the meaning of existence in plato's "sophist"

Download The Meaning of Existence in Plato's

Post on 11-Dec-2016

214 views

Category:

Documents

2 download

Embed Size (px)

TRANSCRIPT

  • The Meaning of Existence in Plato's "Sophist"Author(s): Edith W. SchipperSource: Phronesis, Vol. 9, No. 1 (1964), pp. 38-44Published by: BRILLStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4181732 .Accessed: 14/08/2013 12:49

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

    .

    BRILL is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Phronesis.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 14 Aug 2013 12:49:00 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

  • The meaning of existence in Plato's Sophist EDITH W. SCHIPPER

    In this paper, I should like to give arguments for the following points: (1) that, for the later Plato, what exists must be defined by forms interrelated in logos; (2) that the particular things of experience

    exist, and also are defined by the interrelated forms. Their existence is not that of substantial subjects beyond their predicative forms, but is comprised by the forms, which formulate them and bring them out of the matrix of experience. Thus, Plato is sketching a profoundly original approach to the perennial problems of philosophy.

    I

    It is usually held that, in the Sophist, Plato, in parting from the Par- menidean dictum that what does not exist cannot be spoken of, is distinguishing an "existential" sense of evo= or 6v from another sense which is somehow predicative. This point has been questioned by W. G. Runciman in his acute and careful study of the Sophist. IHe calls the attributive sense "copulative", since it links a subject to a predicate by saying it is something; and points out that Plato did not usually distinguish the "existential" from the "copulative" sense. Regardless of the meaning of "copulative" - which I doubt to be adequate to the meaning of elvoct (or ov) - Plato does seem to stress its attributive or relational meaning, in which sense existence and its modes and relations is a predicate. But, further, for Plato, ec1va (or 6v) has more than a predicative meaning; it also has an existential one. If anything exists in the first meaning, it also exists in the second. That is, what may be significantly ascribed attributes and relations to other things exists in both meanings, as I shall try to show.

    In the discussion of not-being, (Soph. 237c-239b), the Stranger says that not-being must not be attributed to any existent (xCv OVTCJ)V etL -r To ,uf ov oux ota,7ov) and that To "xl" must always be attributed to an existent, (E.it' Ov-n; 237c-d) Here, tL, as all through the dialogues, would seem to at least include an existential meaning. Thus, in the 1 Runciman, Plato's Later Epistemology, Cambridge, Cambridge U. Press, 1962 esp. pp. 84-88.

    38

    This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 14 Aug 2013 12:49:00 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

  • Theaetetus, (188e-189e), Socrates says that sight, hearing, touching and 86om, in being about something (rt), are about something that exists. Likewise, in the Parmenides, (132b-c), Parmenides shows that thoughts must be about something (-), which must exist. Here, the stranger concludes that nothing can be attributed to what does not exist (TO t- ov), which, accordingly, cannot be spoken of (238c).

    If nothing can be said about what does not exist, conversely what exists is that about which something can be said. Mr. Runciman, too, says that "Plato seems to find himself forced to the conclusion that... everything referable must in some sense exist".2 Mr. Runciman himself does not consider the implication of this meaning of existence, since it is too inclusive, and since Plato does not explicitly consider it. How- ever, I would say that Plato does accept this broad meaning of ex- istence, though fictional entities such as mermaids (but not, as Mr. Runciman suggests, their images) would not exist in the same manner as natural entities. For the existence of anything, in its broad meaning, must be limited and defined by its attributes and relations.

    That the nature of the existence of what is perceived is defined by %n - which, in the later dialogues, continue to be the unsensed objects

    of intelligence - is clearly brought out in a passage from the Theaetetus where Socrates says that sound and color both exist ('ao'TOv; 185a), and that existence in the predicative sense ( odv 0oatav) is attributable to everything (exd nXvrwv). Socrates adds, in 186b:

    "the existence ('rmv oUGv) [of what is hard and soft] and what each is, (6 rt arT6v) and their difference from each other, and the nature (or existence in the predicative sense, '4v oAuatv) of this difference, the soul tries to judge for us by comparing them and reasoning about them."

    Thus, the nature of the existence of what is perceived is defined by the common attributes, which, although not explicitly called E'L8&, can only be the forms, since they are the objects of intelligence which are not given in perception. Here, -r-v o6aLxv seems to have primarily the more attributive sense, and is referred to (184c-d) when Theaetetus says that the common attributes defining the nature of what is perceiv- ed include oiuabxv ... XcxL To - q ivot, and likeness and unlikeness and sameness and difference". These characteristics, it will be noted, include three of the five basic forms discussed in the Sophist.

    2 Op. cit., p. 64.

    39

    This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 14 Aug 2013 12:49:00 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

  • Plato, in that discussion of the pyearm yevvn, has chosen five funda- mental forms to exemplify, what all of the forms manifest, the essential interconnectedness of the forms. Just as certain letters or sounds com- bine with others, so certain forms combine with others (253a-c). The forms are inherently interrelated, needing no separate copula to connect them, since they have a capacity to VrzxZLv with each other, as Mr. Runciman points out.3 They define the ways in which what exists may be distinguished, defined, and interrelated.

    Thus, in the Sophist, the forms are inextricably intertwined. That they were ever conceived by Plato as atomic and as simple nameables is a question, since, already in the Phaedo (103e-104e) he spoke of the connections of forms such as fire an(l heat, snow and cold, three and oddness. In the controversial Socrates' "dream" (Theaet. 201D-202c), the conclusion of the argument that logos of a complex of unknowable simples is itself unknowable could be either that we must have know- ledge of simples or that there are no simples apart from the meaning accruing to them from the complexes in which they function. Mr. Runciman prefers the first conclusion,4 although the second is more consonant with later Platonism, as lhe himself interprets it.

    The nature of the forms is defined by and formulated in a logos, an account or argument or statements, as has been maintained by Plato from the Phaedo on.5 He ends his discussion of the intercon- nections of the forms by saying that it makes ),6yoq possible (86a 'rv (X?Xcov xxv etav au t7roxov o Xoyo4 yeyovev ,udv; Soph. 259e) The X6yo4 which "signifies something about action (7piRcv) or inaction or the nature of what is or is not " (262c) must combine verbs and nouns, so that a relationship between them may be expressed. Moreover, it must be about something (-nv6q; 262e). As Gilbert Ryle has said, it must be propositional and contain a "live verb", which relates what is assertable about people or things. In the elp8iox 5 cv Plato relates

    3 Op. cit., p. 105. 4 Op. cit., p. 40-41. 5 In what sense logos is about the forms has been argued by R. C. Cross, in Logos and the Forms in Plato, Mind, vol. 63, 1954; and R. S. Bluck, Logos and the Forms, Mind, vol. 65, 1956. Mr. Cross maintains (pp. 446-8) that the interrelated forms are "logical predicates displayed in logoi", which are about something which is not the forms but their logical subject. Mr. Bluck maintains, on the contrary, (pp. 523-528) that the logos is about the interrelated forms, but is only "an indispensable aid" toward knowledge of them. Since, as Mr. Bluck points out, ocx&r6 T6 xZ rather than being what the form X is about, is the form, I would incline toward his solution.

    40

    This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 14 Aug 2013 12:49:00 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

  • forms such as xtvcjat and eIvaL which express actions and ways of existing.6 Thus, X6yo4 combines forms, which express the interrelation- ships of what exists.

    II

    The particular things, the sticks and stones, of experience, Plato has always said to exist, but with an existence inferior to that of the forms. In the earlier dialogues, particular sensed things were spoken of as having a semi-existence " midway" between existence (which the forms had), and non-existence, which could not be spoken of. The things were accessible only to an unstable opinion (836o; Republic, 478d-479d). In the divided line analogy, things were grasped by conjecture or belief ([a-rLq) apart from the forms; and, together with their images and shadows, by a fluctuating opinion (86R). But, in the later dia- logues, we hear nothing about a mode of existence or grasp of the sensed things separate from that of the forms. There, ao'6 is no longer an uncertain belief about things, but is a silent X6yo4, whic