to

    the

    failure

    or maintenance of deterrence.

    Stein's chapters

    are

    marvelous

    evocations of the

    attitudes

    n both the

    Egyptian

    nd

    Israeli

    High Commands

    during

    the

    period

    1967-1973.

    The dual narratives

    re

    so

    thoroughly

    ompel-

    ling that one may actually feel as well

    as acknowledge

    intellectually

    he

    striking sychologicalparadox, which, Steinbelieves, provided the prereq-

    5. Daniel

    Kahneman, Paul

    Slovic,

    and Amos

    Tversky,Judgment

    nder

    Uncertainty:

    euristics nd

    Biases New

    York: CambridgeUniversity ress,

    1982).

  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    6/13

    New

    Psychologyf

    Warand Peace 179

    uisite to the October War of 1973. In assessing one's abilityto carryout a

    successful attack upon the other, according

    to

    Stein, Egypt could but

    thought t couldn't, while Israel thoughtEgypt

    could

    but wouldn't because

    Egypt thought t couldn't (p. 48). Because

    of

    Stein's

    deft

    weaving together

    of

    her

    sources, one sees

    in

    thisparadox

    not

    mere

    word play,

    but a

    formula

    fortragedy.

    n

    the end the Israelis paid

    too close

    attention

    o

    the

    military

    balance and were lulled by

    numerous false

    alarms

    caused by Egyptian

    mo-

    bilizations

    between

    1967

    and

    1973. They failed,

    n

    Stein's

    view,

    to

    appreciate

    how deeply intolerable he post-1967

    status

    quo was to Sadat and to Egypt.

    Most significantly, ccording

    to

    Stein,

    neither

    leadership can

    be

    said,

    as

    deterrence heorypredicts,

    to

    have

    responded

    to deterrent

    hreats, s they

    were

    understood by each

    deterrer.

    t

    was a

    dialogue of the deaf and the

    deafness,

    in

    her view, has

    a

    psychological explanation.

    Lebow's chapter on the

    Falklands

    War,

    while

    similar o Stein's

    in

    its osten-

    sible

    intent, s much harsher

    n

    tone

    and

    much

    more thoroughly piece of

    self-consciously sychological analysis. Lebow,

    so it

    seems,

    means to accuse

    as

    much as to analyze.

    There

    are

    no heroes

    in

    his account, nor scarcely ny

    ordinarily

    fallible

    people;

    there are

    only

    buffoons. Both

    the

    Thatcher

    and

    Galtieri

    governments, ccording

    to

    Lebow,

    must be deemed

    guilty

    f

    massive

    self-deception.

    n

    an

    extended

    passage

    of

    psychohistory,

    e

    accuses

    the

    Americans of paranoia (p. 114),

    the

    Argentinesof lack of sophistication

    (p. 116), and everyone concernedof selective attention p. 119) and per-

    ceptual

    distortion

    p. 119),

    the

    latter

    of

    which he believes was the real

    cause of

    the

    war

    (p. 119).

    In

    approaching

    the

    participants

    n

    this

    particular

    failure fdeterrence o harshly

    nd

    reductively, ebow appears to push the

    psychologizing

    of deterrence somewhat

    further han the other

    authors.

    In

    Lebow's causal

    account,

    the ssue

    perceived by

    the

    participants s

    that

    which

    led

    to

    the

    failureof deterrence-control of

    the

    Falklands/Malvinas slands-

    seems to fade

    into

    the

    background,

    while

    psychological

    breakdown is

    put

    forth s central.The

    logic

    of

    Lebow's

    argument

    would

    seem to ead

    ultimately

    to

    the view

    that,

    at least

    in the

    case of

    the Falklands War

    (but probably

    n

    other

    failures f

    deterrence s

    well),

    the relationof the

    student of deterrence

    to

    the

    participants

    n

    case studies is much

    like that

    of

    psychiatrist

    o

    patient,

    at

    least

    in the

    diagnostic phase. Lebow,

    it

    seems, would push

    the Freudian

    revolution

    ll the

    way so

    that the

    study of foreignpolicy decision-making

    becomes, eventually, something

    ike a branch of

    depth psychology.

    f

    this

    were ever

    to

    occur,

    the revolt

    against fully

    ational

    deterrence

    heory

    would

  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    7/13

    Internationalecurity 180

    have

    become total. Irrationalactors would replace

    rational actors in the

    analyses of international

    elations specialists, who would

    by then have bid

    goodbye to deterrence nd hello to

    psychology.

    The

    conclusions to the

    volume, contained

    in

    two chapters by Lebow, are

    boldly psychological.6First,

    Lebow argues

    that

    denial,

    selective attention,

    and

    other

    psychologicalsleights

    of

    hand

    (p. 173)

    are

    ubiquitous

    n

    situations

    when

    deterrence

    s on

    the line

    and

    that nternational

    ggression s

    far

    more

    a

    function

    f perceived need than of opportunity. ebow

    thus provides

    an

    extended

    gloss on his well-known rgument

    hat

    tates do not

    ump through

    windows

    of opportunity.As

    Lebow

    sees it,

    states

    or

    presumably

    their

    ead-

    ers) are

    best understood as turning

    nward rather han

    outward toward their

    own

    unresolved wishes

    and fears.

    They leap,

    one

    might

    say,

    into

    murky

    basements of felt need, rather than

    through

    windows

    of perceived oppor-

    tunity.7

    nd

    since the theory nd

    practice of deterrencehas heretofore m-

    phasized the

    arrangements equired

    for

    preventingwindows of

    opportunity

    from

    arising,

    it

    is no wonder,

    according

    to

    Lebow,

    that

    history

    s

    littered

    with

    failures

    of deterrence aused

    by misperception

    nd

    misunderstanding.

    In a

    thoroughly reudian

    argument,

    Lebow

    argues,

    in

    effect,

    hat

    such

    win-

    dows

    (hence rational deterrence

    tself)

    are

    illusions-manageable

    fantasies

    which are

    preferred o

    the

    frightening eality ctually

    faced

    by policymakers,

    especially in the

    nuclear age.8

    This

    is,

    in

    fact, exactly

    the form

    of Freud's

    argument

    gainst

    what he

    regarded

    as the illusion of

    religion.9

    6. Deliberately mittedfrom ritical onsideration re

    the

    two

    chapters

    hat

    mmediately recede

    the concluding chapters n

    Psychologynd Deterrence: atrickM. Morgan, Saving Face for the

    Sake of Deterrence, and JackL. Snyder, Perceptions

    of

    the SecurityDilemma

    in

    1914. This

    is done not because these essays

    are uninteresting r unimportant. n fact,they are

    neither.

    Morgan's discussion of the

    peculiarlyAmerican obsession with reputation r resolve is sugges-

    tive and compelling, and

    Snyder's typology of securitydilemmas involves many interesting

    examples of

    this

    central oncept ofpolitical cience.

    The

    problem,rather,

    s that

    ach is

    strikingly

    abstract nd

    deductive

    in the

    extreme nd thus almost totally

    t

    odds

    with the

    entirethrust f

    therestof the book, which is

    self-consciously oncrete nd inductive.

    n

    short, onsideredapart

    from hese anomalous chaptersbyMorgan and Snyder, he book advances

    a

    significant

    rgument

    for fundamental

    eorientation

    f

    thinking

    bout U.S.

    foreign olicy.

    But the

    chapters

    by Morgan

    and

    Snyder,for

    ll

    their ntrinsicnterest, nly qualify, bscure,and ultimately egatethe central

    methodological rgumentof thebook, which would thus have been farmorecoherentwithout

    them.

    7.

    Richard Ned Lebow, Windows of Opportunity:Do StatesJumpThrough

    Them?,

    Interna-

    tional ecurity, ol. 9, No. 1 (Summer 1984), pp. 147-186.

    8.

    RichardNed Lebow, Between eace

    and

    War:TheNature

    f nternationalrisis Baltimore:Johns

    Hopkins University ress, 1981).

    9.

    Sigmund Freud, The Futureof an Illusion,

    n

    James Strachey,trans. and ed., The

    Complete

    Psychological orks fSigmund

    reud,

    4

    vols. (London: Hogarth, 1966), Vol. 21, pp. 3-56.

  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    8/13

    New Psychologyf

    War

    nd Peace 181

    The policy conclusions to Psychologynd Deterrence

    re a

    curious

    mixture

    of

    sensible

    policy suggestions

    and

    pessimistic handwringing

    about what

    Lebow and his colleagues obviously regard

    as the

    very

    dim

    prospects for

    enacting such policies. The recommendationsfollowdirectly rom

    he

    psy-

    chological analyses: adopt

    a mixed

    strategy,

    s Lebow calls it

    (p. 227),

    in

    which threat nd reassurance

    are

    balanced, according

    to the best

    estimateof

    theneeds, fears,and goals of an adversary.Stein agrees completely, alling

    in

    her own conclusion fora balanced

    mixture

    f accommodation

    and

    coer-

    cion

    (p. 86).10

    Yet in concluding Psychologynd Deterrence,ebow quite obviously recog-

    nizes that he has arrived at a conceptual cul-de-sac.

    He

    demonstratescon-

    siderable intellectual

    courage

    in

    facing up

    to

    what is

    essentially

    a nihilistic

    conclusion. This is Lebow's paradox:

    Deterrence,which, relatively peaking, is easy to implement,may neverthe-

    less not be a very effective trategy f conflictmanagement,because it does

    not address the most important psychological] sources of aggression. On

    the

    other

    hand,

    efforts o

    alleviate the kinds of

    insecurities that

    actually

    encourage

    or even

    compel

    leaders to

    pursue aggressive foreignpolicies do

    not seem

    very ikelyto succeed. (p. 192)

    This is one of the most remarkablepassages in the book. For it repudiates

    the

    classical

    theory

    of

    deterrence

    because

    it

    s

    psychologicallyankrupt,

    while

    it leads us to believe that a psychologicallynformed pproach, while theo-

    retically afer, s probablypragmaticallyankrupt.

    The

    old view is wrongand

    thus

    dangerous;

    the new view

    is right

    but

    irrelevant.

    In

    fact,

    neither

    Lebow nor his coauthors nor,for

    hat

    matter, hisreviewer)

    can

    imagine

    a

    means for

    plausibly ntervening irectly

    nto

    the

    psychological

    lives of policymakers o as to reduce the intensity f the needs which seem

    to motivate

    many

    failures

    of

    deterrence.

    The

    psychological aboratory

    nd

    clinic are

    presently

    and

    very likely

    will remain terra

    ncognita

    for

    foreign

    policymakers.

    At the

    very

    end

    of

    the

    book,

    in

    partialflight

    rom

    he

    nihilistic

    terminus f

    his logic,

    Lebow

    suggests

    that

    perhaps

    we can learn

    important

    10. See Graham T. Allison, Albert Carnesale, and JosephS. Nye, Jr., ds., Hawks, Doves, and

    Ozvls:An Agenda for AvoidingNuclearWar (New York: Norton, 1985), p. 215. Indeed, such

    argumentswould seem to be fully onsistent

    with

    and to provide

    the

    psychologicalfoundation

    for

    he

    canonical endorsement

    of

    balanced deterrence nHawks,Doves,

    and

    Owls. The authors

    of

    that

    book recommendthe simultaneous avoidance

    of

    hawkishprovocation, neffectual ovish

    appeasement, and owlish paralysis. They conclude

    with a

    lengthy

    ist

    of concrete recommen-

    dations

    designed

    to achieve balanced deterrence nd thus to

    preventdangerous crises between

    thesuperpowers. See also JosephS. Nye, Jr.,NuclearEthicsNew York:Free Press, 1986), p. 119.

  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    9/13

    Internationalecurity182

    psychological essons from ome astonishing

    nd

    peaceful reversals

    n

    inter-

    national relations, especially that of Sadat in 1975. But this is exceedingly

    cold comfort or the psychological revolutionariesfor, s Stein points out,

    the key prerequisite to that initiativewas a bloodbath of proportions that

    were unacceptably abhorrent o both sides. Likewise with the superpowers,

    the countries whose sour relationship hovers like a cloud over this entire

    book. The Kennedy-Khrushchev peace initiative f 1963is

    almost unthink-

    able without the terrifying uban missile crisis of October

    1962. And

    so

    it

    goes:

    a

    book whose authors set

    out to

    conduct a psychological

    revolution

    ends

    by engaging

    n

    courageous

    but

    unequivocal conceptual

    self-destruction.

    What has

    gone wrong? Why

    have

    these

    psychological nalyses

    led

    to such

    pessimism?

    Let

    us

    first

    e

    clear about

    what is not wrong:

    the

    psychological

    analyses

    of

    deterrence

    n this volume

    are not uninteresting

    r

    implausible.

    In

    this thoroughly reudian era, very few people try o resist psychological

    explanations per se, and many of themput forth n this volume are very

    compelling.

    On the

    level

    of

    what

    is

    sometimes called politicalpsychology,

    therefore,

    he

    book must

    be

    regarded as a brilliant uccess. There is, one

    is

    inclined to conclude with the authors, a huge psychologicaldeficiency n the

    theory

    of rational deterrence.

    We

    see

    clearly that the theory does not put

    nearly enough emphasis on nonrational determinants f human thinking

    and

    behavior.

    The problem, rather,

    s

    one

    that

    s endemic to the entirefield of political

    psychology.As Stanley

    Hoffmannhas

    pointed out,while politics s wholly

    psychological, roposed solutions to (what may be regardedas importantly

    psychological) problems

    of war and

    peace must be wholly political. 1

    nd

    this

    means

    critically

    hat

    proposed

    solutions must be situated

    firmly

    within

    the

    cognitive

    ontext f the

    policymakers,who must come

    to believe

    that

    the

    proposals

    will

    help

    to solve

    what

    they egard as real problems

    of

    war and

    peace,

    of deterrence

    nd

    reassurance,

    not

    perceptual

    distortion

    r

    para-

    noia or other

    psychological problems.

    Lebow is

    correct

    to conclude

    that

    foreign olicymakers

    re

    quite unlikely

    o

    respond favorably,

    f

    theyrespond

    at

    all,

    to

    overtlypsychological proposals.12They

    are

    in

    fact

    ikely

    to

    regard

    11. Stanley Hoffmann, On

    the Political Psychology of

    War

    and

    Peace: A

    Critique

    and an

    Agenda, Political sychology, ol. 7, No. 1 (March 1986), pp. 1-21; quotation on p. 1.

    12. See J.P. Kahan,

    R.E.

    Darilek, M.H. Graubard, and N.C. Brown,with assistance fromA.

    Platt nd B.R.Williams, reventinguclear onflict: hat an theBehavioralciences ontribute?

    (Santa Monica, Calif.: Rand Corporation,1983);

    and

    Carnegie Corporation, Behavioral

    Sciences

    and the Preventionof Nuclear War (Mimeo, 1984).

  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    10/13

    NewPsychologyf

    War

    ndPeace

    1

    83

    such proposals as, in the felicitous phrasing of

    William

    James, so much

    mythological nd poetic talk about psychology

    and

    of no interest r rele-

    vance to them.13 o believe otherwisewould be mere wishful hinking f ust

    the sort that the authors of this volume find so ubiquitous and discomfiting

    in foreignpolicymakers.

    What can be done about Lebow's paradox?

    Is there a

    psychologically

    informed pproach to deterrence that is policy-relevant? here is indeed,

    although it is unlikely to satisfyeither psychologists

    or

    political scientists

    seeking to borrow disciplinary knowledge

    rom one another

    and

    apply

    it

    directly o pragmaticproblems of war and peace.

    As Lebow

    argues, this does

    not work. The findings of cognitive and clinical psychology,

    n

    all their

    multitudinous

    disciplinary orms,

    re

    unlikely

    o

    be

    helpful

    to

    policymakers.

    What

    would be helpful is

    a

    psychological approach

    that

    takes

    fully

    nto

    account the

    substantial

    nonrational

    component

    of

    deterrence but

    that

    is

    transparent, nconspicuous, and devoid of off-the-shelf

    olutions from

    psychology.Among psychologists,

    his

    pproach

    is called

    phenomenology,

    the studyof the streamof thought s

    it

    appears to

    the

    thinking

    nd

    perceiving

    subject.

    Its chief rchitectwas William

    James.14

    he

    goal

    of such an

    approach

    would

    be

    this in

    the

    phrasing of

    Paul

    Bracken):

    Instead

    of

    trying

    o

    change

    people

    ...

    [we

    should

    try]

    o

    change

    the

    premises

    of their

    decisions

    through

    ... removal of the threats

    that

    compel

    them

    to

    make irrevocable

    choices.... 15 One must be

    psychologically oncerned,

    but

    one must also

    provide genuine policy

    choices. This seems to be

    the most

    promisingway

    to

    avoid the

    psychological

    innocence of rational deterrence

    heory

    while also

    avoiding thepolicyirrelevanceofdisciplinary sychology.

    Toward the end of the Melian

    dialogue, Thucydides

    has the

    Athenians

    accuse the Melians of wishfulthinking, fretreating

    o illusion and thus

    to

    regarding

    what

    is out of sight [as] more certain

    than what

    is

    beforeyour

    eyes. '16

    The authors of

    Psychology

    nd

    Deterrence

    ake

    an

    analogous

    and

    13. WilliamJames,Letter o FrancisJ.Child,

    August 16, 1878, cited

    n

    Gay Wilson Allen, William

    JamesNew York: Viking, 1967), p.

    211.

    14. Extended arguments for a phenomenological

    psychology of

    war

    and

    peace

    and its debt

    to

    WilliamJames re in JamesG. Blight, How Might PsychologyContribute o ReducingtheRisk

    of

    Nuclear

    War?, PoliticalPsychology,n

    press;

    and

    Psychology

    and

    Reducing

    the Risk

    of

    Nuclear War: From Parallel Paths to Fruitfulnteraction, Journal f

    Humanistic

    sychology,

    n

    press.

    15. Paul Bracken, Accidental Nuclear War, in

    Allison et al., Hawks, Doves, and Owls, pp. 25-

    53; quotation on p. 52.

    16. Thucydides, PeloponnesianWar,p. 507.

  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    11/13

    International

    ecurity

    184

    convincingpoint

    about rationaldeterrence heorists

    nd

    practitioners.

    ut

    to

    complete the revolution

    n

    thinking

    bout

    deterrence,

    which

    requires

    not

    merelythe demolition of the old anti-psychology ut also construction f a

    new policy-relevant sychology,we must also apply the

    Athenianaccusation

    to Jervis, ebow, and Stein and urge them, along

    with all

    who study deter-

    rence, to begin the psychologicalanalysis

    where the

    policymaker egins

    and

    thus to ask first nd throughout not what is

    out

    of sight,

    supposedly

    buried

    in

    the deeply layered cognitiveprocesses of

    policymakers,

    ut

    rather

    what

    is before their

    yes, seeming

    to those who must

    make the

    decisions

    to pose threats o deterrence

    nd

    thus

    to

    peace.

    What

    would some such

    psychological approach

    be like that avoids coun-

    terproductive ependence

    on

    obscure

    psychological ssumptions

    and

    litera-

    tures and that also (like Psychologynd Deterrence)s focused

    centrally

    on

    avoidingnuclear

    war

    between

    the

    superpowers? Obviously,

    it

    is

    impossible

    in

    a

    relatively rief eview

    to

    be explicit

    bout all or

    many

    of the dimensions

    and

    emphases

    of

    a

    research

    program

    that meets these

    requirements.

    But to

    get

    the

    proper

    orientation nd to

    begin

    to ask the

    relevant

    questions,

    one

    can do no

    better

    han to follow

    up

    the

    psychological mplications

    f

    the main

    thesisofa previous book by Jervis:

    it

    is not

    an

    exaggeration to speak of the nuclear revolution. Unless

    a

    state

    has first-strikeapability, t s hard to see how having [what

    Paul Nitze

    calls]

    the advantage at the uppermost evel of violence helps.

    Indeed,

    it

    is even

    hard

    to tell what that means

    . . .

    [because] the side that s ahead is

    no

    more

    protected han the side

    that

    s behind.17

    If

    Jervis s correct, hen the nuclear revolution ought to have

    crystal

    lear

    psychologicalreality

    o leaders

    of the

    superpowers

    in

    those

    moments when

    they believe they face the actual, imminent though still

    contingent)proba-

    bility

    f nuclear

    war.

    This is

    exactly

    what we find

    n, for example, the Cuban missile crisis of

    1962: the

    psychological transformation f the

    nuclear

    revolution,described

    by Jervis,

    rommere ntellectual wareness of ts

    ogicalpossibility

    o

    intense,

    preoccupying

    fear of

    its operational consequences.

    Richard

    Neustadt has

    summarized this

    psychological

    shift

    n

    an

    apt aphorism:

    t

    is

    the

    awareness

    of

    the risk of

    irreversibility

    ecome

    rreparable. 1.8

    n

    moments

    of

    surpassing

    17.

    RobertJervis, he llogic fAmerican

    uclear trategyIthaca,N.Y.:

    CornellUniversity ress,

    1984), p. 58.

    18. Richard E. Neustadt,

    Presidential

    ower: The

    Politics

    f Leadership

    rom

    FDR to

    Carter

    New

    York:

    Wiley,1980), p. 158. (Italics n

    original.)

  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    12/13

    New

    Psychologyf

    War ndPeace

    1

    85

    nuclear danger, the

    technological evolutionnoted by Jervis eems to produce

    a psychological

    revolution,namely,

    that nuclear

    weapons are regarded sud-

    denly and

    unequivocally by political

    leaders

    as useless

    in

    the pursuit of

    political

    and

    militarygoals. During

    the

    crises

    in

    Berlin

    (1961)

    and Cuba

    (1962)-the only

    two war-threatening rises between the superpowers

    n

    the

    age of potential,

    mutual annihilation-President Kennedy

    and his

    closest

    advisers could not indeed deriveany concretemeaningfrom he calculation

    of their

    very arge)

    relativeadvantage

    in

    deliverable nuclear

    weapons.19

    Moreover, these instances

    of

    psychological

    nuclear revolutionhad

    conse-

    quences so important

    nd so well

    known that

    t

    s remarkable hat

    theyplay

    no role whatever

    in

    Psychology

    nd Deterrence. hief

    among these is the

    singular bsence

    from

    high-leveldecision-making

    f

    ust

    the sortsof

    psycho-

    logical biases,

    projections, paranoia,

    and so forth

    n

    which

    the decision-

    making during

    the Falklands

    and Middle East wars seems to

    the authors

    literally o be saturated.20 wareness

    of

    gravenucleardanger seems to have

    elicitednot only great fearbutalso greatcaution and enhanced psychological

    maturity.

    he evolution of

    presidential decision-makingduring

    the

    missile

    crisis,

    for

    example,

    is

    in

    large part

    the

    story

    of a

    group

    of

    nuclear

    pilgrims'

    progress toward an understanding

    of

    the

    predicament Khrushchev as

    in.

    Nothing

    resembling

    his sort of

    psychological

    evolution can

    be

    discovered

    in

    the

    case studies

    in

    Psychology

    nd

    Deterrence.

    n

    fact,psychological

    devolution

    in

    crises s theveritable ubject

    of the

    inquiry.

    The psychological

    incommensurability

    etween

    the

    nonnuclear

    and

    nu-

    clear

    cases

    poses grave

    doubts about

    the

    central,

    f

    somewhat

    implicit,goal

    of the book: to produce a more empirical approach to the studyof nuclear

    deterrence ymeans

    of a

    psychological nalysis

    of nonnuclear

    ases,

    of

    which

    we

    may

    have

    many and,

    at

    that, many

    that ran

    their

    course

    all

    the

    way

    to

    war.

    But

    the

    psychologies

    of

    these

    two

    sorts

    of events-nuclear and

    non-

    nuclear-seem

    almost

    to be the inverse

    of

    one

    another

    as, indeed,

    do

    the

    results.

    n

    each case

    examined

    in

    this

    book,

    war

    broke

    out,

    while we have

    yet

    to

    experience

    a

    war between

    the

    superpowers.

    19. See George Ball, McGeorge Bundy, Roswell Gilpatric,RobertMcNamara, Dean Rusk, and

    Theodore Sorensen, The Lessons of the Cuban Missile Crisis, Time, eptember27, 1982, pp.

    85-86. See

    also

    Marc Trachtenberg,

    The

    Influence

    of Nuclear

    Weapons

    in the

    Cuban Missile

    Crisis, nternationalecurity, ol. 10,

    No.

    1

    (Summer 1985), pp.

    137-163.

    20. Irving . Janis, roupthink:sychologicaltudiesf olicy ecisionsnd iascoesBoston: ough-

    ton Mifflin, 982), pp. 123-158. See also Alexander L. George,

    The

    Cuban Missile

    Crisis, 1962,

    in AlexanderL. George, David K. Hall, and William E. Simons, The Limits fCoercive iplomacy:

    Laos, Cuba, Vietnam Boston: Little,Brown, 1971), pp. 86-143.

  • 8/9/2019 Psychology o fWar

    13/13

    International

    ecurity

    186

    Thus, in addition to questions of policy, any psychological nquiry nto

    nuclear deterrencemust also address these issues: first,what, if any, rele-

    vance have nonnuclear cases to nuclear cases in the era of mutual, potential

    annihilation? t appears that, even when viewed within the somewhat re-

    ductive psychological categories favored by the authors of Psychologynd

    Deterrence,he connections

    do not exist.

    Second,

    what

    should be the focus

    of a psychological approach to nuclear crisis decision-making?

    A

    central

    feature,

    t

    appears, ought

    to be the

    ways

    in

    which situational variables

    interactwith what Jervis alls the nuclear revolution o produce heightened

    awareness of ts mplications

    n

    crises. Consistent

    with

    thisorientationwould

    be the avoidance of what is,

    in

    effect, psychology of misperceptions,

    miscalculations, and other presumedly psychologically

    based

    mistakes of

    leaders. It ought to be replaced with a psychology of the evolving fear of

    such

    mistakes, which is

    an

    entirely

    different ort

    of

    inquiry,

    one

    requiring

    far

    ess borrowing frompsychological

    iteratures

    nd

    nonnuclear cases and

    far

    more attention to the nature, structure,

    nd

    pace

    of

    the

    psychological

    evolutionof eaders

    in

    nuclear crises.

    This

    means, finally,

    hatwe must return

    to the study of Berlin n 1961

    and

    most

    of all

    to

    Cuba in

    1962

    to

    decipher

    why, unlike the outcomes of

    the cases discussed

    in

    Psychology

    nd

    Deterrence,

    the United States and the Soviet Union did notgo to war during those deep

    crises. n

    short, n order

    to meet the

    valid

    demand for more

    empirical,

    ess

    deductive approach to nuclear deterrence,

    new sort of mmersion

    n

    psy-

    chology

    s

    required-not

    immersion

    n

    psychological iteratures,

    ut

    rather

    imaginative mmersion nto theway nucleardanger

    looks and feels to those

    who must

    try

    o

    manage

    it.