social ecology

Upload: abdul-ghaffar

Post on 10-Oct-2015

19 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    1/68Harbinger - SPRING2003 {1 }SPRING 2003

    What is Social Ecology?

    Harbinger

    a journal of social ecology

    VOL. 3, NO. 1

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    2/68{2 } Harbinger - SPRING2003

    Harbinger is published occasionallyby the Institute for Social Ecology,1118 Maple Hill Road, Plainfield, VT,05667, USA. Telephone / Fax.: 1 (802)

    454-8493. Email: [email protected]. All material within thepages of Harbingeris copyright bythe author. Reproduction of anymaterial within these pages isauthorized only if the source isindicated and the author hasgranted permission. Opinionsexpressed by the authors do notnecessarily reflect those of theInstitute for Social Ecology.

    Subscriptions: Voting members ofthe Institute for Social Ecology will

    receive subscriptions to Harbinger.Supporters of the ISE who donate$50 US are entitled to receive thenext two issues; $200 US the next

    four issues; $500 US the next eightissues; and $1,000 US the nextsixteen issues.

    Change of Address: Please notifyus of an address change at least fourweeks before your move (the postoffice does not forward magazines).

    Cover Art: This issues cover artcomes to us from the Canada basedcommunity mapping projectCommon Ground and artist GordSeward.

    Colophon:

    Harbingeris printed onWeyerhaeuser Huskey Offset (text)and Springhill Vellum Bristol (cover).The text paper stock includes 30%

    postconsumer content, and the coverincludes 20%. All inks used inHarbingerare soy-based. This issue,at a total run of 600 copies, used twotrees worth of paper (according toP.A.P.E.R.s Paper Wizard). Printed inthe U.S.A. by Alonzo EnvironmentalPrinting, Hayward, CA.

    publishes analysis relevant to the growing social ecology movement and newsof the activities of the Institute for Social Ecology (ISE). It is our intentionto explore the theory and practice needed to help create an ecological society,and to cultivate a generous intellectual outlook that can inform the principleof hope. Just as the outlook proposed by social ecology is concerned with

    both what is and what ought to be, so too is Harbinger and we will explore thetensions between the two. The central questions we address in the pages ofHarbinger regard the process with which we must engage to create anecological society, a society free of hierarchy and domination in all of itsforms.

    A harbinger is a messenger, or a sign indicating that a major event orchange is coming. It was the name given to the journal published byEmerson, the Alcotts, Thoreau and other New England transcendentalistsassociated with Brook Farm in the 19th century. The name was revived inthe early 1980s by the ISE for our literary and philosophical journal. In itscurrent incarnation Harbinger will continue the tradition of criticallyexamining theory and practice, attempt to bring you stimulating work by

    talented authors, and, in addition, update you on the important work of theISE. Our intention is to publish twice a year and we invite your commentsand contributions. While Harbinger will entertain many points of view, ourprimary focus will be on a clarification and expansion of those ideas andpractices that contribute to social ecology. We encourage passionatediscourse tempered by rationality and a radical intentnothing less than thetransformation of our destructive, anti-ecological society.

    Harbinger is a utopian project, but not utopia in the sense of anunachievable cloud-cuckoo land. Rather what we explore are utopian ideasrooted in real, existing potentialities. In the words of social ecologist MurrayBookchin, we seek to Be realistic and do the impossible, because if we dontdo the impossible, we face the unthinkable. Harbinger will examine ideas

    that can allow us to transcend the given, to expand our intellectualframeworks, to give voice to our highest aspirations and our dreams for adecentralized, directly democratic, mutualistic and ecological society.I

    Harbinger, a Journal of Social Ecology,

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    3/68Harbinger - SPRING2003 {3 }

    Welcome to the latest issue of Harbinger, a Journal ofSocial Ecology. This issue has been a long time coming, butwell worth the wait. Our goal, to inform and inspire those

    actively pursuing an ecological society rooted in decentralist, directlydemocratic ideals, is clearly expressed in the articles that make up this

    issue. The thematic core focuses on the vision of social ecology, asexpressed by Peter Staudenmaier, and its relationship to new

    understandings in evolutionary theory. Murray Bookchin, the seminaltheorist of social ecology, provides an historical overview of the issues thathe faced when he first started fleshing out these ideas as far back as the1950s. For social ecology, nature is natural evolution, an ongoing dialecticof change and growth. Biologist Sonia Schmitz offers an assessment of thedialectical naturalism of Bookchin based on her interpretation of neo-Darwinian theory. Additionally Bookchin offers his vision for a newpolitics rooted in the ideas of social ecology, The Communalist Project.

    The history of the Institute for Social Ecology is explored in a timeline

    of the 29 year history of the ISE, and Brian Tokar examines the significantimpact of social ecology on social movements from the 1960s to thepresent. A related series of articles looks at promising contemporarymovements that articulate their visions of direct democracyDemocraticAlternative, from Norway, and the North American based Alliance forFreedom and Direct Democracy.

    We also review the latest developments at the Institute for SocialEcology, including a preview of upcoming programs and an update on ISEprojects.

    Harbinger will continue to publish on an occasional basis, and to bringyou the latest developments in the theory and practice of social ecology, aswell as news of the ISE. We hope that you find this issue interesting and

    informative.I

    Daniel Chodorkoff

    PUBLISHEDBY

    Institute for Social Ecology

    Popular Education for a Free Society

    1118 Maple Hill Road,Plainfield, VT 05667 USA

    www.harbinger.ws

    Harbingera journal of social ecologyMANAGINGEDITOR

    Michael Caplan

    ADVISORYBOARDDan Chodorkoff

    Chuck MorseErin Royster

    Sonja SchmitzBrian Tokar

    PRINT& WEB DESIGNMichael Caplan

    COPYEDITORErin Royster

    CONTRIBUTORSTOTHISISSUEAFADD,

    Beehive Design Collective,

    Murray Bookchin,Michael Caplan,Dan Chodorkoff,

    Andrea del Moral, Cliff Harper,

    Democratic Alternative,Eirik Eiglad, Mike Flugennock,

    nico, Jared Rogness, Erin RoysterSonja Schmitz, Gord Seward,Peter Staudenmaier, Brian Tokar

    Ingrid Young

    SPECIALTHANKSClaudia Bagiackas, Janet Biehl,Michael Cuba, Arthur Foelsche,

    Heidi Hunt of Mother Earth Newsand the many ISE supporters whodonated to support this project!

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    4/68{4 } Harbinger - SPRING2003

    3 Editorial

    67 Call for Contributions

    WHAT I S SOCIAL ECOLOGY?

    6 Reflections:An Overview of the Roots of Social

    Ecologyby Murray Bookchin

    A personal account on the birth of socialecology.

    12 Economics in a Social-Ecological Societyby Peter StaudenmaierWhat would economics look like in anecological society? How might freecommunities arrange their livelihood?

    16 Buttercups and Sunflowers:On the Evolution of First and Second

    Natureby Sonja Schmitz

    Healing the seemingly disparate relationshipbetween nature and culture by reminding us ofthe developmental relationship between them.

    20 The Communalist Projectby Murray Bookchin

    A radical politics for the twenty-first century.

    A H I S T O RY O F T H E I S E

    A celebration of close to thirty years of educationand activism committed to the social andecological transformation of society.

    38 Education and Community Action:A History of the ISEs ProgramsHow the Institute for Social Ecology haschanged the world through its educationalprograms and community involvement.

    44 Social Ecology and Social Movements:From the 1960s to the Presentby Brian Tokar

    Exploring the important role of the Institute forSocial Ecology in many of the pivotal social andecological movements of the past four decades

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    5/68Harbinger - SPRING2003 {5 }

    CONTENTStable ofVolume Three - Number One

    CO N T E M P O RA RY M O V E M E N T S

    50 Radical Alternatives:An Interview with Ingrid Youngby Michael Caplan

    A discussion on a democratic alternative forScandinavia.

    54 Alliance for Freedom and DirectDemocracybyAFADD

    Building a movement for confederal directdemocracy.

    Andrea del M

    RE P O RT F RO M M A P L E H I L L

    56 Directors Report

    57 2003 Spring & Summer Programs

    63 2003 Development Goals

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    6/68{6 } Harbinger - SPRING2003

    THEEXTENTTOWHICHRADICALVERSIONSOFENVIRONMENTALISMUNDERWENTsweeping metamorphoses and evolved into revolutionary ideologies when theNew Left came of age is difficult to convey to the present generation, which hasbeen almost completely divorced from the ebullient days of the New Left, not tospeak of all the major problems in classical socialism, especially in its Marxist

    form. These changes burden us to this very day.In fact, the way in which the New Left initially reacted to my writings on

    social ecology, even to such manifesto-type articles as my Ecology andRevolutionary Thought(1964), was very similar to the way my comrades of theOld Left would have reacted in the 1930s. Perhaps the most sophisticatedleftist movement of the sixtiesand certainly the most arrogant, namely, the

    French Situationists and their American hangers-onwitlessly denounced meas Smokey the Bear(a childlike symbol of the US Forest Service!), soirrelevant was the issue of humanitys place in the natural world to the Left of

    the sixties. Accordingly, I was asked repeatedly where the class struggle waslocated in my writingsas though the class struggle was not implicit ineverything I wrote!after which I was lectured on how Marx and Engels werereally firm adherents of the very views for which I had been denounced a fewyears earlier. My dogmatic opponents of the Left began to shift their ground bytrying to fit environmental issues into such frameworks such as the importance

    of conservation in Marx and Engelss writings. In short, the Left had beenoblivious to ecological issues, which were merely regarded as a petty bourgeoisendeavor to redirect public attention away from a hazy need to abolish

    capitalism pure and simple!This criticism, to be sure, was not without a certain measure of truth.

    Anything resembling a sociallyoriented ecology, such William Vogts OurPlunderedPlanetin the fifties and especially Rachel Carsons SilentSpringin1962, was more concerned with the impacts of human population growth andthe loss of wildlife in an increasingly industrialized world than with the material

    welfare of humanity and the impact of hierarchy on attempts to create arational society. In some respects, ecologists were inspired by the reactionarymotifs raised by Ernst Haeckel, who created the word ecology in the 1880s,notably the harm produced by humanity on the planet rather than the effectsof the capitalist system in producing ostensibly biological problems. AlthoughCarson attacked the chemical industry for promoting the use of toxic pesticides,

    perceptive readers could see that she was more concerned with their impact onbirds than on people. Nor did she and other ecological critics examine thesocially and negativelysystemic sources that produced a growing disequilibriumbetween nonhuman nature and society. She and her fellow ecological criticsoften seemed to think in terms of an abstract humanity (whatever thatsocially ambiguous word means) as distinguished from classes. To Carson andher admirers, it was not a specific social ordernamely, capitalism andentrepreneurial rivalrythat was responsible for the ecological destruction thatwas undermining the biosphere but immoral human behavior.

    ReflectionsAn Overview of the Roots of Social Ecology

    By Murray Bookchin

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    7/68Harbinger - SPRING2003 {7 }

    By contrast, social ecology completely inverted themeaning and implications of societys interaction withthe natural world. When I first began to use the rarelyemployed term social ecology during 1964 in my essay,Ecology and Revolutionary Thought, I emphasizedthat the ideaof dominating nature has its origins in thevery realdomination of human by humanthat is, in

    hierarchy. These status groups, I insisted could continuetoexistevenif economicclasseswereabolished.

    Secondly, hierarchy had to be abolished byinstitutionalchanges that were no less profound and far

    reaching than those needed to abolish classes. Thisplaced ecology on an entirely new level of inquiry andpraxis, bringing it far above a solicitous, often romanticand mystical engagement with an undefined natureand a love-affair with wildlife. Social ecology wasconcerned with the most intimate relations between

    human beings and the organic world around them.Social ecology, in effect, gave ecology a sharp

    revolutionary and political edge. In other words, wewere obliged to seek changes not only in the objectiverealm of economic relations but also in the subjectiverealm of cultural, ethical, aesthetic, personal, andpsychological areas of inquiry.

    Most fundamentally, these relations exist at the verybase of all social life: notably, the ways in which we

    interact with the natural world, especially through labor,even in the simplest forms of society, such as tribal andvillage stages of social formation. And certainly, if wehad major negative ecological disequilibria betweenhumanity and the natural world which could threatenthe very existence of our species, we had to understand

    howthese disequilibria emerged; what we even meant bythe word nature; how did society emerge out of thenatural world; how did it necessarily alienateitself from elemental natural relations; how andwhy did basic social institutions such asgovernment, law, the state, even classes emergedialectically from each other before humansociety came into its own; and in ways thatwent beyond mere instinct and custom, not to

    speak of patricentricity, patriarchy, and a host

    of similar cultural relations whose emergenceare not easily explained by economic factorsalone.

    BUT, ITWOULDBEANERRORTOVIEWTHE

    foregoing presentation of what I would call aminimal account of social ecology as the onlytheoretical source by which one can teach acourse on the subject. I did not develop socialecology only because I was disturbed by the

    nature versus society problem, although it was neverfar from my mind. Fundamentalto my development ofsocial ecology is a crisis that developed in socialisttheory itself, one that I regard as unresolvable in astrictly conventional Marxist or anarchist frameworkor to use the most all-encompassing phrase of all:proletarian socialism.

    This was a painful problem for me to cope withbecause I did not come to a belief in proletariansocialism as a result of an academic storm in a teacup. Iwas a very passionate participant in what I thought was

    a revolutionary labor movement, notably as a member ofthe Communist youth movement early in the 1930s andas result of a thorough training in Marxism andBolshevism. I became a rank-and-file leader of theYoung Communist League as early as 1933 and wasmilitantly loyal to its ultra-revolutionary program (the

    reckless insurrectionism promulgated by the CommunistInternational in 1928, or so-called Third Period line).

    Stalin had yet to make his reputation as the major figurethat he became in the late thirties; accordingly, mycomrades and I of that period never regarded ourselvesas Stalinists but simply as committed Communists orMarxists who adhered to Lenins revolutionary views.

    As a result, I was thoroughly, even intensivelytrained in classicalMarxism. This background provided

    me with a unique insight into problems that, whileforgotten at present by young radicals, haunts all of theirsocial projects. Born when the Russian Revolution wasstill a recent event; when Makhno was still carrying onhis guerrilla war in Ukraine; when Lenin, Trotsky, andnearly all the major theorists and activists of the first

    three decades of the century were still fairly young men;I had the rare chance to imbibe all the fundamental

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    8/68{8 } Harbinger - SPRING2003

    issues and live through most of the great civil conflictsof the erafrom the still buoyant aftermath of theRussian Revolution to the tragic outcome of theSpanish Revolution and Civil War of 1937 to 1939. Bythe outbreak of the Second World War, I was wellversed in the issues the war raised for my generationearly in the century.

    Again, it is difficult to convey to young people,today, how differently proletarian socialists thought andthe ideals to which they were committed prior to 1950,which I regard as the year in which proletarian socialism

    was faced by its most decisive crisis. What cannot beemphasized too strongly is that all of us who survivedthe ideological debacle produced by the war had to dealwith the complete failure of allthe prognoses we heldfive years earlier. Almost all who you care to single outfrom the interwar period (1917-1940), be it a Lenin, a

    Trotsky (in my earnest opinion, the most optimistic andthe most competent theorist of the period), even going

    back in time to Rosa Luxemburg, Karl Liebknecht,Franz Mehring and the like, were absolutelyconvincedthat capitalism was in its death throes. The mostwidely used formulation during this stormy periodfarmore insurgent than the often pseudo-revolutionism ofthe sixtieswas the expression that capitalism (as Ihave already observed) was moribund, or facing the

    imminent certainty of collapse. Nothing seemed moreevident at the time than the apocalyptic belief that wewere witnessing the last days of bourgeois society,notwithstanding the fact that fascism was on the marchthroughout Europe and that proletarian socialistideology was waning and facing defeat.

    THEOUTBREAKOFTHESECONDWORLDWARLEFTNODOUBTin our minds that the conflict would end in socialistrevolutionsor else it was faced with barbarism. And,by barbarism, we meant the expansion of Nazismofmass starvation, ethnic extermination, concentrationcamps, a monstrous totalitarian state, and mass gravesthroughout Europe, if not America and Asia. Ifsocialism did not end the war by producing a new

    society, barbarism was a historic inevitability. For us, the

    victory of socialism was a near certainty, for it wasinconceivable that Europe, in particular, could gothrough the mass slaughter that marked the First WorldWar without producing successful proletarianrevolutions. Barbarism was the only alternative to a

    failure by the working class. To a man like Trotsky, whoStalin had killed in the year that saw the outbreak ofthe world conflict, should barbarism become establishedin the world, we would have to revise allthe

    expectations provided by Marxism and adopt ahistorically new ideological perspective.

    As we know after more than a half century, we werewrong, indeed terribly so. Neithersocialismnorfascismemergedfromthewar, but, to our amazement, liberalcapitalismwith its welfare state and the extension ofbourgeois democracy in most of Western Europe and

    the United States. Indeed, capitalism stabilized itself inthe historic sense that a cold war provided theframework for thinking out social problemsaframework to which the masses clung for nearly fifty

    years. Capitalism, in short, managed to stabilizeitself toa point where it was able to avoid any major economic,not to speak of any social crisis. The New Left, whileretaining many features of the Old Left, essentially tried(and failed) to create a culturalcrisis as a substitute fora revolutionary onewhich, as we now know, became a

    new industry and a commercial success in its own right.Moreover, capitalism, continued to deepenits hold

    on society on a scale and to an extent it had neverdoneduring the course of its history. All the vestigial featuresof pre-capitalist society with their monarchical, quasi-feudal, agrarian and craft strata that were still prevalentin Germany, France, and, at least, widespread inEngland in 1914 gave way, unevenly to be sure, to hugeindustrial corporations, mass production, the

    mechanization of all aspects of the economy, widespreadcommodification at the very base of economic life andmonopolization and global accumulation at itssummitsi.e. the spread of capitalism into every nicheof social life. The concept of Fordism was quiteknown to the Old Left long before it was adopted by

    New Left academics under such old names as massproduction and commodification.

    Finally, the proletariat not only dwindled vastly innumbers (contrary to all of Marxs expectations) butalso in class-consciousness. Workers began to lose theirsense of class identity, even began to see themselves asproperty owners, and significantlyaltered their socialexpectations. Home ownership, the acquisition of land,cars, and most significantly, stock ownership now

    became commonplace. Workers children were

    expected to go to colleges and universities, or, least,enter the professions or create self-employed enterprises.So vastly had class solidarity waned that the once-sturdyproletariat began to vote for conservative parties andjoin with reactionaries in opposing environmental

    conservation, gender equality, immigration fromimpoverished countries, ethnic equality, and similarissues. Pariss famous prewar 1940 red belt, whichfamously gave its votes to the French Communists asthe embodiment of the Russian Revolution in Western

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    9/68Harbinger - SPRING2003 {9 }

    Europe, found itself voting, often enthusiastically, forthe neo-fascism of the French reactionary, Jean-MarieLe Pen.

    Notwithstanding the multitude of breakdowntheories that Marxists and even anarchists advancedduring the interwar period, capitalism has proven to bemore sturdy and robust during the past fifty years than it

    was over the course of its entire history. Not only didcommodificationits most salient featurespreadthroughout the entire world, but it was even spared therecurrence of its notorious periodic crises or business

    cycles which reminded the world that a marketeconomy is inherentlyunstable. Indeed, contrary to allthe expectations that followed from Marxs theories ofsocial life-cycles, the supposition that capitalism wouldbecome an obstacle to the development of technologyanother salient feature of Marxs moribund society

    proved to be nonsense. As a force for advances inindustry and technical sophistication, capitalism

    exhibits incredible vitalitynotwithstanding Marxs

    prediction that it would soon become incapable oftechnical innovation and change. Indeed, all the

    features that were to mark a moribund economy havenow appeared in reverse: unendingtechnologicaladvances, the absenceof the heralded pauperization ofthe working class in the classical areas of capitalistdevelopment (England, France, western Europegenerally, and the United States), the disappearanceofchronic economic crises, and the waningof classconsciousness.

    By the 1950s, it was self-evident that Marxist (and

    anarchist) breakdown scenarios were palpable

    nonsense. The notion that the death of capitalismowing to an economic imperative, such as thedecline in the rate of profit (a theoretical construct ofVolume III of Capital)constituted a basic explanationfor the self-destruction of capitalism was completely

    untenable. The end of the Second World War broughtneitherbarbarism norsocialism but rather an ideologicalvacuum, so to speak, that threatened, like a huge blackhole, to extinguish the veracity of Marxs entiretheoretical corpus. Capitalism, I would like to reiterate,

    had recovered from the war, as I have noted, withunprecedented resiliency and extended its grip on

    society with unprecedented tenacity. As the middle ofthe fifties came into view, nearly all the monarchies,their political and bureaucratic underpinnings; theextensive craft, professional, and agrarian strata thatbarely a generation earlier had linked the Western

    European economy with its feudal pastvirtually allhad been effaced or divested of the authority theyenjoyed a generation earlier. Gone were the PrussianJunkers who survived the First World War, the tsars,

    dukes, and barons who peopled the upper classes ofcentral and southern Europe, the status groups thatpresided over the academies well into the thirties, andthe like. What the German Kaiser and, later, Hitlertried to achieve with terrible weapons and millions ofcorpses in 1914 and 1940, the German Bundesrepublik

    achieved with bundles of Deutsche Marks and, morerecently, a patina of pacifism!!

    ITCANNOTBEEMPHASIZEDTOOSTRONGLYthat, in theabsence of an imperative to challenge the desirability of a

    capitalistic society, and no less importantly, the need todemonstrate that capitalisms death in the foreseeablefuture was inevitable, no objectivereason existed forthe abolition of bourgeois society. Marx, at least, hadsatisfied this need with an economicimperative, namely,an immense body of theory (unparalleled in its scopeand historical knowledge). As I have noted, this theorywas based on such precepts as a chronic crisis producedby the tendency of the rate of profit to decline and by a

    structurally sophisticated class analysis that inevitably

    pitted a proletarian majority of an industrialized countryagainst a dwindling number of capitalists. By the 1950s,however, Marxism revealed for all who have eyes to see,that its traditional imperative was completelyunsoundwhen compared with the realities of the postwar world,

    nor could its economic imperative be renovated to meetthe challenges posed by the last half of the twentiethcentury.

    It was out of thefailureof Marxs economicimperative that social ecology was bornnot solely

    It was out of the failureof Marxs economic imperative that socialecology was born

    not solely because of the impact of pollution, urbandegradation, toxic food additives, and the like.t

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    10/68{10 } Harbinger - SPRING2003

    because of the impact of pollution, urban degradation,toxic food additives, and the like. When, in 1950, Iwrote my almost book length article, The Problem ofChemicals in Food, in No. 10 of ContemporaryIssues,the dangers to public health posed by thechemicalization of food by pesticide residues,preservatives, coloring matter, and the like were still

    relatively minor issues. The problem of nuclear fallout,the vast number and quantity of pollutants that were tothreaten the health of many millions of people, and,later, in 1964, the hazard to the worlds climate created

    by carbon dioxide, were not immediate issues or widelyforeseeable ones. The apocalyptic nature of the 1950article was dismissed by my critics as wild and recklessattacks upon the existing society. Actually, I was tryingto provide a viable substitute for Marxs defuncteconomic imperative, namely an ecologicalimperativethat, if thought out (as I tried to do in TheEcologyofFreedom)would show that capitalismstoodinan

    irreconcilablecontradictionwiththenaturalworld. Nearlyall my articles and bookssuch as OurSyntheticEnvironment (1962), followed two years later by mywidely circulated article, Ecology and RevolutionaryThought, and a companion article, Toward aLiberatory Technology, (1965)were guided primarilyby this project.

    I should note that it was in Ecology andRevolutionary Thought that I used the words, socialecology for the first time and began to sketch out thecomplex body of ideas that ultimately reached theirelaboration in TheEcologyofFreedom, two decades later.Let me be quite outspoken: it was not an unbridled

    passion for wildlife, wilderness, organic food,primitivism, craft-like methods of production, villages(as against cities), localism, a belief that small isbeautiful not to speak of Asian mysticism,spiritualism, naturism, etceterathat led me toformulate and promote social ecology. I was guided bythe compellingindeed, challengingneed toformulate a viable imperativethat doomed capitalism toself-extinction. As the thirties and the war revealed, it

    was not simply the class war between the proletariat and

    the capitalist classdriven almost exclusively byeconomicforces and resulting from the concentration ofcapitalthat were destined to destabilize capitalism andproduce a revolution. More fundamentally, the crisisproduced by capitalisms grow or die imperative could

    be expected to drive society into a devastatingcontradiction with the natural world. Capital, in effect,would be compelledto simplify all the ecosystems onwhose complexity evolution depended. Driven by itscompetitive relations and rivalries, capitalism would be

    obliged to turn soil into sand, the atmosphere and theplanets waterways into sewers, and warm the planet to a

    point where the entire climatic integrity of the worldwould be radically altered because of the greenhouseeffect.

    In short, precisely because capitalism was, bydefinition, a competitive and commodity-based economy,

    it would be compelled to turn the complex into thesimple and give rise to a planet that was incompatibleenvironmentally with advanced life forms. The growthof capitalism was incompatible with the evolution of

    biotic complexity assuchand certainly, with thedevelopment of human life and the evolution of humansociety.

    What is important to see is that social ecology thusrevealed a crisis between the natural world andcapitalism that was, if anything, more fundamental than

    the crisis that was imputed to the falling rate of profitand its alleged consequences. Moreover, social ecology

    opened the very real question of the kindof society thatwould have to follow the abolition of a capitalisteconomy. Self-styled Marxists (in all fairness, unlikeMarx and Engels) made a virtue out of a centralized,bureaucratically planned, and a highly technocraticideal of progress, based on an urban and mechanisticculture that was almost a parody of Corbusiers

    cityscapes.Social ecology tried to fill the gap between the

    industrial and agrarian worlds, not by condemningmachinery, mass production, or even industrialagriculture. My Toward a Liberatory Technology wasdeprecated by anarchists and Marxists alike: the former

    because the article celebrated the use of new gardeningmachines as a substitute for backbreaking toil; the latterprecisely because it was too utopian in its aspirations.Frankly, I regarded both of my supposed failings as realvirtues that, with quality production in allspheres ofeconomic life, freed humanity from the yoke of toil anda technocratic world. Moreover, there were aspects ofthe past which, given modern technics and means ofcommunication were desiderata because they could

    lighten work and vastly increase productivity, without

    which humanity would be afflicted with fears of materialscarcity. Such technological advances were also neededto provide sufficient free time for active participation inpublic affairs. Let me add, again, that my criticsmanyof whom were later to high-jack my alleged failings

    read could to mean would, and pompously declaredthat if post-scarcity simply meant we alreadyhadtremendous technological advances, why were we stillbeset with poverty and exhausting toil? As thoughcapitalism, like a slot machine, would always deliver

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    11/68Harbinger - SPRING2003 {11 }

    the most optimal returns on the goodies its technologycould produce! Typically, they failed to observe that Ihad repeatedly warned my readers that almost nothingcould emerge from within the context of a marketeconomy that was not tainted by the pathologies ofcompetition, rivalry, and, quite bluntly, pure and simplegreed!

    By contrast, social ecologys ecological imperativethe contradiction between a competitive society andthe natural worldis not simply theoretical. By theeighties, it had been tested by the massive degradation

    that is occurring in the social as well as the naturalworld. Speaking for myself, I am astonished by the rapidonset of the greenhouse effect, which, in 1964, Ipredicted in Ecology and Revolutionary Thought, as apossibility that would require two or more centuries tounfold. Yet, as early as the eighties and nineties, the

    contradiction between capitalism and the natural worldwas becoming a very visible reality. Thereafter, the

    greenhouse effect and other destructive imbalances haveassumed proportions that even outweigh morecommonplace problems such as soil erosion and wastedisposal.

    This philosophy forms the basis for an educativeoutlook that yields a lengthy dialectical history andexposition of the phases of human development as it

    emerges out from natural evolution into socialevolution. The philosophy of social ecology centersaround a dialectical unfoldingof a legacy of freedomthat not only intertwinesbut interactswith a legacy ofdomination, and includes the evolution of a concept ofjustice that leads into an ever-expanding concept of

    freedom, of scarcity into post-scarcity, of folkdom intocitizenship, of hierarchy into class, and, hopefully, agrowing horizon of freedom (whosetermination, if any,wearenot yetequippedtoforesee), yielding libertarianmunicipalities and institutions. Taken together, as awhole, this educative outlook forms the basis for apractical theory of politics.

    WEARENOWLIVINGNOTONLYINADIFFERENTCENTURYTHAT

    the Institute for Social Ecology was foundedthe ISE

    was founded, I would remind you, in 1974, nearly thirtyyears ago. I would sound to young people today as analien enterprise from a very different world than the onethat exists today. The world I knew still had a workersmovement in the US and Europe, and the issues it had

    to confront differ qualitatively from those that haveemerged in the past two decades.

    Yet it would be unpardonable if we forgot thatsocialism was meant to be a rational society, not areplication of Stalinism and totalitarianism. Nor can we

    be permitted to forget that it will require a profoundsocial imperativean ecologicalimperative, in myviewto move this mass, even lethargic society alongrational lines. We must always remember that socialismwill come about as the result of logical necessity, theproduct of deep-seated and compelling forces for socialchange, not simply good vibes. To give these precepts

    a lived meaning, we shall have to create an educationalvanguard to keep the terrible pathologies of our dayunder control, at the vary least, and abolish them at thevery most.

    For such demands upon our energy and ourintelligence, our educational activities must result in amovement, not simply in a lifestyle that celebrates itsfreedom in a closeted community at a distance fromreal centers of activity and conflict. I cannot emphasizeenough that our education, be it at the ISE or among

    affinity groups, will be little more than a form of self-indulgence if it is restricted to our minds, completely

    removed from an active life.I would be the first to acknowledge that action is

    only possible when there is a real, dissident public life.For the present, I see no widespread inclination to givereality to a movement for libertarian municipalism,which, at the turn of the new century, lies dormant as aprospect for a new politics. Marx once perceptively

    noted in his early writings that not only must the Ideafollow reality, but also reality must follow the Idea. Thisaphorism might well be regarded as a recognition of theHegelian notion that freedom is a recognition ofnecessity in the sense that we need sufficientpreconditions to produce the most effective conditions

    for social change. When this is not so, the mostbrilliant of ideas lie almost silently in wait for societyitself to ripen and permit the struggle for freedom togerminate. It is then that we can give to education apriority that defies all false appeals to activism for itsown sake.

    But one proviso must be voiced: ideas are only truewhen they are rational. Today, when rationality andconsistency are deprecated in the name of

    postmodernist chic, we carry a double burden of trying

    to sustain, often by education alone, reason againstirrationalism, and to know whento act as well as howtodo so. In such cases, let me note that education, too, isa form of activism and must always be cultivated assuch.I

    Notes

    This article is an abridged version of a longer letter from

    the author to Michael Caplan.

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    12/68{12 } Harbinger - SPRING2003

    INTHEMIDSTOFOURSTRUGGLESFORABETTERWORLD, social ecologists have fre-quently engaged in critical dialogue with other strands of radical thought about

    just what kind of world were struggling for. Such dialogues often address thequestion of how people in a liberated future will organize their material relation-ships with one another and with the natural world. What would economics looklike in an ecological society? How might free communities arrange their livelihood?

    Exploring questions such as these requires us to exercise an important facultyof dialectical philosophy: the capacity to think speculatively. Envisioning afuture beyond capitalism and the state means thinking past the world around usand putting ourselves inside of a different world, a world structured in a verydifferent way, a world that has developed some of the social and ecological

    potentials that we see around us, in distorted form, today. It means trying to see

    the world not merely as it is, but as it ought to be.Social ecologists have put forward a number of concrete proposals over theyears for a municipalized economyand a moral economy. These proposals pointtoward what Bookchin calls the recovery of the productive process itself as anecological mediation of humanity with nature. What these practical proposals

    have in common is an underlying conception of how complex economies couldbe run differently, without markets or classes or bureaucracy, along egalitarianand participatory lines. Social ecologists argue that the economic mechanisms ofa free society, whether for production, distribution, or reproduction, should havefour basic characteristics: they should be conscious, transparent, alterable, andintegrated.

    Conscious: We want economic mechanisms to be deliberately chosen and

    deliberately structured, so that they fulfill the purposes that we collectively giveto them, rather than the economic structures forcing us to fulfill their purposes.

    Transparent: We want every member of society to be able to grasp how societyseconomic mechanisms function. Alterable: We want to be able to change oureconomic structures according to ecological and social needs. And last, we wanteconomic mechanisms to be comprehensively integratedwith all other aspects ofcommunal self-management.

    What might these values look like in practice?How could this ensemble of specula-tive postulates actually be implemented?What follows is a brief attempt to sketch areconstructive vision of economics in a social-ecological society.

    Economics in a Social-Ecological Society

    By Peter Staudenmaier

    Michael Caplan

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    13/68Harbinger - SPRING2003 {13 }

    The World Social Ecologists Envision

    The world we envision is one of adventure and possibil-ity, of radically new relationships and potential forms ofsocial and individual life that are difficult to imagine,much less describe, from the perspective of the present.Most of what will happen in a social-ecological future,

    whether at an environmental level, a personal level, or a

    communal level, will be spontaneous and creativeandthese are things we can neither plan nor propose norpredict. Nevertheless, such spontaneous and creativeunfolding of potentials will require both an institutionalframework and an ethical vision if they are to becomemore than mere dreams. Thus we must turn our atten-tion to the social structures that might make free natureand a free society more likely.

    Social ecologists work toward a society structuredaround freedom, cooperation, and ecological and socialdiversity. Our vision of a better world draws on a wealthof practical experiments and utopian hopes raised

    throughout history by emancipatory movements frombelow. At the center of our vision of free communities is

    direct democracy. Direct democracy means peoplemanaging their own lives, consciously and collectively,for the good of the communities they are part of. Insteadof handing over decision-making power to experts,professionals, representatives, or bureaucrats, socialecology foresees all people participating directly in theself-management of their communal affairs.

    Because we oppose institutionalized forms of domi-nation and hierarchy, social ecologists reject the state as

    such. Instead of positing a separate body that standsapart from society and makes decisions on its behalf, weenvision a network of community assemblies as the basicdecision-making body and as the primary venue forpracticing direct democracy. These assemblies includeall the residents of a local area (in cities at the neighbor-

    hood level and in rural areas at the township level), whomeet at regular intervals to discuss and decide on theissues before them: political as well as economic deci-sions, indeed any social decision that significantly affectsthe life of the community as a whole.

    The popular assembly includes everybody who is

    willing to participate in it and provides a democraticforum for all community members to engage one anotheron an equal basis and actively shape social life. Ongoing

    interactions of this kind encourage a sense of sharedresponsibility and interdependence, as well as offering apublic space for resolving disputes and disagreements ina rational and non-coercive way. Recognizing thatpeople have differing interests, aspirations, and convic-tions, the neighborhood assembly and its accompanying

    civic ethos present an opportunity for reconciling

    particular and general objectives. Direct democracy, inthis view, involves a commitment to the wellbeing of

    ones neighbors.Communal wellbeing, in turn, implies an active

    respect and appreciation for the natural context withinwhich local communities exist. No social order canguarantee that the ecosystems and habitats that host

    our various settlements will thrive, but social ecologistsbelieve that communities built around free associationand mutual aid are much better suited to fosteringenvironmental diversity and sustainability than those

    built around authoritarian systems of power. Insocieties that have overcome domination and hierar-chy, ecological flourishing and human flourishing cancomplement and reinforce one another.

    The ethical outlook that embodies these potentialsis as important as the practical methods themselves.

    Social ecologists want to create social forms thatpromote freedom and solidarity by building these

    values into the very fabric of social relations and publicinstitutions. Thus, our emphasis on face-to-faceassemblies open to all is meant to encourage, notpreclude, the creation of other libertarian and coopera-tive social forms. An enormous variety of spontaneousassociations, living arrangements, workplaces, familystructures, and so forth all have an important place in

    our vision of a free world. The only forms that areexcluded are ones based on exploitation and oppres-sion.

    Social ecologys model of direct democracy cantherefore be realized in a number of different waysdepending on the needs, desires, and experiences of

    those who are inspired by it. This is especially true ofeconomic processes, and the scenario outlined here isonly one possible interpretation of the economicaspects of a social-ecological society. The fundamentalshared perspective is that of a moral economy, in whichthe material conditions of our existence are reinte-grated into a broader ethical and institutional frame-work. A moral economy means making decisionsabout production and consumption part of the civic life

    of the whole community.

    Communal Self-Management in Practice

    In this scenario, workers councils play a crucial role in

    the day-to-day administration of production, whilelocal assemblies have the final say in major economicdecisions. All members of a given community partici-pate in formulating economic policy, which is dis-cussed, debated, and decided upon within the popularassembly. Social ecology foresees an extensive physi-

    cal decentralization of production, so that workers at a

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    14/68{14 } Harbinger - SPRING2003

    particular enterprise will typically live in the samemunicipality where they work. We also foresee acontinual voluntary rotation of jobs, tasks, and responsi-bilities and a radical redefinition of what work means.Through the conscious transformation of labor into afree social activity that combines physical and intellec-tual skills, we envision the productive process as a

    fulfillment of personal and communal needs, articulatedto their ecological context. Along with the rejection ofbosses, profits, wages, and exchange value, we seek to

    overcome capitalisms reduction of human beings toinstruments of production and consumption. Socialecologys assembly model encourages people to approacheconomic decisions not merely as workers and consum-ers, but as community members committed to an

    inclusive goal of social and ecological wellbeing.While the broad outlines of communal production

    are established at the assembly level, they are imple-mented in practice by smaller collective bodies whichalso operate on an egalitarian, participatory, anddemocratic basis. Cooperative households and collec-

    tive workplaces form an integral part of this process.Decisions that have regional impact are worked out byconfederations of local assemblies, so that everybodyaffected by a decision can participate in making it.Specific tasks can be delegated to specialized commit-tees, but substantive issues of public concern are subjectto the discretion of each popular assembly. Directdemocracy encourages the formation and contestationof competing views and arguments, so that for any given

    decision there will be several distinct options available,

    each of them crafted by the people who will carry themout. Assembly members consider these various propos-als and debate their merits and implications; they arediscussed, revised and amended as necessary. When noclear consensus emerges, a vote or series of votes can be

    held to determine which options have the most support.Social ecologys vision of a moral economy centers

    on libertarian communism, in which the fruits ofcommon labor are freely available to all. This principleof from each according to ability and to each according

    to need, which distinguishes our perspective from manyother anti-capitalist programs, is fleshed out by a civic

    ethic in which concern for the common welfare shapesindividual choices. In the absence of markets, privateproperty, class divisions, commodity production, exploi-tation of labor, and accumulation of capital, libertariancommunism can become the distributive mechanism for

    social wealth and the economic counterpart to thetransparent and humanly scaled political structures thatsocial ecology proposes.

    In such an arrangement, the interaction betweensmaller committees and working groups and the fullassembly becomes crucially important to maintainingthe democratic and participatory nature of this delibera-tive process. Preparing coherent proposals for presenta-

    tion to the assembly will require both specialized workand scrupulous information gathering, as well as analysisand interpretation. Because these activities can subtlyinfluence the eventual outcome of any decision, theresponsibility for carrying them out should be a rotatingtask entrusted to a temporary commission chosen at

    random from the members of the assembly.

    Confederal Economic Democracy

    When the assembly has considered and debated and

    fine-tuned the various proposals before it and has agreedon an overall outline for the local economy, communitymembers continue to refine and realize this outlinewhile implementing it in their workplaces, residences,and elsewhere. If obstacles or disagreements arise thatcannot be resolved at the immediate level of a single

    enterprise, institution, or household, they can bebrought back to the full assembly for discussion andresolution. If some aspects of an agreed-upon policy are

    not fulfilled for whatever reason, this will quicklybecome apparent to community members, who can thenalter or adapt the policy accordingly. While most ofeconomic life will be carried out within smaller collec-tivities, in direct cooperation with co-workers,housemates, associates and neighbors, overarching

    matters of public economic direction will be worked out

    The fundamental shared perspective is that of a moral economy, inwhich the material conditions of our existence are re-integrated into abroader ethical and institutional framework.

    A moral economy means making decisions about productionand consumption part of the civic life of the whole community.

    {

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    15/68Harbinger - SPRING2003 {15 }

    within the assembly of the entire community. Whennecessary, city-wide or regional issues will be addressedat the confederal level, with final decisions remaining inthe hands of each local assembly.

    The reason for this emphasis on assembly sover-eignty is two-fold. First, the local assembly is the mostaccessible forum for practicing direct democracy and

    guarding against the re-emergence of power differentialsand new forms of hierarchy. Since the assembly in-cludes all members of the community on equal termsand operates through direct participation rather than

    representation, it offers the best opportunity for extend-ing collective self-management to all spheres of sociallife. Second, the local assembly makes it possible forpeople to decide on their economic and political affairsin a comprehensive and coherent manner, through face-to-face discussion with the people they live with, play

    with, and work with. The popular assembly encouragesa holistic approach to public matters, one that recog-

    nizes the myriad interconnections among economic,social, and ecological concerns.

    Much of this vision will only be practicable inconjunction with a radical overhaul of the technologicalinfrastructure, something which social ecologists supporton environmental as well as democratic grounds. Weforesee most production taking place locally, with

    specialized functions socialized and conceptual andmanual labor integrated. Still, there will be someimportant social goods that cannot or should not becompletely decentralized; advanced research institutes,for example, will serve large regions even though theywill be hosted by one municipality. Thus confederation,

    which offsets parochialism and insularity, plays anessential role within social ecologys political vision.

    While the primary focus of this scenario is on localcommunities generating economic policies tailored totheir own social end ecological circumstances, socialecologists reject the notions of local self-sufficiency andeconomic autarchy as values in themselves; we considerthese things desirable if and when they contribute tosocial participation and ecologically nuanced demo-

    cratic decision making. We foresee a confederation of

    assemblies in consistent dialogue with one another viaconfederal bodies made up of recallable and mandateddelegates from each constituent assembly. These bodiesare established as outgrowths of the directly democraticlocal communities, not as substitutes for them. Since

    economic relations, in particular, often involve coopera-tion with distant communities, confederation offers amutually compatible framework for sharing resources,skills, and knowledge.

    A confederal network of popular assemblies offers a

    Over the past few years, social ecologists and

    advocates of Participatory Economics have started to

    engage in a discussion on these two bodies of

    libertarian thought. This discussion has raised many

    important questions about the form a liberated society

    might take. This past summer, the Institute for Social

    Ecology hosted a debate between Participatory

    Economist Michael Albert and social ecologist Peter

    Staudenmaier on our on-line discussion forums.

    Michael Albert is the co-founder of South End

    Press,Z Magazine, Z Media Institute, and various on-

    line projects, including ZNet. While he writes about avery wide range of topics, one of his primary

    intellectual foci has long been the development and

    popularization of economic vision and strategy. The

    fruits of this labor, largely undertaken with Robin

    Hahnel, are the economic model, vision, and approach

    which they call Participatory Economics.

    The debate sought to examine the work of these

    two bodies of thought as they relate to questions of

    the form a liberated society might take, the underlying

    values that such a society rests upon, and an activist

    practice that would lead us in this direction. The

    debate was framed around two brief position papers

    on each writers vision for a liberated society. These

    position papers were then followed up with critical

    and questioning rejoinders which framed a month-

    long debate. The debate is currently open to the

    public for further discussion.

    Visit the debate on-line at:

    www.social-ecology.org/forums

    Discuss!

    practical way for all people to consciously direct theirlives together and to pursue common goals as part of aproject of social freedom. Bringing together solidarityand autonomy, we can recreate politics, the art ofcommunal self-management, as the highest form ofdirect action. In such a world, economics as we know ittoday will no longer exist. When work becomes

    creative activity, when production becomes the harmo-nization of human and ecological potentials, wheneconomics becomes collective self-determination andthe conscious unfolding of social, natural, and ethical

    possibilities as yet unimagined, then we will haveachieved a liberated society, and the ideas outlined herewill take on concrete form as lived realities and directexperiences.I

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    16/68{16 } Harbinger - SPRING2003

    A REMARKABLEFEATUREOFSOCIALECOLOGYISTHATMURRAYBOOKCHINS

    vision of an ecological society goes beyond the development of eco-technologies and organic agriculture, but expands into the

    philosophical realm through dialectical naturalism. Murray recognizesthe importance of healing the seemingly disparate relationship betweennature and culture (first and second nature) by reminding us of thedevelopmental relationship between them (dialectical naturalism).Through his discourses on dialectical naturalism, Murray invites theparticipation of ecologists, biologists, and scientists generally involved

    in the subject of evolution. The following essay is a critique of oneaspect of dialectical naturalism. It is an attempt and also an invitationto other social ecologists, to develop and refine Murrays important andprovocative work on the relationship between nature and culture.

    For Murray, dialectical naturalism serves as a potential source ofobjective ethics for developing ecological societies as demonstrated bythe following quote:

    Today we may well be able to permit Naturenot God or Spirit or an lan Vitalto open itself up to us as theground for an ethics on its own terms. Contemporary sciences greatest achievement is the growing evidence it

    provides that randomness is subject to a directive ordering principle, mutualism is good by virtue of its fostering the

    evolution of natural variety and complexity.1

    If there are indeed trends or universal laws that determine the evolution of first nature, then humans should deriveethics based upon these principles. Murray is particularly interested in those trends that are compatible with

    anarchist principles. An ecological society would be based upon a harmonious existence within its eco-community(ecosystem)2by fostering mutualistic and non-hierarchical relationships (mutualism), diversity (variation) and self-organization (autopoeisis). In accordance with dialectical naturalism, an ecological society would, in general,maximize the opportunities for unfettered directionality toward greater complexity, diversity, and subjectivity.Murrays ecological society takes the form of libertarian municipalism, the assemblage of multiple self-governingcommunities into a complex of confederations. The complexity of the confederation allows for a cultural diversitythat facilitates freedom by diminishing racism, classism, and any other isms that act to oppress and suppress thepotentialities latent within individuals of the human species.

    As a student of social ecology and one trying to integrate my background as a biologist, I was drawn to the

    question of whether nature could provide a basis for deriving ethics. Scientists have been searching for universallaws in evolutionary biology ever since Darwin. The search represents a contemporary chapter in the historical questfor universal laws in the physical and chemical sciences. Aside from the satisfaction of understanding the world

    around us, there are, after all, practical reasons for deriving lawsthey allow us to make predictions. In theecological sciences they provide a basis for reconstructing ecosystems (restoration ecology) and inform decisionsregarding the conservation and management of wildlife. The laws that determine evolution are not as easily subject

    to testing by the scientific method as in ecology, nor is their practicality obvious. In evolutionary science the trendsare more philosophical in nature: (1) whether the tempo of evolution is rapid or gradual (punctuated equilibrium vs.gradualism), (2) whether evolution is goal-oriented and (3) whether evolution proceeds by an increase in complexityand diversity.

    Murrays argument that nature has directionality toward ever-greater complexity and diversity initially struck meas provocative, if not problematic. The existence of multicellular plants and animals is often used to argue thatevolution proceeds by an increase in complexity. Evolutionary biology is still in the process of describing the

    Buttercups and SunflowersOn the Evolution of First and Second Nature

    By Sonja Schmitz

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    17/68Harbinger - SPRING2003 {17 }

    extraordinary leap life took in its transitions fromprokaryotic cells (bacteria) to the first eukaryotic cells(protists) and from these single celled organisms tomulticellular fungi, plants and animals. One caninterpret this progression favorably by emphasizing thecooperative, communal, and mutualistic tendenciesrequired by these transitions, which is what Murray

    Bookchin does. Murray wants to equate the evolutionof a confederation of multiple self-governingcommunities with the evolution of multicellularorganisms. There is however, a darker side to this

    progression. The evolution of complex life forms is astory rife with tension between the autonomy of theindividual cell and the drive to assemble intocommunities of cells for the sake of survival. This initself is not incompatible with social ecology. But, theassemblage of autonomous beings is usually

    accompanied by the reduction of the individual intospecialized and compartmentalized functions, words that

    conjure images of authoritarian communism and fascistpolitical regimes. Therefore, I would like to examinewhether it is indeed desirable to derive ethics from whatbiologists know about the evolution of first nature.

    The endosymbiotic theory proposed by LynnMargulis suggests that the evolution of eukaryotic cellsmay well have occurred by the ingestion (but

    incomplete digestion) of one bacterium by anotherabout 1.5 million years ago (mya).3 In the process, theundifferentiated soup of molecules that comprised theguts of bacterial cells was organized into an assemblageof specialized compartments called organelles, each witha separate function much like our own organs. The

    resulting eukaryotic cell harbors remnants of itsprokaryotic ancestors, mitochondria and chloroplasts,once intact, autonomous individuals, now dependentupon and part of a greater assemblage. Therefore, theevolution of the eukaryotic cell occurred at the expenseof autonomous bacterial cells, which are mere vestigesof what they once were (mitochondria andchloroplasts).

    The next level of differentiation involves the

    assemblage of single celled eukaryotes (protists) into

    colonies of cells and the first multicellular organisms.Biologists see evidence of this transition in some algalspecies like Volvox. Volvox consists of a hollow spheremade up of a single layer of 500 to 60,000 flagellatedcells that function in photosynthesis and in the motility

    of the colony. Other cells in the Volvoxcommunityfunction solely in reproduction (sex cells). Thismulticellular community operates as a result of thesimultaneous specialization of function of individualcells and a division of labor among them. The next step

    is the organization of hundreds of thousands of cells intotissues and organ systems. Not much is known about

    how this transition occurred, but multicellularinvertebrate animals with organ systems suddenlyappear in the fossil record about 700 mya (Ediacara,Australia). Nevertheless, the same themes of reductionand specialization are observed in the evolution of

    multicellular fungi, plants and animals.An example from the plant kingdom, the buttercup

    and the sunflower, will illustrate how the themes ofspecialization and reduction resurface in the evolution

    of complex multicellular organisms. The buttercupflower is considered primitive, meaning it is one of theearliest flower structures observed in the fossil recordand several million years older than the sunflowerlineage. (There are more ancient lineages amongflowering plants, but I am choosing the buttercup

    lineage because everyone can picture them). Each partof the flower is distinguishable and together comprises a

    reproductive organthe buttercup flower. It has fivegreen sepals, five yellow petals, many single stamens(male flower parts) and many pistils (female flowerparts) that develop into little fruits called achenes.Upon initial inspection, the sunflower does not appearmuch different. It has many green sepals, yellow petals,stamens, and pistils. Although the sunflower looks like

    a buttercup, its structure is deceivingly different. The

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    18/68{18 } Harbinger - SPRING2003

    sunflower is a community of individual flowers, eachwith a specialized reproductive function. The outerflowers each have one yellow petal; their pistils andstamens are inactive or nonexistent. On the otherhand, the petals of the inner flowers have been fusedinto a yellow tube; and their pistils and stamens are stillfunctional. The outer flowers with petals function to

    attract pollinators, while the inner tubular flowersproduce seed.

    The buttercup and the sunflower represent two

    levels of complexity. The buttercup is a simple flowerwith many parts that produces many seeds, while thesunflower is a community of many individual flowerswith specialized functions, each producing a single seed.The buttercup is an autonomous individual capable ofreproduction, while individuals of the mega-sunflowercommunity cannot function autonomously anymore,

    and must reproduce as a unit.I have often thought that Murrays libertarian

    municipalism is like the sunflower; each self-governingmunicipality is a single flower, while the mega-sunflowercommunity represents the confederation. But, uponcloser examination, the analogy is inadequate. The

    evolution of complexity in plants is not compatiblewith, nor can it be equated with, the kind of complexityand diversity Murray envisions as facilitating freedom inhis libertarian municipalities. The sort of reduction,specialization, and loss of autonomy observed in theevolution of multicellular organisms is more compatiblewith the functioning of a nation state or fascist politicalregime. Therefore the evolution of complexity hasoutcomes frighteningly compatible with political

    regimes that do not embrace the ideas of social ecology.

    If the buttercup and the sunflower are interpreted asexamples of the evolution of complexity, do we want tocite this trend for constructing ecological societies orconfederations?

    Perhaps it is inappropriate to compare the evolution

    of plants with the evolution of human social systems.While trends in the evolutionary process can beidentified, they are not universal and do not necessarilyapply across all lineages of life. Each of the fivekingdoms is on a separate evolutionary trajectory, as is

    each phylum in the animal genealogy. Even if we wereto limit our examination to mammals or primates, is it

    appropriate to extend the laws or principles of firstnature and superimpose them upon cultural evolution?I would argue that because cultural evolution is uniquelyhuman, and not a generalized trend among otherlineages, the trends observed in first nature do not

    necessarily apply to second nature.Although Murray applauds science in its

    achievements in illuminating the role of mutualism,

    diversity, complexity (and other anarchist tendencies);evolutionary biology is only beginning to yield underthe scrutiny of the scientific method, or in other words,provide an objective inquiry into the laws of evolution.The exploration into the evolution of complexity hasleft me with grave doubts as to whether social ecologistswant to derive ethics from first nature. My doubts

    however, do not diminish my desire to constructsocieties on the basis of mutualism and diversity.Perhaps the themes of mutualism and diversity hold upbetter under examination than does the evolution ofcomplexity.

    In summary, this essay raises two separate yet related

    questions. Can we derive an objective ethics from thetrends or laws of first nature? And if such trends,principles or universal laws do exist, is it appropriate oreven desirableto cite them for the construction ofecological human societies? I reserve an examinationinto these questions for future essays and invite othersocial ecologists to join in the inquiry.I

    Notes

    1. Murray Bookchin, Toward a Philosophy of Naturein The Philosophy of Social Ecology(Montreal: Black RoseBooks, 1995), p. 64.

    2. Scientific terminology is in parenthesis

    3. Lynn Margulis, Early Life (Boston: Jones andBartlett Publishers Inc., 1984), p. 75-104.

    If the buttercup and the sunflower are

    interpreted as examples of the evolution of complexity,

    do we want to cite this trend for constructing

    ecological societies or confederations?{

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    19/68Harbinger - SPRING2003 {19 }

    Beehive Design Collective

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    20/68{20 } Harbinger - SPRING2003

    By Murray Bookchin

    TheCommunalist

    Project

    Cliff Harper

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    21/68Harbinger - SPRING2003 {21 }

    WHETHERTHETWENTY-FIRSTCENTURYWILLBETHEMOSTRADICALOFTIMESORTHEMOSTREACTIONARYor will simply lapse into a gray era of dismal mediocritywill depend overwhelminglyupon the kind of social movement and program that social radicals create out of the

    theoretical, organizational, and political wealth that has accumulated during the past two centuries ofthe revolutionary era. The direction we select, from among several intersecting roads of humandevelopment, may well determine the future of our species for centuries to come. As long as thisirrational society endangers us with nuclear and biological weapons, we cannot ignore the possibility

    that the entire human enterprise may come to a devastating end. Given the exquisitely elaboratetechnical plans that the military-industrial complex has devised, the self-extermination of the humanspecies must be included in the futuristic scenarios that, at the turn of the millennium, the mass mediaare projectingthe end of a human future as such.

    Lest these remarks seem too apocalyptic, I should emphasize that we alsolive in an era whenhuman creativity, technology, and imagination have the capability to produce extraordinary materialachievements and to endow us with societies that allow for a degree of freedom that far and awayexceeds the most dramatic and emancipatory visions projected by social theorists such as Saint-Simon, Charles Fourier, Karl Marx, and Peter Kropotkin.1 Many thinkers of the postmodern age haveobtusely singled out science and technology as the principal threats to human well-being, yet few

    disciplines have imparted to humanity such a stupendous knowledge of the innermost secrets ofmatter and life, or provided our species better with the ability to alter every important feature of

    reality and to improve the well-being of human and nonhuman life-forms.We are thus in a position either to follow a path toward a grim end of history, in which a banal

    succession of vacuous events replaces genuine progress, or to move on to a path toward the truemaking of history, in which humanity genuinely progresses toward a rational world. We are in aposition to choose between an ignominious finale, possibly including the catastrophic nuclearoblivion of history itself, and historys rational fulfillment in a free, materially abundant society in anaesthetically crafted environment.

    Notwithstanding the technological marvels that competing enterprises of the ruling class (that is,the bourgeoisie) are developing in order to achieve hegemony over one another, little of a subjectivenature that exists in the existing society can redeem it. Precisely at a time when we, as a species, arecapable of producing the means for amazing objective advances and improvements in the humancondition and in the nonhuman natural worldadvances that could make for a free and rationalsociety we stand almost naked morally before the onslaught of social forces that may very well lead

    to our physical immolation. Prognoses about the future are understandably very fragile and are easilydistrusted. Pessimism has become very widespread, as capitalist social relations become more deeplyentrenched in the human mind than ever before, and as culture regresses appallingly, almost to avanishing point. To most people today, the hopeful and very radical certainties of the twenty-yearperiod between the Russian Revolution of 1917-18 and the end of the Spanish Civil War in 1939seem almost nave.

    Yet our decision to create a better society, and our choice of the way to do it, must come fromwithin ourselves, without the aid of a deity, still less a mystical force of nature or a charismatic leader.If we choose the road toward a better future, our choice must be the consequence of our abilityand

    ours aloneto learn from the material lessons of the past and to appreciate the real prospects of the

    future. We will need to have recourse, not to ghostly vagaries conjured up from the murky hell ofsuperstition or, absurdly, from the couloirs of the academy, but to the innovative attributes that makeup our very humanity and the essentialfeatures that account for natural and social development, asopposed to the social pathologies and accidental events that have sidetracked humanity from its self-fulfillment in consciousness and reason. Having brought history to a point where nearly everythingis

    possible, at least of a material natureand having left behind a past that was permeated ideologicallyby mystical and religious elements produced by the human imaginationwe are faced with a newchallenge, one that has never before confronted humanity. We must consciously create our ownworld, not according to demonic fantasies, mindless customs, and destructive prejudices, butaccording to the canons of reason, reflection, and discoursethat uniquely belong to our own species.

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    22/68{22 } Harbinger - SPRING2003

    What factors should be decisive in making our choice?First, of great significance is the immense accumulationof social and political experience that is available torevolutionaries today, a storehouse of knowledge that,properly conceived, could be used to avoid the terribleerrors that our predecessors made and to spare humanitythe terrible plagues of failed revolutions in the past. Of

    indispensable importance is the potential for a newtheoretical springboard that has been created by thehistory of ideas, one that provides the means to catapultan emerging radical movement beyond existing social

    conditions into a future that fosters humanitysemancipation.

    But we must also be fully aware of the scope of theproblems that we face. We must understand withcomplete clarity wherewe stand in the development ofthe prevailing capitalist order, and we have to grasp

    emergentsocial problems and address them in theprogram of a new movement. Capitalism is

    unquestionably the most dynamic society ever to appearin history. By definition, to be sure, it alwaysremains asystem of commodity exchange in which objects thatare made for sale and profit pervade and mediate mosthuman relations. Yet capitalism is also a highly mutablesystem, continually advancing the brutal maxim thatwhatever enterprise does not grow at the expense of its

    rivals must die. Hence growth and perpetual changebecome the very laws of life of capitalist existence. Thismeans that capitalism neverremains permanently inonly one form; it must alwaystransform the institutionsthat arise from its basic social relations.

    Although capitalism became a dominant society

    only in the past few centuries, it long existed on theperiphery of earlier societies: in a largely commercialform, structured around trade between cities andempires; in a craft form throughout the EuropeanMiddle Ages; in a hugely industrial form in our owntime; and if we are to believe recent seers, in aninformational form in the coming period. It has creatednot only new technologies but also a great variety ofeconomic and social structures, such as the small shop,

    the factory, the huge mill, and the industrial and

    commercial complex. Certainly the capitalism of theIndustrial Revolution has not completely disappeared,any more than the isolated peasant family and smallcraftsman of a still earlier period have been consigned tocomplete oblivion. Much of the past is always

    incorporated into the present; indeed, as Marxinsistently warned, there is no pure capitalism, andnone of the earlier forms of capitalism fade away untilradically new social relations are established andbecome overwhelmingly dominant. But today

    capitalism, even as it coexists with and utilizesprecapitalist institutions for its own ends (see Marxs

    Grundrissefor this dialectic), now reaches into thesuburbs and the countryside with its shopping malls andnewly styled factories. Indeed, it is by no meansinconceivable that one day it will reach beyond ourplanet. In any case, it has produced not only new

    commodities to create and feed new wants but newsocial and cultural issues,which in turn have given riseto new supporters and antagonists of the existingsystem. The famous first part of Marx and Engelss

    CommunistManifesto, in which they celebratecapitalisms wonders, would have to be periodicallyrewritten to keep pace with the achievementsas wellas the horrorsproduced by the bourgeoisiesdevelopment.

    One of the most striking features of capitalism today

    is that in the Western world the highly simplified two-class structurethe bourgeoisie and the proletariat

    that Marx and Engels, in The Communist Manifesto,predicted would become dominant under maturecapitalism (and we have yet to determine whatmature, still less late or moribund capitalismactually is) has undergone a process of reconfiguration.The conflict between wage labor and capital, while ithas by no means disappeared, nonetheless lacks the all-

    embracingimportancethat it possessed in the past.Contrary to Marxs expectations, the industrial workingclass is now dwindling in numbers and is steadily losingits traditional identity as a classwhich by no meansexcludes it from a potentially broader and perhaps moreextensive conflict of society as a whole against capitalist

    social relations. Present-day culture, social relations,cityscapes, modes of production, agriculture, andtransportation have remade the traditional proletariat,upon which syndicalists and Marxists wereoverwhelmingly, indeed almost mystically focused, intoa largely petty-bourgeois stratum whose mentality ismarked by its own bourgeois utopianism ofconsumption for the sake of consumption. We canforesee a time when the proletarian, whatever the color

    of his or her collar or place on the assembly line, will be

    completely replaced by automated and evenminiaturized means of production that are operated by afew white-coated manipulators of machines and bycomputers.

    By the same token, the living standards of the

    traditional proletariat and its material expectations (nosmall factor in the shaping of social consciousness!)have changed enormously, soaring within only ageneration or two from near poverty to a comparativelyhigh degree of material affluence. Among the children

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    23/68Harbinger - SPRING2003 {23 }

    and grandchildren of former steel and automobileworkers and coal miners, who have no proletarian classidentity, a college education has replaced the highschool diploma as emblematic of a new class status. Inthe United States once-opposing class interests haveconverged to a point that almost 50 percent ofAmerican households own stocks and bonds, while a

    huge number are proprietors of one kind or another,possessing their own homes, gardens, and rural summerretreats.

    Given these changes, the stern working man or

    woman, portrayed in radical posters of the past with aflexed, highly muscular arm holding a bone-crushinghammer, has been replaced by the genteel and well-mannered (so-called) working middle class. Thetraditional cry Workers of the world, unite! in its oldhistorical sense becomes ever more

    meaningless. The class-consciousnessof the proletariat, which Marx tried to

    awaken in The Communist Manifesto,has been hemorrhaging steadily and inmany places has virtually disappeared.The more existential class struggle hasnot been eliminated, to be sure, anymore than the bourgeoisie couldeliminate gravity from the existing

    human condition, but unless radicalstoday become aware of the fact that ithas been narroweddown largely to theindividual factory or office, they will fail to see that anew, perhaps more expansive form of socialconsciousness can emerge in the generalized struggles

    that face us. Indeed, this form of social consciousnesscan be given a refreshingly new meaning as the conceptof the rebirth of the citoyena concept so important tothe Great Revolution of 1789 and its more broadlyhumanistic sentiment of sociality that it became theform of address among later revolutionaries summonedto the barricades by the heraldic crowing of the redFrench rooster.

    Seen as a whole, the social condition that

    capitalism has produced today stands very much at odds

    with the simplistic class prognoses advanced by Marxand by the revolutionary French syndicalists. After theSecond World War, capitalism underwent an enormoustransformation, creating broadnewsocialissueswithextraordinary rapidity, issues that went beyond

    traditional proletarian demands for improved wages,hours, and working conditions: notably environmental,gender, hierarchical, civic, and democratic issues.Capitalism, in effect, hasgeneralizedits threats tohumanity, particularly with climatic changes that may

    alter the very face of the planet, oligarchical institutionsof a global scope, and rampant urbanization that

    radically corrodes the civic life basic to grassrootspolitics.

    Hierarchy, today, is becoming as pronounced anissue as classas witness the extent to which manysocial analyses have singled out managers, bureaucrats,

    scientists, and the like as emerging, ostensibly dominantgroups. New and elaborate gradations of status andinterests count today to an extent that they did not inthe recent past; they blur the conflict between wage

    labor and capital that was once so central, clearlydefined, and militantly waged by traditional socialists.Class categories are now intermingled with hierarchicalcategories based on race, gender, sexual preference, andcertainly national or regional differences. Status

    differentiations,characteristic of

    hierarchy, tend to converge with classdifferentiations, and a more all-inclusive

    capitalistic world is emerging in whichethnic, national, and gender differencesoften surpass the importance of classdifferences in the public eye. Thisphenomenon is not entirely new: in theFirst World War countless Germansocialist workers cast aside their earlier

    commitment to the red flags ofproletarian unity in favor of thenational flags of their well-fed and

    parasitic rulers and went on to plunge bayonets into thebodies of French and Russian socialist workersas theydid, in turn, under the national flags of their own

    oppressors.At the same time capitalism has produced a new,

    perhaps paramount contradiction: the clash between aneconomy based on unending growth and the desiccationof the natural environment.2This issue and its vastramifications can no more be minimized, let alonedismissed, than the need of human beings for food or air.At present the most promising struggles in the West,where socialism was born, seem to be waged less around

    income and working conditions than around nuclear

    power, pollution, deforestation, urban blight, education,health care, community life, and the oppression ofpeople in underdeveloped countriesas witness the(albeit sporadic) antiglobalization upsurges, in whichblue- and white-collar workers march in the same

    ranks with middle-class humanitarians and aremotivated by common social concerns. Proletariancombatants become indistinguishable from middle-classones. Burly workers, whose hallmark is a combativemilitancy, now march behind bread and puppet

    The more existential

    class struggle has not

    been eliminated any

    more than the

    bourgeoisie could

    eliminate gravity

  • 5/20/2018 Social Ecology

    24/68{24 } Harbinger - SPRING2003

    theater performers, often with a considerable measure ofshared playfulness. Members of the working and middleclasses now wear many different social hats, so to speak,challenging capitalism obliquely as well as directly oncultural as well as economic grounds.

    Nor can we ignore, in deciding what direction weare to follow, the fact that capitalism, if it is not

    checked, will in the futureand not necessarily thevery distant futurediffer appreciably from the system weknow today. Capitalist development can be expected tovastly alter the social horizon in the years ahead. Can

    we suppose that factories, offices, cities, residentialareas, industry, commerce, and agriculture, let alonemoral values, aesthetics, media, popular desires, and thelike will not change immensely before the twenty-firstcentury is out? In the past century, capitalism, above allelse, has broadenedsocial issues

    indeed, the historical social question ofhow a humanity, divided by classes and

    exploitation, will create a society basedon equality, the development ofauthentic harmony, and freedomtoinclude those whose resolution wasbarely foreseen by the liberatory socialtheorists in the nineteenth and earlytwentieth centuries. Our age, with its

    endless array of bottom lines andinvestment choices, now threatens toturn society itself into a vast and

    exploitative marketplace.3

    The public with which the progressive socialist hadto deal is also changing radically and will continue to do

    so in the coming decades. To lagin understandingbehind the changes that capitalism is introducing andthe new or broader contradictions it is producing wouldbe to commit the recurringly disastrous error that led tothe defeat of nearly all revolutionary upsurges in thepast two centuries. Foremost among the lessons that anew revolutionary movement must learn from the pastis that it must win over broad sectors of the middle classtoits new populist program. No attempt to replace

    capitalism with socialism ever had or will have the

    remotest chance of successwithout the aid of thediscontented petty bourgeoisie, whether it was theintelligentsia and peasantry-in-uniform of the RussianRevolution or the intellectuals, farmers, shopkeepers,clerks, and managers in industry and even in

    government in the German upheavals of 1918-21. Evenduring the most promising periods of past revolutionarycycles, the Bolsheviks, Mensheviks, the German SocialDemocrats, and Russian Communists neveracquiredabsolute majorities in their respective legislatives

    bodies. So-called proletarian revolutions wereinvariablyminority revolutions, usually even withinthe

    proletariatitself, and those that succeeded (often briefly,before they were subdued or drifted historically out ofthe revolutionary movement) depended overwhelminglyon the fact that the bourgeoisie lacked active supportamong its own military forces or was simply socially

    demoralized.

    GIVENTHECHANGESTHATWEAREWITNESSINGANDTHOSEthat are still taking form, social radicals can no longer

    oppose the predatory (as well as immensely creative)capitalist system by using the ideologies and methodsthat were born in the first Industrial Revolution, when afactory proletarian seemed to be the principalantagonist of a textile plant owner. (Nor can we use

    ideologies that were spawned by

    conflicts that an impoverishedpeasantry used to oppose feudal and

    semifeudal landowners.) None of theprofessedly anticapitalist ideologies ofthe pastMarxism, anarchism,syndicalism, and more generic forms ofsocialismretain the same relevancethat they had at an earlier stage ofcapitalist development and in an earlier

    period of technological advance. Norcan any of them hope to encompass themultitude of new issues, opportunities,

    problems, and interests that capitalism has repeatedlycreated over time.

    Marxism was the most comprehensive and coherent

    effort to produce a systematic form of socialism,emphasizing the material as well as the subjectivehistorical preconditions of a new society. This project,in the present era of precapitalist economicdecomposition and of intellectual confusion, relativism,and subjectivism, must never surrender to the newbarbarians, many of whom find their home in what wasonce a barrier to ideological regressionthe academy.We owe much to Marxs attempt to provide us with a

    coherent and stimulating analysis of the commodity and

    commodity relations, to an activist philosophy, asystematic social theory, an objectively grounded orscientific concept of historical development, and aflexible political strategy. Marxist political ideas wereeminently relevant to the needs of a terribly disoriented

    proletariat and to the particular oppressions that theindustrial bourgeoisie inflicted upon it in England in the1840s, somewhat later in France, Italy, and Germany,and very presciently in Russia in the last decade ofMarxs life. Until the rise of the populist movement in

    for the