pwaug11critical 18/7/11 15:47 page 17 physicsworld.com ...steven weinberg’s chapter “against...

1
“Philosophy is dead.” So say the venerable physicists Stephen Hawking and Leonard Mlodinow on the first page of their recent bestselling book, The Grand Design. Physicists declaring philosophy to be life- less is nothing new. In his 2010 book In Praise of Science: Curiosity, Understanding, and Progress, Sander Bias likened philosophers’ discussions of science to doctors who diag- nose patients before considering symptoms. In a 2004 New Scientist article, Simon Singh said that scientists do not need philosophers any more than birds need ornithologists. Steven Weinberg’s chapter “Against philo- sophy”, in his classic 1992 book Dreams of a Final Theory, needs no explanation. Why do physicists so often, and confid- ently, condemn a field that is not their own? Where are their instincts to be inquisitive, resist overstepping what they know, withhold judgment until certain and accompany claims with error bars? The evidence that Hawking (using his name as shorthand) cites is essentially the following. Questions such as, “How can we understand the world in which we find our- selves?” and “How does the universe behave?” are traditionally considered to be philosophical. But because philosophers have not kept up with scientists in their answers, therefore “Scientists have become the bearers of the torch of discovery in our quest for knowledge.” No. Philosophers (including myself) approach such questions differently. What philosophy does For philosophers, the world includes more than physical matter. As the Harvard University philosopher Steven Shapin writes in his book, Never Pure, “Plants photosyn- thesize, plant biochemists are experts in knowing how plants photosynthesize, [while] reflective and informed students of science are experts in knowing how plant bio- chemists know how plants photosynthesize.” In other words, the world studied by science researchers includes not just objects, but also connections between scientists and objects. Human beings, after all, engage with the world in different ways. They seek wealth, fame, pleasure, companionship, happiness and other “good” things. They do this as chil- dren, adolescents, parents, merchants, ath- letes, teachers and administrators. All these methods arise through modifications of a matrix of ways by which human beings prac- tically connect to the world that precedes any cognitive understanding. The technical term philosophers use for this matrix is the “life- world”. But scientists are not like plants whose product is knowledge. Plants do not plan to follow laws of nature and do not inter- pret themselves. Human beings, however, do interpret both the world and themselves. The technical term philosophers use for human self-interpretation is “hermeneutics”. Understanding photosynthesis, for instance, is only one – rare – way for human beings to interact with plants. Hawking’s the- oretical stance as an observer of fundamen- tal structures, too, is only one way for humans to engage with the world, and not the default setting either. Humans are not automatic information absorbers; they must be trained to approach the world as he does. They have to pay a special kind of attention, pursue a special kind of inquiry and find that inquiry valuable. The lifeworld is the domain to which philo- sophers bring their torch of discovery. They study similarities and differences between various modes of being in the world – their group structures, if you will – and how each arises out of the lifeworld. To study this is not to undermine or critique these activities, but to understand and help cultivate them. But the lifeworld – a kind of horizon struc- tured by powerful metaphors, images and deeply embedded habits of thought – has its own character that changes over time. Philosophers – and here they differ from other students of science – do not and can- not adopt a “view from nowhere”, in a phrase popularized by New York University philosopher Thomas Nagel, but seek to be reflective. When philosophers think about science, they struggle to be self-aware of that horizon and how it affects human self-inter- pretation. This is why the humanities matter, for they study and help reshape the lifeworld. Without ornithologists, wrote one astute respondent to Singh’s New Scientist article, many bird species, in these ecologically trou- bled times, are heading for extinction. Why it’s misunderstood It is easy to misunderstand what philosophy does, for several reasons. First, like much of physics, philosophy often has a narrow focus and is concerned with special topics or technical issues, whose place in the big picture may not be easy for an outsider to see. Much philosophy of sci- ence is thin or even anorexic and does not flesh out all of the ways in which science is embodied in the world. Second, the lifeworld – like any horizon – tends to drop out of view. It is overlooked in favour of the objects, plans and goals that appear in and thanks to that horizon. That is perfectly understandable; detecting the hori- zon and its impact on our lives is the philo- sopher’s special task. Finally, the particular character of the modern world is that the very successes of science lead us to think that only the meas- urable is worthwhile. The messy, often inchoate lifeworld is bound to seem not only less distinct and valuable, but also less tangi- ble and real, than the grandeur of the designs uncovered by Hawking and others. The critical point On the first page of his book Subtle is the Lord…, the physicist Abraham Pais reports a discussion with Einstein in which the latter asked Pais if he “really believed that the Moon exists only if I look at it”. One could hardly think of a deeper, more challenging question about the concept “to exist”. Yet Pais smoothly characterizes the conversation as “not particularly metaphysical”. Discuss- ing the meaning of reality is okay, evidently, so long as it is done in an amateur way. So is philosophy dead? No; it will live as long as science does. When will physicists stop misunderstanding it? Probably never. But those who are ignorant of philosophy are destined to commit a bad version of it. Robert P Crease is chairman of the Department of Philosophy, Stony Brook University, and historian at the Brookhaven National Laboratory, US, e-mail [email protected] Critical Point Philosophy rules You might not understand what philosophers do for a living, but that does not mean their work is meaningless. Robert P Crease tires of hearing physicists trying to kill his profession Alive and kicking Philosophy has moved on and remained current since the time of Plato’s Academy in Athens, despite physicists’ assertions to the contrary. Photolibrary/DEA/G Cigolini/The Room of the Signature by Raphael, 1509 physicsworld.com Comment: Robert P Crease 17 Physics World August 2011

Upload: others

Post on 09-Jul-2020

2 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: PWAug11critical 18/7/11 15:47 Page 17 physicsworld.com ...Steven Weinberg’s chapter “Against philo-sophy”, in his classic 1992 book Dreams of a Final Theory, needs no explanation

“Philosophy is dead.” So say the venerablephysicists Stephen Hawking and LeonardMlodinow on the first page of their recentbestselling book, The Grand Design.

Physicists declaring philosophy to be life-less is nothing new. In his 2010 book In Praiseof Science: Curiosity, Understanding, andProgress, Sander Bias likened philosophers’discussions of science to doctors who diag-nose patients before considering symptoms.In a 2004 New Scientist article, Simon Singhsaid that scientists do not need philosophersany more than birds need ornithologists.Steven Weinberg’s chapter “Against philo-sophy”, in his classic 1992 book Dreams of aFinal Theory, needs no explanation.

Why do physicists so often, and confid-ently, condemn a field that is not their own?Where are their instincts to be inquisitive,resist overstepping what they know, withholdjudgment until certain and accompanyclaims with error bars?

The evidence that Hawking (using hisname as shorthand) cites is essentially thefollowing. Questions such as, “How can weunderstand the world in which we find our-selves?” and “How does the universebehave?” are traditionally considered to bephilosophical. But because philosophershave not kept up with scientists in theiranswers, therefore “Scientists have becomethe bearers of the torch of discovery in ourquest for knowledge.”

No. Philosophers (including myself)approach such questions differently.

What philosophy doesFor philosophers, the world includes morethan physical matter. As the HarvardUniversity philosopher Steven Shapin writesin his book, Never Pure, “Plants photosyn-thesize, plant biochemists are experts inknowing how plants photosynthesize, [while]reflective and informed students of scienceare experts in knowing how plant bio-chemists know how plants photosynthesize.”In other words, the world studied by scienceresearchers includes not just objects, but alsoconnections between scientists and objects.

Human beings, after all, engage with theworld in different ways. They seek wealth,fame, pleasure, companionship, happinessand other “good” things. They do this as chil-

dren, adolescents, parents, merchants, ath-letes, teachers and administrators. All thesemethods arise through modifications of amatrix of ways by which human beings prac-tically connect to the world that precedes anycognitive understanding. The technical termphilosophers use for this matrix is the “life-world”. But scientists are not like plantswhose product is knowledge. Plants do notplan to follow laws of nature and do not inter-pret themselves. Human beings, however, dointerpret both the world and themselves. Thetechnical term philosophers use for humanself-interpretation is “hermeneutics”.

Understanding photosynthesis, forinstance, is only one – rare – way for humanbeings to interact with plants. Hawking’s the-oretical stance as an observer of fundamen-tal structures, too, is only one way forhumans to engage with the world, and notthe default setting either. Humans are notautomatic information absorbers; they mustbe trained to approach the world as he does.They have to pay a special kind of attention,pursue a special kind of inquiry and find thatinquiry valuable.

The lifeworld is the domain to which philo-sophers bring their torch of discovery. Theystudy similarities and differences betweenvarious modes of being in the world – theirgroup structures, if you will – and how eacharises out of the lifeworld. To study this is notto undermine or critique these activities, butto understand and help cultivate them.

But the lifeworld – a kind of horizon struc-tured by powerful metaphors, images anddeeply embedded habits of thought – has itsown character that changes over time.Philosophers – and here they differ from

other students of science – do not and can-not adopt a “view from nowhere”, in aphrase popularized by New York Universityphilosopher Thomas Nagel, but seek to bereflective. When philosophers think aboutscience, they struggle to be self-aware of thathorizon and how it affects human self-inter-pretation. This is why the humanities matter,for they study and help reshape the lifeworld.Without ornithologists, wrote one astuterespondent to Singh’s New Scientist article,many bird species, in these ecologically trou-bled times, are heading for extinction.

Why it’s misunderstoodIt is easy to misunderstand what philosophydoes, for several reasons.

First, like much of physics, philosophyoften has a narrow focus and is concernedwith special topics or technical issues, whoseplace in the big picture may not be easy foran outsider to see. Much philosophy of sci-ence is thin or even anorexic and does notflesh out all of the ways in which science isembodied in the world.

Second, the lifeworld – like any horizon –tends to drop out of view. It is overlooked infavour of the objects, plans and goals thatappear in and thanks to that horizon. That isperfectly understandable; detecting the hori-zon and its impact on our lives is the philo-sopher’s special task.

Finally, the particular character of themodern world is that the very successes ofscience lead us to think that only the meas-urable is worthwhile. The messy, ofteninchoate lifeworld is bound to seem not onlyless distinct and valuable, but also less tangi-ble and real, than the grandeur of the designsuncovered by Hawking and others.

The critical pointOn the first page of his book Subtle is theLord…, the physicist Abraham Pais reportsa discussion with Einstein in which the latterasked Pais if he “really believed that theMoon exists only if I look at it”. One couldhardly think of a deeper, more challengingquestion about the concept “to exist”. YetPais smoothly characterizes the conversationas “not particularly metaphysical”. Discuss-ing the meaning of reality is okay, evidently,so long as it is done in an amateur way.

So is philosophy dead? No; it will live aslong as science does. When will physicistsstop misunderstanding it? Probably never.But those who are ignorant of philosophy aredestined to commit a bad version of it.

Robert P Crease is chairman of the Department of Philosophy, Stony Brook University, and historian at the Brookhaven National Laboratory, US, e-mail [email protected]

Critical Point Philosophy rulesYou might not understand whatphilosophers do for a living, butthat does not mean their work ismeaningless. Robert P Crease

tires of hearing physicists tryingto kill his profession

Alive and kicking Philosophy has moved on andremained current since the time of Plato’s Academy inAthens, despite physicists’ assertions to the contrary.

Phot

olib

rary

/DEA

/G C

igol

ini/

The

Roo

m o

f th

e Si

gnat

ure

by R

apha

el,

1509

physicsworld.com Comment: Robert P Crease

17Physics World August 2011

PWAug11critical 18/7/11 15:47 Page 17