the arc and the zip -- deleuze and lyotard on art

Upload: dekkn

Post on 14-Apr-2018

221 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    1/27

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP: DELEUZE AND LYOTARD ON ART

    ABSTRACT. Lyotard and Deleuze made extensive use of modern art to mount a

    critique of representation as part of their attack on the enlightenment subject. Art

    breaks out of received rules, conventions, forms, and cliches and is an instance of

    ethical if not revolutionary activity. Lyotard first developed these ideas through

    the concept of the Figure, which Deleuze later adopted. Figure is the desire or

    force that transgresses and deforms the good form of mimetic representation.

    Using Cezanne and Francis Bacon as paradigmatic examples, they argue that art

    creates new feelings and desires (Lyotard) or intensities and sensations (Deleuze).

    For Deleuze this is the model of ethical behavior the creation of new, pro-

    ductive forms of life free from the negativity of judgment. While Lyotard and

    Deleuze started from a common point, Lyotard changed his position in his later

    work on the sublime. Rather than positing a subject of purely affirmative desire

    and ideally free of the limitations of judgment, he posited a subject seized by and

    limited by the law. The subject is by nature divided: always already seized by and

    hostage to an Other, an unrepresentable excess or remainder. He is under an

    obligation to recollect and respond to the Other by bearing witness to it. The

    sublime experience of seizure by the law is exemplified in the paintings of Barnett

    Newman. While Deleuze would have done with judgment, Lyotard can neverhave done with it.

    KEY WORDS: aesthetics, art, Deleuze, ethics, Figure, judgment, Lyotard,

    representation, sublime

    INTRODUCTION

    For many theorists, critique begins with representation. Critical

    lawyers are, or should be, no less concerned with it. This critique

    consists of a rejection of the platonic, mimetic view of representation.

    It implies that there is a world and a cosmic order that defines the

    good, and that that world and good are isomorphically represented.

    This theory has its analogue in the rational, autonomous subject of

    the enlightenment. Representation is an instrument of reason and

    under the control of it.

    If you no longer believe that the subject is defined by reason; or

    if you no longer believe that there is an isomorphic relation be-

    tween reality, thought and image, then the whole enlightenment

    Law and Critique (2004) 15: 231257 Springer 2005

    DOI 10.1007/s10978-004-5434-8

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    2/27

    edifice falls. Representation and the autonomous enlightenment

    subject have been challenged on a number of fronts phenome-

    nological, existential, psychoanalytic, deconstructive, Deleuzian

    and, to the extent that these critiques have come into critical legal

    thought, it has been mainly in terms of language. The critical basis

    of representation, however, is wider than this and can extend into

    the visual. Two theorists who have done so are Lyotard and

    Deleuze.For Lyotard and Deleuze the crucial distinction is not between

    language and the visual but rather between the discursive and art.

    It is art that discovers the creation, deformation and/or limits ofrepresentation and they both delineated a critical category called

    Figure that is before, beneath or beyond representation. This

    means therefore that they were not primarily concerned with the

    content or meaning of images but rather with the way in which

    material or formal properties are the critical, if not fundamental

    element of art. Since visual art, particularly modern painting, keeps

    signification and representation to a minimum, it provides a par-

    ticularly fertile ground to explore these formal properties and both

    Lyotard and Deleuze discuss it extensively. In order to extend the

    critique of representation beyond its narrow focus on language, I

    focus here on visual art.1

    For Lyotard and Deleuze art is not just a weekend activity.

    For both, it gives access to dimensions of life that enlightenment

    theory ignored: the sensate (Deleuze) or the unconscious (Lyotard).

    It is a means of transformation and achieving change and some

    degree of liberation, not least from the illusion of the rational

    and autonomous subject and its theories of justice. Without art we

    are trapped in old and inadequate forms, like being trapped in old

    photos. Art creates its own kind of thought. As it turns out,

    however, although Lyotard and Deleuze started from positions

    that were sympathetic if not similar, they came to radically op-

    posed visions of what that thought was. For Deleuze art flees from

    law, for Lyotard art inscribes it.

    1 Note: Lyotard and Deleuze try to express what exists beyond the representa-

    tional content of language through their writing styles. As a result, discursive sum-

    mary or paraphrase is not entirely adequate. To the extent that is possible in a

    translation, I let them speak in their own words. It is ultimately these that will or will

    not move.

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    232

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    3/27

    LYOTARD I

    In all his works both philosophical and psychoanalytic Lyotard was

    interested in the remainder what escapes thought, knowledge and

    representation. There is something more than the rational subject and

    its productions, and in his early work this is the energy of drive and

    desire. For Lyotard, there is energy, drive and desire on the one hand,

    and rationality, structure and signification on the other hand. These are

    not resolved in representation; rather there is something that remains

    after (below, beyond) it. In discourse, signifiers do not fully re-present

    objects, be they from the external or internal world. Rather there isalways an irrational force that circulates and remains in excess. In his

    early book, Discourse, Figure, Lyotard called this excess Figure.2

    Discourse be it linguistic or visual is infected with Figure.

    First some definitions. Lyotard defined discourse narrowly as a

    structure of signification, more broadly as the informational use of

    language, but it has its analogue in painting. The discourse of

    painting would be rules of perspective, figuration or the well-formed

    image, and narration. For Lyotard, in painting and literature, mod-

    ern art revealed a dimension of language and the visual beyond the

    significative and discursive. This excess he called Figure.

    Lyotard introduced the concept of Figure in Discourse, Figure, along, complex, still untranslated book, written in a style meant to

    capture the excess in language. It analyzes the discursive and Figural

    elements in language and in painting but I will focus on the latter. To

    be precise, Lyotard identifies three kinds of figure. The first, Figure

    image, is what we normally call the figure (as in the distinction

    between figure and ground), the representation that we see in the

    picture of an object.3 It is a contour (an outline) and belongs to the

    visible order.4 The second, Figure-form, is present in the visible, is

    2 J.F. Lyotard, Discours, Figure (Paris: Editions Klinckseick, 1974). Parts have

    been translated in M. Lydon, The Dream-Work Does Not Think, in A. Benjamin,

    ed., The Lyotard Reader (Oxford: Blackwell, 1989), 1955 (Lyotard, ibid., 239270);

    M. Lydon, Fiscourse Digure: The Utopia behind the Scenes of Phantasy, Theater

    Journal 35/3, (October 1983), 333357 (Lyotard, ibid., 327355); M. Lydon, Veduta

    on Discours, figure, Yale French Studies 99 (2001), 1026; V. Constantinopoulous,

    Discourse, Figure: Digression on the Lack of Reality, Architectural Design (March

    1998), 3233 (Lyotard, ibid., 284286); M. Smith, From Discours, Figure, in H.

    Pietersma, ed., Merleau Ponty: Critical Essays (Lanham, MD: University Press of

    America, 1989), 309322 (Lyotard, ibid., 1823; 5359).3 Lyotard, ibid., 71.4 Lydon, Fiscourse Digure, supra n. 2, at 333n.

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    233

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    4/27

    itself visible if need be, but generally is not seen.5 It is the regulating

    line, the Gestalt of a configuration, the architecture of a painting. 6 It

    is an invisible scheme that organizes, as in the scheme of Euclidian

    space as seen in Renaissance perspective.7 This kind of pictorial

    representation is good form or a kind of plastic writing.8

    The third kind, figure-matrix, is the most important, is what

    others mean when they refer to Lyotards concept of the Figure,

    and is what I shall be discussing.9 It is invisible in principle but itis not a structure, which is an intelligible order.10 It comes from

    neither plastic nor textual space. Rather, the Figural comes from

    the other space, beyond the intelligible or rational, which is tosay, the unconscious. The Figure is called the matrix because it is

    the source of disruption to discourse. It is not a thing but an

    energy or a force, like the wind, that works on the discursive

    elements of language and art by disturbing or disrupting or com-

    plicating linguistic and visual representation. It blocks or brings

    together two discontinuous orders, e.g., signification and affectiv-

    ity, to produce what is logically incompatible.11 Thus Figure cre-

    ates a radical rupture with the rules of structural opposition that

    control signification, representation and rational discourse. Figure

    produces difference itself, which cannot be subsumed in the

    structure of oppositions in language, or into an image or a form in

    plastic art.12 In visual art, Figure disrupts the well formed image

    and transgresses the law of good form. It creates and/or is bad

    form or the formless. It is the working or movement of desire

    and is seen for example in Jackson Pollacks action painting, which

    is likened to drooling or dribbling.13

    Lyotards model for the Figure is Freuds Interpretation of

    Dreams: just as desire works on the figures in dreams and phantasies,

    5 Lyotard, supra n. 2, at 271.6 Lydon ,Fiscourse Digure, supra n. 2, at 333n.7 Lyotard, supra n. 2, 277.

    8Ibid., 271.9 A word of caution: terminology here is confusing. A figure is a shape or form, as

    for example the figure of a man or umbrella. A Figure, on the other hand, is a

    theoretical construct created by Lyotard and then used by Deleuze. I have tried to

    maintain a clear distinction between these two by the use of small and capital letters.10 Lydon, Fiscourse Digure, supra n. 2, at 333n.11 Y. Bois and R. Krauss, Formless: A Users Guide (New York: Zone Books,

    1997), 107.12 Lyotard, supra n. 2, 278.13 Ibid., at 277.

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    234

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    5/27

    so Figure works in linguistic and visual discourse.14 One of the rea-

    sons Lyotard was interested in Freuds model was that presentations

    in the unconscious are visual.15 There the word-presentations of

    waking thought are worked over and disguised through processes

    such as condensation and displacement. The dream pushes language

    into visual images and makes it spatial, somewhat like a newspaper

    text that has been crumpled.16 As it does this, it creates something

    different from waking thought. For Lyotard, therefore, the dream issomething that works; it is the effect on language of the force ex-

    erted by the figural (as image or as form).17 The dream molds the

    force of desire, and just as that libidinal force is exerted on thingpresentations in the dream, it is also exerted on linguistic and visual

    discourse to produce an excess.

    Two qualities of dreams (and phantasies) are significant for Ly-

    otards analysis of art. First, the unconscious is a-temporal: things

    that are sequential appear simultaneously and this transgresses the

    laws of rational thought. Second, since there is no negation in the

    unconscious contradictory things can appear together. Thus dreams

    and phantasies have the logic of but also or but and. Desire

    transforms everything into its opposite, holding both of these things

    together at once.18 This transgresses the laws of good (discursive)

    form.

    The capacity of something to be two different things is caused by

    the alteration or pulsation of the drives, Eros and the death drive. 19

    While Eros binds energy and conserves order, the death drive moves

    toward the external, toward a total discharge of energy, to return life

    to its original state; as such it unbinds energy and disrupts. Since the

    14 See also Lyotards critique of (early) Lacan in Lydon, Dream-work, supra n. 2,

    1955.15 Freud makes a distinction between word presentations and thing presenta-

    tions (which are visual). In conscious thought, thing-presentations are bound to

    word-presentations. In the unconscious, however, only thing-presentations are

    found. In dreams, word-presentations are treated as thing-presentations and undergothe primary processes (condensation, displacement, etc.) just as thing-presentations

    do. J. Laplanche and J.-B. Pontalis, The Language of Psychoanalysis (London:

    Karnac Books, 1973).16 Lyotard, supra n. 2, 247.17 Lydon, Dream-work, in supra n. 2, 51.18 R. Krauss, The Optical Unconsciousness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993),

    221. Krauss provides an excellent analysis of Lyotards interpretation of Freuds

    fantasy, A Child is Being Beaten.19 See the discussion in Lydon, Fiscourse Digure, supra n. 2, 352 ff.

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    235

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    6/27

    drives work independently of one another, they produce rhythms of

    pulsation. The drives do not form a complementary system, however,

    but rather are blocked together to occupy an identical position in

    (libidinal) space simultaneously.20 This is the analogue (and the

    source) for the Figure, as it both forms and de-forms.

    The charge and discharge of pulsation of the pleasure principle

    is an on/off throb, a recurrence, guaranteeing that an on will

    always follow an off . This creates good form or rhythm. Thepulsation associated with the death drive, however, is experienced

    as an interruption; existence followed by total extinction, as an

    absolute break, that discontinuity without end that is death. Thisis the formlessness of the death drive operating below the pleasure

    principle.21 Figure therefore expresses the pulsation of pleasure,

    but it is the pulse as well of death and attempts to say what

    cannot be said in discourse. It is not good form, rather it is the

    bad form: the vehicle of undoing form.22

    The Figure as both form and its transgression confines or ar-

    rests difference on the very brink of absolute difference (the dif-

    ference between life and death), on the razors edge in the

    state of tension between tension and discharge, life and death, life-

    death.23 Thus it repeats itself in the scansion of desire.24 What

    particularly interests Lyotard is the edge of the fracture or gap. In

    the same way that Freud hesitates between these two in the Fort/

    Da, figurality as difference is the opening up of a spacing. 25 Thus

    it is not an interval separating two terms that belong to the same

    order, but an utter disruption of the equilibrium between order

    and non-order. Figure de-constructs discourse: underneath the

    figural: difference the principle of disorder, the incitement to

    jouissance.26

    20 Ibid., 343. See also the discussion in G. Bennington, Lyotard: Writing the Event,

    (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1988), 98 ff.21 Krauss, supra n. 18, 222; Lydon, Fiscourse Digure, supra n. 2, 355.22 Bois, supra n. 12, 108.23 Lydon, Fiscourse Digure, supra n. 2, 355; Bennington, supra n. 21, 99.24 Lydon, Fiscourse Digure, supra n. 2, 355.25 This is not the spacing of opposition in a structure, the separating terms that

    belong on the same plane. Rather it is a fracture, or chasm, with two sides of

    widely differing altitudes. Lydon, Fiscourse Digure, supra n. 2, 354.26 Ibid., 334335. See J. Williams, Lyotard and the Political (London: Routledge,

    2000), 6671.

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    236

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    7/27

    CEZANNE

    According to Lyotard, all great art bears some degree of the form-less

    qualities of the Figure and he was interested in modern painting

    because it is primarily based on the Figure rather than on mimesis or

    the representation of nature. For Lyotard, art following Cezanne and

    Klee is the trace of an energy [affect] that condenses, displaces, fig-

    ures forth, elaborates, without regard for the recognizable.27 Paint-

    ing does not live by what it says or communicates, but by what

    affects it conducts.28 The paradigmatic example is Cezanne.

    We tend to forget a painting is simply colored paint on a flatcanvas. Instead we see a figure, a story, a meaning and read it like a

    text. Lyotard and Deleuze, however, are not interested in the semi-

    ology or iconology of paintings and are not interested in reading and

    interpreting figures like texts. Rather, they are interested in what lies

    outside of representation in the intensities, affects and sensations.

    Those are not found in the discourse of a painting but primarily in

    its materiality, in particular in color. In several instances they deal

    with painters who privileged color relations over form and contour.

    Cezanne is one of the greatest of the colorists.

    For Lyotard and Deleuze (and countless others) Cezanne is the

    founder of modern art. Both see Cezanne as the artist who broke withthe regulative regime of good form, the resolved and closed forms of

    representation. In painting, good form is found in the structure im-

    posed by Albertian perspective, in the contours of figures (whether

    ideal as in Leonardo or realistic as in Vermeer) and in narration

    (whether it be the Nativity or Rape of the Sabine Women). In

    painting, these elements are roughly the equivalent of words and

    grammatical rules in language and each poses a problem for the artist

    who would create something new. It is, for example, difficult to paint

    more than a single figure without introducing a narrative between the

    figures, a story indicated by the relation of the bodies or their ex-

    change of gazes. Cezannes paintings of bathers were revolutionary

    because there are a number of figures but they do not exchangeglances and this blocks any narrative relation. Or to take another

    example, Cezannes paintings of Mont Sainte-Victoire do not

    27 Lydon, Veduta, supra n. 2, 21 (Lyotard, supra n. 2, 238).28 Williams, supra n. 26, 70. Lyotard is responding to M. Merleau-Ponty,

    Cezannes Doubt, in Sense and Non-sense, H. Dreyfus and P. Dreyfus, trans.

    (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1964), 11.

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    237

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    8/27

    establish space through Albertian perspective but rather through his

    use of color.

    Lyotard returned to painting and to Cezanne throughout his

    works but it is sufficient here to locate his elementary point. Like

    Deleuze, he argues that the artists task is to break out of discourse

    received rules, forms, representations, and structures. This is the way

    to change and the artist is an exemplary revolutionary in experi-

    menting and working against structures and representations to createnew dispositions, i.e., new feelings, desires, intensities, transferences

    and combinations of affect.29 And the prime artist-revolutionary is

    Cezanne, who broke with the perspective, figuration and narrationthat has dominated art since the Quattrocento.

    Cezanne accomplished his revolution by abandoning contour in

    favor of the intensities and affects of color, in juxtapositions of single

    patches of color that work against representation and unified space.

    For Lyotard, Cezanne achieved a revolution similar to Freuds. Both

    rejected a principle of unity Freud, the unity of consciousness;

    Cezanne, the unity of image and perspective in favor of an un-

    suppressible principle of dispersion.30

    What Cezanne particularly disperses is the Renaissance canon

    of perspective (the syntax of painting). As Lyotard points out, the

    eye sees not only what the viewer focuses on frontally, but also

    what is on the periphery. Thus the eye and its percepts are not

    fixed but mobile. In focusing on an object, we repress the

    peripheral. Any attempt to analyze or grasp the periphery however

    reduces and falsifies it. There is therefore an irreconcilable differ-

    ence between focal and lateral vision. For Lyotard, the periphery

    is not merely blurred, it is other, and any attempt to grasp it loses

    it. Here is difference within the visible. What the artist needs to

    portray is the unbalanced configuration of space before any con-

    struction. 31 The truth of painting therefore is not signification or

    the straight lines of Albertian perspective but is posed otherwise

    as plasticity and desire, curved extension32

    29 Williams, supra n. 70 ff. See Lyotard, La peinture comme dispositif libidinal

    [1972] and Freud selon Ce zanne [1971], in Des Dispositifs Pulsionnels (Paris:

    Christian Bernard, 1980).30 Ibid., 75.31 Bennington, supra n. 20, 74.32 Lyotard, supra n. 2, 13. See B. Readings, Introducing Lyotard: Art and Politics

    (London: Routledge, 1991), 2426.

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    238

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    9/27

    This truth is revealed in Cezannes late paintings of Mont

    Sainte-Victoire. There space is no longer in any way representa-

    tional, it embodies, on the contrary, the deconstruction of the focal

    zone by the peripheral curved range of the field of vision The

    paintings do not present an image of the mountain out there,

    represented according to the rules of Euclidian space or good

    form. Rather they show the mountain in the process of giving

    itself to be seen, so to speak, the landscape as it might be seenbefore looking at it 33 They present the density or thickness of

    the visible which is lost once viewing is understood in term of

    vision, of the transparency of an object for a subject. For [Ce-zanne] the image is divided from itself by its simultaneous par-

    ticipation in radically different spaces, and the effect of this is to

    testify to something that cannot be represented.34 It testifies to the

    Figure, the unrepresentable excess of the image.

    Cezanne insisted that the unrepresentable could not be accessed

    by a grasping rationality but only through an active stillness or

    immobility, through waiting for the mountain to give itself up. He

    described this as waiting until little sensations arose, which sen-

    sations he then registered on canvas in multiple planes and layered

    patches of color. For Lyotard this welling up of sensation is the

    event, the irruption of the figural into good form or a field of

    knowledge.35 It permits the bodys own density to well up into the

    field of perception and carry along with it an unconscious that

    is the object of repression. The paintings of Mont Sainte-Victoire

    record the irruption of the Figural, which is to say, the irruption

    of Cezannes desire.36

    DELEUZE

    Although this was to change, Lyotards formations and deformations

    of the image through the pulsations of libidinal energy are not dis-similar to Deleuzes flows of energy. And indeed that part of

    33 Lydon, Veduta, supra n. 2, 22.34 Readings, supra n. 32, 23.35 Bennington, supra n., 75; cf. Discours Figure, supra n. 2, 21.36 Krauss, supra n., 218; cf. Discours Figure, supra n. 2, 21.

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    239

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    10/27

    Lyotards project was praised by Deleuze and Guattari in Anti-

    Oedipus.37 They are like flows that imply the breaks effected by

    points, just as the points imply the fluxion of the material they cause

    to flow or leak: the sole unity without identity is that of the break-

    flow. The pure figural element the figure-matrix Lyotard cor-

    rectly names desire38 This comports with Deleuze and Guattaris

    ideal of a positive energetics of the body bodies as desiring ma-

    chines or Bodies Without Organs before they have been disciplined,socialized and brought to judgment. For Deleuze and Guattari, such

    judgment is a form of negativity. It restrains or prevents the linking of

    desire (force) to a fundamental yes of affirmation. For Deleuze more the philosopher than Lyotard attacking negativity required a

    complete rethinking of representation and this required a complete

    rethinking of the Western philosophical tradition beginning with

    Plato. Negativity for Deleuze is founded on illusion. It is not some-

    thing etched in nature but is simply a socially-induced restriction to

    the intensity and positivity of force. Negative desire and the ethics it

    generates is one of the problems to which Deleuzes philosophy and

    aesthetics respond.

    From his earliest work, Deleuze argues that the entire edifice of

    philosophical conceptualization the method of determining con-

    cepts, the concepts themselves and the representation of concepts is

    faulty. The metaphysical foundations are based on illusions, as are

    conceptualizations of the subject, the moral law, and ethics. Deleuze

    will replace this with a philosophy of immanence derived from a

    minority tradition including inter alia the Stoics, Leibniz, Spinoza,

    37 G. Deleuze and F. Guattari, Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, R.

    Hurley, et al. trans. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983), 243. There

    is, however, another half to the story of Lyotards Freudianism (as there was for

    Freud). Lyotard treats not only the deformation of images in the unconscious. He

    also treats the way in which these are staged in scenarios that express the repressed

    wish and it is clear that, implicitly at least, he adopted Freuds view of the law of

    castration which means desire is grounded in lack. Thus the positive energy of the

    Figure conflicts with the negative desire of the wish. In the second part of their review

    of Discourse, Figure, Deleuze and Guattari criticize Lyotard precisely on this point

    insofar as it prevented him from linking desire to a fundamental yes. Ibid. Lyotard

    later claimed that Discourse, Figure was too bound up with Freud and too beholden

    to the idea of the wish. Although he claimed that along with Levinas, Freud had been

    his constant companion, he did not write anything overtly psychoanalytic until his

    last and incomplete writings on the theme of infancy and nachtraglichkeit. He used

    this, however, not as a psychoanalytic concept but rather as a philosophical one to

    think a kind of knowledge that consciousness cannot access.38 Ibid., 244.

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    240

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    11/27

    Hume, Bergson and Nietzsche. His resultant logic of sensation finds

    expression in modern art, beginning with Cezanne but seen most

    explicitly in the work of Francis Bacon.

    Deleuzes critique of representation is somewhat different from,

    and more developed than Lyotards, in that it was tied to a more

    general critique of the way in which concepts of the Western philo-

    sophical tradition have come into being. His critique of philosophical

    method can be seen in Bergsonism and then in Difference and Repe-

    tition.39 He criticizes Platos abstraction of singularities into abstract

    forms or essences, as well as Aristotelian method, which distributes

    these into categories, i.e., a static structure of abstraction. In thistradition, concepts are copies of forms and representation follows the

    concept; it is mimesis. For Deleuze, however, it is the other way

    around. Representation determines and then reifies illusory concepts.

    Representation therefore is not a vehicle for establishing truth or the

    good. It is precisely the opposite representation simply embodies

    and crystallizes illusory conceptions.

    What holds for representations in philosophy holds for conven-

    tions and cliches in every day life. In the Platonic tradition, actions

    are measured by the transcendent criteria of a form (e.g., the Good),

    as are the moral law and social conventions. But for Deleuze, these

    criteria are representations and hence illusions. Furthermore, repre-

    sentations have constituted various regimes of signs that have been

    used to enforce social order (what kind of regime depends on the

    social set-up of power).40 Regimes use representations to codify the

    world in general and the body in particular and then regulate these

    through the moral law as well as through social conventions and

    orthodox beliefs. The point for Deleuze therefore is that it is not

    enough to attack representation; it is just the tail of the dog. What is

    necessary is to rethink the whole tradition of philosophical concepts

    and this must start with a different method of thinking.

    For Deleuze, the tradition of essences and their predications takes

    an original multiplicity or heterogeneity of forces the infinite inter-

    actions in which they occur and the infinite varieties they produce and suppresses their difference. Materials have their own singularities,

    idiosyncrasies, and their own intensities or forces and traditional

    39 G. Deleuze, Bergsonism, H. Tomlinson and B. Habberjam, trans. (New York:

    Zone Books, 1988); G. Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, P. Patton, trans. (New

    York: Columbia University Press, 1994).40 See R. Bogue, Deleuze on Music, Painting, and the Arts (London: Routledge,

    2003), 83.

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    241

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    12/27

    philosophy denies the reality of pure difference a sensible existence of

    its own. Reality is constituted by forces and these continuously

    interact to produce difference, i.e., the differential resulting from the

    confrontation of forces. Since all phenomenon is in the final analysis

    the action and interaction of force, life is becoming rather than being,

    natura naturans rather than natura naturata. Thus he replaces tradi-

    tional theories of form and matter with the forces of becoming and of

    creating. For Deleuze beyond prepared [formed] matter lies anenergetic materiality in continuous variation, and beyond fixed form

    lie qualitative processes of deformation and transformation in con-

    tinuous development.41

    Life is the endless and dynamic occurrence ofevents of germination, deformation, and recreation. At the most

    fundamental level, life is the collision and interaction of forces and

    affects rather than a static array of bodies, beings, or forms.

    For Deleuze traditional philosophical concepts have ultimately

    produced a vision of the world constituted by organic bodies

    organized and hierarchically ordered and hence regulated, forms.

    While Deleuzes theory of force applies to all bodies, his observations

    apply most especially to the body we call human. For Deleuze a body

    is not an organism a coordinated, unified, regulated whole, with

    senses that operate together in their reports of the outside world.42

    Rather it should be understood as a body without organs (BWO),

    an intensive body of sensation, sensation being an interaction of

    forces. The BWO is a membrane across or through which forces flow,

    a mediator between one body and the world of other bodies. Thus

    whatever organization is attributed to the body is provisional, always

    in the course of becoming or deforming.

    For Deleuze, the forces of sensation are immanent in all interac-

    tions of and with material. This is a world of invisible forces and

    visible bodies, the body of sensation rendering visible the invisible

    forces that play through bodies.43 In Discourse, Figure, Lyotard re-

    gards these forces as the unconscious workings of desire. For Deleuze,

    however, there is no distinction between mind and other phenomena.

    Not only is desire energy and force but all phenomena are assemblagesof force. While these differences are substantial, for both Lyotard and

    Deleuze, art or the Figure is what makes the invisible force appear.

    41 D. Smith , Deleuzes Theory of Sensation: Overcoming the Kantian Duality, in

    P. Patton ed., Deleuze: A Critical Reader (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996), 43.42 Supra n. 124.43 Ibid., 125.

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    242

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    13/27

    If for Deleuze the function of philosophy is to create new con-

    cepts, the function of art is to create new sensations and this entails

    releasing the sensation beneath and beyond representation. As for

    Lyotard, the function of art is not to imitate but to appear. 44 Art

    makes visible the invisible force for Lyotard the force of desire, for

    Deleuze the force of sensation. For Deleuze, art creates the experi-

    ence of sensation by bypassing the brain and showing on the nerves

    the intensities and collisions of forces. Thus art is a matter ofexhibiting singularities and capturing intensities, just as for Lyotard it

    is a matter of capturing the pulsations of drives. For both, this re-

    quires artistic experimentation in order to break or loosen repressiveand oppressive structures. Deleuze, in particular, emphasizes the fact

    that art is the creation of something new (although implicitly Lyotard

    would agree). Art creates something that is not representation, cliche

    or a conventional way of seeing things, nor is it the visual equivalent

    of signification separated from bodies and their desires.

    For Deleuze, the particular force of painting is that it shows the

    reality of a body without organs, a body freed from organic represen-

    tation. (Lyotards Figure, the formless or bad form produced by desire

    is not dissimilar.) This is accomplished by forming and deforming

    images through the use of color. For Deleuze, therefore, what Cezanne

    paints is the body, not insofar as it is represented as an object, but

    insofar as it is experienced as sustaining this sensation45 He shows

    the sensation and the world of becoming, the folding force of moun-

    tains, the germinative force of a seed, the thermic force of a landscape,

    the applyness of apples.46 In Cezannes art, therefore, beyond figu-ration and representation there is sensation and that comes from a

    power that exceeds every domain and traverses them all. This is a

    power of rhythm, a power more profound than vision, hearing, etc..

    As Cezanne said, this is a logic of the senses and is neither rational,

    nor cerebral. 47

    Deleuzes rhythm of sensation is somewhat similar to Lyotards

    pulsations. It ultimately goes back to Klees theories of artistic

    44 Ibid., 118, citing Henri Maldiney, Regard Parole Space (Lausanne: Editions

    lAge dHomme, 1973).45 G. Deleuze, Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation (London: Continuum, 2003),

    35.46 Ibid., 57, 87. See D.H. Lawrence, Introduction to These Paintings, Phoenix:

    The Posthumous Papers (New York, 1936), 578579.47 Supra n. 45, 42.

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    243

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    14/27

    creation, but Deleuzes immediate source is the phenomenologist

    and art historian, Henri Maldiney, who identifies three movements

    in the creation of painting.48 First, there is a chaotic world of

    sensation (Cezannes abyss), then an opening toward creation, a

    point that leaps into the realm of order and begins to move.49

    Then comes a systolic condensation of elements in which self and

    world are separated from chaos and definite shapes are formed.

    That is followed by a diastolic eruption of forces that dissolvesthose shapes and establishes a pathic communication among the

    components of the whole (Cezannes ecstasy, the blues!).50 Then

    the chaos returns and it starts again. The systolic-diastolic patternis a rhythm of formation and deformation, appearing and disap-

    pearing. For Maldiney this was the rhythm of the lived body. For

    Lyotard it was the dissonant rhythm of the pulsations of the

    drives, of binding and unbinding, of transformation and defor-

    mation in dreams and Figure. For Deleuze however it is the

    rhythm of the affective forces immanent within the real. 51

    Along with Lyotard, Deleuze saw Cezannes revolution devel-

    oping in two different ways in 20th century art: into pure

    abstraction, as in Mondrians geometrical paintings, and into ab-

    stract expressionism and action painting, as in Pollacks dribbles of

    paint. For Deleuze, however, the problem with abstract art is that

    it minimizes the force of chaos and is too dependent on line. It is

    cerebral and had become a new code and form of representation

    or signified. Abstract expressionism goes to the other extreme and

    is immersed in the chaos of materiality. It cannot stand on its

    own (literally: Pollack worked on a horizontal canvas). Deleuze

    finds his ideal in Francis Bacons art of figuralism, a third way

    between the figurative and the abstract.52

    48 Maldiney, supra n. 44.49 Bogue, supra n. 40, 119 quoting Paul Klee, J. Spiller, ed., Notebooks, Vol. 1, R.

    Manheim, trans. (New York: Wittenborn Art Books 1961), 4.50 Ibid., 120.51 R. Bogue, Gilles Deleuze: The Aesthetics of Force, in P. Patton, ed, Deleuze: A

    Critical Reader (London: Blackwell, 1996), 264.52 Images of Bacons paintings, arranged by year, can readily be found at

    www.francis-bacon.cx

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    244

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    15/27

    Bacons work is exemplary for Deleuze. It is figurative, indeed al-

    most exclusively focused on the human body but these figures are

    neither idealized nor naturalistic and in some ways they are analogous

    to Cezannes mountains. Furthermore, throughout his work Bacon

    was interested in the tensions or forces experienced by the body a

    cough, hiccup, spasm, the desire to sleep, to vomit, turn over53

    While these may be ordinary tensions, they show the body rousing itself

    in minor movements from one state to another, which is to say, showthe movement and collision of energies. Although Bacon claimed he

    was interested in the inertia of bodies, for Deleuze the dominant

    characteristic of Bacons paintings is movement, large or small. On agrander scale, therefore, it can be said that Bacons paintings move

    between inertia and arousal, figuration and deformation, contour and

    chaos to create Figure the rhythms of force that stand on their own.54

    Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation is a stunning combination

    of the originality of Deleuze and the genius of Bacon, characteris-

    tically including a minority tradition, in this case, of art historians.

    It is a brilliant reading of Bacon (sometimes literally: it relies

    heavily on Bacons interviews with David Sylvester).55 One can see

    however the way in which Deleuze extends the idea of force and

    with it Lyotards Figure (or the Figural). What Deleuze calls the

    Figure emerges in Bacons paintings through the various combina-

    tions and renditions of contour, form and structure (space). For

    Deleuze the Figure in Bacon does not just show the forces that

    operate under and destroy the figurative or representation. Rather it

    goes beyond deformation to render sensation in itself. Where for

    Lyotard the Figure is the energy and work of desire, for Deleuze it

    is the rhythm of Life.

    In approaching Bacons style, Deleuze first shows the various ways

    in which Bacon presents sensation. He then deepens the analysis to

    show how the forces of the sensations are composed through Bacons

    material and techniques. Deleuze therefore identifies the three basic

    elements of Bacons paintings: these are figure (bodies), contour

    (rings, cubes, etc. which enclose bodies), and structure (the mono-chromatic ground of color). He further distinguishes the Figure or

    53 Supra n. 45, 59.54 See J. Williams, Deleuze on J.M.W. Turner, in K. Ansell-Pearson, ed., Deleuze

    and Philosophy: The Difference Engineer (London: Routledge, 1997), 233246.55 The Brutality of Fact: Interviews with Francis Bacon, 19621979, D. Sylvester,

    ed., 3rd edn. (London: Thames & Hudson, 1987), 48.

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    245

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    16/27

    Figural from the figurative or representation. It implies the rela-

    tionship of an image to an object that it is supposed to illustrate. 56

    As had been the case with Cezanne, Bacons accomplishment was to

    liberate the Figure from the figurative, i.e., from representation,

    illustration and narrative.

    Deleuze goes on to identify genres in Bacons paintings roughly

    corresponding to periods in his work. In the first genre, Bacon iso-

    lates single figures. In the second, he couples them. The third genre isrepresented by triptychs, which present multiple figures on separate

    panels. Each of the genres combines the elements of figure, contour

    and structure to produce three kinds of movements or collisions offorce. The three movements of isolation, deformation, and dissipa-

    tion are analytic moments that illustrate more generally the logic of

    sensation.

    In the first movement of isolation, Bacon situates a single body in

    a ring, box etc. The field (background color) envelops the contour

    and presses in on the body to create vibrations between the two. This

    is the systolic movement toward the condensation of a shape and the

    vibration it creates characterizes simple sensation.

    In the second and diastolic movement, the figure is deformed as

    [a]n intense movement flows through the whole body, a deformed

    and deforming movement57 Something inside it is happening and

    exerting effort to free itself in order to become a Figure, become

    being the operative word.58

    For Deleuze the primary becoming of man is becoming-animal.

    Roughly this means returning to un-organized and dis-organized

    materiality, which for Deleuze is the common fact between man,

    animal and nature. Bacon, for example, often treats the body or flesh

    as meat.59 There is then a tension between the meat-flesh and the

    more durable structure of bone, spine and teeth. For Deleuze [m]eat

    is the state of the body in which flesh and bone confront each

    other60 Flesh sinks into bone; it is drowsy, weighed down,

    56 Supra n. 45, 2.57 Ibid., 19.58 Bogue, supra n. 40, 127.59 Bacon in supra n. 45, 24. (Bacon was fascinated by meat and carcasses in

    butcher shops: Of course we are potential carcasses. Supra n. 55, 46). See e.g.,

    Painting, 1946; Figure with Meat, 1954.60 Supra n. 45, 22.

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    246

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    17/27

    wounded, suffering. Bone on the other hand rises up through flesh as,

    for example, the spine shows through a stretched back or teeth rise up

    through the soft flesh of the mouth.61

    One of Bacons most characteristic deformations is of the face.

    For Deleuze the face is a structured, spatial organization that con-

    ceals the head. The head is the more interesting organ since it is

    dependent on the body and, as such, more integral to it.62 Rather

    than the face being the locus of spirit (as in conventional portraits)the head is a spirit in bodily form It is the animal spirit of

    man63 The head-meat is a becoming-animal of man.64 Bacon

    captures this by undoing the face to reveal the head: in Bacons manyportraits, the face is rubbed out and distorted to reveal somewhat

    animal-like features, like an animal we had been sheltering.65 In

    these deformations, Bacon creates a zone of indiscernability or un-

    decidability, which only art can penetrate.66 The zones of undecid-

    ability here are between man and animal. Man becomes animal,

    animal becomes spirit and most importantly, sensation is seen to pass

    from one to another.

    The third movement of force is dissipation, which completes the

    diastolic. The body presses outward, trying to pass out of itself and its

    contour to dissolve into the field of color. Bacon has several paintings

    of a figure bending or vomiting over a washbasin, or sitting on a

    toilet, or staring into a mirror. It is shown trying to escape or flow out

    of itself, to disappear down or through a hole. The escape is into the

    field of color and into materiality. The contour of the figure becomes

    a membrane as the figure moves toward or into the field of color, the

    material structure.67 In Figure at a Washbasin, 1976, for example, the

    61 Ibid. See e.g., Head I, 1949; Three Figures and a Portrait, 1975. The difference

    between meat/flesh and bone is evidenced in Bacons fascination with the crucifixion:

    on the one hand, the sublime religiosity of the crucifixion shows an attempt to

    redress the body upright toward the radiance of the heavens, but, on the other hand,

    all transcendent uplift is countered by the weighty pulling of the flesh downward

    toward its own animality. D. Polan, Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, in C.Boundas and D. Olkowski, eds., Deleuze and the Theater of Philosophy (London:

    Routledge, 1994), 238. See Three Studies for Figures at the Base of the Crucifixion,

    1944; Three Studies for a Crucifixion, 1962; Triptych Crucifixion, 1965.62 Supra n. 45, 20.63 Ibid.64 Ibid., 27.65 Ibid., 21. See e.g., Three Studies for Self Portrait, 1973.66 Ibid.67 Ibid., 15.

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    247

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    18/27

    body exerts an intense motionless effort upon itself to escape down

    the blackness of the drain, to destiny.68 In escaping from itself, it

    discovers the materiality of which it is composed.69

    In a similar vein, the body can be shown in process of a full and

    violent becoming, racked by spasms, wrenching cries, vibrant thrusts

    of transmuting flesh.70 The most famous examples are Bacons

    paintings after Velasquezs portrait of Pope Innocent X.71 Innocents

    scream is the operation through which the entire body escapesthrough the mouth.72 It seems to flow into the field, as if the color

    itself screams. This is what Deleuze means by painting the invisible

    force, the sensation of the scream itself, not the horror beyond it,which would be a representation.73

    Bacons final and most impressive genre is the triptych.74 These

    are three panels with figures but without the traditional narrative

    element. On each panel, single and/or double figures enter into

    movements and produce sensations along the lines described above.

    On top of those, however, further sensations are produced as the

    sensations of the single panels interact. The sensations draw apart

    from their individual panels and are released across the panels. This

    produces multiple interactions and movements that explode across

    the panels verticalhorizontal, descentrise, diastolesystole,

    nakedclothed, augmentationdiminution.75 Sensations overlap. As

    the figures move across the panels in all directions, they are sent into

    accumulating and accelerating waves of transformation and undergo

    endless change. The limits of sensation are broken, exceeded in all

    directions.76 As color passes into the figure and the figure passes intocolor, the separation of force and material, sensation and body is

    transcended. The intensive rhythm of force (systolicdiastolic) is no

    longer dependent on figure but becomes the Figure.77

    68 Ibid.69

    Ibid., 5455.70 Polan, supra n. 61, 237.71 Among the many, see those painted in 1949 1951, 1953, 1960, 1961.72 Ibid., 16.73 Ibid., 60. See supra n. 55, 48.74 See e.g., Three Figures in a Room, 1964; Three Studies of the Human Body I &

    II, 1970; Triptych In Memory of George Dyer, 1971; Triptych MayJune, 1973.75 Polan, supra n. 61, 244.76 Supra n. 45, 73.77 Ibid., 71, 73.

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    248

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    19/27

    If Deleuze describes what Bacon achieves, he is no less interested

    in how he achieves it. The artist is someone who creates something

    new, in this case sensation, but his manner of creation is no less a

    lesson for all. According to Deleuze (and Bacon himself) there is no

    blank canvas; one necessarily starts with representations, crystallized

    images and cliches (Bacon often started his projects with reproduc-

    tions, prints and photos). They form the initial image or plan that is

    then disrupted by a catastrophe. This could be a line or patch ofcolor that goes off in a new direction, a random mark, a smudge, a

    sponge thrown at the canvas; it becomes a manual diagram that

    suggest new lines to develop. As the catastrophe scrambles or de-forms the initial image, the painting begins to take on a different

    shape. It moves away from the original form and enters the world of

    intuition and accident. (Deleuze quotes the Talking Heads: I am

    changing my shape; I feel like an accident.)78

    There is a zone of indiscernability between the catastrophe and the

    new image. The one is no longer and the other is not yet. This is the

    germinative chaos out of which the new form or rhythm emerges, the

    self-forming, self-shaping activity of art. The essential point about

    the diagram is that it is made in order for something [the Figure] to

    emerge from it and if nothing emerges from it, it fails.79

    The Figure emerges from the catastrophe through the force of

    color. As Cezanne first demonstrated, you must pass through the

    catastrophe for colors to arise80 Color provides a differential

    relation of forces, the result of which is sensation. Thus the color

    system itself is a system of direct action on the nervous system.81 It isthe differential relation upon which everything else depends. The

    expansion of color generates Figural form but this is not represen-

    tation, mimetic form or form imposed by contour. Rather it is a form

    that is generated from within, that arises from within the field of

    color, or the field of color forces. The formula of the colorists is: if

    you push color to its pure internal relations then you have

    everything.82 While structure, figure and contour can be thought in

    78 See, e.g., Deleuzes discussion of Painting, 1946, supra n. 45, 156.79 Ibid., 159.80 Ibid., 111. See Conversations with Cezanne, M. Doran, ed., J. Cochran, trans.

    (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2001), 114115.81 Ibid., 52. Deleuze liked Godards formula, its not blood, its red. See G.

    Deleuze, Cinema 1: The Movement Image, H. Tomlinson and B. Habberjam, trans.

    (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1986), 118.82 Supra n. 45, 139.

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    249

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    20/27

    terms of forces, they all converge in (the force of) color. They are

    little more than pieces of a larger permutational or modulatory

    assemblage governed by the vibratory powers of color83 It is color

    that transforms reality.

    In the section entitled Analogy, Deleuze discusses his problem

    with structuralism, which is, as it was for Lyotard, the way in which it

    is based on clear-cut units and rigorous oppositions. This he likens to

    digital technology. Deleuzes model is more like the modulation andgradation of analogue technology.84 In painting color acts as the

    modulatory assemblage. It is a force of permutation of the various

    elements of structure and contour. It is an assemblage into whichfigurative forms are fed and out of which haptic color relations

    emerge.85 Through the juxtapositions and modulations of hues there

    is no longer an inside nor an outside, but only a continuous creation

    of space, the spatializing energy of color.86 The interactions between

    colors create continuous and variable movements oscillations,

    perturbations, flows, twists, spasms, jolts and result in the forms of

    the completed canvas, not as objects to be represented, but as

    products of a self-forming process whereby color in its systolic and

    diastolic unfolding spatializes space, spreads into monochrome

    fields, fills out figures, communicates across contour membranes.87

    The colors and the forms they create render visible the invisible forces

    inherent in sensation working through the figure.88

    In Bacons painting there is then first representation, crystallized

    image and cliche. Subsequently, by virtue of the catastrophe and

    diagram, it is deformed, reformed and subsumed within a field of

    non-organic forces, i.e., color. At this point figures are hollowed out

    and the Figure emerges from the catastrophe. Here we witness the

    revelation of the body beneath the organism [the BWO], which makes

    organisms and their elements crack or swell, imposes a spasm on

    them, and puts them in relation with forces 89 The Figure here

    takes on its particular Deleuzian twist: heterogeneous forms may be

    caught up in the Figure. Bacon provides the final Deleuzian lesson in

    83 Polan, supra n. 61, 251.84 See Bogue, supra n. 40, 132 ff.85 Ibid., 157.86 Supra n. 45, 134.87 Bogue, supra n. 40, 157.88 Supra n. 45, 151.89 Ibid., 160.

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    250

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    21/27

    the multiplicity, difference and possibility that comes before repre-

    sentation. In this, the Figure is a matter of fact.

    Not only the figures but also the painting itself must go from the

    possibility of fact to fact itself where the whole is given at once.90 As

    the hand executes the diagram the apparently arbitrary elements of

    the painting coagulate in a single continuous flow that has its own

    movement.91 This is where painting discovers how to pass from the

    possibility of fact to the fact itself the pictorial fact.92 Themovement of force through the hand takes over from eye/mind to

    achieve a new thing a new Figure arising through the material or

    color. This is a way of seeing with the hand. With this the work of artquits the domain of representation to become experience.93

    What we witness is an elaborate and continuous circulation of

    force. It is not the imposition of form or concept seen by the eye and

    the cognitive powers. Rather, as the painting takes on a life of its

    own, the artist is as much led as leading. The painting develops, he

    responds. He moves on a level of force that bypasses the brain and

    works directly through the hand. For Deleuze this is where the

    dichotomy between subject and object breaks down, where force and

    formation in the artist and the Figure are one. For Deleuze, this

    passage to haptic vision is the great moment in the act of painting.

    This is where the artist seizes hold of life.94

    If there is a definition of the ethical in Deleuze this is it: to effectuate

    force and seize hold of life; to resist and liberate life from illusion,

    opinion, dead ideas and representations. Art is and shows the way to

    becoming-ethical, a process that necessarily defies law and judgment.

    In an essay entitled To Have done with Judgment, Deleuze argues,

    along with Nietzsche, that Christianity (including Kant) established a

    new form of power: the power to judge.95 It organizes an organic

    body, creates identifications and representations that constrain, and

    judges any deviations. It puts man under an eternal debt or obligation

    that can never be paid off. He is always before a judge (or the internal

    judge of the superego) who applies the law of a transcendent good. This

    90 Ibid., 159.91 Ibid., 160.92 Ibid.93 G.Deleuze Difference and Repetition, P. Patton, trans (London: Athlone, 1994),

    56.94Supra n. 45, 161.95 G. Deleuze, Essays Critical and Clinical, D.W. Smith and M.A. Greco, trans.

    (London: Verso, 1998).

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    251

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    22/27

    prevents the emergence of any new mode of existence.96 To be ethical,

    one must create the new and to do that one must have done with

    judgment: what has value can be made or distinguished only by defying

    judgment.97 By understanding the bodys intensities, its becomings,

    and its will to power, one affirms ones forces and wrestles with

    antagonistic forces. The ethical is therefore a process, of resisting, of

    loosening up rigid molar structures so that they become more molec-

    ular and permeable, of creating situations for de-territorialization andof pursuing lines of flight.98 In all these cases it is a question of

    beginning with difference, with the heterogeneous, multiplicitous

    energies and relations that constitute vital force, of seizing hold of life.One must harness forces and join them to create new ensembles, to

    expand them and to paraphrase D.H. Lawrence, to make them whirl

    until they harness the maximum force in all directions. 99 Thus the

    ethical is what is creative creating new forms be they individual, social

    or political in order to bring forth the difference that has until now

    only been possible, just as Bacon did in his paintings. This is the way to

    a justice that is opposed to all judgment.100

    LYOTARD II

    While Deleuze followed these Neitzschean paths of the positive desireof affirmation, in Libidinal Economy Lyotard intensified the positive

    desire that had been implicit in Discourse, Figure.101 He reports,

    however, that in the process, he came up against the terror of

    injustice, and this could not be solved without consideration of

    law.102 That led him to Kant and Levinas and an extended engage-

    ment with the concept of the sublime.

    The sublime is the experience of something so immense and

    overpowering that the rational faculties are dismantled and the

    powers of representation come to their limit. For Lyotard the sublime

    is the experience of the event, the shock of the absolute Other (aka

    96 Ibid., 135.97 Ibid.98 See Williams, supra n. 54.99 Supra n. 95, 134.100 Ibid., 127.101 J.-F. Lyotard, Libidinal Economy, I.H. Grant, trans. (London: Athlone Press,

    1993) (1st published, 1974).102 J.-F. Lyotard, Just Gaming, W. Godzich, trans. (Manchester: Manchester

    University Press, 1985).

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    252

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    23/27

    excess, lack, void, abyss). It is the experience of a differend that

    reason cannot comprehend and it cannot be represented. It presents

    the unpresentable.

    For Lyotard, the essence of the sublime experience is its affects of

    pleasure and pain (here he borrows from Burke). It is the threat of

    privation (hunger, cold, dark and death) and the fear that nothing

    more will take place followed by relief that, in the midst of the terror,

    something is happening.103 (It is similar to the on/off pulsation ofdrives described in Discours, Figure and in his late works, he identified

    it with primary affect which is only experienced later in apre`s coup.)104

    Lyotard analogizes the experience of the sublime to Kants sei-zure by the moral law. (The content of that law is unknowable and

    unrepresentable as are the criteria for judgments.) He combined this

    with the Levinasian idea that the subject is always already hostage to

    the Other. For Lyotard the sublime is the call or command of the

    Other that places us under an obligation and judges us. We are taken

    hostage by the sublime event and bound to an Other that cannot be

    cognized or represented. The sublime event presents both the Other

    as the excess of representation something that has no representa-

    tion and the command that we bear witness to it. It is only through

    the leveling of reason that we become receptive to this event. With

    this turn to the law, against the unrestrained force of Bacon, Lyotard

    juxtaposes the austerities of Barnett Newman.

    NEWMAN

    Barnett Newman was an abstract expressionist associated with

    Rothko and Pollock and most known for his vast and rigorously

    abstract color field paintings. They are distinguished by a flat, uni-

    form field of color divided from top to bottom by two or three thin

    lines of contrasting color called zips. Whos Afraid of Red, Yellowand Blue III for example is approximately one meter by two me-

    ters.105 On the left edge there is a thin strip of bright yellow, on the

    103 J.-F. Lyotard, Newman: The Instant, in The Lyotard Reader, supra n. 2, 240

    49, 245. See also The Sublime and the Avant Garde, in The Lyotard Reader, supra

    n. 2, 196211.104 See for example Heidegger and the jews, A. Michel and M. Roberts, trans.

    (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1990) and Emma: Between Philoso-

    phy and Psychoanalysis, in H.J. Silverman, ed., Lyotard: Philosophy, Politics, and

    the Sublime (London: Routledge, 2002).105 Excellent reproductions of Newmans paintings can be found in A. Temkin,

    Barnett Newman (Philadelphia: Philadelphia Museum of Art, 2002).

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    253

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    24/27

    right edge a somewhat wider strip of darkish blue. A vast expanse of

    bright orange-red stretches between them. There is no figure, no

    depth, nothing beyond the smooth, flat field of color. Newman

    painted the zips having first applied masking tape to outline them.

    When the zips were dry he tore off the tape and this leaves the

    impression that the strip is incised into the field of color.

    For Lyotard, the experience of a Newman painting is the experience

    of the now of the sublime. It presents the occurrence, the momentwhich has arrived, the visual event in itself. There is no message; the

    painting announces nothing; it is in itself an annunciation and

    Newman allows it to present itself. The only purpose of Newmanspaintings is to present the presentation.106

    As Simon Malpas points out, Lyotards selection of Newman is not

    entirely fortuitous. Newman himself wrote extensively on the meta-

    physics of painting, as well as on the sublime, and he insisted that the

    subject matter of his paintings is artistic creation itself, a symbol of

    Creation itself .107 This is why he called his strips of color zips, from

    the Hebrew word tzimtzum, meaning the moment at which Yahweh

    created the world by separating himself from the cosmos. In Onement

    I, for example, a dark brownish-red field is bisected by a lighter

    brownish-red zip. For Newman, creation comes out of chaos, its

    beginning re-enacted by a line on empty canvas. Like a flash of

    lightningin thedarkness or a line on an empty surface,in Creation, the

    Word separates, divides, institutes a difference and therefore inau-

    gurates a sensible world a world of color, of the painting.108 Without

    the flash there would only be chaos but the flash of the tzimtzum,thezip

    breaks light into colors and arranges them across the surface like a

    universe.109 Creation (including artistic creation) is like the sublime

    event: it is what happens (this) in the midst of the indeterminate.110

    What happens is the sublime event of the painting before us.

    Newmans most ambitious work is a series of fourteen black

    and white paintings of the Stations of the Cross entitled Lema

    Sabachthani (why hast thou forsaken me?). For Lyotard, We are still

    106 Newman, supra n. 103, 241, 244.107 Ibid., 243. See S. Malpas, Sublime Ascesis: Lyotard, Art and the Event,

    Angelaki 7 (2002) 199211, 201 and T. Hess, Barnett Newman (New York: Museum

    of Modern Art, 1971).108 Newman, supra n., 243.109 Ibid., 246.110 Ibid., 243.

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    254

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    25/27

    waiting for the Messiah who will bring meaning to human suffering.111

    Appended to the series is another painting, now entitled Be II. It is

    white with a cadmium red zip on one side and ragged black one on the

    other (perhaps signifying man and death, respectively). The painting

    does not offer a resolution or solution to Christs question. Rather it

    presents a command Be: the recurrence of a prescription emanating

    from silence112 Be the relief that there is is the response to the

    terror of forsaken man.113 This is the sublime event: in the instant, outof nothing, something is happening: light and color are happening.

    This instant of Newmans paintings is the birth of the ethical. For

    Lyotard Newmans paintings give colour, line or rhythm the force ofan obligation within a face-to-face relationship his model cannot

    be Look at this (over there); it must be Look at me, or to be more

    accurate, Listen to me.114 The painting (as otherness, difference)

    creates an obligation to respond and we are judged accordingly. Thus

    while Deleuze strips art down to find a self-originating, self-germi-

    nating sensation in Figure, Lyotard strips art down to find the figure

    incised and divided by law.

    For Lyotard, just as Newmans zips divide his paintings, the law

    divides man from himself. Lyotard comes down firmly on the side of

    castration, lack and debt and there is no hope of moving into credit,

    of force and the body being joined in affirmative desire. Force is

    necessarily constrained; some things are not Neitzschean and cannot

    be affirmed. Rather, Being announces itself in the imperative. 115 The

    law and being are born in the same moment and we exist under a

    constitutive obligation. Looking inward, we are wounded by a law

    that constitutes our uncanny Other, obliges us to it, and excludes it

    from representation. Looking outward, there are the silent and

    invisible Others to whom we are hostage and obliged, those who call

    but who are not and cannot be represented.

    For Lyotard, art is an event that presents the unpresentable. In so

    doing it bears witness to the remainder, what remains in excess of

    representation, and commands us to do likewise. The virtue of art is

    not that it unleashes unrestrained energy; the virtue of art is that itimposes an obligation: to respond, to recollect, to open ourselves to

    see/hear the trace/voice of the unrepresentable, to bear witness. And

    111 Ibid., 248.112 Ibid.; Malpas, supra n. 107, 208.113 Ibid.114 Ibid., 242.115 Ibid., 248.

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    255

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    26/27

    we are judged in terms of that obligation. Unlike, Deleuze, Lyotard

    can never have done with judgment.

    CONCLUSION: THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    Neither Deleuze nor Lyotard happened to write about Bacon or

    Newman. They chose their art carefully for its defining characteristics

    in Bacon, the arc of the figure; in Newman, the zip through the field.

    The arc and the zip are two paradigms for ethics and for justice. One

    shows the confrontation, then expansion of forces until they leap

    beyond the canvas into a rhythm of the future. The other sets force in

    motion but also limits it with a kind of Kantian Achtung! If I were to

    continue this study, it would be to interrogate the dynamics of these

    two lines.

    Deleuze (and Bacons) arcs are rhythmic. Each individual moment

    is taken up into the whole. While they are energetic, they are also

    recurrent and for all their deformation, the figures and paintings are

    curiously whole and graceful. Even as sensation resonates and is

    separated from bodies (as Deleuze would have it) it is reabsorbed into

    the Figure. If this is an analogue for ethical action, it suggests a kind

    of parthenogenesis. It would seem that the ethical actor never gets

    beyond himself. To be sure, he absorbs what is external and then,transformed, projects his new energy back into the standardizations

    of every day life. This is the spiral of the eternal return. But what he

    takes back is himself. It is questionable how productive this is. For

    Lyotard, on the other hand, the zip presents the law, the event that

    interrupts just as for Newman, creation is the event in which God

    separates from himself. It stands outside of and disrupts the arc of

    self-generation. The shattering of unity guarantees there will be no

    reabsorption. The division recognizes something other than self; the

    ethical is produced by two rather than one.

    For now, I offer no resolution: between Bacons movement and

    Newmans austerity; Deleuzes affirmation, Lyotards reality princi-

    ple; Deleuzes optimism, Lyotards responsibility; Deleuzes long,

    detached horizon of revolution, Lyotards more urgent view of the

    least intolerable. The Deleuzian subject hovers on the edge of

    romantic heroism and risks solipsism,116 Lyotards subject teeters on

    116 His examples do not always inspire confidence, cf. General Cipriano as the god

    of war, Huitzilopochtli, in D.H. Lawrences ed., The Plumed Serpent: Quetzalcoatl

    (London: Martin Secker, 1926).

    MARTY SLAUGHTER

    256

  • 7/30/2019 The Arc and the Zip -- Deleuze and Lyotard on Art

    27/27

    the brink of cynicism and risks paralysis. Each has its force as well

    as its shadow.

    If there is no resolution, there is a modest observation. Art (in

    both senses of the word) gives the lie to an illusory and oppressive

    idea of representation. Law and its order are based on representation

    and as such might be considered beautiful. Behind representation

    however is art, just as behind the beauty of the law is the sublimity of

    justice.

    Kent Law School

    University of KentCanterbury, Kent CT2 7NZ

    UK

    E-mail: [email protected]

    THE ARC AND THE ZIP

    257