the human evasion - celia green

Upload: codz3

Post on 08-Apr-2018

222 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    1/64

    The Human Evasion

    by Celia Green

    Foreword by R H Ward

    Chapter 1 -- Sanity

    Chapter 2 -- The Characteristics of Sanity

    Chapter 3 -- The Genesis of Sanity

    Chapter 4 -- The Society of the Sane

    Chapter 5 -- How To Write Sane Books

    Chapter 6 -- The Sane Person Talks of Existence

    Chapter 7 -- The Sane Person Talks of God

    Chapter 8 -- The Religion of Evasion

    Chapter 9 -- The Philosophy of EvasionChapter 10 -The Science of Evasion

    Chapter 11 -The Alternative to Sanity: What Would It Be Like?

    Chapter 12 -Christ

    Chapter 13 -Nietzsche

    Chapter 14 -Why The World Will Remain Sane

    An Open Letter to Young People

    FOREWORD

    One way of seeing reality is to see the appearances we usually take for it inside-out, back-to-

    front or looking-glass fashion. This is very difficult to do, considering how habituated we are to

    those appearances. It is also very difficult to be witty about vital and essential matters, though

    that is one of the best hopes we have of seeing them objectively, which is about the only hope

    we have of seeing them at all. Miss Green has achieved the looking-glass vision and the wit.

    Many, therefore, will call her too clever by half, forgetting that one of the things she is saying

    is that we are not half clever enough, for the very reason that we lack her witty vision becausewe wear the blinkers of our belief in appearances. So anyone who reads this book (as

    opposed to merely reading its words) must be prepared to be profoundly disturbed, upset and

    in fact looking-glassedhimself; which will be greatly to his advantage, if he can stand it. Few

    books, long or short, are great ones; this book is short and among those few. One day,

    perhaps, it will become part of holy writ: a gospel according to Celia Green. Which kind of

    'insane' statement belongs to the book's own kind of truth.

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#fhttp://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#1http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#3http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#4http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#5http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#6http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#8http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#9http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#10http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#10http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#11http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#11http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#12http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#12http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#13http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#13http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#14http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#14http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#openhttp://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#1http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#3http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#4http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#5http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#6http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#8http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#9http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#10http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#11http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#12http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#13http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#14http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#openhttp://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#f
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    2/64

    R. H. WARD

    Chapter 1

    SANITY

    On the face of it, there is something rather strange about human psychology.

    Human beings live in a state of mind called 'sanity' on a small planet in space. They are not

    quite sure whether the space around them is infinite or not (either way it is unthinkable). If

    they think about time, they find it inconceivable that it had a beginning. It is also inconceivable

    that it did not have a beginning. Thoughts of this kind are not disturbing to 'sanity', which is

    obviously a remarkable phenomenon and deserving more recognition.

    Now sanity possesses a constellation of defining characteristics which are at first sightunrelated. In this it resembles other, more widely accepted, psychological syndromes. A

    person with an anal fixation, for example, is likely to be obsessional, obstinate, miserly,

    punctilious, and interested in small bright objects. A sane person believes firmly in the

    uselessness of thinking about what he does not understand, and is pathologically interested

    in other people. These two symptoms, at first sight independent, are actually inextricably

    related. In fact they are merely different aspects of that peculiar reaction to reality which we

    shall call the human evasion.

    As I shall be using the word 'reality' again I should make it plain at once that I use it to mean

    'everything that exists'. This is, of course, a highly idiosyncratic use of the word. I am awarethat it is commonly used by sane people to mean 'everything that human beings understand

    about', or even 'human beings'. This illustrates the interesting habit, on the part of the sane, of

    investing any potentially dangerous word with a strong anthropocentric meaning. Let us

    therefore consider the use of 'reality' a little longer.

    It is first necessary to consider what might be meant by the word 'reality' if it were usually

    used to mean 'everything that exists'. It would have to include all processes and events in the

    Universe, and all relationships underlying them, regardless of whether or not these things

    were perceptible or even conceivable by the human mind. It would also include the fact that

    anything exists at all -- i.e. that there is something and not nothing. And it would include thereason for the fact that anything exists at all, although it is most improbable that this reason is

    conceivable, or that 'reason' is a particularly good name for it.

    In fact it is quite obvious that to most people 'reality' does not mean anything like this.

    Particular attention should be drawn to the phrase 'running away from reality' in which 'reality'

    is almost always synonymous with 'human beings and their affairs'. For example: 'It isn't right

    to spend so much time with those stuffy old astronomy books. It's running away from reality.

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    3/64

    You ought to be getting out and meeting people.' (An interest in any aspect of reality requiring

    concentrated attention in solitude is considered a particularly dangerous symptom.) This

    usage leads to the interesting result that if anyone does take any interest in reality he is

    almost certain to be told that he is running away from it.

    Although so far we have given only one illustration, some impression may already begin to

    emerge of the way in which the sane mind has allocated to all crucial words meanings whichmake it virtually impossible to state, let alone to defend, any position other than that of sanity.

    In fact by now this is the chief means employed by sanity to defend itself from any possible

    attack. Formerly it found it necessary to claim a certain interest in 'reality' in the sense of 'that

    which exists'. There were religions, and systems of metaphysics, you may remember, which

    professed a certain interest in the creation of the world, and the purpose of life, and the

    destiny of the individual.

    Now no such disguises are necessary.

    I am reminded of a book called Flatlandin which an imaginary two-dimensional world isdescribed. Towards the end of the book a non-dimensional being is encountered -- a point in

    space. The observers listen to what it is saying (but of course, since they are of higher

    dimensionality than its own, the point being cannot observe them in any way). What it is

    saying to itself, in a scarcely audible tinkling voice, is something like this: 'I am alpha and

    omega, the beginning and the end. I am that which is and I am all in all to myself. There is

    nothing other than me, I am everything and all of everything is all of me and all of me is all of

    everything...'

    The human race has taken to producing similar noises. Perhaps we would not be surprised at

    the sociologists murmuring to themselves from time to time, 'in society we live and move and

    have our being', as they scurry from communal centre to therapeutic group, but these days

    everyone is at it.

    The philosophers have discarded metaphysics and have a tinkling song of their own which

    says, 'In the beginning was the word and the word is mine and the word was made by me.'

    This is rather a strong position in its way, because if you try to criticize it they will point out

    that you can only do so in words, and they have already annexed all the words there are on

    behalf of humanity. (And the meaning of the words is the meaning humanity gave them, and

    they shall have no meaning beside it.)

    The theologians are finding theology rather an embarrassment, and one can only suspect

    they would be happier without it. Their tradition does make it a little more difficult for them to

    put God in his proper place, but all things considered, they're keeping up with the times pretty

    well. Sartre said 'Hell is other people'; the up-to-date theologian says 'God is other people'.

    It might have been thought that the 'existentialists' would make some sort of a stand for the

    transcendent, but it hasn't been serious. In fact many people have found that a liberal use of

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    4/64

    existentialist language, loosely applied, has been extremely helpful in stimulating an

    obsessional interest in human society. (This interest is variously known as 'commitment',

    'involvement', and 'the life of encounter'.)

    The questions which remain are these. Arepeople, in fact, matters of ultimate concern to

    other people? And still more, can they be sources of 'ultimate solution' to them? If they are

    not, what psychological force is at work to ensure that these questions are so seldom asked?Why, if you ask a question about man and the universe, are you given an answer about 'man

    in society'?

    Chapter 2

    THE CHARACTERISTICS OF SANITY

    Sanity may be described as the conscientious denial of reality. That is to say, the facts of the

    situation (apart from a few which are judged to be harmless) have no emotional impact to a

    sane mind.

    For example, it is a salient feature of our position that we are in a state of total uncertainty.

    Possibly the universe started with a 'big bang' a few aeons ago, or perhaps something even

    more incredible happened. In any case, there is no reason known to us why everything

    should not stop existing at any moment. I realize that to my sane readers I shall appear to be

    making an empty academic point. That is precisely what is so remarkable about sanity.

    The sane person prides himself on his ability to be unaffected by important facts, andinterested in unimportant ones. He refers to this as having a sense of perspective, or keeping

    things 'in proportion'.

    Consider the wife of the Bishop of Woolwich. She says - I have sometimes been asked

    recently: 'What effect has Honest to Godand all the reaction to it had on your children?'[1]

    That is to say, what effect has it had on her children that their father has written a book about

    the nature of reality which has attracted a great deal of attention. Have they become

    interested in their father's importance as a possible influence on the course of history? Have

    they started to take themselves seriously and determined to influence their generation? Or

    have they begun to take a precocious interest in theology, whether agreeing or disagreeing

    with their father? The Bishop's wife assures us that none of these unpleasant things have

    happened. What effect, then, hasit had? 'The simple answer is -- practically none at all,' she

    says. 'Life goes on much as it did before.' The vital questions continue to be 'Do you have to

    go out tonight?', 'What can I wear for the party?', and 'What's for supper?''

    This ability to keep things 'in perspective', or upside down, is beautifully exemplified by certain

    remarks made by the aging Freud.

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.1http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.1
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    5/64

    Seventy years have taught me to accept life with a cheerful humility....

    Perhaps the gods are kind to us in making life more disagreeable as we grow

    older. In the end death seems less intolerable than the manifold burdens we

    carry.... I do not rebel against the universal order.... (Asked whether it meant

    nothing to him that his name should live) Nothing whatsoever.... I am far moreinterested in this blossom than in anything that may happen to me after I am

    dead.... I am not a pessimist, I permit no philosophic reflections to spoil my

    enjoyment of the simple things of life.[2]

    To appreciate the full force of these remarks one must realize that Freud had already had five

    operations for cancer of the jaw, and was in more or less continuous pain. (It may be held that

    when Freud looked at a blossom and found it more interesting than pain and death and fame,

    this was because he was overcome by the astonishing fact that the blossom existed at all. But

    if this were so, I think he would scarcely refer to it as one of the 'simple' things of life.)

    He was not entirely immune from reminders of his finite condition, as is shown by other

    statements which he made at various times.

    ... there is deep inside a pessimistic conviction that the end of my life is near. That

    feeds on the torments from my scar which never cease. [3]

    When you at a youthful 54 cannot avoid often thinking of death you cannot be

    astonished that at the age of 80 1/2 I fret whether I shall reach the age of my father

    and brother or further still into my mother's age, tormented on the one hand by the

    conflict between the wish for rest and the dread of fresh suffering that further lifebrings and on the other hand anticipation of the pain of separation from everything

    to which I am still attached.[4] The radium has once more begun to eat in, with pain

    and toxic effects, and my world is again what it was before -- a little island of pain

    floating on a sea of indifference.[5]

    However, in spite of all this he didn't lose interest in trivia, and in the eyes of any sane person

    this establishes his claim to possess great 'emotional stability'.

    Seeing things in perspective usually means that you stand at a certain distance away from the

    objects of observation. The 'perspective' in which a sane person lives depends on avoidingthis manoeuvre. You have to hold a flower very close to your eyes if it is to blot out the sky.

    The sane person holds his life in front of his face like someone with short sight reading a

    newspaper with rather small print. It follows that he cannot have emotions about the universe,

    because he cannot see that it is there.

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.2http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.3http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.4http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.5http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.2http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.3http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.4http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.5
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    6/64

    This is a salient feature of sanity -- it does not include emotions about the universe. Some

    sane readers may object: 'Once I was excited about anti-particles for several hours'. or 'I tried

    out solipsism for three whole days'.

    So, if it is insisted upon, we may qualify this statement as follows: Sanity may occasionally

    allow transitory emotions about the universe or reality, but it does not allow them to exercise

    any perceptible influence as motives in the life of the individual. At this stage in our argumentwe must regard it as an open question whether this is an accidental by-product of sanity, or

    whether it is the deliberate but unstated objective at which all sane psychology is aimed.

    I must explain what I mean by an emotion about the universe -- since this is an unfamiliar and

    bizarre phenomenon -- so let me give an example. Ludwig Wittgenstein, the founder of

    linguistic philosophy, which has made so great a contribution to intellectual sanity in this

    century, was himself not quite so sane as he would have liked. Indeed, it may be argued that

    linguistic philosophy was itself the product of his strenuous attempts to remain sane enough.

    A case of an irritated oyster producing a pearl -- the sane may reply - which does not detract

    from the value of the pearl. Possibly.

    But it is undeniable that Wittgenstein did occasionally have emotions about the universe. So

    his biographer records: 'I believe that a certain feeling of amazement that anything should

    exist at all, was sometimes experienced by Wittgenstein.... Whether this feeling has anything

    to do with religion is not clear to me.'[6]

    Notice in passing the fastidiousness with which his biographer hastens to disclaim any exact

    comprehension of this feeling. ('I believe the lower classes eat fish and chips from

    newspaper. Whether this practice has anything to do with nutrition is not clear to me.')

    What more can be said of the sane person? He is ubiquitous, and so his characteristics are

    invisible. There is nothing to compare him with.

    But let us consider the picture given in a jolly little booklet called 'A positiveapproach to

    Mental Health'.[7] (The cover is adorned with a picture of a happy fakir sitting beside an

    abandoned bed of nails.)

    'How does the person who is enjoying good mental health think and act?' the booklet asks,

    and proceeds to inform us, among other things, that 'He gets satisfaction from simple, every-

    day pleasures.' Freud, you see, certainly qualified.

    'He has emotions', the booklet also informs us, 'like anyone else.' However, they are 'in

    proportion' and he is not 'crushed' by them. I think by now we have established what is meant

    by keeping things 'in proportion' -- i.e. you have most of your emotions about unimportant

    things. The booklet does not state this explicitly, but it certainly does not state anything to the

    contrary. It might, for example, be said that 'the mature man is not unduly interested in

    matters of purely local significance, such as the state of affairs on this particular planet,

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.6http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.6http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.7http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.6http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.7
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    7/64

    because he realizes that they are of little ultimate significance.' You will observe how

    outlandish that sounds.

    The booklet becomes a little lightheaded when it comes to the matter of the mentally healthy

    person's interest in facts. 'He's open-minded about new experiences and new ideas.' A more

    accurate statement might be 'A mentally healthy person has made a value judgement in

    advance that no idea or experience can be qualitatively more important than those he alreadyunderstands. He is able to rely on his defense mechanisms and can listen with a bland

    expression to people with unpleasant ideas.'

    How does the mentally healthy person feel about his limitations? 'He feels able to deal with

    most situations that come his way.... He tries for goals he thinks he can achieve through his

    own abilities; he doesn't want the moon on a silver platter.' That is to say, he has so arranged

    his life that he doesn't try to do anything that doesn't seem pretty easy. 'If he can't change

    something he doesn't like, he adjusts to it.' 'He knows he has shortcomings and can accept

    them without getting upset.' That is, he has ways of pretending he does not mind about

    anything he cannot alter easily.

    And how does he feel about other people? Here a slightly threatening note of reciprocity

    appears. 'He is tolerant of others shortcomings just as he is of his own. He doesn't expect

    others to be perfect, either.' 'He expects to like and trust other people and assumes that they

    will like him.... He doesn't try to push other people around and doesn't expect to be pushed

    around himself.' Let us just imagine what might have been said instead -- I know it will sound

    like the wildest fantasy. 'He regrets his own shortcomings and is always willing to admire

    people with greater virtues and capacities than his own. He wishes to help other people,

    particularly those with higher aims and a more intense sense of purpose than he has himself.

    He does not expect to be liked in return for his help.'

    We have established that the mentally healthy person isn't going to let his life, with all its

    content of simple pleasures, be pushed around by anyone.

    This, if you give it a moment's thought, ensures that all his relationships must be

    characterized by mutual purposelessness. If you once admit a purpose to the situation, it may

    make differential demands on different people.

    Nevertheless, the sane person 'is capable of loving other people and thinking about their

    interests and well-being. He has friendships that are satisfying and lasting. He can identify

    himself with a group, feel that he is part of it, and has a sense of responsibility to his

    neighbours and fellow men.'

    Notice that a friendship should be satisfying -- i.e. it is an end in itself, and not a means to an

    end. It should also be 'lasting'. Obviously if the friendship depended on community of

    purpose, it might be outgrown.

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    8/64

    So it is plain that people constitute a rather large part of the mentally healthy person's world,

    but that all associations of persons have to be characterized by a mutual sacrifice of

    purposiveness.

    I am reminded of the porcupines of Schopenhauer. They wanted to huddle together to keep

    one another warm, but found that their spines pricked one another. If they kept too far apart,

    they became cold again. So they established a distance at which they could keep one anotherwarm without actually making contact with one another's spines. 'This distance was

    henceforward known as decency and good manners.'

    The attitude of the mentally healthy person towards other people might be stated as follows:

    'He expects to derive warmth from his proximity to other people. He does not expect to derive

    anything else, and is willing to let other people derive warmth from him so long as they, too,

    abandon their prickly claims to possess needs of any other kind.'

    Before we leave this little booklet, let us consider that brilliant expression 'mental health'. It is,

    of course, a social euphemism of the same genre as 'rodent operative' and 'cleansing official'.It saves sane people from embarrassment by permitting them to say that their confined and

    extraordinary relatives are not madbut 'mentally ill' or even 'mentally unwell'. It implies that

    the human mind grows naturallyand by biological necessityinto the image and likeness of the

    Human Evasion, as the human body grows to a certain specified kind of shape. It implies that

    any deviation from the Human Evasion is the same kind of thing as a tumour or a running

    sore. It sanctifies the statistical norm. 'Mental disease', the booklet says, 'doesn't indicate lack

    of brain power but rather a malfunctioning of the brain and emotions. The individual just

    doesn't respond to various situations the way a normal person would' (my italics).

    What can we add to this picture of the sane? One sane opinion. '... if I could spend the courseof everlasting time in a paradise of varied loveliness, I do not fancy my felicity would be

    greatly impaired if the last secret of the universe were withheld from me.' [8]

    This opinion was held by a Gifford Lecturer in the 1930s. His lectures were entitled 'The

    Human Situation', and they are a marvel of sanity from beginning to end. But they are

    outdated in one respect. We do not talk any more about 'the human situation'. The phrase

    implies that humans can be seen in relation to something other than humans. What we talk

    about now is sociology. Everyone is very proud of this fact. It is the quintessence of sanity.

    [1] John A.T. Robinson, The New Reformation, S.C.M. Paperback,

    1965, p.123.

    [2] Ernest Jones, Sigmund Freud: Life and Work, Vol. III,

    The Hogarth Press, 1957. p.133.

    [3] Ibid., Vol. III, pp.70-71.

    [4] Ibid., Vol. III, p.226.

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.8http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#2.8
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    9/64

    [5] Ibid., Vol. III, p.258.

    [6] Norman Malcolm, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Oxford University Press

    Paperback, 1958, p.70.

    [7] Richard Christner, Published by the National Association for

    Mental Health, 1965.

    [8] MacNeile Dixon, The Human Situation, Edward Arnold and Co.,

    1937, p.14.

    Chapter 3

    THE GENESIS OF SANITY

    It is fashionable to locate the origins of psychological attitudes very early in life. The taste for

    doing so is not, perhaps, entirely unmotivated.

    It is obviously fairly agreeable to regard one's psychology as the result of conditioning rather

    than of choice. It is relaxing; one has nothing to blame oneself for; one cannot be expected to

    change. It is, of course, possible that the infant mind is capable of significant emotional

    decisions, but this possibility is never discussed.

    However, a perfectly satisfactory beginning may indeed be postulated for sanity, and this

    does not interfere at all with standard theories of psycho-analysis. Psycho-analysis deals with

    that part of a person's psychology which has become fixated on other people; so it may well

    describe what happens to the child in so far as that child becomes sane.

    It is well known that the younger people are, the less sane they are likely to be. This has lead

    to the heavily-loaded social usage of the term maturity. It is an unquestionable pro-word.

    Roughly speaking, the matureperson is characterized by willingness to accept substitutes,

    compromises, and delays, particularly if these are caused by the structure of society.

    Young people are usually immature, that is to say, they wish their lives to contain excitement

    and purpose. It is recognized (at least subconsciously) by sane people that the latter is muchthe more dangerous of the two, so the young who cannot at once be made mature are

    steered into the pursuit of purposelessexcitement. This is actually not very exciting, and is

    well on the way to an acceptable kind of sanity, as it leads to the idea of 'excitement' being

    degraded to that of 'pleasure'.

    Adolescents are known to think about metaphysics more than most people; thus thinking

    about metaphysics becomes associated with the negative concept 'immaturity'. If someone

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    10/64

    thinks about metaphysical problems at a later age, they are said to show signs of 'delayed

    adolescence'.

    Now let us go back to the very beginning of the 'maturation' process. It is to be presumed that

    a baby which is being born experiences helplessness as helplessness. That is to say, it

    experiences the painful and incomprehensible process without any of those reflections which

    are such a miraculous source of comfort to the sane -- such as 'It will soon be over', or 'Afterall, it happens to everybody', or 'It shouldn't be allowed. It's theirfault'.

    The infant may be presumed to find its condition intolerable -- because it is out of control of it.

    At this point of its life, what it minds about is that it cannot control reality, not that it cannot

    control people.

    Now so long as one is finite -- i.e. one's knowledge and powers are limited -situations may

    always arise which one cannot control. But it is very hard for an adult human to feel any

    emotion about his limitations vis-a-vis impersonal reality. What emotion arises in you when

    you think that you would be quite unable to lift Mount Everest? On the other hand, it isprobably quite easy to feel some emotion at the thought that so-and-so is an inch taller than

    you are, or can always beat you at badminton. You may also (though less probably) still be

    able to feel a pang of jealousy or regret that you are not Nijinsky or Shakespeare or Einstein.

    Obviously a process of psychological development takes place which ensures (so far as

    possible) that the limitations of the individual will be experienced onlyin comparisons with

    other people. Now it is obvious that the emotion which accompanies the original experience of

    helplessness is very strong. If you can recall any experience of impotent fury or horror in early

    childhood you may get some idea of this. This gives some clue to the strength of the human

    evasion. If people are to take the force of all this displaced emotion, it is scarcely surprisingthat they should be the object of such exclusive attention.

    At first very young children are not immune from a feeling of helplessness per se. But it may

    be presumed that the part of their environment which is most readily manipulable is soon

    seen to be other people. The younger the child, the truer this is. Its own physical and mental

    grasp of the situation is greatly exceeded by that of adult humans -- particularly its mother --

    who can affect the situation in its favour if they feel inclined to do so.

    It is very painful to try to do something and to fail. The retrospective attempt to reject the

    combination of trying and failure is well known in social life. 'I didn't really care about the

    game today.' 'Actually I was thinking that even if I was elected it was time I resigned to spend

    more time on my other interests.' Therefore, by the time it has reached adulthood, the sane

    person has evolved ways of relinquishing the attempt in favour of some compensatory aim, in

    any situation in which it does not feel almost certain to succeed. For example, as a mature

    adult, you cannot even try (with any emotional involvement in the act of trying) to jump over a

    house. By the same taken, you cannot tryto make a door open by willpower alone, or tryto

    arrive home quickly without traversing the intervening space and navigating such obstacles as

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    11/64

    stairs, walls, gates, etc., in the approved fashion. Your immediate sensation if you attempted

    to try, would be an overwhelming sense of impossibility.

    It is (philosophically or factually speaking) the case that no future event can be demonstrated

    to be impossible. If something has happened once, this may be said to show it is possible. If it

    has never happened this does not show that it can never do so. But as has pointed out,

    reflections of this kind although true, have no emotional impact to a sane person.

    As already mentioned, you may still (in rare circumstances) be able to tryto achieve

    exceptional things in some socially recognized and strictly limited field. I.e. you may still be

    able to try and equal Nijinsky, Shakespeare, etc.

    But it is far more likely that you have acquired some compensatory attitude towards any such

    symbols of outstandingness. It can give a very pleasant sense of gentle superiority to discuss

    Beethoven's deafness, and Shakespeare's Oedipus Complex, and Nietzsche's lack of

    success with women, in a more or less informed manner. Thus MacNeile Dixon:

    So with the famous monarchs of the mind. They terrify you with their authority....How royal is their gesture, how incomparable their technique!

    There is, however, no need for alarm. Pluck up your heart, approach a little nearer,

    and what do you find; that they have human wishes and weaknesses like yourself.

    You may discover that Kant smoked, played billiards and had a fancy for candied

    fruit. The discovery at once renders him less awe-inspiring.[1]

    This kind of approach is not only useful for eliminating a sense of inferiority, it also makes it

    much easier to ignore anything Kant, Nietzsche, Hume, etc., may have said about reality.Now although the ambitions of the adult are already restricted to narrowly defined types of

    social recognition, even this form of aspiration is a strictly unstablestructure in sane

    psychology -- i.e. if it is displaced slightly from its equilibrium it will tend to fall further away

    from that position, and not return to it. On the other hand, compensationis

    a stablepsychological position in sane psychology.

    The replacement of aspirationby compensationis perhaps most clearly seen among college

    students. They frequently arrive at university with immature desires for greatness and an

    exceptionally significant way of life.

    Not infrequently, also, this leads to emotional conflicts and disappointments of one kind and

    another. They adjustto their problems with startling rapidity. The solution which occurs to

    nearly all of them, and is suggested to them by psychological advisers, etc., if it does not

    occur to them spontaneously, is to accept their limitations. The acceptance of limitationsis

    accompanied by a marked increase in the valuation placed on other people.

    'I used to be quite self-sufficient and thought I wanted to be nothing but an intellectual. I lived

    for my work, and of course maths/classics/anything you like is the nearest thing there is to

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#3.1http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#3.1
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    12/64

    heaven. But it would be selfish to live like that. I see now you've got to take an interest in life

    -- I mean, you have to live with other people. It's difficultto get on with people. Social

    problems aredifficult. The other is easy. It's running away from reality.'

    What is usually omitted from this exposition by the patient is that between the period at which

    classics (or whatever it may have been) was 'nearly heaven' and the period at which human

    relationships became the central thing in life, there was usually a stage at which classics wasno longer particularly easy.

    It is a simple law of human psychology, therefore, that as soon as conflict arises, it will be

    eliminated by some compensatory manoeuvre in which other peopleare the central pivot. The

    process of becoming thoroughly sane depends on repeated manoeuvres of this kind.

    This process may be presumed to have started in earliest infancy, when it was much more

    rewarding to aim at responses from one's mother than at controlling the environment directly.

    Here began the child's lifelong efforts to limit its trying to regions in which it could succeed.

    This process, of necessity, remained imperfect in early life, as moderate (though neverdisproportionate) efforts to learn things must be sanctioned in the young.

    These efforts are almost at once heavily conditioned by social acceptability, though this is not

    yet the exclusive criterion. It is possible to find people who remember, as children, having

    tried (or attempted to try) to walk away from the stairs into the air instead of going on down

    them one by one. But even then they found it impossible to try very hard.

    Why is it so painful to failin something you have tried to do? In the case of the young child it

    is evidently because it reminds it of its limited powers, which suggests the possibility of

    permanent finiteness.

    It is bad enough to be finite at present; it is intolerable to believe that one will always be so. If

    one tries and fails it proves that one's trying is insufficient. Better therefore to believe that one

    doesn't want to try-- at least at present.

    This view of the matter is not so far removed from that of orthodox psycho-analysis, which

    does, after a fashion, recognize the child's desire for omnipotence. Psycho-analysis is,

    however, most concerned with what happens once human persons, such as the child's father,

    have become partial symbols of omnipotence. There is also a tendency to describe the child

    as having a muddle-headed beliefin its own omnipotence. This is, of course, less justifiable

    than a desirefor omnipotence. Sane people cannot distinguish very easily between differentattitudes of this kind.

    Of course in the child and adolescent there are still remains of the belief that one will, at some

    judiciously selected time in the future, attempt altogether more ambitious things. In true

    adulthood this idea has disappeared (or becomes transformed into some such form as 'it

    would make all the difference if people were only decent to me and gave me my rights').

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    13/64

    Thus the sane, adult person wants (or tries to want) to have what it can have and to do what it

    can do, and exercises a good deal of ingenuity in attempts to want not to have what it cannot

    get.

    One or two points must be made in parentheses. The sane person will not, of course, admit

    that the prospect of being permanently finite is intolerable.

    Even if he looks so miserable that he cannot with any conviction claim to be happy himself, he

    will utter constant affirmations that 'most people are perfectly all right and quite happy as they

    are.' 'Why should I mind about being finite? Suppose Ienjoyit like this?'

    This does not make our hypothesis about the development of the human evasion any less

    probable. Our argument is that a sane person's life has been spent in an increasingly

    successful attempt notto find finiteness intolerable. Thus if he makes assertions of this kind,

    he is telling us only that he has succeeded.

    After all, it is accepted in psycho-analysis that one of the objects of a psychological reaction to

    an unacceptable fact is, eventually, to conceal the true origin and purpose of this reaction.

    The sane adult will, of course, object that what happens when one comes up against one's

    limitations is not that one is reminded of the possibilityof permanent finiteness. It

    is certainthat the limits of one's capabilities are defined by what one can and cannot achieve.

    The very young child reacts emotionally as if it believed that limitation is only potential; it does

    not yet identify itself with its limitations. In this its emotions are in accordance with the most

    abstract philosophy; whatever may be achieved in certain circumstances on one occasion or

    even on a great many occasions, it may still be the case that something quite different may beachieved on a future occasion. In the most abstract sense, this might simply happen in the

    way that everything might stop existing at any moment or start existing according to different

    laws. This, I know, is the sort of consideration that has no force at all to a sane adult. But

    even within the normal world-view, it cannot be claimed that very much is known about the

    psychological factors that restrict or permit achievement, and the possibility cannot be ruled

    out that if someone adopted a different kind of psychological attitude from any they had had

    before, they might find their abilities radically changed.

    Initially, then, the child is merely horrified at the prospect that a single failure may contain

    some implication of permanent restriction; some barrier set forever between him and the

    possibility of omnipotence. It is a matter of social conditioning that he increasingly learns that

    he is regarded by others as defined by his failures, so that any single one comes to have the

    force of a permanent measurement of what he unchangeably is.

    This process is accompanied by a continuous shifting of the idea of failure away

    from absolutefailure (i.e. failure to fulfil one's own will) toward 'failure by comparison with

    other people'. To the mature adult only the latter is of any interest.

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    14/64

    The child is trained, then, to react to failure not only by regarding his limitations as final, but by

    substituting something more readily obtainable for what he originally wanted. The substitution

    is usually eased by a shift of emphasis from what the individual himself wants, to what other

    people want from him. It may be the substitution of a differentambition from the first one, on

    the grounds that it will be just as useful to society, or it may be the substitution of social

    approval per sefor any ambition at all.Consider some well-known gambits. 'Never mind, darling. Even if you fail your exams, you

    know we'll still love you.' If the person concerned is actually worried about the exams, there is

    an obvious motivation for attempting to find this comforting. 'Well, we know you did your best,

    and that's what counts.' The latter is particularly subtle, since it combines the idea of finalityof

    failure with the offer of social approval. What it is really saying is: 'Provided you accept that

    you couldn't possibly have done better, and you really are worse than all the other boys, you

    may have our affection as a good boy who tries.'

    Now the child may well have an obscure feeling that in some way he wasn't

    feeling rightabout the thing; or that somehow everything felt wrongat school in some

    indefinable way that made it quite certain that he couldn't do that kind of thing there. But his

    mind must be distracted from any attempt to work out how one does make oneself feel right to

    do things. (If he does start reflecting on the effect of circumstances upon him he will most

    likely be told he is 'making excuses'.)

    The denial of psychological reality is very important to sanity. It cannot afford to admit the

    existence of a psychology of achievement, still less to understand it. However, one of the few

    pieces of psychology that is understood by sanity is how to make young humans with

    aspirations feel discredited and absurd. Any aspiration bears an uncomfortable resemblance

    to a desire not to be finite at all. Inspiration is of little interest to modern psychology; it is about

    as unfashionable as witchcraft. If the subconscious mind is considered at all, it is considered

    solely as a repository of associations of ideas about parts of the body and members of one's

    family.

    Of course there is a kind of non-aspiring psychology of success which is understood by

    sanity. It is roughly as follows: the most stable, least excitable, most normal, people will tend

    to be most consistently successful.

    Even if this seems to be supported by observation, it must be borne in mind that these are the

    conditions for success (of a moderate kind) in a society composed of sane people.

    [1] Ibid., p.16.

    Chapter 4

    THE SOCIETY OF THE SANE

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    15/64

    Society begins to appear much less unreasonable when one realizes its true function. It is

    there to help everyone to keep their minds off reality. This follows automatically from the fact

    that it is an association of sane people, and it has already been shown that sanity arises from

    the continual insertion of 'other people' into any space into which a metaphysical problem

    might intrude.It is therefore quite irrelevant to criticize society as though it were there for some other

    purpose -- to keep everyone alive and well-fed in an efficient manner, say. Some degree of

    inefficiency is essential to create interesting opportunities for emotional reaction. (Of course,

    criticizing society, though irrelevant, is undeniably of value as an emotional distraction for

    sane people.)

    Incidentally, it should be noticed that 'keeping everyone alive and well-fed' is the highest

    social aim which the sane mind can accept without reservation or discomfort. This is because

    everyone is capable of eating -- and so are animals and plants -- so this qualifies

    magnificently as a 'real' piece of 'real life'. There are other reasons in its favour as well, of

    course, such as the fact that well-fed people do not usually become more single-minded,

    purposeful, or interested in metaphysics.

    It has been seen that the object of a sane upbringing is increasingly to direct all emotion

    towards objects which involve other people. Now basically the situation of being finite is an

    infinitely frustrating one, which would be expected to arouse sensations of desperation and

    aggression -- as indeed it may sometimes be seen to do in very young children. I am aware

    that I must be careful, in using the word aggression, to state that I do not mean aggression

    directed towards people. What I mean is an impersonal drive directed against reality -- it is

    difficult to give examples but it may be presumed that geniuses who are at all worthy of the

    name preserve a small degree of this.

    However, since allemotion must be directed towards people, it is obvious that the only form

    of aggression which a sane person can understand is aggression against people, which is

    probably better described as sadism or cruelty.

    Now it is obvious that the open expression of cruelty towards other people would have a

    destructive effect upon society, apart from being unprofitable to the human evasion in other

    ways. So the usual way in which aggression is displaced onto other people is in the form of a

    desire that they should be limited. This, after all, is very logical. If the true source of youranger is that you are limited yourself, and you wish to displace this anger onto some other

    person, what could be more natural than that you should wish them to be limited as well.

    This desire is usually expressed in the form of a desire for social justice, in one form or

    another. ('In this life you have to learn that you can't have it all your own way.' 'Well he can't

    expect to be treated as an exception for ever.' 'It's time he learnt to accept his limitations.'

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    16/64

    'Don't you think you should try to think more what other people want? We all have to do things

    we don't like.' 'Why should theyhave all the advantages.')

    This means that societyis not only the chief source of compensation to a sane person, but his

    chief instrument of revenge against other people. It is useless to point out that there is no

    need to revenge himself upon them. If he were ever to admit that they were not responsible

    for his finite predicament, he would have to direct his hatred against the finite predicamentitself, and this would be frustrating. It is this frustration that the human evasion exists to

    evade.

    Any attempt to dosomething involves the possibility of failure and may remind you of reality.

    For this reason the sane society discriminates against purposefulaction in favour of pleasure-

    seekingaction. The only purposes readily recognized as legitimate by the sane mind are

    those necessitated by the pursuit of pleasure. E.g. pleasure seeking cannot efficiently be

    carried on unless the individual is kept alive and moderately healthy. Therefore his physical

    needs are regarded as important and ambulances are provided with noisy bells. There is no

    corresponding necessity that he should fill, say, his intellectual potentialities. In fact the

    attempt to do so is likely to appear unduly purposeful.

    It is obvious in any number of ways that a sense of purposerepels rather than attracts

    assistance. You have only to consider the immediate sympathy that would be aroused in a

    sane mind by the complaint of some child that it was being driven to work at things far too

    difficult for its capacities, compared with the distrust and reserve with which it would view

    complaints by the child that it was not being allowed to work hard enough.

    To the sane mind, even aggression against people is infinitely better than aggression against

    infinity. And it is the chief defect of sane society that it is boring. It is so boring that even sanepeople notice it. And so, from time to time, there is a war. This is intended to divert people's

    minds before they become so bored that they take to some impersonal kind of aggressive

    activity -- such as research, or asceticism, or inspiration, or something discreditable of that

    kind.

    In wartime, rather more purposeful activity than usual is permissible. Even sane people relax

    their normal beliefs that nothing matters very much, and some time next week is soon enough

    for anything. This is regarded as justified because the war is always about something

    connected with other people, and may be regarded as an assertion of the belief that the thing

    that matters most is politics.

    And yet it might seem that war was going rather far. It does contain a very considerable risk of

    contact with reality. It is difficult to pretend that people never die, or that they only die in

    soothing situations with up-to-date medical care and loving relatives to keep their minds

    occupied with family news. War is full of reminders that things happen, and that space and

    time are real, and that before the bomb blows up is not the same as after, and that there are

    risks and uncertainty.

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    17/64

    How then can a sane society run the risks of allowing its population to have experiences of

    this kind, even occasionally? I think if you ask this question it is simply because you do not

    appreciate the robustness of sanity. If you shut people up in a prison camp, and torture them

    for a few years, they will not come out saying: 'I am a finite animal in existence and it is

    beyond endurance. How can I go on living in a body that can be tormented in these ways? I

    demand that human society stops all it is doing and starts attacking finiteness in everyconceivable way....'

    Instead, they will come out saying: 'It is terrible that other people should let wars happen, in

    which it is possible to be so degraded and reminded of one's limitations. It shouldn't happen; it

    is contrary to human rights; we are appalledat the evil in the heart of man. Meanwhile we

    demand reparation from society -- employment, and housing, and disablement allowances...'

    Society, they say, exists to safeguard the rights of the individual. If this is so, the primary right

    of a human being is evidently to live unrealistically.It has been pointed out that by the time a person is fully mature he will not, in normal

    circumstances, be made aware of his finiteness except in comparisons with other people.

    It is not possible to ensure this absolutely. But it is possible to limit the loopholes to those of

    physical accident, illness and death. Human beings regard it as a sacred duty to be

    particularly untruthful about these things -- particularly to the afflicted person and to any

    young person who may be around. For example, the following account of the death of

    Madame Curie may well seem rather touching to a sane person.

    Then began the harrowing struggle which goes by the name of 'an easy death' - in which thebody which refuses to perish asserts itself in wild determination. Eve at her mother's side was

    engaged in another struggle; in the brain of Mme Curie, still very lucid, the great idea of death

    had not penetrated. The miracle must be preserved, to save Marie from an immense pain that

    could not be appeased by resignation. Above all, the physical suffering had to be attenuated;

    the body reassured at the same time as the soul. No difficult treatments, no tardy blood

    transfusions, impressive and useless. No family reunion hastily called at the bedside of a

    woman who, seeing her relatives assembled, would be suddenly struck to the heart with an

    atrocious certainty.

    I shall always cherish the names of those who helped my mother in those days of horror. Dr.Toben, director of the sanatorium, and Dr. Pierre Lowsy brought Marie all their knowledge.

    The life of the sanatorium seemed suspended, stricken with immobility by the dreadful fact:

    Mme Curie was about to die. The house was all respect, silence and fervor. The two doctors

    alternated in Marie's room. They supported and solaced her. They also took care of Eve,

    helped her to struggle and to tell lies, and, even without her asking them, they promised to lull

    Marie's last sufferings by soporifics and injections.

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    18/64

    On the morning of July third, for the last time Mme Curie could read the thermometer held in

    her shaking hand and distinguish the fall in fever which always precedes the end. She smiled

    with joy. And as Eve assured her that this was the sign of her cure, and that she was going to

    be well now, she said, looking at the open window, turning hopefully towards the sun and the

    motionless mountains: 'It wasn't the medicines that made me better. It was the pure air, the

    altitude...'[1]It may be remarked that although the vulnerability of the human body makes it possible even

    for a fully-matured human being to be reminded of his limitations, no power on earth can

    remind him of the transcendent, in any shape or form. His reactions to pain, danger and death

    are limited to fear, depression, anxiety and commonsense. They do not include liberation,

    elation, or an interest in infinity. That is to say, the impact of reality has been rendered entirely

    negative.

    In order effectively to distract people from reality, society has to provide them with pseudo-purposes, guaranteed purposeless. (Or, alternatively, with pseudo-frustrations, guaranteed

    permanent.) There are two main kinds of pseudo-purpose or -frustration; they are known as

    'earning a living' and 'bringing up a family'. They both provide a person with a cast-iron alibi

    for not doing anything he wants with his life. (He does not, of course, want to be free to do

    what he wants, so this is all right.)

    Sane people regard an apparently purposeful activity as disinfected by numbers -- i.e. if a

    sufficiently large number of people is involved, they feel sure that the outcome will be

    harmless to sanity, no matter how frenzied the labours may seem to be. The most large-scale

    examples are war and politics.

    Into these activities, people allow themselves to enter with almost single-minded devotion.

    Both war and politics have played a particularly helpful part in retarding the march of

    progress. In fact, the history of the human race is only comprehensible as the record of a

    species trying not to gain control of its environment.

    [1] Eve Curie, Madame Curie, Garden City Publishing Co. Inc.,

    1900, pp397-398.

    Chapter 5

    HOW TO WRITE SANE BOOKS

    It will be convenient to have a name for that part of reality which is not emotionally regarded

    as 'real' by the sane person. We shall call it the Outside.

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#4.1http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#4.1
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    19/64

    The Outside consists of everything that appears inconceivable to the human mind. In fact

    everything is inconceivable to the human mind (if only because it exists) but not many people

    notice this.

    In religious and philosophical writings it is often difficult to eliminate all reference to the

    Outside. There are a number of ways of dealing with this problem. One of the most successful

    is to generate a distinctive kind of ambiguity about the meanings of crucial words.

    Consider the following passage in which the words 'being' and 'existence' are used. 'The term

    'being' in this context does not designate existence in time and space.... (It) means the whole

    of human reality, the structure, the meaning and the aim of existence.'[1]

    It is tolerably clear that at least when Tillich firstuses the word 'existence' he means by it what

    I also mean when I use the word. It seems that what we both mean by 'existing' is 'being

    there'.

    However, Tillich then explicitly repudiates this sense and goes on to define the word 'being' in

    a second sense. The term 'being' means the whole of human reality, Tillich says. Themeaning of this phrase is not obvious.

    Perhaps Tillich means the sum total of the mental content of all humans -illusions and all?

    What humans think is real? Or that part of reality which is accessible to the human mind?

    The last seems to be the best we can do. So let us suppose that 'human reality' does mean

    that part of the mental content -- actual or potential -- of humans which is actually in

    accordance with what exists.

    'Human reality' is then placed in apposition with 'the structure, the meaning and the aim of

    existence'. What is to be understood by this? The 'aim of existence' seems at first sight to beclear, unless 'existence' has made an unannounced change of meaning since it was first

    used. It would seem that this phrase must mean 'the purpose for which everything exists'.

    But this is difficult, because 'the aim of existence' is in apposition with 'human reality' which

    certainly does not include the purpose of existence.

    This leads us to a distinct suspicion that when Tillich talks of 'the structure, meaning and aim

    of existence' he does not mean 'existence' at all, but 'human life' instead. If he does mean

    this, there seems no reason why he should say so -- except that it would rob what he is

    saying of a status it does not possess. And if he does mean this, we have arrived at the

    following definition of the word 'being' -- 'whatever happens to be realistic in the mental

    content of humans; the structure, the meaning and the aim of human life'.

    In fact, we may suggest this paraphrase of what Tillich is saying: 'When we talk of 'being' we

    do not mean the Outside. We mean the Inside.'

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#5.1http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#5.1
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    20/64

    This example illustrates a standard procedure for appearing to take the Outside into

    consideration without actually doing so. The rules for this kind of writing are very simple and

    roughly as follows.

    There are a number of words and phrases which may mean something about existence or

    something about humans. For example: 'existence', 'depth', 'ground of being', 'ultimate

    concern', 'meaning', etc. Whenever what you really mean is 'human relationships' or 'day-to-day living' you should replace it by some existential-sounding combination, such as 'the depth

    of being'. It is a good idea to use compound phrases ('the depth of historical existence', 'the

    ultimate ground of meaning') as a considerable degree of obscurity can be created by

    summating the uncertainty of a number of uncertain terms.

    It is usual to define these terms as little as possible. But if you wish to appear to do so, it is

    best to use a series of phrases in apposition (as in the example just considered: 'the whole of

    human reality, the structure, the meaning and the aim of existence'). This gives a very good

    effect of struggling to define something difficult with precision while actually generating

    ambiguity (on the principle of summation of uncertainty already mentioned). The device of

    apposition itself introduces an additional modicum of doubt, since if you appose two such

    phrases as 'the depth of meaning' and 'the inmost structure of reality' no one will be sure

    whether the two phrases are ways of saying the same thing, or whether they are intended to

    complement one another.

    Other verbal devices may be used for placing together in the closest possible proximity

    'human' words and 'Outside' words. Words like 'ultimate' and 'reality' should be used in

    phrases like 'human reality' and 'ultimate concern', and the word 'meaning' should be softened

    into 'meaning and coherence'. (The word 'meaning' might be regarded as informationally

    sufficient; however, the addition of 'coherence' contributes a useful implicit suggestion that

    'meaning' must hang together in a way that is recognizable and rather agreeable to humans.)

    To illustrate these instructions, consider the typical phrase 'life and existence'. Now the word

    'existence' may mean 'human life', but if it does it is adding nothing to the meaning of the

    phrase. So this phrase would seem to mean 'human living andthe fact that things are there' --

    which seems a strange combination to discuss in the same breath.

    Another example of the way in which abstract words such as 'transcendent', 'meaning',

    'existence' should be combined with human words such as 'life' and 'confidence':

    High religions are ... distinguished by the extent of the unity and coherence of life

    which they seek to encompass and the sense of a transcendent source of meaning

    by which alone confidence in the meaningfulness of life and existence can be

    maintained.[2]

    May I suggest a paraphrase, which I think does not reduce the informational content. 'High

    religions are distinguished by making the whole of human life feel meaningful to the human

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#5.2http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#5.2
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    21/64

    being.' As human life already feels meaningful to sane human beings, this would appear to let

    anything or nothing qualify as a 'high religion'.

    It is true that my paraphrase reduces Niebuhr's meaning if he is using the word 'transcendent'

    in a transcendent sense. If so, what he is saying becomes more complex, but questionable.

    Assuming 'transcendent' to mean 'possessing a validity which cannot be affected by any

    consideration whatever', or perhaps 'directly related to the reason for existence', it is difficultto see why a 'transcendent source of meaning' should be expected to maintain anyone's

    'confidence in the meaningfulness of life'. For this to be true, we should have to accept the

    psychological supposition that people can only confidently accept transcendent meanings as

    meaningful. What is more, we should also have to accept that a transcendent source of

    meaning would have the characteristic of making a human being confident about the meaning

    of his life. It is an interesting sidelight on human psychology that it should be so often

    assumed that a transcendent purpose mustbe one that 'gives a meaning to life'. In fact,

    anyone sufficiently unusual to think occasionally about transcendence finds that it makes his

    life feel intolerably meaningless. (This is why people do not go on doing it.)

    If we assume that Niebuhr is using the word 'transcendent' in one of the senses defined

    above, the most obvious characteristic of a transcendent meaning would seem to be that it

    invalidates all subordinate meanings. This, after all, is what 'transcendent' means -- that which

    invalidates, but cannot itself be invalidated. So if Niebuhr is really using the word

    'transcendent' to mean that which transcends, what he is saying becomes: 'High religions are

    distinguished by making the whole of life meaningful by reference to something which makes

    the whole of life meaningless, which is the only way in which it is possible to maintain

    confidence that life is meaningful.'

    As this is patently absurd, I assume that he is not in fact using the word 'transcendent' in a

    transcendent sense. It is much more likely that when he talks of a 'transcendent source of

    meaning' he means 'anything which is capable of making the whole of human life seem

    meaningful to a large number of people'.

    I leave the reader to appreciate the following without further explanation:

    God made the world, and is never absent from it. So, within the mind of modern

    secularism there are feelings after the meaningfulness of human existence,

    recognition of supreme obligations in human relations, gropings after an undefined

    'otherness'.[3]

    The name of this infinite and inexhaustible ground of history is God. That is what

    the word means, and it is that to which the words Kingdom of Godand Divine

    Providencepoint. And if these words do not have much meaning for you, translate

    them, and speak of the depth of history, of the ground and aim of our social life,

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#5.3http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#5.3
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    22/64

    and of what you take seriously without reservation in your moral and political

    activities. Perhaps you should call this depth hope, simply hope. [4]

    [1] Paul Tillich, Systematic Theology, Vol. I, p.17.

    [2] R. Niebuhr, An Interpretation of Christian Ethics, Meridian

    Books, 1956, p.17.

    [3] Archbishop of Canterbury, Sunday Times, December 20, 1964.

    [4] Paul Tillich, The Shaking of the Foundations, Penguin Books,

    1949, p.65.

    Chapter 6THE SANE PERSON TALKS OF EXISTENCE

    When the sane person talks about life he sometimes mentions the Outside, but here a

    splendid confusion can be created from the simple fact that other peopleare, in a certain

    sense, outsiderelative to the individual. And so it is possible to find passages like the

    following:

    And what, too, would our reactions to (ESP) tell us about ourselves? That we feel

    safer living in splendid isolation, a huis clos? Or that we are prepared to face thepossibility of being members of one another in a world which, as mathematicians

    already know, is first and foremost one of relationships, and which now, as a great

    mathematician, Hermann Weyl, has dramatically put it, is being made by modern

    science itself 'to appear more and more as an open one... pointing beyond itself.' [1]

    This, incidentally, provides a particularly ostentatious example of the use which is constantly

    made by sane people of words with two possible meanings.

    Here the word 'relationship' is used to assimilate the two concepts 'human relationship' and

    'mathematical relationship'. A little analytical thought should convince the reader that a personmay be interested in human relationships without the slightest attraction towards

    mathematical ones, and vice versa.

    A distinction may be made, though it is a difficult one for a sane mind to grasp, between the

    idea of a world 'pointing beyond itself' to mathematical abstractions, and one 'pointing beyond

    itself' to human mutuality and cohesion.

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#5.4http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#6.1http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#5.4http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#6.1
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    23/64

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    24/64

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    25/64

    There is no evidence that people who feel like particles of dust relative to the

    universebecome paralysed and inactive, although it is a fact of clinical psychology that

    people who feel worthless relative to other peopleoften spend a good deal of time in bed.

    Virtually all categories of modern thinkers unite in chanting 'There is no Outside'. The

    existentialists, alone, say 'There isan Outside'. On account of their sane upbringing they feel

    that this is a difficult thing to say and they say it with a kind of metaphysical stutter, inventing

    new words profusely in their desperation to make themselves understood. Of course in a

    sense they are right in supposing that it is difficult; no sane person is likely to understand it.

    But the difficulty is emotional, not philosophical.

    (Incidentally, how well the human evasion has arranged matters when anyone who would say

    'There is an Outside' is driven to express himself at enormous length, in all but unreadable

    books.)

    Existentialists admit that there are certain states of consciousness in which ideas aboutdeath, existence, isolation, responsibility, urgency and so forth may have some emotional

    significance. But these are rare and transitory.

    The weakness of the existentialists' case is that they do not distinguish sufficiently between a

    philosophical attitude and a psychological one. A sane person may be made to admit, as a

    philosophical point, that everything is fundamentally uncertain, but this will not give it any

    power as a motive force in his life. Even a person who wished to realize the fact of uncertainty

    would find it difficult to perceive it with any vividness, or to eliminate other emotional attitudes

    which he saw to be incompatible with it.

    Having accepted that one may, at certain times, become startlingly aware of certain things,

    the existentialist argument usually goes on to talk of 'authentic' and 'inauthentic' being. If what

    is meant by 'inauthentic being' is living without awareness of these things, then obviously

    everyone is very inauthentic indeed. 'Authentic being' would mean to live in constant

    awareness of these things, with all the modifications that would entail. But this is a problem in

    psychology; it must be asked what forces are at work to prevent this awareness, whether it is

    possible to defeat them, and how. It is particularly useless to give prescriptions for 'authentic

    being' by involvement or commitment in the world. If we realize that we are talking about

    states of consciousness, it becomes clear that the procedure being recommended is this: 'If

    you should chance to have a flash of awareness of things of which you are not usually aware,

    you will realize that your life is full of things which seem meaningless to you so long as you

    are in this state of awareness. What are you to do to overcome your sense of

    meaninglessness?' There is a simple answer. 'The awareness will pass. You can forget it

    easily and go on living as before. But since you want to convince yourself that you are doing

    something about this flash of awareness you have had, you are recommended to return to

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    26/64

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    27/64

    [1] Rosalind Heywood, The Infinite Hive, Chatto and Windus,

    1964, p.224.

    [2] Quoted in William James, The Varieties of Religious Experience,

    Random House, 1902, p.158.

    [3] Th. Jouffroy, quoted in William James, Varieties of ReligiousExperience, Random House, 1902, p.173.

    [4] Erich Fromm, The Fear of Freedom, Routledge and Kegan Paul,

    1942, pp.16-17.

    [5] David E. Roberts (on Karl Jaspers), Existentialism and Religious

    Belief, Oxford University Press, New York, 1957, p.248.

    Chapter 7

    THE SANE PERSON TALKS OF GOD

    The human race has always been unable to distinguish clearly between metaphysics and

    morality. Thus the word 'God' can be used to mean 'origin of existence' or it can be used to

    mean 'intelligent being interested in the social behaviour of humans'. These two concepts are

    not, however, the same, and any relationship between them would have to be carefully

    established.

    In the same way 'religion' could mean two different things. It might mean something like 'a

    person's attitude to the Outside in general, and the fact of existence in particular'. As it

    happens, it does not mean this, and no one expects it to. It is actually used to mean 'a

    person's attitude towards social interactions with other people, with some reference to a

    supposed intelligent being who is interested in these interactions'. The last clause is

    dispensable. Most people would have little hesitation in accepting as 'religious' someone who

    showed the required behaviour patterns, whether he said he believed in a God or not.

    It is usually impossible to make sense of passages in which the word God appears at all

    often. Consider, for example, this description by Erich Fromm of an up-to-date, sensible kind

    of religious person.

    The truly religious person, if he follows the essence of the monotheistic idea, does

    not pray for anything, does not expect anything from God; he does not love God as

    a child loves his father or his mother; he has acquired the humility of sensing his

    limitations, to the degree of knowing that he knows nothing about God. God

    becomes for him a symbol in which man, at an earlier stage of his evolution, has

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    28/64

    expressed the totality of that which man is striving for, the realm of the spiritual

    world, of love, truth and justice. He ... considers all of his life only valuable

    inasmuch as it gives him the chance to arrive at an ever fuller unfolding of his

    human powers -- as the only reality that matters, as the only object of 'ultimate

    concern'; and eventually, he does not speak about God -- nor even mention his

    name. To love God, if he were going to use this word, would mean, then to long forthe attainment of the full capacity to love, for the realization of that which 'God'

    stands for in oneself. [1]

    Let us see what becomes of this passage if it is rewritten with the term 'God' understood to

    mean 'reason for existence' throughout.

    'The truly religious person, if he accepts the idea of a single overriding cause which originated

    all that exists, does not expect this cause to be directly related to what goes on in his own life,

    and does not expect it to do anything for him. He does not ask it for anything and does not

    expect to enter into a security-giving personal relationship with it. He realizes that he is a finitebeing, and that the reason for existence is inconceivable to him. He realizes that he is one of

    a certain race of animals which has evolved on a certain planet of a certain star in a certain

    galaxy, and that as they evolved these animals formulate certain ideals at which to aim. The

    reason for existence becomes to him a symbol for the security and consistency which his race

    of animals would like to have. He considers his life only valuable inasmuch as he considers it

    valuable. He regards what interests him as the only reality that matters, and the only object of

    any importance to the overriding cause which originated all that exists. Eventually he does not

    ask any questions about the reason for existence -- nor even refer to it in passing. To desire

    the knowledge of the reason for existence would mean to him, then, to long for the attainmentof the full capacity to have an intense interest in the welfare of other members of his species.

    This is the realization of that part of one's psychology for which the words 'reason for

    existence' stand.'

    Modern thinkers are at last feeling free to divorce the ideas of 'God' and 'religion' from any

    direct connection with the fact that things exist. Some go further. Not only has 'God' nothing in

    particular to do with the origin of existence, but also it has nothing whatever to do with

    anything human beings do not understand about -- that is, it has nothing to do with the

    Outside.

    Fromm's treatment of the idea of God depends on never defining it. A further advance has

    been made by the Bishop of Woolwich, who admittedly does not define it either, but says

    explicitly that it isn't there.

    What is of interest about the Bishop of Woolwich is not that he is supposed to be a Christian

    (which is a matter of definition), but that he is human. One might say that he is veryhuman.

    He speaks for his time; not only for the Christianity of his time but for human psychology as it

    stands facing the unknown -- or rather, with its back to it.

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7.1http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7.1
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    29/64

    I do not mean to be unduly condemnatory of human beings for standing in this position. It is

    the done thing. In fact, it has always been the done thing, although formerly some pains were

    taken to disguise the fact. When people talked about 'God' they used to pretend that what

    they said had something to do with questions about the meaning of existence and the

    purpose of life.

    The splendid discovery made by the Bishop of Woolwich is that the human race is completelyuninterested in such questions, but now it is all right to say so. Man has 'come of age'.

    It is not very easy to understand what the Bishop of Woolwich is saying, but it is easier if you

    start by ascribing a zero value to the term 'God'. What I mean is that you need to leave a sort

    of blank hole in every sentence in which the word 'God' appears. It is never defined, and so it

    is semantically redundant.

    However, though he does not say who or what God is, the Bishop wants most earnestly to

    assert that God is not Out There.

    But the signs are that we are reaching the point at which the whole conception of aGod 'out there' ... is itself becoming more of a hindrance than a help ... Suppose

    belief in God does not, indeed cannot, mean being persuaded of the 'existence' of

    some entity, even a supreme entity, which might or might not be there, like life on

    Mars? ... Suppose that all such atheism does is to destroy an idol, and that we can

    and must go on without a God 'out there' at all?[2]

    What can we make of these statements? Something (unspecified) is not Out There. Does this

    mean nothingis Out There? Or nothing of any significance is Out There? A little reflection

    convinces the questing mind that what the Bishop really means is 'There is noOut There.'To make this a little more grammatical, let us rephrase it as 'There is no Outside'. As we have

    mentioned, we define the Outside as 'that which falls outside the comprehension of the

    human race'. Now whatever else God might be supposed to be, one would imagine that he,

    she or it wasunquestionably Outside.

    But the Bishop has two reasons for supposing that God is not Outside.

    One of them is that the Inside is getting bigger. We are better at science than we used to be,

    and our expectation of life is increasing. We can make aeroplanes and control malaria. We do

    not know what everything is existing for, but neither do we care.God is an 'x' in the equation whom we cannot get on without, a cause, controller or

    designer whom we are bound to posit or allow room for -- this hypothesis seems to

    men today more and more superfluous.[3]

    Note, incidentally, a nice piece of sane writing. If you talk of 'God' impersonally as 'a cause' it

    is difficult to reject the hypothesis that 'there is always room for a cause we do not know

    about.' If, however, you talk of God as a 'designer', you are obviously bringing in all those

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7.2http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7.3http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7.2http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7.3
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    30/64

    anthropomorphic associations which make the idea of God ludicrous. This is where apposition

    is so useful.

    But the Bishop's main reason for supposing that God is not Outside is that we are none of us

    interested in an Outside, and we areinterested in other people.

    The world is not asking 'How can I find a gracious God?' It isasking 'How can I find

    a gracious neighbour?'[4]

    So if 'God' is to be of any interest, it must mean something about human relationships.

    (Just whatabout human relationships it could mean is never clear. The Bishop's only

    elucidation takes the form of periodically intoning such words as 'depth' and 'ultimacy'.)

    Of course, the Bishop is not alone in all this. He quotes extensively from Tillich, for example.

    When Tillich speaks of God in 'depth', he is not speaking of another Being at all.

    He is speaking of 'the infinite and inexhaustible depth and ground of all being', of

    our ultimate concern, of what we take seriously without reservation.[5]

    (I leave the reader to work out how many of the techniques described in 'How to Write Sane

    Books' are used in those two sentences.)

    Tillich maintains that God is the 'ultimate concern' of every man. I think all modern theologians

    would agree. However, the question is whether you take 'God' as defining 'man's ultimate

    concern', or take 'man's ultimate concern' as defining 'God'. Naturally, in this democratic age,

    the latter procedure is usually followed. (There is only one of God whereas there are a

    number of human beings; it would obviously be undemocratic to take God as a standard.) I

    am happy to see the old opposition between God and man has all but vanished from moderntheology. There is now the most extraordinary sympathy, not to say identity, of outlook.

    We must -- even if it seems 'dangerous' -- affirm that the glory of God and the glory

    of man, although different, actually coincide. There is no other glory of God (this is

    a free decision of his will) than that which comes about in man's existence. And

    there is no other glory of man than that which he may and can have in glorifying

    God. Likewise God's beatitude coincides with man's happiness. Man's happiness is

    to make God's beatitude appear in his life, and God's beatitude consists in giving

    himself to man in the form of human happiness.[6]

    So far we have only considered the modern kind of theologian, who does not believe in God.

    This should not be taken to imply that the human evasion has only just started to operate in

    this area.

    Even when people believed in God you may remember that there was a certain difficulty in

    driving any metaphysical argument with them beyond a certain point. They would suddenly

    round on you, with or without a sweet smile, and say, 'Ah, but the important thing is that God

    http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7.4http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7.5http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7.6http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7.4http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7.5http://www.theabsolute.net/minefield/humevas.html#7.6
  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    31/64

    is a person.' This effectively prevented any further discussion of his possible existence or

    attributes, particularly as the concepts 'person' and 'personality' appeared to defy analysis.

    It is, of course, entirely compatible with the human evasion that it should suddenly interpose

    the 'personal' and the reason for existence -- by whatever name it calls it. It is no less

    compatible with it that the people who disbelieve in God should do so on the grounds that he

    was a personalGod. 'It is evident', they say, 'that when people believed in God they werethinking of something like a human being with whom one could have emotional interactions.

    This is Freudian. It is obvious that there is no Outside because when people thought there

    was, they treated it like a person. I am well-adjusted and do not need a God to have

    emotional interactions with. I can have them with other people. Consequently there is no

    Outside.'

    [1] Erich Fromm, The Art of Loving, Allen and Unwin Paperback,

    1957, p.54.

    [2] John A. T. Robinson, Honest to God, S. C. M. Paperback,1963, pp.15-17.

    [3] John A. T. Robinson, The New Reformation, S.C.M. Paperback,

    1965, p.108.

    [4] Ibid., p.33.

    [5] John A.T. Robinson, Honest to God, S.C.M. Paperback, 1963,

    p.46.

    [6] Karl Barth, The Faith of the Church, Collins Fontana Books,1958, p.13.

    Chapter 8

    THE RELIGION OF EVASION

    The basic tenet of sane theology is that the chief barrier between man and God is constitutedby pride-- that is, self-sufficiency and ambition, which prevent him from recognizing his true

    place in the scheme of things. And we are enjoined to be humble -- that is, to accept our

    place in the scheme of things and adopt an attitude of unassuming trustfulness.

    This is remarkably like the standard prescription for preserving the human evasion, especially

    as it is usually accompanied by exhortations to take a particularly thorough interest in our

    fellow humans.

  • 8/7/2019 The Human Evasion - Celia Green

    32/64

    Now it might actually be true that a man was prevented from perceiving very much of reality

    (or from perceiving anything very interesting about it) by his satisfaction with himself as he is.

    But if we tried to say anything about this in ordinary language the most extraordinary results

    would ensue. We should have to say, for example, that the essence of humility was to

    recognize one's desire to be God.

    This follows from the fact that if you define 'pride' as 'what makes people feel they can

    manage all right as they are', 'anti-pride' or 'humility' should be 'what makes people aware that

    being as they are is unsatisfactory'.

    The idea of anyone desiring to be God is very shocking to a sane mind which, with its usual

    facility for confusing the issue, makes no distinction between 'desiring to be God' and

    'imagining oneself already to be God'. Now what would actually happen to someone who

    desired to