the subjectivity of the present

41
The Subjectivity of the Present Craig Callender Dept of Philosophy University of California, San Diego

Upload: gypsy

Post on 25-Feb-2016

20 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

DESCRIPTION

Craig Callender Dept of Philosophy University of California, San Diego. The Subjectivity of the Present. 1. Introduction. Objects are booming and buzzing by, vivid present perceptions are replaced, and we feel ourselves inexorably slipping into the future. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: The Subjectivity of the Present

The Subjectivity of the Present

Craig CallenderDept of PhilosophyUniversity of California, San Diego

Page 2: The Subjectivity of the Present

1. Introduction Objects are booming and buzzing

by, vivid present perceptions are replaced, and we feel ourselves inexorably slipping into the future.

By contrast, the time of fundamental physics doesn’t speed up or slow down, distinguish the past from future, or single out a time as now.

To echo another debate, we have an ‘explanatory gap’ between time in experience and time in science.

Page 3: The Subjectivity of the Present

Time in Physics

No present No asymmetry No flow

The set of temporal events in physics has lots of structure, e.g., ordering relations, topology, metric. But it does not have…

Is the time of natural science incomplete or inaccurate? Has physics missed the properties of time that cause the above? Or is the time of physics all the time that is needed? Can the rest be explained with psychology, environmental features and complicated relations between them?

Page 4: The Subjectivity of the Present

Two Different Answers

“Tenseless”

– Past, present and future ‘equally’ exist.

– Fundamental temporal properties are relations of earlier than, later than and simultaneous with.

– No distinguished present

– B. Russell, J.J.C. Smart, A. Gruenbaum

“Tensed”

– Many varieties, e.g., presentism, becoming, primitive tenses, branching, etc.

– All of these distinguish the present in some way

– A.N. Prior, C.D. Broad,

Page 5: The Subjectivity of the Present

Time

Space

Your death

Past

Your birth

Today’s lecture

Page 6: The Subjectivity of the Present

Presentism

NOW

Mom’s memories

of your birth

Page 7: The Subjectivity of the Present

Dialectical Situation “Nuclear” Arguments

Against Tenses

– McTaggart– Smart/Broad “How

fast…?”– Relativity No-go

theorems

Arguments for Tenses

– Semantics of now– Headache argument– Temporal “Knowledge”

argument– Experience

Detensers typically concede that tenses do better with experience, but claim that nuclear objections overwhelm these arguments. However, when the debate goes conventional…

Page 8: The Subjectivity of the Present

Plan for Today Fight back on the experiential

front, too!

Oddly, given the centrality of temporal experience to the arguments in the field, empirical work on the topic is virtually absent from the field.

Focus on the present and experience

Bracket “nuclear” objections and also bracket knowledge argument.

I’ll put the mind into the mind-dependent present. On the basis of recent work in cognitive neuroscience and psychophysics, I’ll develop a tenseless rival to the tensed metaphysics hypothesis.

By using essentially Mill’s methods, I argue this rival hypothesis is better supported by the evidence than the tensed theory is.

Page 9: The Subjectivity of the Present

2. Experiencing the Present

Pig experiencesbacon

Pig calendarsetc

Experience of the present

The Now

Page 10: The Subjectivity of the Present

Do We Experience an Objective Present?

Like Hume searching in vain for his self, I don’t perceive any stamp of present on my experiences…

Whether something is past, present or future doesn’t change the way it looks. The light from a lighthouse 1 mile away and from Jupiter look the same, even though one image is of an hour in the past and the other is of 0.000005 seconds past.

We cannot, as Mellor writes, “refute someone who claims to see the future in a crystal ball by pointing to the visible pastness of the image: there is no such thing” (1998, 16).

Page 11: The Subjectivity of the Present

Divide in Tensed CampCraig (2000, 143) writes:

as a result of physics and neurology, we now realize that nothing we sense is instantaneously simultaneous with our experience of it as present. But in most cases, the things and events we observe are contained within a brief temporal interval which is present Éand our basic belief makes no reference to instants, so that s uch a basic belief remains properly basic even fo r scientifically educated persons like ourselves. The fact that under extraordinary circumstances our basic belief in t he presentness of some event/thing should turn out to be false is no proof at all either that we h ave no basic beliefs concerning the presentness of events/things in the external world or that such beliefs are not properly basic. Mellor is therefore simply wrong when he asserts that we do not observe (defeasibly) the tense of events.

Page 12: The Subjectivity of the Present

What is this Experience? Tensers seem to read the theory into the data--or not mention the data explicitly.

– Craig 2000: we’re “appeared to presently”– Schlesinger 1991: the present is “palpably real”– Smith the presentness we sense “inheres” in every state of affairs; we have

an “unreflexive awareness of events as present”– Balashov 2005: some events are “known to be present simpliciter”

Confinement? Our experience is confined to the present.

– Mellor: if this means we only experience present events or objects, then this claim is false.

– If we re-phrase to ‘the sensory experiences we have are present when we have them’, then contentious: my experience of a hospital when born is not present.

Page 13: The Subjectivity of the Present

Problem with Token-Reflexive Theory? Oaklander 1994: "There is nothing more, ontologically speaking,

to the presence of experience than our being conscious of our experiences when they are happening.”

Detensers understand ‘e is present’ as e is roughly simultaneous with the judgment.

The token reflexive account explains a correlation between a propositional attitude about presentness and an experience. It doesn't account for or describe an experience itself.

Tensers steadfastly maintain that there is an experience of presentness.

Page 14: The Subjectivity of the Present

Presentness Qualia?Perhaps it's impossible to describe the experience. Compare: if I try to describe the phenomenological character of redness then I can contrast this feature with other features also in my experience. I can contrast redness with greenness and employ lots of color vocabulary to describe the redness and its difference with greenness, e.g., its brightness, how saturated it is, and so on. But all aspects of my alleged experience of presentness are present.

Page 15: The Subjectivity of the Present

Inference to Tensed Metaphysics Tensers believe an experience (that we haven’t been able to

cleanly identify) warrants belief in a global objective present.

For Craig the belief in such a present “enjoys such powerful positive epistemic status for us that not only can we be said to know that tense and temporal becoming are real, but also that this belief constitutes an intrinsic defeater-defeater which overwhelms the objections brought against it.”

But of course, even our experience of red doesn’t guarantee objective red things in the world. We have reason to believe that there are red things in the world (and tables, chairs and pigs) just in case the evidence best confirms these hypotheses.

Page 16: The Subjectivity of the Present

300,000,000m/s

t

t*: Object is chair-shaped

3. The Framework

Butterfield 1984 seeks to explain some of our intuitions about the objectivity of the present.

Typically macro-objects in our local environment change much more slowly than the rate at which light and sound travels to us, plus time to form beliefs.

Consider looking at a chair nearby: visual lag of roughly 0.5s. At t* I form a belief about an object at t. Thanks to rapidity of light/processing and the above fact, the result of this process is a belief at t* that is typically accurate. The lag t-t* typically does not make the belief about local macroscopic objects false.

t-t* doesn’t affect truth value!

Page 17: The Subjectivity of the Present

Same goes for communication, say, by signing; same goes for some other sensory modalities. None of these types of information require a time stamp for reliable information transfer. (By contrast, consider mail and smell).

All of this makes good sense from an evolutionary perspective. Evol pressure to make t-t* small… And it makes sense to update rapidly…

These circumstances allow for great inter-subjective agreement about what happens “now”, agreement that can be used to explain why we’re tempted to restrict existence to the present and say that we share a now but not a here.

Call a region over which a ‘time stamp’ is not needed for reliable information transfer a Now Patch. Now Patches can be “glued” together to form a “global” Present. This explains why we think there is an objective global Present.

Page 18: The Subjectivity of the Present

Now

Now

Now Now

Now

Now Patches as local patches that we ‘glue’ together to form a global Now—explains alleged objectivity of the Present…

Now’s as Local Patches

Now

Now

Page 19: The Subjectivity of the Present

Mechanisms of Simultaneity Constancy

Although I think Butterfield has it more or less right, the main character in the mind-dependence story is left out…yet it seems important.

E.g. multisensory integration There are temporal integration mechanisms in

the brain that weld together inputs as present. Instead of defining Now Patches via time

stamps, define them via these temporal integration mechanisms. This offers a deeper and more accurate explanation than the time stamp theory.

What psychologists call simultaneity constancy explains the apparent objectivity of the present.

Page 20: The Subjectivity of the Present

4. Evidence of the Constructed Present: A. Sim Windows

Subjective Simultaneity

Put headphones on a subject and let her listen to tones lasting for 1ms. If the left and right ears are stimulated simultaneously, then the subject hears not two tones but one fused tone. Hirsh and Sherrick 1961, Poppell 1988; Euler 1997

Page 21: The Subjectivity of the Present

Subjective Simultaneity

Compensation of Subjective Simultaneity

Subjective Time

Now delay one of the tones. Up to a certain threshold, the two tones will still be fused as one.

Page 22: The Subjectivity of the Present

Visual Simultaneity

+

t

If

<20ms

Simultaneoust

If

>20ms

Not Simultaneous

Page 23: The Subjectivity of the Present

Different sensory modalities

Different resolutions:•Vision: > 20 ms• Tactile: > 10 ms• Audition: > 2 ms

Event Fusion Thresholds

Page 24: The Subjectivity of the Present

Temporal order

+

t

If

20-40ms

Not Simultaneous but no reliable temporal order

t

If

>40ms

Reliable Temporal Order

Page 25: The Subjectivity of the Present

Simultaneity Windows

In all the sensory modalities, the simultaneity window varies from person to person. (In hearing, for instance, from 2ms to 5 ms.) It also varies with age, older people fusing more events than younger people, and many other factors. In each person the minimum threshold of simultaneity cannot be shrunk.

Whose simultaneity window coincides with the Present?

Page 26: The Subjectivity of the Present

Stone et al 2003 Recent experiments by Stone et al 2003 bolster the earlier experiments. In 1000

trials Stone et al presented 23 subjects with light-sound pairs of stimuli separated from -250ms (sound first) to +250ms. In each trial subjects were asked to indicate if the pair occurred simultaneously or not. These responses picked out a time t between -250ms and 250ms as the point of subjective simultaneity. Stone et al found two items of particular interest about PSS.

(1) PSS is observer specific. The points varied greatly, from -21ms to 150ms, among subjects. Remarkably, the difference between each subject was statistically significant.

(2) But—revealed in another experiment—the PSS is remarkably stable for each

individual.

Given the mind-dependence theory, we might expect (1). But the second item is also one we should expect. Navigating about the world is not merely a question of aligning the visual with the auditory; it is also a question of calibrating that alignment with motor control. However your PSS differs from that of your friends, it had better be the case that it remains stable over time if you are to play table tennis at all well.

Page 27: The Subjectivity of the Present

B. Flash Lag Effect

QuickTime™ and aYUV420 codec decompressor

are needed to see this picture.

Page 28: The Subjectivity of the Present

Non-laboratory Example?

“64 matches, 337 offsides were analysed using digital video technology. The error percentage was 26.2%. During the first 15 min match period, there were significantly more errors (38.5%) than during any other 15 min interval. As predicted by the flash-lag effect, we observed many more flag errors (86.6%) than non-flag errors (13.4%).”

J Sports Sci. 2006 May;24(5):521-8

Page 29: The Subjectivity of the Present

B. Flash Lag Effect Explanations: motion extrapolation, positional

averaging, latency difference

“Bouncing” flash lag: Eagleman and Sejnowski (2000): postdiction. What we see for t depends on next 80ms.

Temporal integration mechanism: what we see depends on the average difference between different position signals over a temporal integration window. (Lappe and Krekelberg 1999, 2000)

Gelard and Sherrick’s 1972 cutaneous rabbit…

What is interesting is that the present we experience is not just the present, nor even just the slightly recent past, but rather something constructed from sampling across past and “future” times.

There may not be an isomorphism between the temporal order of brain processes and the represented temporal order of events in the world. “Time is not its own representation.”

Page 30: The Subjectivity of the Present

C. Recalibration

Consider again binding together auditory and visual inputs from a common target.

We know two features help sound “catch up”a. Mechanical transduction is

faster than chemical transduction

b. Neural transmission time from visual cortex to cerebral cortex is longer than time from auditory cortex to cerebral cortex

But if a and b were the sole explanation of our ability to bind together info as synchronous, we would only be able to bind together inputs over a very restricted range of target distances (10-12m).

Page 31: The Subjectivity of the Present

Input Neural Processing

Multisensory Simultaneity

Time Course of Neural Events

Subjective Simultaneity

Subjective Time

Compensation of Subjective Simultaneity

Subjective Time

-2-Slide borrowed from Fujisaki et al,VSS 3rd Annual Meeting 5/10/03

Page 32: The Subjectivity of the Present

Synchronicity Plasticity Recent experiments have suggested that one's

experience of synchronicity--of two things happening at the same time--change when intentions are involved.

Cunningham et al 2001: subjects moved a mouse that caused a spot on a computer screen to move in a video game.  Gradually a lag between the movement of the mouse and the resulting effect on the screen was introduced.  Subjects informally reported that after a while their actions and effects were simultaneous again. 

Haggard et al 2002 then set about testing directing whether this was so, whether, that is, a subject’s intentions affected the experience itself of what things happen simultaneously. They showed that it did. (See Eagleman and Holcombe 2002.)

Page 33: The Subjectivity of the Present

Temporal Ventriloquism A temporally proximate audible click

“captures” a flash. Fendrich and Corbalis 2001; Vroomen et al 2004.

Fujisaki et al 2004: experiments “suggest that the brain attempts to adjust subjective simultaneity across different modalities by detecting and reducing time lags between inputs that likely arise from the same physical events"

Harris, forthcoming: "reconstructive process is involved that is able to resynchronize asynchronous signals by taking into account many factors, both internal and external, which would otherwise distort accurate knowledge of timing."

Page 34: The Subjectivity of the Present

Sound and Simultaneity Sugita and Suzuki “Implicit Estimation of Sound-

Arrival Time” Nature 27 Feb 2003

Subjects were presented through headphones bursts of white noise (10ms duration) to simulate external sound from frontal direction. Brief light flashes were produced by an array of 5 green LEDs at different distances (1-50m). Intensity of light altered so as to produce consistent intensity at the eye.

Subjects were told to imagine that the LEDs were the source of the light and sound, while listening to sound directly from source.

To estimate subjective simultaneity, observers judged what came first, light or sound.

Subjective simultaneity increased by about 3 ms with each 1 m increase in distance up to about 40m. Sound travels 1m/3ms at sea level and room temp.

“Our results show that the brain probably takes sound velocity into account when judging simultaneity” (911)

Page 35: The Subjectivity of the Present

Variations on Sugita and Suzuki’s experiment have often not replicated this result. Why?

– Taking into account target distance would be a computationally complex task. Probably there are various “rules of thumb” and/or proxies used by the brain to do this.

It may be, as Fugisaki et al suggest, that the brain tries to reduce lags between inputs that likely arise from the same source.

– Zambini et al 2005 show that subjects are more likely to report stimuli as simultaneous when they originate from the same spatial location than when not.

Page 36: The Subjectivity of the Present

Explanations & Open Questions Harris et al, forthcoming, suggest a 3-stage process:

1. Stimuli are fit into windows; these are candidates for recalibration2. Unfamiliar stimuli delayed according to fixed rules (e.g., 40ms

delay for sound to be bound w/ light plausibly from same source)3. Familiar stimuli are delayed according to more fine-grained

process

Many open questions:

– One mechanism or more?– Bottom-up (i.e., neural transmission) or top-down (i.e., “decision

point”)?– What is the neural basis?

And one closed question: the need for a temporal integration mechanism is “self-evident” (Stone et al).

Page 37: The Subjectivity of the Present

Temporal Integration

Page 38: The Subjectivity of the Present

5. Bearing on the Tense Debate? None of the phenomena prove that our experience of presentness is of

a subjective property rather than an objective metaphysical property. Revealing the operations of the mind in forming our impressions can only do so much…

But once the detensers have an alternative hypothesis, they can then compare this to the alternative tensed theory explanation of the phenomena, just as a materialist theory of (say) beliefs could be compared with the dualist alternative. We can compare P(E/H)’s. The evidence seems to be pointing one way. The phenomenology of the present bears the hallmarks of perceiving something mind-dependent, not mind-independent. The subjective present

– is highly contingent on environmental variables, e.g., what you take yourself to causally affect, what you’re attending to, how loud stimuli are, where in field of vision, etc.

– varies dramatically from person to person– varies intra-personally too, depending on your age, etc.– dependent on later information

Page 39: The Subjectivity of the Present

Compare with Dualism Debate Daily discoveries of the dependence of mental

phenomena on neural dynamics do not falsify mind-body dualism. If the physical “receiver” is broken or at the wrong station, same tune won’t be played…

But dualism is still explanatorily inadequate: Why should caffeine and valium affect my non-material mind’s mood differently? Dualist answers are either ad hoc stipulations or ride piggyback on the explanation from natural science—but at the peril of leaving nonmaterial minds nothing left to explain.

Background: evolution, biology

Simplicity

Upshot: dualism looks really bad

Page 40: The Subjectivity of the Present

ClaimI submit that the tensed theory of time is in precisely the same situation as dualism.

We group various experienced inputs together as present; we are tempted to think this grouping is done by the world, not us.

But we have learned that our impression of subjective present-ness varies inter- and intra-subjectively and that it can be manipulated in a variety of ways. These changes and manipulations are not at all what one would expect if our impression of now-ness were the impression of a mind-independent global monadic present. Tensers must provide stipulative answers to questions such as why age but not weight affects the size of my simultaneity window; alternatively, they can adopt a detensed answer, but again, only at the risk of leaving tenses with nothing to explain.

Background: tenses aren’t needed and in fact aren’t wanted by the natural sciences.

Upshot: The tensed theory is in trouble.

Page 41: The Subjectivity of the Present

“…our brain furnishes an integrative mechanism that shapes sequences of events to unitary forms…that which is integrated is the unique content of consciousness which seems to us present. The integration, which itself objectively extends over time, is thus the basis of our experiencing a thing as present.…The now, the subjective present, is nothing independently; rather it is an attribute of the content of consciousness. Every object of consciousness is necessarily always now—hence the feeling of nowness.”

(Pöppell, 1987, 62-63)