two rival programmes in 19th. century classical...

302
TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE VERSUS FIELD THEORIES. This thesis is submitted for the degree of DOCTOR of PHILOSOPHY , by HAWORTH MARTIN HARROP FRICKE, a candidate registered at the LONDON SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS AND POLITICAL SCIENCE.

Upload: others

Post on 10-May-2020

1 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS

ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE VERSUS FIELD THEORIES.

This thesis is submitted for the degree of DOCTOR of PHILOSOPHY ,

by HAWORTH MARTIN HARROP FRICKE, a candidate registered at the

LONDON SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS AND POLITICAL SCIENCE.

Page 2: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS

ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE VERSUS FIELD THEORIES.

BY /

HAWORTH MARTIN HARROP FRICKE

ABSTRACT

The thesis is a historical case-study in which I.Lakatos's Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes is applied to 19th. Century classical electrodynamics. Two research programmes are appraised. One, the Action-at-a-distance programme, had as its hard core the theory that electromagnetic phenomena were the outcome of sources acting at a distance across empty space on each other.

2

Its rival, the Field programme, had the hard core that electromagnetic phenomena were the outcome of behaviour by the space between the apparent sources. It is argued that the Action-at-a-distance programme was always the superior one of the two. This revision in the standard historical appraisal results from the use of Lakatos's methodology. The Action-at-a-distance programme developed progressively, through the theories of Ampere, Weber, and their successors, to a satisfactory and fairly complete account of the phenomena of electrodynamics. In contrast, the Field programme degenerated as it consisted of a sequence of ad hoc or heuristically ad hoc theories. Faraday, Maxwell, and Helmholtz vigo~ously criticised the Action-at-a-distance programme. These criticisms were extremely influential and some historians regard them as persuasive today. It is shown that these criticisms are entirely without merit and further that they could easily have been seen to be without merit at the time of their proposal. Finally, many subsidiary theses, advocated by writers in the history and philosophy of the development of c~assical electrodynamics, are critically assessed.

Page 3: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

CONTENTS

TITLE PAGE, ABSTRACT, and CONTENTS

CHAPTER 1 : INTRODUCTION

I. Introduction.

2. The A.A.D. Programme Its Hard Core and

Heuristic.

3. The Philosophical Objection to A.A.D.

4. The Origins of Electrodynamics : Oersted and

\ Ampere.

5. First Criticisms of A.A.D. : Faraday's

Objections and His Foundation of the

Field Programme.

6. The Rival Views on the Sources and

Receivers of Force.

7. The Early Development of A.A.D. : Weber's

Unification of Electrodynamics and Other

p. I

p.8

p.9

p.15

p.19

p.23

p.25

p.29

Theoretical Advances. p.37

8. The Growth of the Field Heuristic 1840-60. p.40

9. The Field Programme to 1860. p.48

10. An Appraisal of the Two Programmes Until 1860 p.51

11. Maxwell's Theories of Electromagnetism. p.53

12. The A.A.D. Theory of Light and An Appraisal of

the Two Programmes from 1860-1900. p.56

3

Page 4: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

4

CHAPTER 2 THE ORIGINS OF ELECTRODYNAMICS OERSTED AND

AMPERE : p .63

I. Introduction. p.64

2. Agassi on the Philosophy of Discovery of

General Facts. p.68

3. Oersted's Discovery of the General Fact that

Current Electricity Produces a Magnetic Field. p.73

4. The Production of Amp~re's Law by Rational

Problem Solving within the A.A.D. Programme

-- Dorling on Demonstrative Induction. p.82

" 5. The Evidence for Ampere's Law and the Significance ,

of Oersted's and Ampere's Results for the A.A.D.

and Field Programmes. p.98

6. Amp~re's Theories of Magnetism and the Epistemological

Interpretation of Them. p.IOO

7. The Origin, Validity, and Epistemological Status

of the Biot and Savart Law. p.102 ,

8. Tricker on the 'as if' Interpretation of Ampere's

Theories. p.105

9. Summary. p.I08

CHAPTER 3 : EARLY CRITICISM OF THE A.A.D. PROGRAMME : FARADAY'S

OBJECTIONS AND HIS FOUNDATION OF THE FIELD PROGRAMME p.I09

I. Introduction. p.IIO

2. Faraday's Criticism of Particular A.A.D. Theories. p.IIS

Page 5: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

3. Faraday's Direct Criticism of the A.A.D. Programme. p.118

4. Faraday's Indirect Criticism: The Field Programme

and Faraday's Major Discoveries.

5. Faraday's Discoveries and Their Relation to the

Field Progranune.

p.126

p.128

CHAPTER 4 : THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE A.A.D. PROGRAMME 1830-60 :

WEBER'S UNIFICATION OF ELECTRODYNAMICS AND OTHER THEORETICM,

ADVANCES: p.132

I. Introduction. p.133

2. Sources and Receivers of Force.

3. Gauss -- The Unification of Electrodynamics and

the Retardation of Forces.

4. Weber's Deduction of His Law.

5. The Significance of the Law for the A.A.D.

Programme •

6. Criticisms of the Law and Their Evaluation.

7. Riemann's Attempt to Deduce Weber's Law from ~

Propagated Force Law.

8. Electrical Actions Propagated at the Speed

of Light.

9. Summary.

CHAPTER 5 : MAXWELL'S THEORIES OF ELECTROMAGNETISM

1. Introduc tion.

p. 137

p.141

p.144

p.IS3

p.IS7

p.164

p.169

p.170

p.l71

p. I 72

5

Page 6: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

2. 'On Physical Lines of Force' (1862).

3. A Critical Appraisal of 'On Physical Lines of

of Force' and of the Theses of Heimann and

Bromberg Concerning It.

4. The Later Theory.

5. A Critical Appraisal of the Later Theory.

6. Sutmnary.

CHAPTER 6 : THE A.A.D. THEORY OF LIGHT

I. Introduction.

2. Ludwig Lorenz's Theory of Light.

3. Hertz's 1884 Paper, 'On the Relations Between

Maxwell's Fundamental Equations and The Fundamental

Equatioris of the Opposing Electromagnetics'.

4. A Comparison of the A.A.D. Theory of Light and

Maxwell's Theory of Light.

5. The Theory of Helmholtz.

APPENDIX I : HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE

I. Introduction.

2. Inductivist versus Hypothetico-Deductivist

Historiography : The Problem of Selection.

3. The Growth of Scientific Knowledge : The Problem

of the History of Science.

p.179

p.183

p.191

p.196

p.206

p.207

p.208

p.21S

p.222

p.224

p.226

p.229

p.230

p.232

p.23s

Page 7: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

4. Methodologies of Science: The Problem of Appraisal.

5. Methodological Bias: The Problem of Objectivity.

6. Lakatos's Suggestion: History of Science as a

Test of its Methodology.

7. Rejection of Lakatos's View.

8. Sunnnary.

APPENDIX 2 FALLIBILIST REALISM VERSUS INSTRUMENTALISM.

APPENDIX 3 WEBER'S LAW AND THE CONSERVATION OF ENERGY.

B IBL IOGRAPHY .

p.243

p.2flS

p.266

p.267

p.270

p.272

p.282

p.284

7

Page 8: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

8

Chapter 1 Introduction.

1. Introduction.

2. The Action-at-a-distance (A.A.D.) Programme Its Hard Core

and Heuristic.

3. The Philosophical Objection to A.A.D. ,

4. The Origins of Electrodynamics: Oersted and Ampere.

5. First Criticis~ of A.A.D. : Faraday's Objections and His

Foundation of the Field Programme.

6. The Rival Views on the Sources and Receivers of Force.

7. The Early Development of A.A.D. : Weber's Unification of

Electrodynamics and Other Theoretical Advances.

8. The Growth of the Field Heuristic 1840-1860.

9. The Field Programme to 1860.

10. An Appraisal of the Two Programmes to 1860.

11. Maxwell's Theories of Electromagnetism.

12. The A.A.D. Theory of Light and an Appraisal of the Two

Programmes from 1860 - 1900.

Page 9: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

9

1. Introduction:

Imre Lakatos died in 1974. His contribution to the philosophy

of science was twofold : a theory for the appraisal of scientific

views and a theory on the relations between the history and the

1 philosophy of science. The former -- the Methodology of Scientific

Research Programmes (M.S.R.P.) was complete; even so, like most theories,

it was accompanied by an agenda of unsolved problems. The latter <

lay behind Lakatos's pleas for historical case-studies, and still only

2 3 a few of these have been written. '

4 known.

The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes is well

In brief, it suggests that only a series of theories should

be appraised. A series is characterized by a hard core which is a

theory which runs through the series giving it continuity, and a

heuristic which is the problem solving mechanism which dictates

the lines of research. For example, the Newtonian research programme

1. The theories receive their fullest expression in I.Lakatos (1970), 'Falsificationism and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', and I.Lakatos (1971), 'History of ~cience and Its Rational Reconstructions'.

2. The ones in existence are collected together in C.Howson (ed.) (1976), Method and Appraisal in the Physical Sciences, and this volume also contains a reprint of Lakatos (1971).

3. My initial attraction to the topic of this dissertation arose as follows. Lakatos's (1971) suggests that case-studies should scrutinize rival research programmes which predict novel facts. Classical electro­dynamics had the rival research programmes of the Continental action-at­a-distance school and the British field theorists, and in the anticipation of propagated electromagnetic waves it had one of the most stunning novel facts ever. As Planck writes: ' •••• the criterion of the value of a theory, that it explains quite another phenomena besides those on which it was based, has never been so well satisfied as with Maxwell's theory ••• This must for all time remain one of the greatest triumphs of human intell­ectual endeavour.' Maxwell (1931), James Clerk Maxwell·: a Commemorative Volume 1831-1931, page 57.

4. See Lakatos (1970) and references therein.

Page 10: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

10

had as its hard core the law of gravity and the three laws of dynamics

and part of its heuristic was the instruction 'First treat the planets

as mass points, then as mass balls, then as spinning mass balls, then

as spinning mass balls with perturbations ••• &c'. A research pro­

gramme is good in so far as the members of the sequence predict novel

facts, and bad in so far as the programme lags behind the facts and can

explain them only in an ad hoc fashion. This notion of ad hoc covers

two cases: the old standard use of ad hoc, and a new sense of

heuristically ad hoc which occurs when the facts are actually explained

but they are not explained in accordance with the plan of research.

Such an appraisal is a function of time -- a programme may become better

or worse -- and is in principle without end in that the value of it

does not have to settle to a limit. l Occasionally, for clarity, I will

avoid the jargon by talking of research programmes as consisting of a

single theory and a heuristic -- the single theory referred to here is

the hard core theory of the series; so I might describe the Newtonian

research programme as being composed of the gravitational-dynamic theory

plus its heuristic.

What does the appraisal indicate? I maintain, and this is

argued in Appendix 1, that it measures three properties. First it shows

the epistemological superiority of one theory in the series over its

predecessor -- if one of two more or less similar theories makes a

successful prediction which the other cannot account for, then that pre­

diction can serve as objective grounds for preferring one theory. Thus,

with a good developing programme, one can say that knowledge is growing.

Second, and probably the most controversially, often it can show the

epistemological superiority of one programme over its rival at a given

1. In connection with this, see Lakatos (1971) page 104 Note.

Page 11: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

I I

time. Finally, it indicates the heuristic power of a whole programme

for the continuing discoveries are good evidence for the potential

to discover.

Any author of a case-study ought to face the questions: Why

should the case-study be done? and How should the case-study be done?

These questions too are considered in Appendix 1. TRis case-study's

significance lies in its describing the growth of a sector of knowledge.

The answer proposed to the second question is that the history must be

approached theoretically and fallibly and -- given this -- it is

preferable to do so from a methodologically advanced standpoint which

is explicitly stated. Here the standpoint is Lakatos's M.S.R.P.

Descriptions of the growth of classical electrodynamics fall

into three alternative styles:

a) The account given by most physicists is that all the develop-

ments were due to field theories; as a result, the so-called

Maxwell equations figure largely in phyaics textbooks;

b) The account given by most historians acknowledges the existence

of an alternative electrodynamics -- the action-at-a-distance

theories -- and claims that.both approaches made contributions

and that the modern view is a synthesis of the two;

and finally,

c) The account, generally considered to be outrageous, due to,

and championed solely by,A. O'Rahilly,to the effect that the

action-at-a-distance tradition was the important one. l

The physicists' story is implausible because half of Maxwell's

so-called equations were not due to Maxwell, and also the modern unified

1. A.O'Rahilly (1965), Electromagnetic Theory. First published in 1938 as 'Electromagnetics'.

Page 12: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

12

view contains the Lorentz force law and the theory of electrons both

of which were alien to field methods.

The historian tells the tale as follows. There were field

ideas, which had their basis in Maxwell's translation into mathematics

of Faraday's work. Field theories had one major success and one major

failure; the success was in the propagated electromagnetic waves, whose

existence was suspected from early on; the failure was in the inability

to provide a coherent account of the source of the fields. Both

Faraday and Maxwell tended to identify charges with merely the term-

ination of lines of force, or -- more extremely -- with the result of

polarization of the medium; but then the polarization was supposed to

be caused by the charges and so it seemed that the polarization was

caused by itself. Action-at-a-distance theories, on the other hand,

also had one major success and one major failure. The success was the

discovery of electrons, whose existence was suspected from early on;

the failure was in the inability of the theories to anticipate the

propagation of electromagnetic waves. Eventually the field theories

were wedded to the theory of electrons and a coherent account

resulted. 1

There is merit in the historian's view,but my sympathies and

my arguments lie with O'Rahi1ly for action-at-a-distance (A.A.D.)

electrodynamics has received harsh treatment from scientists and

historians. The field theories seemed unsatisfactory to O'Rahi1ly

but he lacked the philosophical sophistication to back up his instincts

1. For examples of this, see Mary Hesse (1961) !orces and Fields; w. Berkson (1974) Fields of Force; T. Hirosige (1962) 'Lorentz's Theory of Electrons and the Development of the Concept of Electromagnetic Field'; and A.F. Chalmers (1971) The Electromagnetic Theory of J.C. Maxwell and Some Aspects of its Subsequent Development.

Page 13: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

13

with fair and objective evaluation. His fault was that he was eclectic

and inconsistent; he adjusted his grading criterion to yield the value

judgements he had antecedently decided upon. For instance, Maxwell's

equations were interpreted by Maxwell as being about a polarizable

vacuum, and O'Rahilly savages Maxwell for this (see the Chapter 3 to his

book), and Ludwig Lorenz's equations were interpreted by Lorenz as being

about conducting matter distributed through empty space, yet O'Rahilly

describes this interpretation as being an irrelevant addition (see page

183) and focusses on the equations -- but the two assumptions about

space were similar, and their relations to their equations were the

same. I will add a sound philosophical base to O'Rahilly's instincts. l

I also add historical detail and an epistemological slant to O'Rahilly's

case. However, I do not offer a critical comparison between O'Rahilly's

work and mine, for my aim is to fortify his theses and to make our

claims resilient to attack fro. outside.

The problem of this dissertation is to give an account of the

growth of classical electrodynamics as knowledge, and this chapter is

devoted to a sketch of the material to be covered. I argue in Appendix

1 that this problem of knowledge is equivalent to the question 'Which

theory or theories should the scientists of the period have advocated as

a description of the electrodynamic properties of the world?' and

conclude that the scientists should advocate those theories judged best

by Lakatos's M.S.R.P. As far as I have been able to find out, there

have been no attempts to argue the superiority of one programme over the

1. O'Rahilly frequently uses the modern textbook as the touchstone when judging historical theories. See, for example, page 83 of his (1965). This practice is unacceptable philosophically. For the basic arguments, see J. Agassi (1963), Towards An Historiography of Science.

Page 14: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

14

other at a particular time, apart from those by O'Rahilly and by the

scientific figures involved. Historians would rather describe theories

than evaluate them. O'Rahilly was unorthodox, for the second time,

in 1 this -- his was an essay in 'constructive criticism', and as

such was historiographically superior to most works in this field.

My thesis, an epistemological variant of O'Rahil1y's

outrageous views, is that the A.A.D. programme was the superior one

throughout the 19th century; the A.A.D. programme will be argued to

be scientifically and philosophically better than the Field programme.

1. See the Preface to his book. O'Rahi1ly -- a Professor of Mathematical Physics -- must have been surprised at the curious reception of his book. Historians thought that the book was not history because they felt that histories should describe theories and not evaluate them. These feelings are responsible for the preponderance of book titles like 'A History of Theories of Electricity'. Scientists thought that the book was not science because Scientists should evaluate modern theories not historical ones. My view is that O'Rahi1Iy's work is a superior type of history.

Page 15: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

15

2. The A.A.D. Programme: Its Hard Core and Heuristic :

The A.A.D. programme was the result of the attempt to

harness electricity and magnetism to the sophisticated heuristics of

Newtonian Gravitational theory. Such a union seemed natural once it

had been found that electricity and magnetism were governed by

inverse-square laws of the form

, where F is the electric or magnetic force,

Ml and M2 are the electric or magnetic 'masses',

and d is the distance between the 'masses'.

The programme had as its hard core the thesis that electromagnetic

phenomena were the outcome of sources acting at a distance on each

other. Two further views were central though not part of the hard

core. First, that the laws involved were inverse-square central

force laws analogous to the law of gravity. The similarity here was

not total -- there was only one form of gravitating matter, whereas

there were positive and negative charges and North and South magnetic

poles. Secondly, that the sources were discrete; A.A.D. electrodynamics,

in common with most types of streamlined Newtonianism, contained atomism

1 as a part. An important decision to be made about the hard core

concerns whether it contained the view that these distance forces act

instantaneously. What rests on this is the truth of the suggestion

that Field views had an intrinsic advantage because A.A.D. had to be

1. In connection with this, see R.Kargon (1969), 'Model and Analogy in Victorian Science', page 424 and f.

Page 16: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

instantaneous whereas Field accounts had to have finitely propagated

effects and electromagnetic action actually does take time to spread.

Rosenfeld, to take a typical example here, writes

central force physics was doomed to ultimate failure in the domain of electromagnetic phenomena, where the basic idea of instantaneous action at , distance meets with an essential limitation of its validity.

I reject this allegation. I also refuse to accept Woodruff's

recolllDendation :

We [confine] the term 'action at a distance' to forces acting instantaneously at a distance •.• On the other hand, we take it as characteristic of field theories in their fully developed form .•• that the pr"opagation of the influence of a par~icle through space takes time, and occurs at a finite speed.

Berkson too goes astray here :

Field theories predicted that all actions of one body on another took time to move between bodies, while action3at­a-distance theories said the action was instantaneous.

The question is whether it is more fruitful for historical purposes

to identify the A.A.D. programme by the hard core 'sources plus

empty space' or by the hard core 'sources plus empty space plus

instantaneous propagation'. I favour the former. Action-at-a-

16

distance forces do not have to act instantaneously, and Fields do not

have to lead to finitely propagated effects. Newton himself, and

following him the other Newtonians such as Laplace, Amp~re, and Gauss,

1. L.Rosenfeld (1957), 'The Velocity of Light and the Evolution of Electrodynamics', page 1641.

2. A.E.Woodruff (1962), 'Action at a Distance 1n Nineteenth Century Electrodynamics', page 440.

3. W.Berkson (1974), page 3.

Page 17: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

thought it impossible that there could be instantaneous action at a

. 1 dtstance. That gravity was a function of distance at all and was

perhaps to be explained by exchange particles or a medium carried the

mild suggestion that gravity did not act instantaneously. As

Whittaker puts it

That gravity is propagated by the action of a medium, and consequently is a process requiring time for its accomplishment, had been an article of faith with many generations of physicists. Indeed, the dependence of the force on the distance between the attracting bodies seemed to suggest this idea; for a propagation which is truly instantaneous would, perhaps, be more naturally conceived to be effected by some

17

kind of rigid connection between the bodies, which would be 2 more likely to give a force independent of the mutual distance.

Laplace should be mentioned here. He used a propagated gravity to

solve problems connected with the moon's orbit, but with his assumptions

the speed of propagation had to be 100 million times the speed of

light. 3 Instantaneous propagation was not a necessary property of

gravitational force. And, as a contrast to this, fields did not

have to lead to finitely propagated effects -- with perfectly rigid or

incompressible media the transunssion of some kinds of action is

instantaneous, and the notion of being compressible is not intrinsic

to that of a field. Descartes, to take an example, required an

4 infinite velocity for light and used a rigid aether to obtain it.

I favour saying that the question of speed of action is open in

both Field and A.A.D. accounts. And, as an additional

argument, the alternative characterization excludes

I. See, for instance, Newton's Opticks, Query 21.

2. Sir E.T.Whittaker (1951), A History of Theories of Aether and Electricity, poige 207.

~ . C'l 1. p.S.Laplace, Mechanlque e este, Book X, Chap. 7, § 22.

4. And he thought that an infinite velocity was essential 'I declare to you that if this lapse of time could be observed my whole philosophy would be completely ruined.', Descartes (1634), 'Lettf.'r to Bf.'f.'ckIMn'.

Page 18: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

18

the views of Weber, Gauss, Riemann, and Lorenz from being part of the

A.A.D. programme, but historically the debate was between those continental

scientists and the Field theorists Faraday, Maxwell, and Thomson.

The A.A.D. heuristic consisted of the established Newtonian

techniques, which by this time included Potential theory. The A.A.D.

programme was well developed even before the discovery of electrodynamic

phenomena. Poisson had used potentials to transform electrostatics

into an advanced mathematical and physical theory, and in the early 1820's

he applied these methods to magnetism; important here is that he produced

the mathematical theory of polar forces which he used in the context

1 of induced magnetism. George Green also used A.A.D. and potentials

to make significant contributions to theoretical electrostatics and

2 magnetostatics.

1. S.D.Poisson (1812). 'Mimoire sur la Distribution de l'E1ectricit: a la Surface des Corps Conducteurs', (1811, published 1812), and S.D. , ~

Poisson (1821-7). 'Hemoire sur la Theorie du Magnetisme', (1821, and 1823 (published 1827».

2. George Green (1828), 'An Essay on the Application of Mathematical Analysis to the Theories of Electricity and Marnetism'. See also H.E.J.Carr (1949), The Development' of Mathemat cal Theories of Electricity Prior to Maxwell with Special Reference to the Concept Potential.

Page 19: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

19

3. The Philosophical Objection to A.A.D. :-

The A.A.D. programme also inherited from Newtonianism a phil-

osophical objection. This criticism was widely voiced by Field theorists

and their use of it illustrates the philosophical essentialism adopted

by followers of the Field programme.

I will describe the objection in terms of A.A.D. gravitation,

then answer it. The reply involves the philosophy of explanation, and

to avoid digressing too far I will merely state my views and use foot-

notes to cite the backing arguments.

Typical variants of the objection run :

Action at a distance does not explain any phenomena because no one understands how a body can act where it is not.

Action at a distance may describe the behaviour of bodies, but it does not explain their behaviour.

Action at a distance at best tells us how bodies behave, but it does not tell us why they do so.

The first presupposition often used here is that explanation

should be aimed at subjective understanding -- that explanation is relative

to an individual and that it should set the mind at rest by reducing the

1 unfamiliar to the familiar. This is a mistake. 2 Explanation should

be aimed at objective understanding, and this is perhaps best achieved

by the hypothetico-deductive model. So that, for example, relativity

theory explains the bending of light around the sun, even though many

people do not understand that explanation.

on the accidental aspect of what it

(One can remark here

1. For expressions of this presupposition in electrodynamics, see Maxwell, 'On Action at a Distance', page 302, and O.Lodge (1892), Modern Views On Electricity, pages 386-7 and f. Maxwell's article also reveals that he understood most of the points that I make in this section.

2. See J.Hospers (1956), 'What is Explanation ?' page 96 and f. This excellent paper contains a clear statement of almost all the views on explanation that I wish to defend.

Page 20: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

20

is that we do understand. Traditionally people 'understand' action-

by-contact because they observe it all the time, but do not 'understand'

action-at-a-distance, because it is not part of their daily lives. But

if we had been bigger or more massy, then we would use action-at-a-

distance gravitational forces every day to move objects. Should this

mean that whether A.A.D. explains depends on how massy we are?)

To reformulate one variant of the criticism, taking into

account the objective requirement of explanation:

Action at a distance does not explain any phenomena because no explanation has been given of how a body can act where it is not.

What lies behind this objection is Essentialism. l There will

always exist a finite regress of available explanation& : a phenomenon

to be explained, an explanation of the phenomena, an explanation of the

explanation, and so on. And one can ask of each of the links in this

explanatory chain 'Why?' or 'What is the explanation of that?' and of

most receive tn answer the explanation represented by the immediately

superior link. What should happen if the question is directed at the

top link? Essentialism holds that the top link must not be open to the

question 'Why?' -- it must not be in need of explanation. This is

achieved by the top link being a statement of essence; that is, the

definition of a defining property. Aristotle's example was 'Man is

rational' -- if this appears at the top of an explanatory chain one

cannot sensibly ask 'why?' because any object lacking rationality could

not be a man for being rational is the essential property of man.

Essentialism goes further than this. It holds that all the members of

an upward explanatory chain which is not terminated by a statement of

essence fail to explain anything at all. Unterminated chains simply do

1. See the pages cited in the Index to K.R. Popper (1945). The Open Society and Its Enemies.

Page 21: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

21

not explain. And this is where A.A.D. was supposed to be at fault

A.A.D. was never a link to a terminated chain. 1 But essentialism

2 is mistaken. And a case can be made that even the early Newtonians

knew this. The eventual early Newtonian reply to the objection came

in 1713 from Cotes in the Preface to the 2nd Edition of Newton's

Principia:

either gravit~ must have a place among the primary qualities of all bodies, or extension, mobility, and impenetrability must not.

One reading of this is that Newton and Cotes thought that Descartes's

properties of extension, mobility, and impenetrability were, contrary

to widespread belief, not essential -- presumably they thought that

there were no such properties as essential ones. 3

Essentialism arose to combat the apparent lack of explanatory

progress due to an infinite regress of 'why's?'. Campbell expresses

these fears thus:

To say that all gases expand when heated is not to explain why hydrogen expands when heated; it merely leads us to ask immediately why all gases expand. An explanation which leads immediately to another question of the same kind is no explanation at a11.4

1. Nor, for that matter, was any other explanation. There was a socio­psychological asymmetry here. Field theorists did not explain their mediums, but this was supposed to be of no consequence; A.A.D. theorists did not explain A.A.D., but this was taken to be a failing.

2. Hospers (1956) page 115 and f., and K.R. Popper (1945).

3. Many read Cotes otherwise, so that gravity is essential. Thus Maxwell describes the 'dogma of Cotes'. See J.C. Maxwell (1873), A Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism" 865.

4. N.R. Campbell (1953), What is Science?, page 80.

Page 22: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

22

But the regress is harmless. Newton's theory of gravity answers the

question why the planets behave as they do, but to ask 'why?' or 'why

is it true?' of Newton's theory is to ask a new and deeper question.

And so progress is made.

In an explanatory chain, each link explains its immediate

predecessor. So all links, other than the bottom one, are explanations;

and all links, other than the top one, have explanations. But the links

are also descriptions.l

Newton's theory of gravity describes how the

gravitational forces are functions of masses and distances. The theory

explains the behaviour of the planets, but does not explain the workings

of gravity; and the theory describes the workings of gravity but does

not describe (or does not merely describe) the behaviour of the planets.

The theory tells us how gravity works and why the planets behave as

2 they do.

The A.A.D. theorists should have either rebutted the objection

using arguments similar to those sketched here or shown that the

objection applied equally to Field theories, which are also not part of

a terminated explanatory chain, and thus that no advantage accrued over

3 this to either prograume.

1. A typical statement that I oppose is Tricker's 'Science, however, can never provide ultimate explanations but only describe', that is; there is a dichotomy -- either ultimate ££ descriptive. See R.A.R. Tricker (1966) The Contributions of Faraday and Maxwell to Electrical Science, page 130.

2. Jon Dor1ing has made a preliminary announcement of an interesting alternative account of explanation which may well bear on the issues discussed here. See his (1978) 'On Explanations in Physics: Sketch of an Alternative to Hempel's Account of the Explanation of Laws'.

3. One indirect argument that A.A.D. theorists did come up with was that at best Field theories replace macro-A.A.D. by micro-A.A.D. Fields were often mechanical mediums and inter-molecular A.A.D. was usually adduced to explain the properties of these. This argument -- as was pointed out in the well known objection by Hare -- hits Faraday's theories head on. Faraday would not tolerate A.A.D., yet his own theories required A.A.D. over distances of about 1/2 inch. (See R. Hare (1840), 'A Letter to Prof. Faraday, on Certain Theoretical Opinions'.)

Page 23: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

23

4. The Origins of Electrodynamics: Oersted and Ampere:

Electrodynamics starts in 1820 with Oersted's discovery that

current electricity affects a magnetic compass. This effect was

independent of both programmes. The Field programme was not yet in

existence, and the A.A.D. theorists had not considered whether the

newly discovered current electricity behaved any differently from

static electricity which they thought Coulomb had proved could not

interact with magnetic poles. l Oersted's discovery was a real challenge

to the A.A.D. programme for, prima facie, the interaction between

electricity and magnetism must involve non-central forces because, in

modern terms, the lines of force circulate a current carrying wire. As

Pearce Williams explains:

Hitherto only central forces ••• had been known. A circular force was both unanticipated and inexplicable. The first 'skew' force in the history of mechanics threatened to upset the whole structure of Newtonian science. 2

I will argue in Chapter 2 that Ampere produced a central

force law which, when used with his simple idea that magnets were

really currents, brought the interaction entirely within A.A.D. The

law, which resulted from routine application of heuristic, was:

F a: G

where G is a geometrical factor, ida the product of the current and

circuit element, and d the distance between circuit elements.

1. See L.P. Williams (1962), 'Amp~re's Electrodynamic Molecular Molecule', page 113 and f.

2. L.P. Williams (1965), Michael Faraday, page 140. And Agassi thinks the same. See J. Agassi (1968), The Continuing Revolution, page l8S.

Page 24: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

24

Ampere's law passed all the tests that it was subjected to,

subsumed all forces between currents and magnets under the one law,

and predicted, for example, that Coulomb's law of magnetism should

hold between magnets. This meant that it was a major triumph for the

A.A.D. programme and counted as good evidence for that view. An open

problem remained: static electricity and Coulomb's law of electro-

statics were outside the reduction. Even at this stage it was clear i

how the problem was to be solved: current elements should be analysed

ending up with a theory which would yield Coulomb's law as the static

case and Ampere's law as the dynamic one; magnetism, static electricity,

and current electricity would then all be united under the one law.

Ampere wrote, after he had found his law:

(supposing electric molecules in motion], it is no longer contradictory to admit that from the actions proportional to the inverse square of the distance which each molecule exerts, there can result between two elements of conducting wires a force which depends not only on their distance but also on the directions of the two elements ••• If, starting from this consideration, it were possible that the mutual action of two elements is in fact proportional to the formula by which I have represented it, this explanation of the fundamental fact of the entire theory of electrodynamic phenomena should evidently be preferred to any other. But it would require investigations for which I lack time. l

, "" , .... 1. A.~.A.pere (1826), Theori. Mathe.atlgua des Ph.no~ena8 llectrodyn-smigues Unlguemant Oedult de L'lxp~rienCA, pages 96 and f.

Page 25: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

5. First Criticisms of A.A.D.: Faraday's Objections and His

Foundation of the Field Programme:

One apparent defeat for A.A.D. was thus turned into a

victory; what about other criticisms? A major critic of the A.A.D.

enterprise was Faraday. The M.S.R.P. tells us what to look for in his

attack on A.A.D. for it identifies two types of criticism; of

particular theories in a ~rogramme, and of the programme as a whole.

Faraday offered both types. I argue in Chapter 3 that his strictures

against particular A.A.D. theories were well made, but that the

theories' shortcomings did not affect the whole programme, and that

his attack on the programme as a whole was ineffective.

To anticipate.

25

There were two main examples of local criticism. Faraday

refuted Grotthuss's A.A.D. theory of electrolysis -- but Grotthuss's

theory was not the result of routine use of A.A.D. heuristic. Secondly,

Babbage and Herschel attempted to explain Arago's disc in A.A.D. terms

using induced magnetism: Faraday, after he had discovered electro­

magnetic induction, explained it successfully in terms of induced

currents; again, more than routine development was involved.

Global criticism can be indirect, consisting of the production

of a better rival programme, or direct. Direct scientific objection

normally amounts to the claim that the programme cannot solve a given

key problem. To argue this soundly the critic must not only appreciate

the extant theories in the programme, but also the heuristic and its

strengths and weaknesses. Take an example. Newton objected to the

wave programme of light on the grounds that it could never solve the

problem of dispersion. Newton knew not only the wave theories but also

the ploys that the wave theorists used in solving problems. And he

judged that the one plus the other could not yield an explanation of

Page 26: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

dispersion. With Faraday there were important differences. He did

not know what the A.A.D. theories really were and, as a result of

knowing no mathematics at all. had no idea of the limitations of the

heuristic. For instance, he wrote to Ampere in 1825:

With regard to your theory, it so soon becomes mathematical that it quickly gets beyond my reach ••• 1

In short, he was not well qualified as a critic. Nevertheless he

offered objections and these have to be judged in their own right.

I list the major ones here and show in detail in Chapter 3 that they

are not damaging:

A the phenomena of curved lines of force -- A.A.D. has straight

line central forces, whereas lines of magnetic or electro-

static force can be curved, hence electromagnetic phenomena

2 cannot be A.A.D.,

B that the forces were not independent of the medium as they

3 perhaps should have been given A.A.D.,

C the detailed behaviour of dielectrics -~ Faraday altered

the force between two charges by putting a layered pile of

mica discs between them and also found that when the layers

were separated out the discs carried + or charges on

their surfaces; thus, th. action took plac. in the

medium and was not primarily concerned with the source charges

themselves. 4

1. L.P. Williams (1965), page 143.

2. M. Faraday (1839) Experimental Researches in Electricity, Vo1.1, § 1224 anu also see references cited in the Index to Vo1.3.

26

3. See, for instance, Mary Hesue (1961) pages 198 and f. and Mary Hesse (1955) 'Action at a Distance in Classical Physics' page 342.

4. M. Faraday, Diary, Vol. III, page 72 and f.

Page 27: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

D that lines of force in space were primary and existed on

their own independently of their 'sources,l

and E 2 That A.A.D. violated the conservation of energy.

Faraday's indirect criticism amounted to the foundation of the Field

programme. He proposed the thesis which became the hard core of the

programme: electromagnetic phenomena were the outcome of behaviour

by the space between the (real or apparent) sources. As Maxwell

described it:

For my own part, I look for additional electricity from a study of what takes vening between the electrified bodies. character of the mode of investigation

light on the nature of place in the space inter­

Such is the essential pursued by Faraday ••• 3

At this time the heuristic of the programme was extremely weak. True,

27

there was the general directive 'look at the intervening space', but there

waa no mathematical knowledge and no body of problem solving skills that

could be learned and passed on. Faraday once wrote:

I do not think that I could work in company, or think aloud, or explain my thought at the time. 4

As a result, he had no students, no followers, and no one thought his

theories sound. Faraday kept his theories to himself; indeed Pearce

Williams claims to be the first person since Faraday to have any real

5 idea what his theories were. Faraday's reticence is easy to explain

-- he judged his theoretical speculations to be insufficiently

supported to be put before a wider audience. He published all the views

1. L.P. Williams (1965) page 204.

2. See L.P. Williams (1966) The Origins of Field Theory page 116.

3. J.e. Maxwell (1873) A Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism §37.

4. Quoted from I. Agassi (1971) Faraday as a Natural Philosopher page 199.

5. L.P. Williams (1975). 'Should Philosophers be Allowed to Write History', page 250.

Page 28: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

that he thought would withstand critical scrutiny. To quote Pearce

Williams:

The experimental results were clearly and firmly reported; the theoretical aspect was hedged with fuzzy and tentative language; was hesitantly and sometimes confusedly presented. It is, I think, fair to say that no one in the 1830's took the theory seriously. 1

28

The Field programme has to be appraised by the discoveries which it leads

to. Faraday made five major discoveries -- electromagnetic induction,

the laws of electrolysis, dielectrics, the rotation of the plane of

polarization of light by a magnetic field, and diamagnetism -- but none

of these was a credit to the Field programme. Faraday searched for

correlations of forces, and his discoveries were loosely connected with

that pursuit. This means that, if anything, the discoveries were

evidence for the thesis that all forces are correlated. The other idea

-- that the space plays a key role in all electrodynamic phenomena

was proposed only at the end of his career after all the discoveries

had been made.

1. L.P. Williams, 'Faraday' articl~ Dictionary of Scientific Biography, page 537.

Page 29: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

6. The Rival Views on the Sources and Receivers of Force:

Some advanced warning should be given of the difficulties

to be faced over sources and receivers of force.

The A.A.D. view is crystal clear. In contrast the Field view

is a morass -- so much so that many experts regard it as intrinsically

inconsistent and beyond comprehension. Duhem tells us that Maxwell's

theories are:

compromised by contradictions which are not contingent ••• but essential and inseparable from the totality of the work. l

And O'Rahilly writes:

Never did a great physicist throw out such a mass of incoherent ideas, calmly pur$~ing his course with intuitive genius amid a welter of discre~ant theories. 2 ,3

For electrostatics, the A.A.D. theories tell us that there

are source and receiver electrical fluids4 which act at a distance on

each other so that with no medium the circumstances may be depicted:

e A: (the vacuum case) (empty space)

e

29

If there is a medium present then the Poisson-Mossotti-Thompson analysis

1. P. Duhem (1902), Les Theories Electriques de J.C. Maxwell, page 223.

2. O'Rahilly (1965). page 79.

3. There are many passages similar to these for example, Ehrenfest's 'kind of intellectual primeval forest, almost impenetrable in its fecundity' or Boltzmann's 'So solI ich den mit saurem Schweiss, Euch lehren, was ich selbst nicht weiss.' -- see also H. Hertz (1892)

~ , Electric Waves, Introductio~, H. Poincare (1901), Electricite et Optique, viii, J.J. Thomson (1885), Report on Electrical Theories', page 125 and o. Heaviside (1893), Electromagnetic Theory, Preface.

4. These electrical fluids were generally considered to be atomic in constitution; that is, the sources and receivers of force were taken to be positive or negative 'electrons'.

Page 30: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

1 of polar forces and dielectrics applies the bounding fluids

attract and repel fluids in the medium with the result that the medium

becomes polarized and shows polarization fluids on its boundary

surface, thus:

B: (the dielectric case) :11-9 __ me_di_um __ tB------I

There is here free charge and polarization charge, and the positive

fluids in the medium move away from the positive free charge so that

2 the polarization current or displacement is in the diagram from left

to right:

C: (the dielectric case) medium

It is the free source fluids which cause the polarization and

polarization current in the medium.

30

e e

For electrostatics, the Field view denied that there were

electrical fluids acting at a distance. 3 There were to be no electrical

fluids and no action at a distance •. Instead the medium was all

pervasive, and it was occasionally under stress and this resulted in

polarization. As Maxwell puts it:

1. Poisson (1821-7), F.O. Mossotti (1847) in Archives de Sciences Physiques e~ Naturelles, i, (1847), page 193, and W. Thomson (1845), 'On the Mathematical Theory of Electricity in Equilibrium'.

2. I use the direction of travel of the positive fluids to identify the direction of the polarization current.

3. For a more detailed account of the Field views, see J. Bromberg (1968), 'Maxwell's Electrostatics', P.M. Heimann (1971), 'Maxwell, Hertz, and the Nature of Electricity', and A. Chalmers (1971), Chapter 4.

Page 31: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

••• we must regard electrification as a property of the dielectric medium rather than of the conductor which is bounded by it. 1

Or again:

The charge therefore at the bounding surface of a conductor and the surrounding dielectric, which on the old theory was called the charge of the conductor, must be called in the theory of induction the surface-charge of the surrounding dielectric. According to this theory, all charge is the residual effect of the polarization of the die1ectric. 2

Typically:

A': (the 'vacuum' case) medium

B': (the dielectric case) I~ medium el

31

There is here only polarization charge, and the positive apparent charge

in the medium moves towards the boundary where it is manifested so that

the 'polarization current' in the diagram is from right to left:

C': (the dielectric case) medium < (1) e ~

There is one minor variation that should be mentioned. The Field

theorists discussed polarization as a mechanical stress, and they

also discussed lines of force which mapped this stress. Faraday and

Maxwell vacillated over the question of whether it was the polarization

that was primary or whether it was the lines of force -- Faraday

eventually favoured the lines of force, and Maxwell eventually favoured

1. Maxwell (1881), An Elementary Treatise on Electricity, §62.

2. Maxwell (1873), §111.

Page 32: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

32

1 mechanical stress. Under either view there were to be no ~enuine

sources. A preliminary difficulty concerns the causes of the stress or

apparent charge. A rubber band will become stretched and remain so

only if there are forces to hold it out. Similarly polarization or

line of force stresses seem to require forces to implement them. What

are these forces? No satisfactory answer was given. One possibility

would be to take the line of force as a primitive notion -- Faraday

did this; but Maxwell favoured mechanical stresses and taking them as

2 primitive would have run up against Newton's third law. Maxwell

describes this:

It must be carefully borne in mind that we have made only one step in the theory of the action of the medium. We have supposed it to be in a state of stress, but we have not in any way accounted for this stress, or explained how it is maintained •••

I have not been able ••• to account considerations for these stresses in the therefore leave the theory at this point

by mechanical dielectric. I

3

I think that it was the desire for a unified view that lay

behind the Field approach to sources. If there are several non-inter-

acting substances, then there is the seemingly paradoxical problem of

how they interact. Source fluids interact under Coulomb's law;

masses interact under Newton's law, but masses presumably do not inter-

act with source fluids. How then do bodies retain the fluids to become

charged? A unified Field view avoids this problem. I do not know of

1. See P.M. Heimann (1970), 'Maxwell and the Modes of Consistent Representation' for a further discussion of this topic.

2. C.W.F. Everitt, the recognized authority on Maxwell's views, argues that for Maxwell electric force is primitive (see his (1975), James Clerk Maxwell, page 124 and f.). I agree entirely that such an inter­pretation makes sense of Maxwell's views, but I think that Maxwell's mechanical essentialism made this interpretation unavailable to him.

3. Maxwell (1873) §llO-lll.

Page 33: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

1 the Field theorists using this argument. Instead they conjured up

weaker ones. Maxwell's favourite was the conservation of substance

together with the cancelling out of electrical fluids. The optical

phenomenenof interference was to him incontrovertible proof that light

was not a substance:

We cannot suppose that two bodies when put together can annihilate each other; therefore light cannot be a substance. 2

In a similar vein he argued:

. it is difficult to conceive how the combination of the two fluids can have no properties at all. 3

(But having zero resultant effect does not mean that the causes them-

selves add to non existence; there is zero resultant gravitational

force at the midpoint between two equal masses.) Maxwell and Faraday's

other plea was that electrical fluids had not been proved by experiment

33

to exist -- an objection that applied universally to theories, including

their own ones of stresses and lines of force.

The A.A.D. account was always perfectly satisfactory. And

this is where the difficulties originate. The Field theorists accepted

the A.A.D. view of dielectrics as a mathematical and phenomenological

description. Indeed it was the Field theorist Thomson who brought the

theory to the attention of British scientists:

Poisson has investigated the mathematical laws of [magnetic polarity]. These laws seem to represent in the most general manner the state of the body polarized by influence; and therefore ••• we may make use of them to form a mathematical theory of electrical influence in dielectrics the truth of which can only be established by a rigorous comparison of its results with experiment.

1. The problem -- of the possible interactions of 'imponderable' fluids -- was considered mainly by A.A.D. scientists. And, by the way, was solved by them for electromechanical interaction by means of the electron.

2. Scientific Papers, II, page 764.

3. Maxwell (1873) §36. See also, for instance, §63.

4. W. Thomson (1845), page·SS.

Page 34: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

And Maxwell says of the Poisson-Mossotti theory that it:

1 'may well be true.'

But rethinking the Poisson-Mossotti-Thomson analysis in terms of

'apparent charge' as an epiphenomenon of stress led to immense con-

fusions. These confusions are most marked over questions of the

directions of the 'polarization' or 'displacement' or 'polarization

currents' or 'displacement currents'. This is why Maxwell made many

inconsistent uses of signs. And he ends up with such puzzles as

'all electricity results from polarization' (i.e. div ~ ~ 0), yet

'polarization is the motion of electricity which behaves like an

incompressible fluid' (Le. div.f = 0).

For magnetism, the early A.A.D. view was that there were

source and receiver magnetic fluids which act at a distance on each

other, and this idea was complemented with the Poisson account of

2 induced magnetism. Then Ampere substituted circulating microcurrents

and current shells for magnetic fluids so that the later A.A.D. view

was that magnetic fluids could be used as a convenient representation,

34

but really only electricity was needed to explain electromagneti~

behaviour. The A.A.D. account here .fared reasonably well. The magnetic

vagaries of materials posed problems, but the Ampere-Weber tradition

provided better explanations than any rival of diamagnetism and

similar oddities.

1. Maxwell (1873), §62.

2. The Poisson theory of polar forces was first applied to magnetism then, as Maxwell once remarked, Mossotti translated French into Italian and magnetism into electricity to obtain the (Poisson)­Mossotti theory of dielectrics.

Page 35: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

35

For magnetism, the Field theorists generally discussed

magnetic poles acting at a distance, and adopted the Poisson theory of

induced magnetism. I think they wished to reach an acceptable view of

apparent electrical sources before attempting to give a similar account

of apparent magnetic sources.

Current electricity was discovered at the beginning of the

nineteen century and initially there were two theories as to its

nature: that it was the flow of electrical fluid, and that it was a

vibration or oscillation in the wire.

The A.A.D. scientists took the view first that current was

the flow of electrical fluids, then that current was the flow of atoms

of these electrical fluids, and finally with Weber that current was

the flow of inertial atoms of electrical fluids.

The Field theorists remained silent as to the nature of

currents. Again, phenomenologically the A.A.D. account was perfectly

satisfactory -- it explained Faraday's results that galvanic electricity

and flow of initially static electricity produce exactly the same

effects, and much more besides. l But since the Field theorists denied

that there were electrical fluids, ~hey could hardly accept that such

fluids flowed in wires. Instead they issued warnings about what had

not been proved by experiment. Faraday writes:

There are many arguments in favour of the materiality of electricity and but few against it; but still it is only a supposition; and it will be as well to remember, while

1. For instance, it explained ~lectrolysis, Ohm's law, convection current effects, and the Hall effect.

Page 36: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

pursuing the subject of electro-magnetism, that we have no proof of the materiality of electricitYl

or of the existence of any current through the wire.

And Maxwell warns:

Electricity, Fluids, and Heat all tend to pass from one place to another ••• A fluid is certainly a substanc, heat is as certainly not a substance ••• we must be careful not to let the one or the other analogy suggest to us that electricity is either a substance like water, or a state of agitation like heat.2

1. Faraday (1821), 'Historical Sketch of Electromagnetism', page 196.

2. Maxwell (1873), §72. See also §574, §243, §244, and §355.

36

Page 37: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

7. The Early Development of A.A.D.: Weber's Unification of E1ectro-

dynamics and Other Theoretical Advances:

By 1930, the A.A.D. programme contained three prominent

theses:

1. That static electricity was governed entirely by Coulomb's A.A.D. Law.

2. That, in a manner of speaking, there was no such thing as magnets or magnetism; instead there were currents which produced the effects.

3. That current electricity (and thus magnetism) was governed entirely by Ampere's A.A.D. law.

During the following twenty years Weber and his colleagues

developed these three into five replacement theses:

1'. That electricity is atomic in structure.

2'. That currents are streams of electrical 'atoms'.

3'. That the forces acting operate directly between electrical atoms and not between conductors.

4'. That the forces acting do not do so instantaneously.

5'. That all electrodynamic phenomena (that is, all forces, inductions, etc.) may be deduced, by statistical summation, from an A.A.D. force for~u1a for electrical atoms.

These developments -- due to Ohm, Fechner, Kirchoff, Gauss,

Ri~mann, and Weber -- are considered in Chapter 4.

37

Electrodynamic induction was the major problem facing e1ectro-

dynamics in the early 1830's. It was a new problem and was not

anticipated by either of the two Programmes. But the A.A.D. programme

still had the unfinished task of unifying static and current electricity

by analysing current elements. Weber completed this by deducing a

force law from Ampere's law and a reasonable theory of currents. TIle

law was:

1 (1 --

c 2

2 (dr)

dt

Page 38: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

38

where r is the distance between charges, c is a constant of propor-

tionality, and ql and q2 are the charge magnitudes. Weber's force law

not only superseded Ampere's and Coulomb's laws but also it predicted

all the various forms of electrodynamic induction. Thus an A.A.D. theory

explained induction, and the explanation was produced independently of

Faraday's discovery of induction -- had Faraday not discovered induction.

1 A.A.D. would still have p~edicted it theoretically. Weber's law, when

proposed in 1846, accounted for all known electrodynamic phenomena.

Far from being well received, Weber's law was subjected to

severe criticism which apparently damned it for once and for all.

Helmholtz stated that the law violated the conservation of energy, and

this. allegation was used by Field theorists (and many historians) as a

fatal criticism of A.A.D. electrodynamics. Here we see aspects of the

harshness of A.A.D.'s fate. For not only was Helmholtz mistaken, but

also his arguments were transparently fallacious.

The other replacement theses fared rather better. The analysis

2 1'-3' predicted the Hall effect, and the outcome of Rowland's

convection current experiments.

4' -- that the forces should be retarded -- was first

advocated in earnest by Gauss in 1835. Gauss made progress but did

1. The priority of discovery here is of no significance. since none of the theories predicted the effect. In fact, Ampere himself nearly discovered induction (see S.P. Thompson, Phil Mag., 1895): and also a case can be made that Henry was an independent and simultaneous discoverer of it, and Henry was an A.A.D. theorist. (Henry certainly discovered self-induction.)

2. It anticipated a Hall-type effect - the exact effect depends on whether it is the positive electrical fluids that move in the conductor or the negative or both. In contrast, the Field programme made no predictions regarding this kind of phenomenon.

Page 39: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

did not solve the problems involved. 4' yielded A.A.D.'s next problem

for Weber's force law used instantaneous transmission and thus was

inadequate. Yet another force law was needed, using retarded forces,

from which Weber's law, or an approximation to it, could be derived.

Riemann made a brave but unsuccessful attempt to solve this in 1857.

39

Page 40: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

8. The Growth of the Field Heuristic 1840-60:

Maxwell and Thomson constructed the Field heuristic out of

three components: the re-interpretation of A.A.p. mathematics as

Field mathematics, the search for a single mechanical aether, and the

1 use of mechanical models and analogies.

The first constituent of the Field heuristic is what we

would now call vector analysis.

Most of the essential results concerning potential fields and

force fields had by this time been derived by Gauss, Poisson, Laplace,

Green, and other A.A.D. theoreticians. The potentials and forces were

written both as functions of the sources and in terms of partial

derivatives as functions of the local fields. The two approaches were

interchangeable for most mathematical purposes, but physically the

source or cause of the fields was in both cases the distant electrical

fluids.

Thomson, and later Maxwell, made discoveries, re-discoveries, and

2 re-interpretations concerning this localized mathematics. The distant

40

source fluids were quietly forgotten, and the local mathematics in terms

of partial differential equations we~e taken as the true expression of

Faraday's intuitions that electrodynamics was concerned essentially with .

the behaviour of the space. Thus Maxwell writes:

1. See for additional background J. Turner (1955a), 'Maxwell on the Method of Physical Analogy'; J. Turner (1955b), 'A Note on Maxwell's Interpretation of Some Attempts at Dynamical Explanation'; J. Turner (1956), 'Maxwell on the Logic of Dynamical Explanation'; and Jed. Z. Buchwald (1977),'William Thomson and the Mathematization of Faraday's Electrostatics'.

2. See W. Thomson ,(1872) Papers on Electrostatics and Magnetism, pages I 15, 42, 52, 340; W. Thomson (1882) Mathematical and Physical Papers , , ( -page 76; and Maxwell's view of Thomson s 1872) in J.C. Maxwell collected Papers, II, pages 301-7. Thomson was to find out that George Green had anticipated many of his results.

Page 41: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

••• Faraday, in his mind's eye, saw lines of force tra­versing all space where the mathematicians saw centres of force attracting at a distance: Faraday saw a medium where they saw nothing but distance: Faraday sought the seat of the phenomena in real actions going on in the medium, they were satisfied that they had found it in a power of action at a distance impressed on the electrical fluids.

When I had translated what I considered to be Faraday's ideas into a mathematical form, I found that in general the results of the two methods coincided, so that the same phenomena were accounted for, and the same laws of action deduced by both methods, but that Faraday's methods resembled those in which we begin with the whole and arrive at the parts by analysis, while the ordinary mathematical methods were founded on the principle of beginning with the parts and building up the whole by synthesis.

I also found that several of the most fertile methods of research discovered by the mathematicians could be expressed much better in terms of ideas derived from Faraday than in their original form.

The whole theory, for instance, of the potential, considered as a quantity which satisfies a certain partial differential equation, belongs essentially to the method which I have called that of Faraday. According to the other method, the potential, if it is to be considered at all, must be regarded as the result of a summation of the electrified particles divided each by its distance from a given point. Hence many of the mathematical discoveries of Laplace, Poisson, Green and Gauss find their proper place in this treatise, and their appropriate expressions in terms of conceptions mainly derived from Faraday.l

(I cite this passage only as evidence of the aims and methods of the

Field programme, I certainly do not wish to defend some of the theses

expressed in it -- for instance, it "is clear that the A.A.D. theoret-

icians would have disputed Maxwell's claim that the true expression of

2 their ideas was the Faraday one.)

1. J.e. Maxwell (1873), page ix.

2. Notice the inconsistency in the Field theorists' interpretation of mathematics. Electric currents and heat flow were governed by similar equations -- the Field theorists warned against concluding from this that electric current was a thing that flowed. The electric field and heat flow were governed, as the young Thomson showed. by similar Laplacian equations - the Field theorists concluded from this that the electric field was a thing going on in the apparently empty space.

41

Page 42: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

The second constituent -- the search for a mechanical aether

represents an addition that Thomson and Maxwell made to Faraday's

original venture.

A criticism that Faraday made of A.A.D. was the standard

philosophical one that matter cannot act where it is not, and this type

of objection applied to gravity and e1ectromagnetism. l Faraday

quoted with approval the fhird letter of Newton to Bentley in which it

is denied that gravity is essential and asserted that there must be

2 mutual contact between the distant matter. As we have seen, Faraday's

eventual suggestions here involved non-mechanical unified fields of

force. Initially he regarded the electromagnetic space as being

stressed to produce polarization, and it is important to note that with

this view a wire about to have current induced in it was in a special

42

state of stress the 'electrotonic state'. This account is mechanical and

thus involved, in an informal way, an aether. He later took forces and

lines of force to be primary and then induction became the cutting of

lines of fo~ce or the change in the flux threading a circuit. Under

this view there is no aether there is only a field of force.

Maxwell favoured Faraday's first view. 3 Basically he thought

that mathematically lines of force may describe the phenomena including

induction, but that the real explanations would have to be in terms of

mechanics:

1. See also Section 3 above.

2. M. Faraday, Experimental Researches, III, §532n., §571.

3. Maxwell changed his mind several times. This complex issue is discussed in P.M. Heimann (1970), 'Maxwell and the Modes of Consistent Representation' •

Page 43: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

When any phenomenon can be described as an example of some general principle which is applicable to other phenomena, that phenomenon is said to be explained. Explanations, however, are of very various orders, according to the degree of generality of the principle which is made use of ••• when a physical phenomenon can be completely described as a change in the configuration and motion of a material system, the dynamical explanation of that phenomenon is said to be complete. We cannot conceive any further explanation to be either necessary, desirable, or possible, for as soon as we know what is meant by words configuration, motion, mass, and force, we see that the ideas which they represent are so elementary that they cannot be explained ~y means of anything e1se. 1

This later was to mean that even though he was content to describe

Faraday's 'electronic state' in terms of a vector potential he still

wished to explain it mechanically. Maxwell's mechanical essentialism

has the internal difficult that often one branch of mechanics is

explained in terms of another; thus it needs supplementing by the

identification of the ultimate mechanical explanations. In particular

Maxwell was puzzled over the question of gravitational A.A.D. He too

quotes with approval Newton's letter to Bentley,2 and he also tried on

occasions to introduce a mechanical medium to explain gravitational

A.A.D. On the other hand he must have known that A.A.D. was part of

3 Newtonian mechanics and thus may not be in need of explanation.

43

And the attempts he made to explain gravity ran into severe difficulties.

He writes, for example:

1. Scientific Papers, II, page 418. Maxwell uses the word 'dynamics' for 'mechanics'. See also II, page 592. The quoted passage also appears in the draft of his (1864), 'A Dynamical Theory of the Electro­magnetic Field' -- see University Library Cambridge Add. MSS §7655 'On the Dynamical Explanation of Electric Phenomena'.

2. Scientific Papers, II, page 316.

3. Chalmers makes a mistake here in his (1971), page 47. He quotes Maxwell's presentation of Maxwell's opponents views as if it were Maxwell's own view.

Page 44: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

the assumption~ therefore~ that gravitation arises from the action of the surrounding medium in the way pointed out, leads to the conclusion that every part of this medium possesses, when undisturbed~ an enormous intrinsic energy~ and that the presence of dense bodies influences the medium so as to diminish this energy whenever there is a resultant attraction. [:]

As I am unable to understand in what way a medium can possess such properties, I cannot go any further in this direction searching for the cause of gravitation. l

The troubles over the constitution of the mechanically ultimate did not

impinge on electromagnetism - the preliminary step for electromagnetism

was to explain it in terms 2 of any branch of Newtonian mechanics.

Thomson and Maxwell thought that the finite velocity of light

and heat, and the transversality of light waves should be explained by

means of a mechanical aether possibly involving rotational or vortex

3 elements. The vortices were introduced because magnetism appeared to

be genuinely rotational in character -- as is evinced by Oersted's

44

results, and the magnetic rotation of the plane of polarization of light

__ and consequently Thomson postulated vortex mechanical mediums. 4

I suggest that they always considered that one aether would be

1. Maxwell (1864)~ 'A Dynamical Theory of the Electromagnetic Field', §82.

2. Mechanical essentialism was the dominant thought in 19th Century science. As Hertz put it, 'all physicists agree that the problem of physics consists in tracing the phenomena of nature back to the simple laws of mechanics', H. Hertz (1899), The Principles of Mechanics~ author's preface.

3. See Maxwell (1877), Matter and Motion §l08 for the proof of the existence of aether from the finite velocity of light. See also Maxwell (l864)~ Sections 5 and f.~ for the objective reasons behind the postulation of aether.

4. Thomson's and Helmholtz's mathematical results suggested that lines and vortices are duals so that either electricity was a line phenomenon and magnetism a rotational one or vice-versa. That electrolysis appeared to be in a straight line, and the plane of polarization of light appeared to rotate absolutely motivated the former choice.

Page 45: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

sufficient for light, radiant heat, electricity, magnetism and gravity.

Faraday writes:

it is not at all unlikely that, if there be an aether, it should have other uses than simply the conveyance of [light] radiations. 1

And the developing background knowledge -- such as that on the inter-

action between magnetism and light -- supported this idea. Thomson

writes to Faraday:

I enclose the paper giving an analogy for electric and magnetic forces, by means of the strain propagated through an elastic solid. What-I have written is merely a sketch of the mathematical analogy. I did not venture even to hint at the possibility of making it the foundation of a physical theory of the propagation of electric and magnetic forces, which, if established at all, would express as a necessary result, the connection between electrical and magnetic forces, and would show how the purely statical phenomenon even of magnetism may originate either from electricity in motion, or from an inert mass such as a magnet. If such a theory could be discovered, it would also, when taken in connection with the undulatory theory of light, in all probability explain the effect of magnetism on polarized light. 2

And Maxwell thought that the task was to discover the exact properties

of this aether. 3

The third constituent was the postulation of mechanical

models and analogies.

There appear to have been several ideas behind this. One

role it had was that of an existence or consistency proof -- a

mechanical model demonstrated that a particular process could be

mechanical. (Then the problem became to show that it was mechanical

1. Experimental Researches, III, page 330.

2. In S.P. Thompson (1910), The Life of William Thomson, i, page 203.

3. For detailed argument, see A.F. Chalmers, (1973a), 'Maxwell's Methodology and his Application of It to Electromagnetism', Section II, page 154 and f.

45

Page 46: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

and to identify the unique mechanism associated with it. ) Another

purpose models had was that of a mathematical or physical heuristic.

Technical skill in Newtonian mechanics could be transferred to other

domains by means of the models, and the British scientists seemed to be

more adept at mechanics than at other branches of mathematics. l

Maxwell writes:

We must retranslate [symbols] into the language of dynamics. In this way our words will call up the mental image, not of certain operations of the calculus, but of certain character­istics of the motion of bodies. 2

46

The models were intended also to be a physical heuristic. It was thought

that the failing of standard approaches was that scientists advocated

theories they hoped were true -- and this meant that physicists were

constrained by their pet theories or prejudices. Maxwell writes:

If we ••• adopt a physical hypothesis, we see the phenomena through a medium, and we are liable to that blindness to facts and rashness in assumption which a partial explanation encourages. We must therefore discover some method if invest­igation which allows the mind at every step to lay hold of a clear physical conception, without being committed ••• 3

Models were to be the means of liberation -- a scientist was to be

free to propose any model merely to see if the properties it possessed

suggested unsuspected physical properties in the archetype. A

1. Duhem's well known joke that the British scientists lead us not into the tranquil abode of reason but into a factory is not that far wide of the mark. There are external factors here. It was the England of the Industrial Revolution and many scientists -- Rankine, for example -­were engineers for whom mechanics had pride of place.

2. Scientific Papers, II, page 308. See also the opening few para­graphs of his (1856), 'On Faraday's Line of Force'.

3. Maxwell (1856), page 155.

Page 47: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

criticism here is that if a process has a modelling mechanism, then

-- as Maxwell knewl

-- it will have an infinite number of mechanisms;2

consequently the physically suggestive role of the mechanism is prima

facie no better than that of arbitrarily adding an unknown property

3 to the original phenomena.

1. See Maxwell (1873), §83l.

2. This may be seen if the system is considered in terms of Lagrangian mechanics.

47

3. We may set this difficulty aside if we admit that Maxwell and Thomson were 'committed' in so far as they held that some of their models -­though perhaps false -- had verisimilitude and thus could be a guide as to the nature of the world. This admission, though, puts Maxwell and Thomson back among the ordinary scientists who propose theories that they hope will be something like the world.

Page 48: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

48

9. The Field Programme to 1860 :-

The research of Thomson and Maxwell prior to 1860 predicted

no new results, and thus the Field programme was degenerating during

this time.

It is important to stress this. Thomson and Maxwell worked

to show that the Field programme could offer mathematical derivations

leading to descriptions of phenomena discovered by the rival A.A.D.

programme. And they argued that success in this task would mean

that the two programmes had equal merit. Most historians agree, and so

direct their attention to the question of whether Maxwell and Thomson

did succeed. But the M.S.R.P. offers an improved system of appraisal,

under it only new predictions count. Consequently my concern is

with whether Maxwell and Thomson produced new results, not with whether

they re-cast old ones.

The papers of Thomson relevant to the Field programme are

those concerned with its heuristic, discussed in the last section, and

those concerned with energy and energy density. Thomson made a suggestion,

later adopted by Maxwell, to locate the energy of electromagnetic

1 interactions throughout space. ~e choice here appears to be letting

the energy arise from the configuration of the sources, or letting it

2 be distributed throughout space. For example, the potential energy of

a pendulum bob above the surface of the earth could be interpreted as being

1. See W.Thomson (1882), Mathematical and Physical Papers, 1, page 447. This

2is the

20rigin of one common modern method of using all space integrals

of E and B to calculate energy.

2. See A.Shadowitz (1975), The Electromagnetic Field, page 192 and f.

Page 49: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

49

due to the configuration of the bob and the earth and thus have no

location or it could be interpreted as having a location in the

gravitational field. Field theorists favoured distributing the energy

as it seemed that this would require a medium as the store of the

energy; and also the alternative meant sources and configurations of

sources, which they were trying to avoid. There were two physical

arguments against the Field approach. Distributing energy should work

also for gravity but, ~ince the energy of a medium would have to be

positive definite, absurd results are obtained -- for example, that

in regions where there are no masses there is infinite gravitational

1 potential energy. The other argument -- not so strong I feel -- is

that potential energy is about differences in energy, yet a distribution

involves an absolute value. Mathematically, if the energy does

arise from the configuration of the sources then it can be transformed

2 into a surface or volume integral of an energy density. Thomson's

interpretation needs independent evidence in its favour, none was

forthcoming in the period before 1860.

One early paper of Maxwell's should be discussed his

(1856) 'On Faraday's Lines of Force'. He proves in this, by means

1. See Maxwell (1864), f 82. This difficulty with gravitation defeats Faraday's intuition on local energy, mentioned in my Chapter 1 Section 5 and explained in Chapter 3, which was later expressed by Maxwell thus :

We are dissatisfied with the explanation founded on the hypothesis of attractive and repellent forces directed towards the magnetic poles, even though we may have satisfied ourselves that the phenomenon is in strict accordance with that hypothesis, and we cannot help thinking that in every place where we find these lines of force, some physical state or action must exist in , sufficient energy to produce the actual phenomenon.

(See his (1862), 'On Physi.cal Lines of Force' page 452.)

2. See R.P.Feynmann (1964), Lectures on Physics, 1!, 8.5.

Page 50: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

of a hydrodynamica1 analogue :

a ••• system of propositions ••• which is in itself a collection of purely geometrical truths •••

He also introduces the vector potential as an analytic measure of

Faraday's electrotonic state; however, as he himself writes, this

mathematical description does not constitute an explanation

I do not think that it contains even the shadow of a true physical theory; in fact, its chief merit as a temporary inst~ent of research is tha~ it does not, even in appearance, account for anything.

There are no discoveries in this paper.

1. Maxwell (1855), Letter to William Thomson, page 17.

2. Maxwell (1856), 'On Faraday's Lines of Force', page 207. His italics.

50

Page 51: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

51

10. An Appraisal of the Two Programmes Until 1860 :

The Field programme had no evidence in its favour before

1860. No electrical or magnetic effect could even be shown to be

a consequence of the thesis that the medium was the seat of electromagnetic

behaviour let alone was predicted from this base. There are two

possible exceptions to my claim. There was a period of twenty years

during which some scientists argued that the existence of dielectrics

was evidence for a medium -- this ran from the time that the Field ~

theorists Faraday and Snow Harris statedAdielectrics defied Coulomb's

law until the Field theorist Thomson showed that they did not.

1 this time the A.A.D. programme was able to explain dielectrics.

Throughout

Electromagnetic induction also seems to merit further discussion. The

Field explanations developed in two stages. Faraday described induction

in terms of flux-cutting and flux-threading these descriptions were

unsatisfactory, as I shall show in Chapter 3. Then Maxwell described

induction in terms of the rate of change of a vector potential. Does

this vector potential description constitute a Field explanation of

induction ? 2

Maxwell says not. And, for other reasons, I too say not.

An analogue is this. Say the problem is to explain the observations of

an orbiting satellite, then Newton's theory explains that the orbit

should be an ellipse, and an elliptic path 'describes' or'weakly

explains' the observations. The last qualification arises because

1. See my Chapter 1, Section 3.

2. In the passage quoted a few pages ago -- Maxwell (1856), page 207.

Page 52: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

52

our observations, though multitudinous, are finite whereas ellipses

are continuous curves of continuum many points; thus strictly speaking

the ellipse hypothesis does explain the observations in that it both

has the observations as consequences and is independently testable.

But once Newton's theory has been proposed it seems more appropriate

to treat the ellipse hypothesis as a description of a general fact

which is in turn explained by Newton's theory. With electromagnetic I

induction the sequence was as follows. In 1835 Gauss showed that

induction could be described mathematically in terms of the rate of

change of a vector potential; in 1845 F.E.Neumann published this result;

in 1846 Weber's force law had been shown to explain induction and to

predict that a vector potential should describe the effect; and in the

1 early 1850's Weber's derivations had been published in English. In

1856 Maxwell'discovered' that a vector potential could be used to

describe induction. My view is that either Maxwell's vector potential

theory is not an explanation, or it is an A.A.D. explanation.

In contrast with the Field programme, the A.A.D. view of

no medium and distant sources could satisfactorily explain all electromagnetic

phenomena known before 1860.

1. These results are discussed further in Chapter 4.

Page 53: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

53

11.Maxwell's Theories of Electromagnetism

By 1860 the Field programme had acquired the ability to solve

problems. But did it ever surpass its rival ? The key issue here is

the electromagnetic theory of light. Most historians would regard

the thesis that the A.A.D. programme was the better one as unusual, but

probably they would admit that the thesis was sound until 1860. But

they would qualify their admission. Surely, they would add, the

electromagnetic theory of light, developed during the 1860's, gave the

Field programme its decisive victory ?

I think not, and I argue the point in Chapters 5 and 6.

It was Maxwell who developed the Field theories of light

and he did so in two stages : the 'early' theory of '00 Physical Lines

1 of Force' , and the 'later' theory of 'A Dynamical Theory of the

2 Electromagnetic Field' and subsequent publications.

The early theory sets out to solve the problem of electromagnetic

induction using an extremely natural mechanical model which filled the

intervening space with a mechanism. This model apparently has the

independent and unexpected consequence that it supports transverse waves

and further these waves travel at the speed of light, so that :

we can scarcely avoid the inference that light consists in the transverse undulations of the same meiium which is the cause of electric and magnetic phenomena.

Thus the model seems to solve the out.tanding problem of the Field programme

while predicting a rudimentary electromagnetic theory of light. It also

1. Maxwell (1862), 'On Physical Lines of Force'.

2. Maxwell (1865), 'A Dynamical Theory of the Electromagnetic Field'.

3. Maxwell (1862), page 500, his italics.

Page 54: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

54

seems to link electrical and optical properties by predicting that in

dielectrics the refractive index is proportional to the square root of

the dielectric constant.

In reality, though, the model is ad hoc and heuristically ad hoc.

It has an open texture and indeterminateness with regard to the values

of the crucial parameters, and is heuristically ad hoc in its shift

from being a hydrodynamical model to being an elastic solid model (the

latter being needed to support a transverse wave). As it stood, with the

parameters settled upon by Maxwell, it predicted that the velocity of

1 a transverse disturbance should be~ times the velocity of light. The

model was refuted by the actual velocity of light, not confirmed by it.

And the other 'predicted' relationship -- between refractive index and

dielectric constant -- also failed experimentally.

The later theory consists of purely electrical postulates

and has as its main feature a derivation that there should exist

transverse electromagnetic waves in dielectrics. The derivation is

then coupled with a key thesis of the Faraday-Maxwell tradition -- that

the vacuum is a dielectric -- to reach the conclusion that there should

be transverse electromagnetic waves in a vacuum. Light was suggested

to be such a wave. Then the later theory is interpreted in terms of

the Lagrangian methods of analytical mechanicd, and this interpretation

is taken to signify that the postulates describe a mechanical aether.

The later theory was heuristically ad hoc. Its origins lay

with purely electrical arguments based on A.A.D. background knowledge

and not with the Field programme's heuristic. The use of Lagrangian

Page 55: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

mechanics did not improve the pedigree of the theory. The later

theory did make predictions. Many of these were consequences of

background knowledge, and the other novel predictions -- generally

about the vacuum -- were either untried or unsuccessful. The later

theory made no successful novel predictions within decades of its

proposal in 1865.

55

The early and later theories are components of a degenerating

research programme.

Page 56: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

56

12. The A.A.D. Theory of Light and An Appraisal of the Two Programmes

from 1860 - 1900 :

The A.A.D. programme also had a theory of light -- one

that postulated retarded scalar and vector potentials emanating from

electron sources.

The major theoretical problem facing the A.A.D. programme

from 1840 on was that of modifying the instantaneous force laws

so that electrical fortes took time to spread through space.

An answer to this came in 1867 from Ludwig Lorenz who proposed

a retarded force conservative generalization of the A.A.D.

• • 1 electrodynam1c equat10ns. In his theory the scalar potential •

and the vector potential A propagate at the speed of light. The

theory is conservative in the sense that it does not contradict

the established experimental base of quasi-stationary phenomena;

but Lorenz was not se~king merely to generalize the A.A.D. equations,

he was also searching for a theory of light.

He had earlier put forward a desideratum for a theory of

light in the form of a differential equation to be satisfied by

the light vector ~. In Lorenz's ~lectrodynaudc system Ohm's

law is stated as the current density vector 1 being equal to the

product of the electric vector E and the reciprocal of the

resistance; and !satisfies the desideratum; but 1 does not, although

it nearly does so. For reasons to be explained in Chapter 6,

Lorenz identified the light vector with the current density

I. L.Lorenz (1867), 'On the Identity of the Vibrations of Light and Electrical Currents'.

Page 57: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

vector 1. He writes

'the vibr,tions of light are themselves electrical currents'

This identification is incorrect from his own point of view, and

further the interpr~tation it leads him to is in direct conflict

with the A.A.D. programme. He then argued that the current

density vector must be able to be non-zero in a vacuum to permit

the propagation of light, and in turn that this meant that the

vacuum must contain electrons or conducting matter; he writes

•.• there is scarcely any reason for adhering to the hypothesis of an aether; for it may well be assumed that in the so-called vacuum there is sufficient matter

57

to form an adequate substratum for the motion [electric currentJ

This interpretation must be incorrect or incomplete. The vacuum

is empty, and so the current density vector must be zero there --

Lorenz's identification might be defensible for conducting matter,

but it cannot hold for the vacuum.

The light vector should be identified with the electric

vector E, and consequently the A.A.D. programme should adopt Lorenz's

basic idea, but not the strict form of his theory and not his

interpre tation. The need for this identification is made even

3 clearer by Hertz's 1884 paper. In this paper Hertz proves the

formal equivalence of the retarded scalar and vector potentials

of Riemann and Lorenz and the electromagnetic axioms used by

Maxwell in his derivations; and thus the retarded potentials

I. Lorenz (1867), page 288.

2. Lorenz (1867), page 301.

2

3. H.Hertz (1884), 'On the Relations Between Maxwell's Fundamental Equations and The Fundamental Equations of the Opposing Electromagnetics'.

Page 58: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

58

are shown to entail the propagation of transverse electric waves.

Although the two sets of equations are formally equivalent,

they have different interpretations. Maxwell's theory concerns

propagating transverse electric waves in dielectrics, and this account

is extended to the vacuum by the postulate that the vacuum is itself

a dielectric. The theory waS heuristically ad hoc, and in the 1880's

neither the means of production and detection of the waves nor

the boundary conditions between media for the waves ~ understood.

The theory of retarded potentials applies primarily to the vacuum (and

actually needs development to apply to dielectrics, as dielectrics

supply secondary sources of the waves). The theory was heuristically

acceptable, and Lorenz had given the means of production, detection,

and. the boundary conditions, for the waves. None of the predictions

of either theory was confirmed before Hertz's well known experimental

work of the late 1880's.

These A.A.D. theories, and the A.A.D. theory of light seem

to have been understood best by the Field theorists in Britain and

in particular by Maxwell. The majority of continental scientists

were misled by Helmholtz and his accounts of electrodynamics -- as

I will show in Chapters 4 and 6. Maxwell, though, had a good

appreciation of the strengths of A.A.D. methods and emphasizes them

Page 59: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

repeatedly throughout his publications. For example, he writes

According to a theory of electricity which is making great progress in Germany, two electrical particles act on one another directly at a distance, but with a force which, according to Weber, depends on their relative velocity, and according to a theory hinted at by Gauss, and developed by Riemann, Lorenz, and Neumann, acts not instantaneously, but after a time depending on the distance. The power with which this theory, in the hands of these eminent men, explains every kind of electrical phenomena must be studied in order to be appreciated.

Another theory of electricity, which I prefer, denies action at a distance and attributes electric action to tensions and pressures in an all-pervading medium, these stresses being the same in kind with those familiar to engineers, and the medium being identical with that in which light is supposed to be propagated.

Both these theories are found to explain not only the phenomena by the aid of which they were originally constructed, but other phenomena, which were not thought of or perhaps not known at the time; and both have independently arrived at the same numerical result, which gives the absolute yelocity of light in terms of electrical quantities.

But he did not think that the A.A.D. theory of light was the

59

equal to his own. The reason for this was the mechanical essentialism

discussed in Sections 3 and 8 of this Chapter. Maxwell rebuts

tbe retarded potential theory on these grounds. I should explain

that for Maxwell the vector potential was an analytic measure of

Faraday's electrotonic state and was thus a mechanical state of

the aether, but the scalar potential

, ••• is a mere scientific concept; we h2ve no reason to regard it as denoting a pbysical state.'

t. W.D.Niven (ed.) (1965), The Scientific Papers of James Clerk­Maxwell, Vol. 2, page 228.

2. Maxwell (1881), page 53.

Page 60: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Maxwell writes as his rebuttal :

Now we are unable to conceive of propagation in time, except either as the flight of a material substance through space, or as the propagation of a condition 1 of motion or stress in a medium already existing in space.

To sum up; the retarded potentials fail to explain the behaviour

of light because he, Maxwell, cannot understand how it is that

a propagated scalar potential is itself to be understood in

. 1 2 mechan1ca terms.

The pure A.A.D. programme led to no new theoretical

predictions in the thirty years from 1870 to 1900. There simp ly

were no scientists working within the A.A.D. tradition. But many

of the earlier predictions of theories in the programme were

confirmed during this period, principally those relating to the

atomic nature of the sources of electrical force. Most of these

predictions are discussed in Chapter 4. The A.A.D. programme

continued into the twentieth century and through to the present

day -- contributors here range from Ritz3and Wiechert4working

at the turn of the century through to Wheeler and Feynmann and

1. Maxwell (1873), f866.

2. This hesitancy about the scalar potential makes Maxwell adopt the Coulomb gauge, and this leads to the curious result that the scalar potential acts instantaneously at a distance, whereas the vector potential propagates.

3. See W.Hovgaard (1932), 'Ritz's Electrodynamic Theory'. Ritz claims allegiance to Gauss in his (1908b), 'A Critical Investigation of Maxwell's and Lorentz's Electrodynamic Theories', page 231. Modern physics students are told that ballistic theories like Ritz's are refuted by the transverse Doppler effect. Apparently though

60

it is not clear that the experimental results do mean that Ritz's theory is faulty. Ritz's theory is explained in A.O'Rahilly (1965).

4. See T.Hirosige (1966), 'Electrodynamics Before the Theory of Relativity 1890-1905', pages 18 and f.

Page 61: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

other roodern theoreticians.

Research continued 1n the no-source Maxwellian aether

Field programme until 1905. The main scientists involved were

Heaviside, Poynting, Fitzgerald, and Lodge (although the latter

two did on occasions discuss atomic sources). And the work was

fruitful. The results were mostly of a theoretical kind,

not leading to empirical discoveries; and the most important one

concerned the standard Field technique of locating energy in the

fie ld. I argued in Section 9 that the Thomson-Maxwell energy

density method of calculating the energy of electromagnetic

interaction was without independent evidence before 1870. Also

I mentioned that during this time the Field theorists were

unable to explain what it was for a current to flow through a

wire. Poynting and Heaviside's work changed all this. Using

the Poynting vector in the way that is now standard, they showed

61

that when a current flows through a wire one can maintain that nothing

does happen in the wire, instead there 1S an energy flow through the

space around the wire (possibly a flow of kinetic energy of the

aether), that a travelling electromagnetic wave carries energy

(and momentum), and that the locations and movements of energy could

be described consistently. These interpretations led to no

empirical discoveries, but they were certainly novel theoretical

uni fica tions • One other theoretical consequence should be mentioned

Page 62: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

for its somewhat ironic connection with Helmholtz's reasons for

preferring the Field programme; Helmholtz rejected the A.A.D.

theories because they employed velocity dependent forces, yet

Heaviside used velocity dependent forces as a natural part of the

Field programme.

62

Page 63: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

63

, Chapter 2 The Origins of Electrodynamics Oersted and Ampere

1. Introduction.

2. Agassi on the Philosophy of Discovery of General Facts.

3. Oersted's Discovery of the General Fact that Current Electricity

Produces a Magnetic Field.

\ 4. The Production of Ampere's Law by Rational Problem Solving

within the A.A.D. Programme -- Dorling on Demonstrative

Induction. ,

5. The Evidence for Ampere's Law and the Significance of Oersted's ,

and Ampere's Results for the A.A.D. and Field Programmes.

6. Amp~re's Theories of Magnetism and the Epistemological

Interpretation of Them.

7. The Origin, Validity, and Epistemological Status of the Blot

and Savart Law.

, , ' 8. Tricker on the As if Interpretation of Ampere's Theories.

9. Summary.

Page 64: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

1. Introduction

Classical electrodynamics originates with Oersted's discovery

in 1820 that current electricity affects a magnetic compass, and it was

this interaction which constituted the first challenge to the A.A.D.

programme.

The discovery is clearly an important one and has to be

discussed. It turns out, though, that Oersted's theories are uninter-

esting in as much as they are not rationally defensible nor even are

they pretenders to knowledge. In short, primary source material is

unexciting, although the question does remain of how Oersted made a

discovery that others failed to make. Secondary literature consists

of Meyer's biography, Dibner's and Stauffer's historical studies, and

1 Agassi's philosophical and historical work. Agassi gets very agitated

about discoveries (which is defensible in that discoveries advance

knowledge) and put his ideas into action on Oersted.

It seems useful to relate what little I claim about Oersted

to Agassi's philosophical and historical assertions. I maintain that

Agassi's philosophy is unfruitful and, more importantly, his history

is mistaken.

The challenge posed by Oersted's discovery was successfully met by

Ampere. He used onlsimp1e idea and routine application of heuristic to

produce a law which brought the interaction entirely within A.A.D. The

idea was that of simulating or replacing magnets by loops of current.

There appear to have been two strands of thought here. From the fact

1. Kirstine Meyer (1920), H.C. Oersted, Scientific Papers, Collected Edition with Two Essays on His Work; B. Dibner (1961), Oersted and the Discovery of Electromagnetism; R.C. Stauffer (1953), 'Persistent Errors Regarding Oersted's Discovery of Electromagnetism', Isis 1953; R.C. Stauffer (1957), 'Speculation and Experiment in the Background of Oersted's Discovery of Electromagnetism', Isis 1957; J. Agassi (1963), Towards an Historiography of Science.

Page 65: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

that a current affects a compass and that the magnetic Earth affects

1 a compass to the guess that the magnetic Earth was really a current

then only a little geometrical intuition is required to see that the

current must be in the form of a loop or solenoid to mimic a magnet.

And from the realization that the earlier claims of Coulomb were really

65

to the effect that only likes interact, and that Oersted had refuted this

unless currents were really magnets or magnets really currents. Thus ,

Ampere suspected, and then found, that ~ current carrying wires would

2 interact on their own. This is the background to his well-known

experiments on the magnetic forces between two parallel wires each

3 carrying a current. The substitution of loops of current for magnets

1. He used a thought experiment. Imagine, he suggested, that the develop­ment of electromagnetism had occurred in reverse: that first Oersted had discovered that a current could align a magnetic needle, and that later it was found that a magnetic needle would point to the North Pole; what would be a reasonable guess as to what was happening? See Ann.Chim.Phys., XV, 1820, Section II, pp.59-76 and 177-208.

2. Arago described Oersted's results to the French Academy on 11th September 1820 ('Experiences sur l'effet du conflict electrique sur l'aiguille aimant~e, par M.H. Chr.Oersted', Ann De Chimie, VIX, 1820, p.417). There was quite a reaction 7"'- especially since Coulomb had 'proved' some forty years earlier that there could be no effects between electricity and magnetism. Within a week Ampere had stated publicly that there was a force between two parallel current carrying wires. His achievement was belittled on the grounds that it was a consequence of Oersted's discovery. Ampere rebutted this: 'When M.Oersted discovered the action which a conductor exerts on a magnet, it really ought to have been suspected that there could be interaction between two conductors; but this was in no way a necessary corollary of the discovery of this famous physicist. A bar of soft iron acts on a magnetised ;eedle, but there is no interaction between two bars of soft iron.' (Memoires de L'Academie Royale des Sciences 1823 (issued 1827), probably written in 1826.)

3. I offer a minor historical conjecture here. Contrary to most histories, Ampere discovered first that the two current carrying helices would inter­act. Such an experiment makes better sense than the parallel wires one, and the documents reveal that in the Academy meeting of 25th September 1820 Amp~re announced ~ the interaction of helices and the interaction of parallel wires.

Page 66: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

changed the problem raised by Oersted's discovery into that of giving an

account of interacting currents, and this Ampere solved by an inverse-

66

square central force law which was produced by standard textbook methods.

The law was:

, I ' ids i 'ds' dF .. (sin a sin a cos w - '2cOS a cos a )=~~~-

r2

where dF is a differential of force acting centrally, ids and i'ds'

are products of currents and differential circuit elements, r is the

distance between these circuit elements, a is the angle between one

element and r in their plane, a' is the angle between the other

element and r in their plane, and W is the angle between two planes.

Historians have never made sense of what Ampere was doing. He presented

his work as inductivist deduction from the phenomena, but yet he used

an explicit assumption -- that the phenomena were governed by a central

force law. This use of an unproven and untested assumption means that

Ampere's claim is false historically as a description of the process

of discovery and false logically as a description of the status of his

law. Typical here are Pearce Williams's:

Ampere first described the law of action of electric currents, 1 which he had discovered from four extremely ingenious experiments.

and Whittaker's:

2 The weakness of Ampere's work evidently lies in the assumption.

How was the law discovered and what is its status? One philosopher

3 Jon Darling -- has an answer. It was discovered by Demonstrative

1. 'Ampere' article, Dictionary of Scientific Biography, page 145. My italics.

2. Sir E.T. Whittaker (1951), A History of Theories of Aether and Electricity, page 86.

3. J. Darling (1973), 'Demonstrative Induction: Its Significant Role in the History of Physics'.

Page 67: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

67

Induction and had the status of a plausible hypothesis. I agree with

Dorling over the question of discovery, and I agree that the law had the

status of a plausible hypothesis, but I will express reservations about

Dorling's arguments on status. The M.S.R.P. also suggests a solution

__ according to it most laws are discovered by the evolution of a

programme under its heuristic. I agree with this solution too. In this

case, Demonstrative Induction was the heuristic tool which suggested that

certain experiments be performed and then enabled the law to be deduced

from the facts.

Ampere's law was a great triumph for A.A.D. It reduced to one

law all known electromagnetic forces except the static electrical one.

This omission left the problem of bringing the Coulomb electrical force

into the scheme.

The reduction was accomplished with the aid of the elimination

of magnetic poles as an ontological category. I briefly explain this

and discuss its epistemological significance. In particular, the main

secondary source on Ampere -- Tricker -- urges an instrumentalist inter-

pretation here. I criticize his view in Section 8 and discuss the

instrumentalism versus fallibi1ist r.ea1ism debate in Appendix 2.

Modern scientists do not use Ampere's law when calculating

forces between circuits, instead they use a law which was produced at

about the same time as Ampere's law by Biot and Savart:

ids X rO dB - ~~~~ (where B is the magnetic field

and r·is 8 unit vector)

" 1 Prima facie, then, this was 'a rival to Ampere s law. I consider this

in Section 7.

1. Similar theories -- that is, theories based on forces between current elements and derived from assumptions and geometrical considerations -_ were offered by Grassman in 1845, Stefan in 1869, and Korteweg in 1881. (See J.J. Thomson (1885) Report on Electrical Theories.) I do not discuss these because I hold that the A.A.D. tradition started with Ampere's current elements and developed to the electron theories of Weber by 1845. Later current element theories were a retrograde step.

Page 68: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

2. Agassi on the Philosophy of Discovery of General Facts:

Agassi offers a bold thesis on the discovery of general facts:

behind every such discovery there exists a theory which the discovery

1 refutes.

68

He arrives at this view as follows: He considers the problems:

a) How are discoveries made?

b) Why are discoveries not made earlier than they are? and,

subsidiarily,

c) How can we make discoveries?

The type of discovery at issue here is that of general facts for example,

o that water boils at 100 C. Agassi then looks at the possible logical

relations between the discovery and scientific theories. He maintains

that either:

a) the discovery is independent of all theory,

or b) the discovery is predicted by a theory,

or c) the discovery is forbidden by a theory (that is, the discovery

refutes a theory),

and he treats these three as exclusive and exhaustive categories. In his

(1975), page 79, he writes:

I should stress again that the choice is only between inter­preting a discovery to be a verification, or a refutation, or an accident.

That discoveries are, or should be, independent of all

theories Agassi calls Bacon's view. Under this, all true discoveries

are accidental. Their novelty consists in not being known previously;

that is, in being independent of all prior knowledge. Many observers,

however, do entertain theories and become blinded by these 'prejudices'

and that is why discoveries are not made earlier than they are. The

1. J. Agassi (1963), pp.60-67, and J. Agassi (1975), 'On Novelty', Chapter 3 of Science in Flux (see especially the Appendix on page 73f.)

Page 69: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

remedy, and the recipe for making discoveries, is for searchers to purge

their minds.

That discoveries are predicted by theories Agassi calls

Whewell's view. Whewell agrees with Bacon that factual novelty lies

in being independent of existing theory, but argues that if the effects

are not expected then they would not be noticed. New factual occurrences

are predicted on the basis of new ideas: Scientists produce new theories

and on the rare occasions that these work a factual discovery may result.

Discoveries are not made earlier because they need the advent of the

theory which predicts them. And the advice to the discoverer is to think

up new ideas.

Finally, that discoveries refute theories is Agassi's view. He

aligns himself with Whewell against Bacon over the impossibility of

recognizing independent happenings but attacks Whewell's account with

the point that many discoverers just plain did not believe their own eyes

when making a discovery and so they could not have expected their

discoveries. The only other possibility is that discoveries refute

theories. The discoveries are not made earlier because they have to

wait for the proposal of the theory which they refute. Further, the

neophyte discoverer is to actively criticize or try to refute theories.

Agassi's case is not strong.

The first point to be made against Agassi (and Whewell also)

is that their views are practically irrefutable. The closure of

proposed scientific theories is hard to delimit, and the consequence

classes of members of this closure will be recursively enumerable but

not recursive; that is. it is easier to show that a discovery refutes

or confirms an existing theory when it does, than it is to show that no

such theory exists when indeed no such theory exists. This means that

Page 70: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

70

the onus should shift to Agassi to show the virtue of his irrefutable

suggestion. We can look only at the arguments he uses and at the

fruitfulness as a historical tool of his search for the refuted theory

behind each discovery. The arguments are lacking and in the case of

Oersted, which is Agassi's favourite, the search is unrewarded.

A second point to be made about the discovery of general facts

is that even these 'facts' have a theoretical content. True a rough

distinction can be made between factual and theoretical, or items to

be explained and explanations; but such a demarcation will shift

through time and will be only a relative one so that 'facts' will have

a certain theoretical backdrop. For instance, that water boils at lOOoC

could hardly have been discovered before notions of temperature,

Centigrade I temperature scales, boiling, and so on were familiar. This

consideration partly explains why many discoveries were not made earlier

and it is also a serious objection to Bacon's atheoretica1 facts.

Agassi's own account is sloppy logically, weak heuristically,

and is founded largely on armchair psychology of discovery.

The categories he considers are not exclusive -- an effect may

we1l be predicted by one theory but yet forbidden another. The logic of

1. One approach here is to reduce all discoveries to discoveries that ••• where the blank space is filled in by a proposition. So, for example, instead of talking about the discovery of oxygen we talk of the discovery that there was a gas with atomic weight 16 (or whatever). This move brings the theoretical content out into the open and permits conclusive debate of rival assertions. Whereas discussing issues like 'Who discovered oxygen and when was it discovered?' is hopeless because the discoverer has both to encounter oxygen and to know or to recognise what he had encountered, and the last requirement is just too vague. A.E. Musgrave has done some preliminary work here -- see page 195 of A.E. Musgrave (1976), 'Why did oxygen supplant phlogiston? Research Programmes in the Chemical Revolution', in C. Howson (Ed.) (1976), Method and Appraisal in the Physical Sciences.

Page 71: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

71

the matter is complex. There is an amorphous background containing all

sorts of views ranging from specific theories, rationally acceptable at

the time or not rationally acceptable, to vague expectations, both

fashionable and unfashionable; and this conglomerate will be inconsistent.

A scientist should hold a consistent selection of rationally defensible

views, but he will be aware of many more ideas than these, and in par­

ticular will often be able to recognize that the prediction of a crankish

idea has actually occurred.

Much of Agassi·s discussion concerns in essence psychology of

discovery. We are offered:

a) Bacon's claim that if you hold no theories you will observe all

facts whereas if you adopt a theory (or are prejudiced) you can

see only confirmations of it.

b) Whewell's claim that if you hold no theories you will be

'swamped' by possible perceptual information and will not be

able to see anything of Significance in it, whereas a theory

serves to focus interests; then you notice occu~nces you expect

to happen.

c) Agassi's claim that provided ~hat happens refutes a decent theory

then it will not slip by; you notice things you do not expect.

I do not know what is the right answer here and frankly I doubt the

ability of philosophers doing a 2riori research to find it. Even so,

Agassi's account is not the right one. He supposes that refutations are

few and far between and thus their significance is manifest. But, as

we will see in Appendix 1, any decent scientific theory has a Plethora of

(real or apparent) refutations and thus the Aggasi-ite would find himself

as swamped as the Baconian. Historical example runs against Agassi here.

Thermodynamics, for instance, was 'refuted' by Brownian motion even before

it was proposed, yet there was a wait of eighty years until statistical

Page 72: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

mechanics plucked the refutation from the background noise of exceptions

1 and gave it significance.

Finally, the heuristic advice seems unlikely to result in a

rash of discoveries. There is no need to try to refute theories

theories apparently go wrong allover the place. What is required is

some sifting and fortifying of these exceptions and that, as Feyerabend

has carefully argued, is better achieved by proliferating and developing

2 rival ideas and explanations.

1. This example, and the general idea of proliferation, run through many of Feyerabend's papers of the late 1960's. See, for instance, P.K. Feyerabend (1968), 'How to be a Good Empiricist -- A Plea for Tolerance in Matters Epistemological', in P.R. Nidditch (Ed.) (1968) The Philosophy of Science.

2. See Feyerabend (1968).

72

Page 73: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

3. Oersted's Discovery of the General Fact that Current Electricity

Produces a Magnetic Field:

In July 1820, Oersted announced that an electric current

and the magnetic needle of a compass can interact. His findings pose

several historical problems; primarily, Why did he succeed where

others had failed?

My view is that Oersted held several unorthodox theories

and as a result had a rough idea as to how the interaction should

occur, even 50 he was lucky to find it. Others failed because in

the main they were not looking, as Coulomb had convinced orthodox

science that there could be no interrelation. l The argument will be

developed by criticizing two descriptions of Oersted's work and

extracting from each an important unresolved question which my

account answers.

As we have just seen in the last section, some hold that

true discoveries are accidental and in particular the discovery of a

completely new effect, like Oersted's, has to be accidental. The

first of these myths was provided by Ludwig Wilhelm Gilbert when he

1 translated Oersted's initial announcement into German and published

73

1. Amp~re wrote to M. Roux-Bordier February 21, 1821: 'You are quite right in saying that it is inconceivable that for twenty years no one tried the action of the voltaic pile upon a magnet. I believe, however, that one can assign a cause for this; it was Coulomb's hypothesis on the nature of magnetic action. People believed this hypothesis was a fact and discarded any idea of an action between electricity and the so-called magnetic wires ••• Everyone had already decided that [interaction] was impossible.' Quoted from L. Pearce Williams (1962), 'Amp~re's Electrodynamic Molecular Model', page 114.

Arago tells us in his Oeuvres Compl~tes, (1854), Vol.2, page 50 that Amp~re used to announce in his 1802 lectures that he would: 'DEMONSTRATE that the electrical and magnetic phenomena are due to two different fluids which act independently of each other.'

2. 'What avary search and effort had not produced, cemA to PrafRasoT Oersted ••• by accident ••• ', Annalen dar Physik, ~, (1820), paQ8 292.

Page 74: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

it in his Annalen der Physik in 1820.

Oersted himself quickly produced a defense:

All my auditors are witnesses that I mentioned the result of the experiment beforehand. The discovery was therefore not made by accident, as Professor Gilbert has wished to conclude from the expressions I used in my first announce­ment. l

The background here was Oersted's belief in the unity of the forces

of nature and an acceptance of the widespread scientific view that

2 only likes interact. He was sympathetic to F.W.J. Schelling's

Naturphilosophie. This discipline was a type of mystic, Kantian,

a priori study of the universe which stressed the role of intuition

and the unity of physical forces. 3 The opinion that only likes

interact was undermined by the discovery that frictional or static

electricity could produce chemical effects such as dissociation, and

74

this difficulty was further emphasized by the discovery of electrolysis

in 1800. This suggested an analogy between static and current

electricity but did nothing to connect the pair with chemical forces.

One idea was to assume that there was one primordial force which could

take on different aspects; then electrolysis does not refute the view

1. Footnote to H.C. Oersted (1821), 'On Electromagnetism (A.) The History of my previous Researches on this Subject.', new translation in Stauffer (1957).

2. 'Throughout his literary career, he adhered to the opinion, that the magnetical effects are produc~ by the same powers as the electrical. He was not so much led to this, by the reasons commonly alleged for this opinion, as by the philosophical principle, that all phenomena are produced by the same original power.'. H.C. Oersted (1830), 'Thermo-Electricity', The Edinburgh Encyclopaedia, XVIII (1830). Oersted writes about himself in the third person in this paper.

3. See, for instance, I. Kant (1786), Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. (Translation, J. Ellington (1970).)

Page 75: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

75

that only likes interact since chemical forces and electrical forces

are likes in so far as they are both transformations of the primordial

force. This modification was confronted by electricity and

magnetism which are naturally occuring forces but yet which were not

known to interact -- there should be some ~ay of either transforming

the primordial force into electricity and magnetism or of converting

the latter pair into each other. l Thus Oersted's problem was to find

the conditions of transmutation, and it is this that he refers to

when he says that he expected the result.

This background forces a modification of the accidental

discovery story and a much more cogent version was given by Professor

Hansteen in a letter to Michael Faraday:

Already in the former century there was a general thought that there was a great conformity, and perhaps identity, between the electrical and magnetical force; it was only a question of how to demonstrate it by experiments. Oersted tried to place the wire of his galvanic battery perpendicular (at right angles to) over the magnetic needle, but marked no sensible motion. Once, after the end of his lecture, as he had used a strong galvanic battery in other experiments he said, 'Let us now try once, as the battery is in activity, to place the wire parallel to the needle'; as this was made, he was quite struck with perplexity by seeing the needle making a great oscillation (almost at right angles with the magnetic meridian). Then he said: 'Let

1. Oersted describes this: electrical bodies act upon magnetic bodies as if they were not animated by any particular force whatsoever. To remove this difficulty completely would be very interesting for science; but, since the present state of physics has not yet furnished facts sufficient for that, we shall show at least that this involves merely a difficulty, not a fact absolutely contrary to the identity of the electrical and magnetic forces ••• The galvanic mode of activity lies midway between the magnetic mode and the electrical. There the forces are more latent than in electricity and less than in magnetism •

••• Magnetism exists in all the bodies of nature ••• For this reason it is felt that magnetic forces are as general as electrical forces. One should test whether electricity in its most latent form has any action on the magnet as such. This experiment would offer some difficulty because electrical effects are always likely to be involved, making the observations very complicated.' H.C. Oersted (1813), 'Recherches sur l'identite des forces chemiques et electriques. '.

Page 76: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

us now invert the direction of the current' and the needle deviated in the contrary direction. Thus the great detection was made; and it has been said, not without reason, that 'he tumbled over it by accident'. He had not before any more iyea than any other person that the force should be transversal.

The account seems inaccurate. If, as Hansteen states, the magnetic

76

force was strong enough to produce a ninety degree deflection then, in

the original perpendicular case, it would have been perfectly obvious

that the needle was adjusting itself perpendicular to the wire and

not aligning itself in the magnetic meridian; again, if Oersted had

chosen the wrong direction of East-West or West-East he would have seen

the spectacular occurence of the needle rotating through 180 degrees. 2

Hansteen's letter, which was written 37 years after the event,

probably contains imaginary embellishments. 3

It does, though, highlight one question which any viable

reconstruction should answer. Most historical accounts of the

discovery have this reference to parallel and perpendicular placements

of the needle. It must therefore be asked: Why was it that the

needle was placed initially perpendicular to the wire? This is the

first unresolved question that I mentioned earlier.

Agassi takes it on, and as a result has a twofold problem:

why the perpendicular placement and what is the theory that the

discovery refutes? He starts with the important insight that:

1. Hansteen (1857), Letter to Michael Faraday 30th December 1857.

2. It is not impossible to obtain the results described by Hansteen, but it is unlikely that such should occur. The directions 'perpendicular to the wire' and 'the magnetic meridian' are identical if perpendicular is exactly ninety degrees. But setting the wire perpendicular would in practice usually mean setting it roughly perpendicular and then there would be a vibration of the needle when the current is switched on. So, if the 50 : 50 chance of having the current in the correct direction favoured you, and you had the wire within a few degrees of perpendicular, and you failed to notice the vibration -- you could produce the results described by Hansteen.

3. Stauffer argues in his (1953) that Hansteen did not witness the discovery, and he develops this theme in his (1957).

Page 77: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

77

[Oersted's theories1 led him to introduce the electric current

!~~~d:~~a~~;e:~!g:!!O~t~';o~~ep~~~~~~:di~;e;!y:~: ~~~ ~~;~~ed.l Oersted did not hold the received view that an electric current is the

flow of electric matter; instead. Agassi suggests, Oersted thought

that currents were transformations of forces, that:

••• in an electric discharge the electric force is transformed into other kinds of force; namely, heat and light. And that if the current is sufficiently strong it might also turn electricity into magnetism. 2

So that if a more powerful cell were used -- which, by the way,

Oersted invented in 1816 -- the current carrying wire would become

a weak magnet. However. Agassi continues, Oersted did not know any

more about this magnet and, in particular was ignorant of the position

of the poles; but Oersted believed, being a Newtonian. that the

magnetic forces involved were central. Agassi goes on:

Now, if one has a long weak magnet, if one does not know where its poles lie or which is North and which South, and if one wishes it to interact with a compass, some knowledge of Newton's theory of force will tell one to place the magnet in the East­West direction. One does so and sees no result. Hence one appears to have made a mistake. One concludes that either (a) the long weak magnet is weaker than thought, or (b) that it is no~ a magnet after all, or else (c) that the Newtonian hypothesis concerning forces is false. 3

When eventually Oersted tested the third assumption:

he gasped; he saw at once how much more important his discovery was than he had ever hoped. 4

Therefore Oersted's 'accidental' discovery was a refutation of the

Newtonian hypothesis that all forces are central.

Agassi's account is interesting but not satisfactory. It

relies on the hypothesis that Oersted held that the current-carrying

wire was a longitudinal magnet. Oersted states categorically in his

1. Agaesi (1963) page 69.

2. Agassi (1963) page 71.

3. Agassi (1963) page 72.

Page 78: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

writing that he thought that the wire was not a magnet at all;

rather he thought that magnetic influence would emanate from the wire

in all directions. For example. Oersted wrote:

As the luminous and heating effect of the electrical current. goes out in all directions from a conductor. which transmits a great quantity of electricity; so he thought it possible that magnetical effect could likewise eradiate. 1

Agassi dismisses this on the grounds that it was in Oersted's

interest to invent post hoc a theoretical background. But all

Oersted's descriptions ~- both before and after the event -- cohere

together well.

Besides, there are objective reasons why the assumption

that the wire was a longitudinal magnet would be the very last one

that Oersted would make. There had been plenty of thought about

the connection between electricity and magnetism before Oersted's

discovery. At first there seemed to be many similarities between

the unusual attractive and repulsive powers of lodestone and amber.

and in particular that inverse-square force laws ruled. The com-

parison here was between static electricity and magnetism.

The major disanalogy was that no matter how a magnet was made, or

cut up after manufacture, it always had two poles; whereas the two

forms of static electricity were easily available independently of

each other. The galvanic cell, when invented, provided the natural

analogue of the magnet for it too was dipole. But the analogy was

sustained only as long as the cell was on open circuit. As soon

as the terminals were connected there was a galvanic current which

~as an entirely new effect apparently not connected with either

electricity or magnetism. By analogy then. a cellon open circuit

should be a longitudinal magnet. Accordingly there were many

1. Oersted (1830).

7R

Page 79: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

experiments trying to align suspended cells in the earth's magnetic

1 field. All produced negative results, so a cell was not a magnet

whose line of action was that joining the terminals. Apparently,

perhaps due to frustration with the negative results, the experiment

was also tried with a straight piece of wire connecting the terminals

2 __ again there was no success. Oersted certainly did not hold that

the current-carrying wire was a longitudinal magnet; to emphasize

that he wrote:

••• he conjectured, that if it were possible to produce any magnetical effect by electricity, this could not be in the direction of the current, since this had been 60 often tried in vain, but that it must be produced by a lateral action. 3

Furthermore, if Oersted actually had refuted the Newtonian assumption

one would expect him to claim this very important discovery with some

79

vigour; in fact, he always regarded the interaction between electricity

and magnetism as the discovery and merely mentions without special

comment that the forces appeared to be rotational.

Agassi's account is mistaken.

The value of Agassi's work is that it draws attention to the

question of why Oersted employed galvanic electricity. This is the

second problem mentioned earlier. Oersted had an unorthodox view of

current. The transmission of current was oscillatory and the

electricity possessed great activity. When a wire was being heated

electrically the electric forces combined together becoming neutral

1. See P.F. Mottelay (1922), BibliOgra~hiCal History of Electricity and Magnetism page 376. Hach~tte and D sormes's experiment on align­ing an insulated pile was widely known.

2. Oersted's friend Johann Wilhelm Ritter claimed success, but the experiment was not reproducible. Oersted was wary of freak effects. Earlier he had been castigated by the Anneles de Chi~ et de Physique for enthusing baselessly on the results of Ritter's imagination (See L.P. Williams, 'Oersted', article in Dictionary of Scientific Biograpl~.)

3. Oersted (1830).

Page 80: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

and yet still showed great activity by reappearing in an entirely

different form as heat. To effect this transformation and produce

heat, thin wires of high resistance are needed. Oersted also knew

that if the cells were strong enough and the wires thin enough, the

current undulations could be converted into light. And next comes

his conjecture. If the wires are yet thinner still, and the cells

yet stronger still, perhaps the current undulations will produce

magnetism as well as heat and light.

The experiment was tried in the spring of 1820:

Since I expected the greatest effect from a discharge associated with incandescence, I inserted in the circuit a very fine platinum wire above the place where the needle was located. The effect was certainly unmistakable, but still it seemed to me so confused that I postponed further invest­igation to a time when I had more leisure. l

Two remarks are called for here. The small effect was due to the

low current flowing because of the high resistance of the platinum

wire. This is where Oersted's luck comes in -- the conditions

which he insisted upon were those which produced the weakest magnetic

field, so he was fortunate to observe it. Second, he did not

become excited at the mild positive result because he had often

2 experienced disappointment with effects that were not reproducible.

Three months later:

In the month of July 1820, he again resumed the experiment, making use of a much more considerable galvanical apparatus. The success was now evident, yet the effects were still feeble in the first repetitions of the experiment, because he employed only very thin wires, supposing that the magnetical effect would not take place, when heat and light were not reproduced by the galvanical current; but he soon found that conductors

1. Oersted (1821).

2. See footnote 2 on page 79. Besides cells lasted only a few minutes, so reproducible effects were difficult to obtain.

80

Page 81: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

of a greater diameter gave much more effect; and then he discovered by continued experiments during a few days, the fundamental law of electromagnetism, viz., that the magnetical effect of the electric current has a circular motion round it. l

To sum up. The needle was placed perpendicular to the wire

because the magnetic influence was expected to emanate like heat,

and the parallel placement had apparently failed to detect this

emanation. Oersted stresses these objective grounds during his

own reconstructions, and this is why the stories arose about him not

2 using the parallel placement. The expectation of magnetic

emanation was a loose consequence of the non-standard oscillatory

view of electric current and its role as the link in the transform-

ations of the primordial force.

Oersted's results were given public expression in the

3 well-known Latin paper.

1. Oersted (1830).

2. My view apparently does not explain what it should. Under my account the wire should be placed in any direction other than parallel -- there is no requirement that it be placed perpendicular. I suggest that commentators used 'perpendicular' to describe any set up in which the needle crossed the wire -- that is, 'perpendicular' means 'any direction other than parallel'.

3. H.C. Oersted (1820), 'Experimenta circa effectum conflictus e1ectrici in acum magneticam'. Translated in Thomson's Annals of Philosophy, Oct. 1820, XIV first series pp273-6.

81

Page 82: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

82

, , 4. The Production of Ampere s Law by Rational Problem Solving within

A.A.D. Dorling on Demonstrative Induction : ,

In the early 1820's, Ampere put forward a law which encompassed

all steady current and magnetic phenomena known at the time. The

law was :

ids. i'ds' dF == G ---'0';"";"'--'--'--

2 r

where dF is a differential of force acting centrally, ids and i'ds'

are products of currents and differential circuit elements, r is the

distance between these circuit elements, and G is a geometrical factor.

I maintain that the law was a hypothesis produced by rational

problem solving within the A.A.D. programme. I support this thesis

by reconstructing the heuristic path to the law. My reconstruction

will be objective and such that any Newtonian would find plausible

reasons for making each of the assumptions or decisions in it -- no

innovations are required. This means that the law is tightly bound

to the A.A.D. programme and reflects favourably on it. After presenting

my reconstruction, I will consider the arguments of Jon Dorling to the

effect that it was Demonstrative Induction which yielded and fortified

the law.

The problem is to find a central force law which gives the

force between two current carrying circuits.

The total force is considered to be the resultant of the forces

due to the elements of the circuits, and these elementary forces are

Page 83: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

83

are assumed to be central.

A decision is required at this point. What should be

considered as the elements of a circuit ? Wires or currents differ

from masses in that they have direction as well as position, and thus

it seems that a slight d~parture from standard A.A.D. methods is required.

But this difficulty is not new. Magnets are directed line segments,

and the technique with them is to look into their inner structure and

to regard their behaviour as being the resultant of the effects of the

two individual poles. This apparently is the best way of analysing

wires; an alternative is to try the calculation using directed line

segments as elementary.

If we follow the latter line, the question becomes

what is the central force between two arbitrarily orientated circuit

elements separated by a distance r :

\ \

r I ------~l

A Newtonian force is eentral and has magnitude proportional

to MI M2 where Ml and M2 are some factors of the sources and

n r

n is an integer, usually 2. With circuits, the force is zero with no

current, its direction reverses if either current is reversed, and is

Page 84: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

84

greater the longer the wire. M is guessed to be ids so that the force

1 is proportional to

ids. i'ds'

n r

(n usually 2)

The next step is to impose some order on the arbitrary

orientations. It is assumed that these can be split up into cases.

Say the first element is in the x-y plane, thus

then it will have a projection onto the x-axis of dx - ds cos e and

onto the y-axis of dy - ds sin 9 . The second element is placed in a

• plane with r at angle tAl to the x-y plane and 8 is measured in i 'ds 's

• own plane, then dx' = ds' cos e ,dy' = ds' sin e' cos W , and dz = ds' cos IoU

There are thus five cases

a) dx with dy' · ..... b) dx and dz' · ..... (\

c) dy " dx' · ..... d) dx " dx' · ..... e) dy " dy' I . · .....

There can be no forces in cases (a) , (b) , and (c) , by symmetry.

1. Amp~re's own reasoning on this point may be paraphrased thus The mutual action of two elements of electric current is proportional to their length; for, assuming them to be divided into infinitesimal equal parts along their lengths, all the attractions and repulsions of these parts can be regarded as directed along one and the same straight line, so that they necessarily add up.

Page 85: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

d)

e)

Only (d) and (e) are left

)

A constant k can be used to denote the ratio between the force in (d)

and that in (e), with the currents flowing as drawn.

Finally, n, the exponent in the denominator, is assigned

its expected value of 2.

The result is Amp~re's law: I ,

dF • ( sin e sin e cos W + k cos f} cos e) ids. i' ds '

2 r

, Ampere gave this law public announcement on December 4th

1820, a little over two months after he had heard of Oersted's

discovery. k was later found to be - ~.

85

The discussion so far has concerned the origin of the law, and the

argument has been that it was produced by 'text-book' application of

A.A.D. techniques. Nothing has been asserted as to the truth or

validity of the law -- that is discussed in the next section. ,

My reconstruction should be compared ~ith Ampere's writings

and in particular with the experiments he drew attention to. I say

that he should have performed two experiments -- one to see if the

arbitrarily orientated element can be projected on to the axes, and the

other to find k -- and maybe he should perform a third experiment to find n.

Page 86: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

, What is uncontroversial historically is that Ampere drew

attention to four experiments and held that he had proved from them

1 that his law was true. The experiments were of a sophisticated

2 and elegant 'null' variety. Even so they do not support an

inductive proof. ,

Ampere's derivation used the Newtonian format and

central force assumption and this strips the proof of its certainty.

Further, much to the disgust of most scientists and historians, the

< ' fourth experiment was not even performed, as Ampere freely admits.

He 'knew' how it would turn out and describes it merely to allow

others to complete the inductive proof. Two steps are required in ,

such a proof; to show that the law can be of the form Ampere gave

8~

1. There are two reasons for being even more cautious than usual about the words of the great man. First, the documents. Amp~re used his position as secretary of the Academy to amend his papers and keep them in line with his thought. The results of this stand unused in Paris. Many of the transcriptions of his sources have been added to or altered by the transcribers. (See, L.P. Williams, 'Amp~re' article, Dict. Sci. Bi~&.) Fortunately there is a reasonable version of M~oire sur la , ~ ~ ~

th orie mathemati ue des henomenes electrod nami ues uni uement deduite de l'experience (1827) in M moires surl' lectrodynamique (Paris 1885-7). All that is readily available in English is R.A.R. Tricker (1966), Early Electrodynamics about which Bromberg writes ' ... it is dangerous to discuss Amp~re on the basis of translations in Tricker' (see Joan Bromberg (1976), Review of W. Berkson's Fields of Force, page 133). Second, the false consciousness. Amp~re describes his task as proving from experience that his law was certainly true (that is why his book has in its title ' ••• uniquement deduite de l'experience'). , Since laws cannot be so proven, Ampere was not doing what he said he was doing.

2. At first sight these null experiments, in which one force is balanced against another so that there is no resultant force to move a magnet or conductor, are extremely sound. Indeed most commentators remark on their accuracy and conceptual elegance. In fact they are not especially reliable. Weber pointed out that if there were friction there might not be movement even if there was a small resultant force. Weber redesigned the experiments and put them on a firm basis. Sethis (1848), 'On the Measurement of Electrodynamic Forces', page 491.

Page 87: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

it, and to show that the law cannot be of any other form. I hold

that the second requirement is always unsatisfiab1e and no attempt

should be made to meet it. ,

Ampere tried to meet it, and that

explains the divergences from my reconstruction.

The first experiment was that a wire doubled back on

itself exerts no magnetic effect when a current is put through it:1

This is to show that if the current is reversed the magnetic force

is reversed. ,

This experiment was unnecessary as Ampere knew from

other experiments what its outcome would be. But his aim was to use

the experiment to sharpen up his proof by eliminating one of the

assumptions, and this experiment validates the use of 'null' methods.

It also backs up the symmetry arguments: - a current element cannot

87

exert a force on another element in a plane at right angles to itself

because, considering one element, the current approaches the common

perpendicular for one half of the element and recedes from it for the

other half and so the two halves produce equal and opposite forces

which cancel.

The second experiment was that a wire doubled back on

itself, but with the outgoing segment straight and the return segment

lot bent into arbitrary si~usities, also exerts no magnetic effect:

1. Fuller descriptions of the inessential experimental details are available in Amp~re (1827), Tricker (1965), or A.E. Woodruff (1962), 'Action at a Distance in Nineteenth Century Electrodynamics'.

Page 88: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

88

This is a key experiment. It shows that a small straight piece

of circuit produces exactly the same magnetic effect as another

piece with identical end points but of arbitrary path. This allows

the replacement of a straight piece of random orientation by three

other pieces running parallel to the axes, with the same end points.

For example, a current element, entirely in the x-y plane, with ends

(0,0) and(l,l) is completely equivalent to a current element running

from (0,0) to (0,1) connected to an element from (0,1) to (1,1).

Note the absurdity of the Pearce Williams's suggestion, quoted in ,

the Section ~ .1, that Ampere's law was discovered inductively from

experiment. An eternity would elapse before anyone would merely

happen to try an experiment of this kind; just as an eternity would

elapse before anyone just happened to take themselves off to South

America and look at the stars behind the sun during an eclipse, as

in the Eddington eclipse experiment. ,

Ampere's second experiment was

a deliberate probe of Nature prompted by the A.A.D. heuristic.

The third experiment was that a movable circular arc of a

circuit cannot be put in motion by magnetic interaction with a second

circuit of any shape:

What this shows is that there is a mathematical constraint on k (or

on the relation between k and n). For if the force is summed around

one complete circuit it can exert no tangential force on a circuit ,

element. Ampere integrated by parts the force around one circuit and

showed that the no tangential force condition is equivalent to:

n + 2k - 1 (i.e. if n is 2, then k is -~).

Page 89: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

The fourth experiment, which was not performed, was to the

effect that the linear dimensions of the circuit are irrelevant,

provided solid angle proportions are maintained. The magnetic force

between two circuits A and B was exactly balanced by that between A

and another circuit C which was of similar shape to B but of, say,

half the size of B and half the distance from A as B; C, of course,

was in reverse orientation to B. This result means that the force

is an inverse-square one so that n is 2.

Experiments three and four were a sophisticated way of fix-

ing n as 2 and k as -~ and were an attempt to rule out other

possibilities. Experiment four was unnecessary (except perhaps as

a good test of the law, once it was available, n could have been

guessed as 2 (which, after all, is what Amp~re did». Experiment

three was an elegant, maybe too elegant, way of finding k. A more

89

natural way to have done this would have been to have simply measured ,

the ratio of forces in the (d) and (e) cases, but Ampere also wanted

a null experiment for accuracy. (Actually, it took him seven years

to think of this way of determining k, as compared with under two

months to find the rest of the law.)

As far as I am aware only one philosopher -- Jon Dorling

, 1 has looked in detail at Ampere's deduction. Dorling's arguments

exhibit one way in which the positive heuristic functions, and so

his paper is of value here. Dorling's thesis is that the valid

argument form of Demonstrative Induction (D.I.) is valuable for

discovery and justification. My view is that D.I.'s main merit is

for discovery.

1. J. Dorling (1973), ' Demonstrative Induction: Its Significant Role in the History of Physics'.

Page 90: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Demonstrative Induction has the feature of the explanans

being deduced from one of its own explananda:

~e principle schema] ••• is one in which a universal generalization is deduced from one of its own particular instances. Of course this deduction involves the use of additional theoretical premises. The important thing about these additional premises is that they must not themselves imply the universal generalization in question and that they be such that, in a realistic situation, we could have more initial confidence in them than in the universal generalization which we propose to deduce with their help.l

j

And a typical D.I. might proceed:

1. A universal law of specified form characterized by the

90

value of a parameter covers the phenomena. (Existence Assumption) 2. This parameter has at most one value. (Uniqueness Assumption) 3. In a specific measured (or observed) instance of

the law-schema the parameter has value k. (Experimental Result) Therefore

4. A universal law of the appropriate form characterized by parameter value k covers the phenomena. (Specific Law)

W.E. Johnson gives a clear illustration of a simple type of 0.1.:

Every specimen of argon has some the same atomic weight. This specimen of argon has atomic weight 39.9.

Therefore 2 Every specimen of argon has atomic weight 39.9.

1. J. Dorling (1973), page 360.

2. Quoted from J. Dorling (1973), page 370.

Page 91: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

, , Dorling reconstructs Ampere s argument as follows

TH£ORlE MATH£MATIQUB DES PH£NOM~NES £LECfRO-DYNAMIQUES UNIQUEMENT D£DUlTE DE V£XP£RIENCE

, A.-M. AmpUe 1827.

A ralloNll "etlru/r.clloll 0/ W1Illtak~·. rallollal r.cOIUlrucllorr 01 Amplr.·. deductioll (The Enalish quotations ue from Whittaker (27), p. 8S. Notice tbat what he describes as Am­pUe'a experimental results ue really Jaw level aeoeralizatioDS from them. Uobroken arrows li,nify __ tiN inferences, broken urows hypotbetico-deductive inferences or inductive infereoc:a acc:orclina to your philosophical fancy.) Force lAw Amplr.·. EXJnrim,rrl6

1. 4F

2.U

3. ..

4. ...

5. ..,

. Under the conditions of Am~re·. specific W(I. r ... .... I)-+-cxperiments the force depends 04.,.---- -experiments

(perhaps only IItIer mia) on these unnecessary nriablcs.

t--~·Expt. 1: The effect of a current is reversed when tbe direction or the current is reversed" 04 - - - - - - --- actual Expt. 1 proportionality to 1 by definition. to r by

aU physical .... .." '" 0<'"'" .nd ~1

rGF('" .... I) ewtonian mecbanics ..... --experience fon::e is aIon,liDe AD forces reduce to joiDiq current elements inter-particle forces "4 - - - -"riell PI •• ' oppo.e"

(central do.ma) ntl/( ..... '.I)

t--_-iavariance aeder traDslatloDS and lotations ..... -- -- __ -commOD experience ~_~-IDvariance UDder reflections ..... - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - --?

Irftl/( ...... ..,.M .... M.r.r .... r • .. ·.1) "ExpL 2: The cft'ect or a current ftowiDa In a

linearity and c:ircuit twisted into smaJllinuosities is the ..... - -- - actual EKpt. 2 bomoaeneity in-....... If the dreuit were amoothed out" .. ~~ d~~

"-equality or action aDd nldionTNewtonian mecbanic:s ..... --experiencc

U'f(A(rX .. · .. ' + .(rX ... rX .. ·.I» LAD forca reduce to -1' ,_ • " iDter-particle fon::es ..... - rKIf,.. 6 °PPO"

.. proportional to I,,. ..... ------ --- ------------ -- ----'I Iff ra ( •. ( ..... , + 6.(".t)(~.t»

"Expt. 4: The on:c betwecll two elements of currents is t-_-t--uuft'ectcd wben aUlincar dimensions are increased .- actual EllPt. 4

proportionately, tbe cuneot stren,tbl remaioin, unaltered"

1ft 7. dF ,..( •. ( ... M) + 6.( ... t)( .... f»

"Expt. 3: The Corce exerted by a closed circuit on an 1---4-~clemcnt of another circuit is at rl,ht-anlles to the latter .. ~--actual Ellpt. 3

8. dF ~(2(".1Ia') - 3(".tXdl·.t»

The lian or k is -ve if two parallel currents auract;_additional Set the MI,nitude of Ie - I. by an appropriate unspecified dern. of current strenllh experiment

9. dF ~3( ... fX..,.f) - 2( ..... ')

(dF is the force caertcd by circuit element .. (current streDllh I) OD circuit element .. ' (current atrenatb ,'. relative position I».

A TYl"ICAL CASE OF A DEDUCTIVE JUSTIFICATION OF A NEW FUNDAMENTAL HYPOTHESIS

9)

Page 92: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

D.I.'s of the parameter fixing type occur from 6 to 7

and from 7 to 8. In the main the other steps are D.l. 's of the

form:

3n Vx [ Fnx & Gx ]

\/x Fkx

Therefore

\/x[ Fkx & Gx ]

Notice here that the conclusion is logically equivalent to the con-

junction of the premises.

I will consider three questions: Is Demonstrative Induction

acceptable? Does it occur in science? and What are its merits?

and I will argue that it is acceptable, it does occur, and that its

main merit is that of solving problems for a research programme.

Demonstrative Induction is a valid argument form and is

thus acceptable.

It occurs frequently in science. It would probably be

more recognizable if we called it parameter fixing instead of

Demonstrative Induction. Parameter fixing is common, for it is the

main task of normal science.

What are the merits of Demonstrative Induction?

It can be an aid to discovery. A research programme usually

assumes that laws have a characteristic form; its positive heuristic

therefore directs the scientist to perform specific parameter fixing

1 experiments; and thus laws can be found by Demonstrative Induction.

1. Dorling does not state this, although it is clear that he would do so. He tends, in his less explicit momentR, to reconstruct the situation as that of a scientist just merely happeninR to perform an experiment and then using general principles to DemonRtratively Induce a general law. I think he would articulate the heuristic steps as follows. It is the general principles which direct the scientist to perform experiments, then a Demonstrative Induction is made t(' discover a law.

Page 93: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

, Both Ampere's law and Weber's law were discovered in this way by

parameter fixing within the A.A.D. programme.

Dorling argues that it is an aid to justification -- with

the proviso that Demonstrative Induction does nothing to solve the

problem of induction since there are general principles among the

premises. Dorling writes:

and

and

A hypothesis is placed at a considerable advantage if it can be shown to be required by the facts provided we assume certain p1eusible general principles. l

the naive hypothetico-deductivist [might] treat [formula 9] as Amp~re's hypothesis and ••• ignore the deductive steps , which led to it. However such a construction of Ampere's theory would lead to the mistaken inference that any , experiments which later threw doubt on Ampere's formula merely called into question a single rather arhitrary­looking hypothetical force formula, whereas in fact, had such an experimental refutation been devisable, it would have called into question some of the most fundamental assumptions of classical physics. 2

The importance of Weber's formula is ••• that ••• its expertmental refutation would have called in question either the quite plau8ible assumptions on which Weber's deduction of it rests, or Aap~re's formula and the assumptions on which that rests. 3

So Dorling thinks that:

93

A 0.1. 's include among their premises theoretical principles in

which we have a relatively high initial confidence and from

these a specific law Is deduced in which our confidence is

not SO high;

B this means that if the particular law fails, then deeper

principles in which we have more confidence are called in

1. Oor1ing (1973) page 371.

2. Dorling (1973) page 364.

3. Oor1ing (1973) page 366.

Page 94: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

94

question;

so that,

C the particular law is placed at a considerable advantage

by being tied to more general principles in which we have

more initial confidence.

I will scrutinize the notions: 'relative initial confidence',

'calling in question', and 'being placed at an advantage'.

'Relative in~tial confidence' is an undefined and

unexplained notion for Dorling. One might seek a concept of

absolute initial confidence, then obtain relative initial

confidence by comparing absolute initial confidences. However. I

have a proposed desideratum on relative initial confidences which

will clarify matters without introducing absolute initial

confidences:

If A~B then one should be not less initially confident in B than in A.

I defend the principle on the grounds that in a valid argument if

the conjunction of the premises is true then so is the conclusion,

and even if the conjunction of the premises is not true, the

conclusion may be true. What are the relative initial confidence

relations in Demonstrative Induction? We have:

1. Existence. 2. Uniqueness. 3. Instance.

Therefore 4. Specific Law.

And 4 ~ 1, 4 j- 2, 4 J- 3, and 1 & 2 & 3 )- 4. That is: more

c~nfident in any of the premises individually than in the conclusion.

but equally confident in the conjunction of the premises and the

conclusion.

One result needs discussing; that is: 4 J- 2. The

question here is whether inferences like

Page 95: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Every specimen of argon has atomic weight 39.9. Therefore

Every specimen of argon has the same atomic weight.

are valid.

On the face of it they are, but a natural symbolization can render

them invalid for validity requires a uniqueness condition. But

atomic weights (and other parameters for that matter) are the

sorts of things that atoms (or whatever) have only one of -- that

is why scientists talk of the atomic weight of argon. So the

more proper statement 'Every atom of argon has the atomic weight

39.9' has an implicit uniqueness condition. And this also applies

to other parameters. In short, 4 j. 2 provided that the pre-

suppositions are spelled out.

What now about Dorling's 'calling into question' notion?

What is the principle that lies behind it? Clearly it is the

following: If the conclusion of a valid argument is false, then

all the premises are 'called in question'. Is this principle

sound? If the conclusion of a valid argument is false, then the

conjunction of the premises is false or. to put it another way.

at least one premise is false. Whether this 'calls in question'

each individual premise is another matter. Intuitions suggest

that it need not. Take the example,

2 + 2 - 4 If 2 + 2 • 4, then 2 + 2 - 5.

Therefore 2 + 2 • 5.

Does this valid argument with a false conclusion call in question

the arithmetical truth 2 + 2 - 41 I think not. Further, I would

be surprised if the Nobel prize were forthcoming for the scientist

who called in question Einstein's Theory of Relativity as follows:

95

Page 96: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Einstein's Theory of Relativity is true. If Einstein's Theory of Relativity is true, then 2 + 2 = 5.

Therefore 2 + 2 = 5.

What Dorling tends to do here is to surreptitiously discard the

experimental result and imagine that the deduction proceeds from

only general principles ('fundamental assumptions of ... physics')

with the result that failure of a law refutes a general principle. l

He is mistaken -- the failure of a law might equally well refute the

experimental statement.

Finally, what about 'being placed at an advantage'?

Presumably here the advantage accrues to a hypothesis which can be

Demonstratively Induced over one that cannot. There are no such

advantages. All experimentally tested hypotheses can be

Demonstratively Induced -- here is the prescription:

Take your specific law: a) Existentially quantify over any parameter to obtain

your 'General Theoretical Principle' (Existence), b) Infer uniqueness from the uniqueness presupposition

of your specific law (Uniqueness), c) Infer from the specific law the practical

experimental result that you have tried. (Experimental Result).

Then from (a), (b), and (c) Demonstratively Induce your law. Notice that since (a), (b), and (c) individually follow from your specific law, you must h~ve higher initial confidence in them than in the law (by the relative confidence desideratum); also (a) and (b) alone do not imply the specific law; consequently all the preconditions of a Demonstrative Induction are satisfied.

No doubt Dorling's best response to this is to emphasize that he

has strengthened his initial requirement on general principles from

'additional theoretical premises ••• such that we could have more

initial confidence in them than [in the conclusion of a D.IJ' ,

to, in the case of Ampere, 'fundamental assumptions of .•. physics'.

In other words, my concocted existential generalizations, although

in receipt of relatively more confidence, are not fundamental ,

enough. What then is? In the Ampere deduction it is the major

1. See again the Amp~re quote -- quote 2 page 93.

96

Page 97: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

theoretical assumption that dFO(.~, dF here is the differential r

of force between directed line segments. Is this one of 'the

most fundamental assumptions of classical physics'? There was

one precedent. The force between two magnets -- for magnets are

directed line segments; and this force was known not to be of

the form dF~.!.... rn (The dipole field was known to be approximately

inverse cube, but it was also known to be not exactly inverse

1 anything.)

What then are my views on the justificatory role of D.I.?

First, since the experimental result can be deduced from the

specific law a D.I. seems to show that the law has passed an

experimental test. But if the law is discovered by D.I., this is

not so. The experimental result dictates the specific form of the

law and so the law does not run the risk of being refuted by it

there is no test. Second, since the 'fundamental assumption of

physics' can be deduced from the specific law a D.I. seems to show

that the law has passed a theoretical test. The general principle

here is usually one championed by a research programme in which

case the theoretical test shows that the law is not heuristically

ad E££. But since the law is usually discovered by a D.I., this

'theoretical test' is also no test.

So, when D.I.'s are used for discovery -- as they usually

are -- they play no justificatory role.

" I maintain that Ampere's law may well have been discovered

by Demonstrative Induction or a process akin to it. but -- unlike ,

Dorling -- I do not hold that it was thereby placed at an advantage.

1. Jon Dorling has satisfied me in a private communication that he has an answer to my criticisms. It seems that my arguments exploit an incompleteness in the expression of his ideas. rather than expose an inherent weakness in them.

97

Page 98: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

, 5. The Evidence for Ampere's Law and the Significance of Oersted's

, and Ampere's Results for the A.A.D. and Field Programmes:

, Ampere's law was a great triumph for A.A.D. Maxwell, a

Field theorist, writes:

The experimental investigation by which Amp~re established the laws of the mechanical action between electric currents is one of the most brilliant achievements in science. The whole, theory and experiment, seems as if it had leaped, full grown and full armed, from the brain of the 'Newton of electricity'. It is perfect in form, and unassailable in accuracy, and it is summed up in a formula from which all the phenomena may be deduced, and which must always remain the cardinal formula of electro-dynamics. l

The law quantitatively accounted for all known current-

electric, magnetic, and electromagnetic forces, passed all the

tests that it was subjected to, and predicted novel facts like

that of a current-bearing helix orientating itself in the Earth's

2 magnetic field. It also immunized apparent counter-examples.

For instance, in 1821 Faraday made the first conversion of electric

force into continuing mechanical work with his 'electromagnetic

rotations' experiments; these allegedly showed the vortex nature

of electromagnetic phenomena; ,

but Ampere pointed out that his law

predicted this exact occurrence, and Faraday concurred.

Magnetism. and in particular Coulomb's law of force

between magnetic poles, was brought into the reduction by means of

the substitution of current shells for magnets. This is discussed

further in the next section.

98

The statical electrical force was the only known electromagnetic

force omitted from the reduction. This then was a problem to be solved.

1. J.e. Maxwell (1873), A Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism, f528.

2. The demonstration of this was the favourite laboratory 'party piece' of the time.

Page 99: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

99

There is a contrast here between my views and those of

Dorling on the relationship between Amp~re's law and the A.A.D.

programme. His interest is in the epistemological strength of

Amp~re's law and he argues that it was fortified by being linked

by Demonstrative Induction to 'fundamental assumptions' (that is,

to the general principles of A.A.D.). My interest is in the

epistemological strength of the A.A.D. programme and I argue that

the A.A.D. programme is fortified by its ability to generate

Amp~re's law by Demonstrative Induction. For me, the strength

, that Ampere's law has -- given that it was not heuristically ad hoc --

derives only from its ability to survive experimental test.

The Field programme was not in existence when Oersted and

'\ Ampere made their discoveries, and when in existence was never able

, , to explain Ampere slaw.

Page 100: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

, 6. Ampere's Theories of Magnetism and the Epistemological

Interpretation of Them: ,

As has been mentioned several times, Ampere eliminated

magnets as an ontological category by replacing them with equivalent

1 current shells:

The reduction leads to an important philosophical and ,

scientific question about which Ampere and I are in disagreement

with Tricker, the main secondary source, and most modern

2 scientists. The problem is that of realism versus instrumentalism.

Amp~re's first theory of magnetism, just described, was

in terms of macro-currents. Amp~re took the theory as a realistic

description of the world, and consequently had to resolve some

difficulties. Ordinary currents need a source to drive them and

give out heat when flowing through iron. Whereas magnets are not

hot3 and apparently have no means pf supporting perpetual currents.

, What Ampere did was to offer a second theory in terms

of micro-currents, which again he interpreted realistically. When

1. The mathematics of this is given in most modern textbooks.

2. Amp~re's philosophy of science is as follows. He distinguished phenomenal laws, which were proven certain truths, from hypotheses. His law of current elements was the former, whereas his theory of magnetism was the latter. Both types were interpreted as realistic descriptions of the world. I deny his distinction, but defend his interpretation.

3. At first he thought that the currents in the Earth would explain the Earth's heat, but later realized that this account would run into trouble with iron magnets.

100

Page 101: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

molecules were aligned suitably these molecular currents cancelled

across adjacent boundaries but yet had a resultant around the edge

of the material (rather like what happens in popular proofs of

Stokes's Theorem jJcur1 Y dA - §y.dS). These molecular currents

\ were subject to Ampere's law, but yet were perpetual and did not

give off heat. At this stage, the second theory represents a degen-

erate step; however it opened up a whole line of research that of

explaining gross magne~ic properties in terms of molecular currents ,

-- which was later successful ~hen developed by Ampere and Weber. ,

Tricker suggests that ~hat Ampere should have done was to

avoid the criticism by retreating into an instrumentalist

interpretation: ,

Though Ampere would like to go further there is, in fact, no compulsion to look upon his theory as more than an interpretation of magnetic phenomena in terms of the mutual action of electric currents and thus unifying them by means of one system~ His theory actually necessitates only the adoption of the principle that magnetic materials behave, when magnetized, as though there were electric currents circulating round them ••• 1

This is bad advice and runs contrary to my view of

science as an epistemological venture. I will criticize Tricker's

suggestion after I have described the Biot and Savart law and

Tricker's instrumentalist interpretation of that.

1. Tricker (1965) page 87, his italics.

101

Page 102: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

7. The Origin, Validity, and Epistemological Status of the Biot

and Savart Law: ,

Modern physicists do not use Ampere's law when calculating

forces between circuits instead they use a law which was produced

by Biot and Savart in the early 1820's:

o dB - ids x r

2 r

(where B is the magnetic field and

rO denotes a unit vector) ,

The Biot and Savart law is formally inconsistent with Ampere's law

but the two are practically equivalent in that they give the same

values for fields and forces for complete circuits; (we now know

102

that this is because they are provably equivalent for closed circuits).

An unusual feature of the Biot and Savart law is that it contradicts

Newton's third law. In the illustrated orientation:

B -+

A exerts a magnetic force on B, but B does not exert a force on A.

Three problems crop up with the Biot and Savart law:

a) How could early 19th century scientists have arrived at a

law which contradicts Newtonian physics?

b) Was the Biot and Savart law part of a better electro-

dynamic world view than A.A.D.?

and c) How should the law be interpreted?

The historical problem turns out to be uninteresting.

Biot and Savart, with loma matnematica1 n~lp from Laplace,

, J

·I"~C."'UJ the law from experience vi. a low-level experimental

generalization. They placed a current-bearing straight wire in a

vertical position and used a magnet suspended on a torsion pendulum

to determine that the force per magnetic pole was inverse as the

Page 103: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

distance:

(that is, roughly B = is x rO ) r

Then Laplace told them that the required form for infinitesimals

able to integrate to an inverse-distance law was inverse-square:

dB = ids x rO 2

r

, The law was not as well tested as Ampere's one -- there

were non-uniformities and background magnetic fields which were

known to interfere.

The Biot and Savart law was just an experimental law

and was not produced as part of a research programme, further --

because of its denying that action equals reaction -- there were

good reasons for thinking it false. In other words, scientists

of the time should not have maintained that the electrodynamic

world was as Biot and Savart described it.

As to the interpretation of the law, I hold that it

should have been taken as a putative realistic account. Tricker,

in contrast reverts here to the main philosophical theme of his

(1965). He commences by telling us what Newton did:

He [Newtonl is content to work out the consequences of the fact that bodies behave as if they attracted each other by a force proportional to their masses and inversely proportional to the square of the distance between them. 1

Then we are given the same interpretation for magnetism:

So long as it is known that electric circuits and magnets

1. Tricker (1965) page 35, his italics.

103

Page 104: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

behave as if magnetic poles existed. it would be perfectly legitimate to employ the concept in magnetic theory.l

, And then he urges it for the Ampere and Biot and Savart laws:

It is. however. surely only sensible not to complicate out calculations unnecessarily and. so far as is known. the assumption that steady currents in closed circuits behave as if their constituent elements obeyed Amp~re's law (in whatever form we choose to employ it) is perfectly adequate to describe the phenomena. 2

I will take issue with Tricker in the next section.

1. Tricker (1965) page 41, his italics -- see also page 87.

1. Tricker (1965) page 105, his italics. The phrase in parantheses 'in whatever form we choose to employ it' -- means that the

Biot and Savart law is included.

104

Page 105: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

8. , l

Tricker on the 'as if' Interpretation of Ampere's Theories:

I regard the best scientific theories as defensible views

on the world's structure; that is, scientific theories are given

epistemological weight by being taken as realistic descriptions of

the world. Such a view is controversial. The~e are arguments

that theories be interpreted instrumentally -- that scientific

theories do not describe instead they are mere classificatory

systems or 'rules of inference' which serve to generate the

appropriate predictions. This issue burns hot in classical

electrodynamics. First, because A.A.D. makes extensive use of

potentials and potentials are apparently just mathematical

contrivances not intended to be real and descriptive of the actual

world. Second, because commentators -- Tricker is the first --

urge Instrumentalism.

This then is a philosophical issue that needs to be dis-

cussed and I do so in a general context in Appendix 2. Here I

restrict myself to criticizing Tricker's precepts to Amp~re.

Tricker's prescriptions have two faults: they are likely

to be unfruitful, and they are difficult to apply consistently.

(In addition, they conflict with the spirit of this dissertation

because I hold that the aim of science should be knowledge.)

1. One of the intellectual forerunners of Tricker is H. Vaihinger with his (1924) The Philosophy of 'As If'. The key point about Vaihinger's work is that the admittedly false may be practically valuable (and we can all agree with him - for instance, over earth­stationary astronomy being useful for celestial navigation). But Vaihinger claims that all scientific theories are admittedly false but are none the worse for that. And Tricker has really much the same view: 'as ifs' are fictions, that is. they are factually false. So whereas I wish scientific theories to be like the world, Vaihinger and Tricker prefer them not to be like the world.

105

Page 106: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

The instrumentalist restricts the problem agenda, and thus

he runs the risk of excluding a fruitful problem. This is best

1 illustrated by an example. In Ptolemaic astronomy, eccentric

circles and the appropriate epicycles and deferents are

mathematically equivalent:

Ptolemy knew this and chose to employ the eccentric as it was

simpler using one circle rather than two. The instrumentalist

2 approves of this. And Tricker would like it too. He would say

that, for instance, the sun behaved 'as if' it was on an eccentric

and it also behaved 'as if' it followed an epicycle and deferent;

and he would continue that the scientist had free choice between

the two and that any discussion of what was 'really' happening was

unfruitful (and possibly meaningless). But consider the issue

from a realist point of view. The two hypotheses are physically

different. These circles are actually spb«es and the planets

are mounted on the spheres. Then the eccentric circle predicts

that the planet always presents the same face to the Earth, whereas

the epicycle and deferent predicts that the planet rotates present-

ing all faces to the Earth. So, while the instrumentalist sleeps

the realist looks for evidence of rotation and perhaps even finds

the moving sunspots in the case of the sun. In brief, a realist

can rationally appraise these physically different hypotheses, and

may make discoveries as a result. To put the whole argument as

1. This example is due to A.E. Musgrave.

2. See, for instance, P. Duhem (1969), To Save the Phenomena, Chapter 1.

106

Page 107: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

107

two rhetorical questions on other scientific matters. How could

anyone following Tricker's precepts have discovered X-ray

diffraction? How could anyone following Tricker's precepts have

discovered Einstein's theory of Brownian Motion?

Tricker's prescriptions are difficult to apply because

they rely on a demarcation between observable and theoretical,

and --- as is well known -- such a demarcation is difficult to

i

draw. This consideration can be used to force Tricker into a

solipsistic idealism. He would hold that in the world there are,

for example, tables and that these behave 'as if' they were made

of atoms and electrons. But should he be allowed to draw the line

there? Must not he say that in the world there are sensations and

that these behave 'as if' there were tables which produced them?

And so on.

Page 108: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

108

9. Summary:

In this Chapter, I have:

a) criticized Agassi's philosophy of the discovery of general facts,

b) refuted Agassi's historical account of Oersted's discovery,

c) described Oersted's discovery and solved certain historical

problems concerning it, ,

d) argued that Ampere's law was produced by problem solving within

the A.A.D. program*e and critically discussed Dorling's account

of Demonstrative Induction,

e) argued that the A.A.D. programme was massively corroborated by ,

Ampere's law, and

f) criticized Tricker's philosophy of the 'as if'.

Page 109: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Chapter 3 : Early Criticism of the A.A.D. Programme : Faraday's

Objections and His Foundation of the Field Programme

1. Introduction.

2. Faraday's Criticism of Particular A.A.D. Theories.

3. Faraday's Direct Criticism of the A.A.D. Programme.

4. Faraday's Indirect Criticism : The Field Programme and

Faraday's Major Discoveries.

5. Faraday's Discoveries and Their Relations to the Field

Programme.

109

Page 110: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

110

1. Introduction:

In the early 1820's, then, scientists should have held that

the electrodynamic world was as it had been described by the A.A.D.

programme. At this point Faraday criticized the enterprise and tried

to persuade scientists that the A.A.D. account was unsatisfactory.

The main problem of this Chapter arises from this. How

should Faraday's objections have been appraised? This is a problem

which has not been considered before. Historians either follow their

usual practice of reporting without judging or slip into some philosophical

naivety such as Pearce Williams's:

My estimate of the relative worth of the contributions of Faraday and Maxwell to the development of Field theory will also, I suspect, meet with opposition. Here my defense 1 is somewhat stronger; I have only followed Maxwell's own estimate.

that is, Faraday's and Maxwell's contributions were great because Maxwell

said they were ! My view on the objections is that there is no

substance in them.

Once again historians have not made much sense of what

Faraday was doing here and once again the M.S.R.P. tells us what to

look for in his onslaught on A.A.D. The M.S.R.P. identifies two

types of criticism : of particular theories in a programme, and of

the programme as a whole. Faraday's strictures against specific

A.A.D. theories were well made, but were confined locally -- I argue

this in Section 2. Criticism of a programme as a whole can be direct

1. L~P.Williams (1966), The Origins of Field Theory, page x.

Page 111: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

or indirect. I show in Section 3 that the direct criticisms were

not damaging. The indirect criticism consisted of the foundation

of the rival Field programme, and this is considered in Section 4.

The Field programme has to be appraised by the discoveries that it

leads to. And Faraday made many discoveries. However, the

discoveries were not the result of his holding the Field programme;

so at this stage the Field programme was poor and thus the indirect

1 criticism had no force.

111

This argument of mine leaves a subsidiary problem. After all,

Faraday did make many discoveries -- if he did not make them by virtue

of the Field programme, how did he make them ? As Helmholtz writes

A single remarkable discovery may, of course, be the result of a happy accident, and may not indicate the possession of any special gift on the part of the discoverer; but it is against all rules of probability, that the train of thought which has led to such a series of surprising and unexpected discoveries, as were those of Faraday, should be wi~hout a firm, although perhaps hidden, foundation of truth.

I look at this in Section 5. There is no monolithic answer. From

early in his scientific career Faraday held the metaphysical view

that the world was constituted of interconvertible forces. This

view -- similar to that of Oersted, Kant, and the Naturphilosophers

1. I must qualify the negative tone of what I have to say about Faraday. I have immense admiration for Faraday, both as a person and as a scientist. But my concern in this dissertation is solely with research programmes and their appraisal. My guess is that Faraday, who was always perfectly honest and fair, would have said the following : 'At this time there is more evidence for A.A.D. than for any other rival view. However, I am convinced that A.A.D. has shortcomings and cannot be right, so I have given my life to the search for a viable alternative. I think that I have found that alternative in Fields. These show great promise and I think that with more work the balance of evidence can be tipped in their favour.'

2. H.Helmholtz (1881), 'On the Modern Development of Faraday's Conception of Electricity', page 278.

Page 112: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

) ) 2

led him to seek correlations of forces. But the view did not tell him

the conditions of transmutation and thus· did not immediately direct

his research. For the same reason the metaphysical view was only

weakly confirmed when he discovered successful relationships between

forces. The metaphysics required supplementing with ideas on how the

forces were to be converted, but it was not the Field programme that

provided the subsidiary ideas. Fields played a different role.

Faraday madlprimary discoveries by luck or by metaphysics together

with a variety of inspirations, he then described these in his evolving

'Field' terms and made secondary discoveries concerning similar issues.

For example, although he expected magnetic forces to be able to correlate

with or produce electric forces his actual discovery of electromagnetic

induction was little more than an accident; he then described the

process of induction as one where a current is produced when lines

of magnetic force are cut by a conductor, and he then discovered other

unsuspected cases of induction. I think that the key point here is

that Faraday knew no mathematics, and the Field descriptions were his

surrogate heuristic. Faraday's life work was not that of announcing

the Field programme and then following its heuristic; rather his life

work culminated in the foundation of the programme. Faraday was great

friends with Thomson and they had lengthy discussions on the significance

1 of his discoveries and how best to describe them. It was these that

1. See also Jed Z.Buchwald (1977). 'William Thomson and the Mathematization of Faraday's Electrostatics', and Barbara Giusti Doran (1975), 'Origins and Consolidation of Field Theory in Nineteenth-Century Britain : From the Mechanical to the Electromagnetic View of Nature', page 163 and f.

Page 113: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

113

led Faraday to articulate the hard core : electromagnetic phenomena are

the outcome of behaviour by the space between the (real or apparent)

sources, and the positive heuristic : look at the intervening space,

describe phenomena in terms of lines of force, and •.•

A remark should be made on the sifting of conjectures in this

Chapter. I use L.P.Williams's book Michael Faraday critically and

1 with caution as a source on Faraday's writings and thoughts.

Pearce Williams claims, probably rightly, that he is the only person

2 other than Faraday to have any idea what Faraday's theories were.

The temptation is to become independently the second person with

sound ideas on Faraday. But two considerations encourage me to resist.

First, it can be seen without too much difficulty that Faraday held an

unorthodox world view roughly about the convertability of all forces

light, heat, sound, electrical, magnetical, chemical, gravitational,

and so on; this has little to do with electrodynamics and will not

be relevant to this dissertation. Second, only rarely did Faraday

vent his speculations in public, so one possible guide for the historian

is missing. Fortunately, Pearce Williams's book -- with two suspect

areas -- is now taken as the body of historical background knowledge

3 on Faraday's views. The exceptions concern a dispute about the

4 influence of Boscovich on Faraday and that is of no interest here ,

1. The reader can be assured that I am critical where Pearce Williams's work is concerned -- substantial theses of Pearce Williams's are refuted in Chapters 2, 3, and 5 of my dissertation.

2. L.P.Williams (1975), 'Should Philosophers be Allowed to Write History', page 250.

3. B.S.Finn provides a typical reviewer's assessment : 'It is unlikely ever to be surpassed in its clear account of his work' -- ISIS (1965), page 485.

4. See J.Brookes Spencer (1967), 'Boscovich's Theory and its Relation to Faraday's Researches: An Analytic Approach' and P.M.Heimann (1971), 'Faraday's Theories of Matter and Electricity'.

Page 114: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

114

and a dispute about whether it was Faraday's theories or his discoveries

which came first. The latter disagreement is important. Agassi

and Berkson maintain that Faraday's discoveries were predicted consequences

1 of his theories. Were this 90, the M.S.R.P. deems those discoveries

evidence for the theories. On the other hand, Pearce Williams holds

that the theories came after the discoveries -- in which case they are

not evidence. I think that what settles this is the decisive arguments

given by Pearce Williams in his review article 'Should Philosophers be

2 Allowed to Write History'. The discoveries came first.

1. J.Agassi (1971), Faraday as a Natural Philosopher, and W.Berkson (1974), Fields of Force.

2. L.P.Williams (1975).

Page 115: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

115

2. Faraday's Criticism of Particular A.A.D. Theories :

Faraday successfully attacked specific A.A.D. theories about

electrolysis and Arago's disc, but without thereby discrediting the

A.A.D. programme. Not every failure of an A.A.D. theory is a black

mark against the A.A.D. programme-- for were it so, a critic could

destroy the programme merely by arbitrarily concocting a pathetic

A.A.D. theory. What is important is the relation between the theory

and the programme -- whether the theory is heuristically ad hoc or

whether it is heuristically generated by the programme. The

theories of electrolysis were heuristically independent of the programme.

The theory of Arago's disc was weakly heuristically generated, but it

did not represent the straightforward A.A.D. approach.

Electrolysis -- discovered around 1800 -- was an extremely

important phenomenon for it seemed to represent a point at which

electrical and chemical forces were connected. It was also complex and

difficult to explain. There was no natural way for A.A.D. electrodynamics

to approach it simply because chemistry and chemical forces were

involved. There were individual scientists who did look at electrolysis

in A.A.D. terms -- Grotthuss was one, and he started a tradition of

theories in which the electrolytic poles acted-at-a-distance on polarized

molecules, or polarized-and-sheared molecules, in solution. Faraday

1 refuted many of these theories, and thus showed that A.A.D. electrodynamics

had to that time failed to succeed in electrochemistry. This failure

to succeed should not have reflected adversely on the A.A.D. programme

1. See L.P.Williams (1965). Michael Faraday, pages 227 and f.

Page 116: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

116

since there was no reason to suppose that the programme should apply

unproblematically in this domain. As Pearce Williams explains

Electrochemistry, before Faraday's researches, was in a state of almost total confusion. Theoretical models abounded and, most importantly, the phenomena had not been successfully subjected to mathematical analysis. Electrochemical action at a distance had only been suggested as an analogy with electrostatic action at a distance with the hopes that this would help clarify matters. Certainly the mathematical physicist felt that almost anything could happen in chemistry which steadfastly refused iO bow before the analytical powers of his mathematical tools.

Also, once Faraday had to some extent found out what occurred

experimentally during electrolysis, the A.A.D. programme was well suited

to explaining his discoveries -- as I shall show in Section 4.

Arago discovered in 1824 that if a copper disc is spun above

a magnetic compass then the compass itself turns sluggishly following

2 the disc. Arago's disc involves only magnets and forces and is thus

a phenomenon that any adequate electrodynamics should explain. I

suggest, though, that there was no clear way for the A.A.D. programme

to account for it. Let us try to reason out a solutio~ using the

A.A.D. techniques of 1825. The problem involves : a) the forces and

motions as described, b) the fact that there are no forces when the

disc is at rest, and c) the fact that copper cannot be magnetized.

One must postulate sources acting between the needle and the copper,

3 and the choice of type of source is between 'magnetic' ,electrostatic,

and current. Electrostatic looks unlikely, since the magnetic compass

1. L.P.Williams (1965), page 283.

2. Ann.Chim.Phys. XXVIII, (1825), page 325 and see also Oeuvres Compl~tes Vol. IV, (1854), page 424.

3. 'Magnetic' is in inverted commas because according to the A.A.D. programme there were no magnets in the world -- 'magnets' were current shells. See my Chapter 2 Section 6.

Page 117: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

is not charged -- unless the motion charges the compass. Magnetic

looks unlikely, since copper cannot be magnetized -- unless the

motion gives copper the ability to become magnetized. Current

looks unlikely, since the copper has no currents -- unless the

motion creates currents in the copper. There is no obvious path

to follow. Two additional facts were known in the mid-1820's.

The magnitude of the effect depends on the conductivity of the disc,

and the effect can be made to disappear by cutting radial slits in

the disc. The best hope of an explanation does seem to be currents

in the copper.

Babbage and Herschel tried to account for the disc's

1 behaviour using induced magnetism and a time lag ! They were

mistaken. Faraday later discovered electrodynamic induction and

117

then successfully explained Arago's disc in terms of induced currents.

What is the significance of Babbage and Herschel's failure

for the appraisal of A.A.D. ? I think that the failure was a failure

only in so far as A.A.D. did not anticipate the new effect of e1ectro-

dynamic induction. Once induction was known as a phenomenon it fitted

in naturally with the A.A.D. programme to provide an explanation of

the disc. Further, I argue in Chapter 4 that the A.A.D. programme

would have predicted, and then discovered, induction, if Faraday, Henry,

and Lenz had not the fortune to accidentally discover it first.

1. C.Babbage and J.F.W.Hersche1 (1825), 'Account of the Repetition of M.Arago's Experiments on the Magnetism Manifested by Various Substances During the Act of Rotation'.

Page 118: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

3. Faraday's Direct Criticism of the A.A.D. Programme :

Faraday attacked the A.A.D. programme as a whole. As I

mentioned in Chapter 1, he was not well qualified as a critic.

Nevertheless he offered criticisms and these have to be judged in

their own right. I list the major ones and then give an appraisal:

A the phenomena of curved lines of force -- A.A.D. has straight

line central forces, whereas lin~of magnetic or electrostatic

force can be curved, hence electromagnetic phenomena cannot

be A.A.D. Faraday writes that this was

strong proof [that induction is1 an action of contiguous particles affe1ting each other in turn, and not an action at a distance.

And Pearce Williams tells us :

118

the lines of transmission of this action were curves, whereas action at a distance took place in straight lines. From this [Faraday) concluded, and was to insist upon it time and time again, that when it could be shown that force was transmitted in curved lines it must

2be the

result of the action of contiguous particles.

B that the forces were not independent of the medium as they should

have been given A.A.D. Faraday discovered dielectrics and these

meant that Coulomb's force law was false. Pearce Williams

describes this :

Faraday also, with astonishing calm, and almost in passing, demolished the experimental basis of electrostatics. Coulomb's law relating charge, force, and distance was discovered to be only a quite special case of the action

1. Experimental Researches f 1224, and see the references cited in the Index to Volume 3. See also Mary Hesse (1961), Forces and Fields, pages 198 and f., Mary Hesse (1955), 'Action at a Distance in Classical Physics' page 342, and L.P.Williams (1965) page 296.

2. L.P.Williams (1965) page 250.

Page 119: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

of contiguous particles. If it were still to be retained, it would have to be restated in terms which took into account the nature of the medium or media through which the force was propagated. The force varied inversely as the square of the distance only under speci,l conditions which now had to be stated explicitly.

And Agassi writes

He [Faraday] refutes Coulomb's theory of electrical action at a distance by showing how decisive is the function of ~he material medium in electrostatic interaction.

Instead of the force being m.~" it equalled r r

m.m' 2

r

where

is a function of the medium, being perhaps 1 in a vacuum but

less than 1 in air or in wax. A similar result applied to

magnetism. Mary Hesse writes

119

f

nothing in the intervening medium had been found to affect the propagation of gravity, whereas the effect of the intervening medium was one of the main reasons for 3 asserting the reality of the electromagnetic field.

C further evidence that the medium was all important was provided

by the detailed behaviour of dielectrics. Faraday placed a

layered pile of mica discs between two charges -- this altered

the force; and when the layers were separated out the discs

4 were found to carry + or - charges on their surfaces. Thus

the action took place in the medium and was not concerned primarily

with the source charges themselves.

1. L.P.Wil1iams (1965), page 298.

2. Agassi (1971), page 234.

3. Mary Hesse (1955), page 353.

4. Diary, V.III, page 72 and f. of Physical Forces, page 108.

See also W.Grove (1867), The Correlation

Page 120: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

120

D lines of force were a property of space and not of 'sources'.

Some examples of electromagnetic induction showed that the

line of force in space was primary and existed on its own

independently of its 'sources , -- and therefore the A.A.D.

programme, with its sources and empty space, could not explain

these cases. Faraday used two experiments here 1

(a) sliding contacts (b) sliding contacts l

------I ,

N 1 N copper disc copper disc

S S

In (a) the disc and magnet are fixed together, and a current

is induced when they rotate. In (b) the disc is held stationary

while the magnet is rotated, and no current is induced. Faraday

used a flux-cutting explanation of induction under which a current

is induced when a conductor cuts lines of force; the magnet is

accompanied by lines of force which are either like hairs and

rotate when the magnet does or are fixed in space and do not

move when the magnet is spun; experiments (a) and (b) show that

lines of force are not 'hairs', but rather must be a property of

space. Faraday writes :

Thus a singular independence of the magnetism an~ the bar in which it resides is rendered evident.

1. See L.P.Williams (1965), page 204 for a discussion of this.

2. L.P.Williams (1965), page 204.

Page 121: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

And Pearce Williams informs us :

It goes without saying that this new property of magnetism appeared incompatible with Amp~re's theory, for there the magnetic forces were tied to the molecules of the magnet; when these molecules moved the lines of force had to move with them.

E A.A.D. violated the conservation of energy. Faraday always

121

felt that there should be enough 'energy' locally to produce any

actions or forces. He coupled this intuition with a thought

experiment. If only one body exists, and another is then

created, the second one is immediately attracted by the first;

but there is no local energy around the second body, therefore

2 the conservation of energy is violated.

What should have been made of these criticisms 7 First,

curved lines of force. It was well known that gravitational lines of

force could be curved; and gravitational lines are structurally similar

to electrostatic lines for attracting charges. Faraday just did not

have the scientific knowledge to realize this, but the other major

scientists would have been aware of it. ,

Besides, Ampere had just

shown that Oersted's curved lines could result from straight line

forces ! Faraday's thesis that c~rved lines cannot be the outcome

of straight line forces was known to be false. Second, dielectrics.

Indeed A.A.D. forces are independent of the medium, but the case is

subtle. The real gravitational force between two masses is independent

1. L. P • Williams' (1965), page 204.

2. L.P.Williams (1966), page 116. See also L.P.Williams (1965), page 458.

Page 122: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

of the space between them, but the apparent gravitational force

between the two masses can change if further gravitating matter

is introduced into that space. (It may be clearer to discuss

the case in terms of component and resultant forces : the component

force on a mass A due to a mass B is unaffected by the presence of

other masses, but the resultant or total gravitational force on A

depends on how many masses are present to be sources of the component

forces.) The A.A.D. prolramme is unequivocal about this the force

is unaffected by the medium, unless the medium introduces new sources

of force. Dielectrics are new sources. Faraday, Pearce Williams,

and Hesse are just wrong. Listen again to Pearce Williams :

Note the change that [Faraday's electrical theory] forces upon Newtonian physics. Previously, one needed to know only the position and momentum of bodies to determine their future positions. The forces acting upon them were assumed simply to act at a distance. Now one also had to ask what the medium was in which these bodies existed for this affected the forces acting upon them. The space between bodies had previously

122

been measured merely by a mathematical line; it now became a 1 physical entity to be ignored only with great risk of inaccuracy.

Needless to say: Pearce Williams is mistaken; before Faraday's theory

was proposed one had to know the sources, after Faraday's theory

had been proposed one had to know ~he sources, nothing changes. There

are, of course, slight differences between the gravitational and the

electrostatic cases. With gravity, anything material in the intervening

space affects the apparent force and anything non material does not;

1. L.P.Wil1iams (1966), page 87.

Page 123: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

123

and nothing 'non-material' becomes 'material' as a result of its insertion.

There is no real analogue of the 'creation' of sources by polarization.

However, induced magnetism was well known at this time, and Poisson

had given the full mathematical theory of it using magnetic fluids

acting-at-a-distance; and so these subtle disanalogies were peripheral.

Third, the mica discs. These really do show that there are sources in

the medium. Not only did the A.A.D. programme predict sources, but

it also had an explanation of how they worked for all that was needed

was an application of Poisson's theory of polar forces to electrostatics.

Faraday himself on occasions offered Poisson-type explanations of

dielectrics :

The particles of an insulating dielectric whilst under 1 induction may be compared to a series of small magnetic needles •••

And the Field programme simply adopted the A.A.D. view on dielectrics. 2

Fourth, the induction counter-examples. The conflict here is between

Faraday's explanation of these cases and A.A.D., not between experimental

reports and_A.A.D. theories. But should Faraday's explanation have

been accepted 1 I think not. First, Faraday knew full well that in

general lines of force did move with the magnet, as he would have

seen iron filings following a magnet moving transversely. Second, his

'explanations' of induction were awry. He used the now familiar flux-

cutting and flux-threading explanations interchangeably. Flux-cutting

is defeated by transformer action in the case where a solenoid (with

no external magnetic field, and therefore no external flux) is used

1. Experimental Researches f1679

2. See my Chapter 1 Section 6.

Page 124: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

124

to induce a current in a surrounding wire. Flux-threading works

here, but only by acting at a distance on the surrounding wire. It

is doubtful whether Faraday could explain his own experiments (a)

and (b). The dynamo, an invention of Faraday's, is a third

variation

sliding contacts

(c) 1 rotating copper disc

N

stationary magnet S

This -- the homopolar gerterator -- is a well-known puzzle for 'flux-

threaders' (so much so that school textbooks falsify Faraday's

discovery by giving the disc radial slots and thus converting it

into a Barlow wheel which is amenable to flux-threading.) In contrast,

the A.A.D. theory of inter-charge forces gives a direct account of all

these oddities of induction. Fifth,and finally, the conservation of

energy. Faraday did not know what energy was, and his objection was

made some years before the idea of conservation of energy arose. So

understanding him literally, which I will do first, will be unfaithful

to his intentions. Faraday's thought experiment is weak. If we

can suppose that a mass is created, then we can equally well suppose

that energy is created with it. Most Newtonians would have said that

potential energy was simply a matter of configuration, then indeed

Page 125: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

if the configuration is created the energy is created also. And

Faraday's intuitions on the necessity of local energy led into

1 difficulties. Really, though, Faraday's objection is not about

energy. His thought experiment amounts to a plea for an explanation

of the workings of gravity together with a blind faith assertion

that none can be given. The response to it is to reject the

essentialist presupposition on which it is based. The theory

of gravity is a sound explanatory theory on its own; and as to the

explanation of gravity itself, Faraday offers no arguments that no

2 explanation ~ be given.

My view on Faraday's criticisms is summed up by the field

theorist Thomson :

••• [Liouville] ••• asked me to write a short paper •.• explaining the phenomena of ordinary electricity observed by Faraday, and supposed to be objections fatal to the mathematical theory [Le.· A.A.D.]. I told Liouville what I had always thought on the subject of

3these objections

(i.e. that they are simple verifications).

125

1. See Maxwell (1864), 'A Dynamical Theory of the Electromagnetic Field', § 82, my Chapter 1 Section 5, and. Chapter 1 Section 9.

2. See my Chapter 1 Section 3 for a discussion of the philosophical objection to action at a distance.

3. Thomson's March 1845 letter to his father quoted from S.P.Thompson (1910), The Life of William Thomson, Vol. 1, page 128, my italics.

Page 126: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

4. Faraday's Indirect Criticism: The Field Programme and Faraday's

Major Discoveries:

Faraday's indirect criticism amounted to the foundation of

the Field programme. Towards the end of his career he proposed

the thesis which became the hard core of the programme:

electromagnetic phenomena were the outcome of behaviour by the space between the (real or apparent) sources.

At this time the heuristic of the programme was extremely weak.

True, there was the general directive 'look at the intervening

space', but there was no mathematical knowledge and no body of

problem solving skills which could be learned and passed on. As

a result, Faraday had no students, no followers, and no one thought

his theories sound.

The Field programme has to be appraised by the discoveries

which it led to. Faraday made five major discoveries: electro-

dynamic induction, the laws of electrolysis, dielectrics, the

rotation of the plane of polarization of light, and diamagnetism.

But they are individually either independent of the Field programme

or are only weakly linked with it. Electrodynamic induction was

not a complete surprise to Faraday' as he thought that all forces

were interconvertib1e; however this metaphysical view gave him no

indication of the conditions of transformation. Its occu~ce was

unexpected and unexplained on the basis of the Field programme. The

126

laws of electrolysis too were not expected on the basis of his theories.

Further, the second law -- that electrochemical equivalents are

liberated -- seemed to ask for explanation in terms of atoms of

electricity. As Faraday put it:

If we adopt the atomic phraseology, then the atoms of bodies which are equivalent to each other in their ordinary

Page 127: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

chemical action, have equal quantities of electricity naturally associated with them. 1

But, as I have explained, electrical fluids and atoms of electricity

were foreign to his approach and he resisted this interpretation.

This awkwardness over electrolysis was inherited by the Field

programme. Maxwell later defined a 'molecule of electricity' and

then wrote:

This phrase, gross as it is, and out of harmony with the rest of this treatise, will enable uS at least to state clearly what is known about electrolysis, and to appreciate the outstanding difficulties. 2

This is a tactful admission that A.A.D. is more suited to explain-

3 ing electrolysis than is the Field programme. The existence of

dielectrics was to be expected on the basis of embryonic Field

ideas -- so here is evidence for the value of Faraday's methods.

But the victory was limited since, as I have described,dielectrics

were explained by A.A.D. The rotation of the plane of polarization

127

of light in a magnetic field was unexpected; so too were diamagnetics,

although initially they were explained well by Faraday in terms of

abilities to conduct lines of force. 4

In short, in the early 19th Century the newly born Field

programme was poor.

1. Experimental Researches f869

2. J. C. Maxwell (1873) § 260.

3. Helmholtz later wrote: 'If we accept the hypothesis that the elementary substances are composed of atoms. we cannot avoid concluding that electricity also, positive as well as negative. is divided into definite elementary portions which behave like atoms of electricity' • Helmholtz (1881) page 277.

4. See L.P. Williams (1965) p438f. It is to be noted though that most of the progressive work in the 19th Century on the magnetic vagaries of materials resulted from the Ampere - Weber tradition using electrons, currents, and orientation of micro-currents.

Page 128: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

5. Faraday's Discoveries and Their Relation to the Field Programme:

In this section I look at how Faraday made his discoveries.

Faraday discovered electrodynamic induction while

experimenting with a powerful electromagnet made to a design of

Henry. I think that there was nothing magnificent about this, since

Henry and Lenz -- both A.A.D. theorists -- discovered the effect at

more or less the same time. Now our knowledge of the immediate

background to Faraday'. exper~ents is extremely hypothetical.

Pearce Williams warns:

The sources ••• are extremely meagre. The attempt is to reconstruct Faraday's thoughts from the hints thrown out in the laboratory diary and follow him as he struggled towards success ••• This account contains a good deal more conjecture than is desirable. The result is a coherent tale, but perhaps not the only nor the correct one; unfortunately, it seems unlikely that new evidence will be uncovered and we must make do with what we have. l

Pearce Williams' story is this: Faraday held that currents consisted

of an oscillatory wave which was not specifically confined to its

conductor; he had observed accoustical induction where one

vibrating object starts another body oscillating; hence he

expected electrodynamic induction. Let us accept the story. Then,

first, the key to induction lies in the vibrating currents and not

in the medium or field; that wires interact via their electric,

magnetic, or electromagnetic forces was well known since Coulomb,

Amp~re, and Oersted; so it was not the interaction that was

important, it was the vibration. And second, induction should occur

with steady currents, which it does not. So, if induction was

discovered this way, it was the refutation of a view about currents I

1. L.P. Williams (1965) page 169.

128

Page 129: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

The laws of electrolysis were discovered as a result of

I research on the identity of electricities. There was the question

of whether current electricity, produced by a cell, and a flow of

initially static electricity were the same. Faraday tried to find

out if all known effects of the one could be produced by the other,

and eventually found that they could. One property that the

electricities had was that of deflecting a galvanometer needle a

set amount according tb their quantity. And voltaic electricity

could be used to decompose electrolytes. Faraday considered

whether flow of static electricity could decompose electrolytic

solutions and whether the amounts produced by decomposition were a

function of the quantities of electricity; and thus he discovered

the laws of electrolysis. Again, this has no relation with Fields.

Dielectrics were discovered as a result of paying attention

to the intervening space. Faraday had early Field-style explanations

of electrolysis and suspected correctly that substances could be

2 polarized without shearing.

1. L.P. Williams (1965), pages 211 and f.

2. Actually, it was the A.A.D. theorists who first predicted the existence of dielectrics. One problem for A.A.D. was that of keep­ing the source fluids with their conductors; one answer was the theory that air was an insulator and then fluids stayed with the conductor due to hydrostatic pressure; further it was this pressure that caused the electrostatic force; then it was reasoned that if air was replaced by another substance less impermeable to electrical fluids, the electrostatic force must change. See R. Murphy (1833) Elementary Principles of the Theories of Electricity, Heat and Molecular Action.

129

Page 130: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

130

The rotation of the plane of polarization of light by a

magnetic field was discovered by luck. Faraday thought of electro-

static lines of force as a stress or line of polarization in the

medium, and it was well known that mechanical stress on glass

rotates the plane of polarization of light passing through it. So

Faraday, encouraged by Thomson, sought to find his electrostatic

stress by investigating glass and polarized light. He failed to

find it. Having failed, he switched from electric lines to magnetic

lines produced by a powerful electromagnet. Lo and behold, there

was the rotation! This was pure luck. Pearce Williams disagrees,

he says that electric forces were weak, perhaps too weak, but e1ectro-

magnets exerted immense forces so it was natural to try them after

1 the initial failure. This is not so. Consider the theories.

Electric lines are stresses and glass is a dielectric so electric

lines should stress glass and rotate polarization. Magnetic lines

-- under Faraday's theory -- were not mechanical stresses.

Magnetic lines were non-divergent, there was no 'free' pole, and so

the lines were nothing to do with mechanical stresses. Further,

glass was not a magnetic material and so could not have been stressed

by magnetic lines even if magnetic lines had been stresses.

(Diamagnetism was not known at this time.) So, since the glass was

not under stress, background knowledge plus Faraday's theories

predict no rotation. So, if anything, this discovery was a refutation

of Faraday's theories on the nature of lines of force.

These rotations pointed the way to the discovery of dia-

magnetism. The rotations showed that magnets or magnetic fields

could affect (apparently) non-magnetic materials. It was but a short

1. See 'Faraday' article, Dictionary of Scientific Biography, page 538. And L.P. Williams (1965) page 386.

Page 131: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

step from there to find:i_.lg diamagnetisr:

To sum up. With the exception of dielectrics, none of

Faraday's discoveries were evidence for the Field programme.

131

Page 132: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

132

Chapter 4 : The Development of the A.A.D. Programme 1830-1860 :

Weber's Unification of Electrodynamics and Other Theoretical Advances.

1. Introduction.

2. Sources and Receivers of Force.

3. Gauss -- The Unification of Electrodynamics and the

Retardation of Forces.

4. Weber's Deduction of His Law.

5. The Significance of the Law for the A.A.D. Programme.

6. Criticisms of the Law and Their Evaluation.

7. Riemann's Attempt to Deduce Weber's Law from a Propagated

Force Law.

8. Electrical Actions Propagated at the Speed of Light.

9. Summary.

Page 133: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

133

1. Introduction:

By 1830, the A.A.D. programme contained three prominent

theses :

1. That static electricity was governed entirely by Coulomb's A.A.D. law.

2. That, in a manner of speaking, magnets did not exist; instead there were currents which produced the effects.

3. That current electricity (and thus magnetism) was governed entirely by Amp~re's A.A.D. law.

During the following twenty years Weber and his colleagues

developed these three into five replacement theses

1'. That electricity is atomic in structure.

2'. That currents are streams of electrical 'atoms'.

3'. That the forces acting operate directly between electrical atoms and not between conductors.

4'. That the forces acting do not do so instantaneously.

5'. That all electrodynamic phenomena may be deduced, by statistical summation, from a force formula applied to electrical atoms.

This chapter looks at these advances.

A few remarks are in order on the origins and advantages of

these theories.

l' results from the common association of Newtonianism and

atomism and it has the merit, as I explained in Chapter 3, of being

in harmony with Faraday's laws of electrolysis.

2' is a routine development of l' and background knowledge

on voltaic and frictional currents. The principal scientists involved

Page 134: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

134

were Ohm, Fechner and Kirchoff. In the mid-1820's Ohm offered his

application of Fourier conduction-analysis to currents in conductors -

1 the work was almost entirely ignored. The one man to take an interest

was Fechner -- later to become Weber's colleague at Leipzig. Fechner

carried out the experiments and favoured Ohm's theoretical analysis. 2

Ohm once wrote:

My theory has found in him [Fechner] alone, if I am not mistaken, a very gallant defender; and I have found into the bargain an honest friend ••• 3

The main difficulty with Ohm's theory was in identifying the physical

counterpart of the mathematical 'electric tension' function -- that is,

the question was what is the true electrical analogue of 'temperature'

used in the Fourier heat case. In 1849 Kirchoff identified 'electric

tension' with Poisson's electrostatic potential function V, and this

completed his earlier extension of Ohm's theory to three dimensions.4

Thus the advanced A.A.D. theoretical electrostatics of Poisson (and

George Green, and others) became linked with Ohm's theory of electric

circuits and conductors. Needless to say the Ohm-Fechner-Kirchoff

analysis fared well when tested by experiment. Ohm's research remained

unknown to the Field theorists in England for near twenty years. But

Weber and Gauss used it as early as 1813 for their research on terrestrial

5 magnetism and for their construction of electromagnetic instruments.

1. See R. Taylor (1841), Scientific Memoirs, Vol II, page 401 for a translation of one of Ohm's papers and see also Morton L. Schagrin (1963), 'Resistance to Ohm's Law'.

2. See, for instance, G.T. Fechner (1831), ~sbestimmungen uber die galvanische Kette.

3. Quoted from H.J. Winter (1944), 'The Reception of Ohm's Electrical Researches by His Contemporaries', page 378, my italics.

4. Ann. de Phys. LXXV (1848) page 189 and Ann.de Phys. LXXVIII (1849) page 1.

S. Actually, Gauss derived most of the network analysis results twenty years before Kirchoff. See Schaefer (1931), 'Gauss's Investigations on Electrodynamics', page 340.

Page 135: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Ohm's theories themselves in no way stem from the A.A.D. programme;

however, the Ohm-Fechner-Kirchoff analysis placed the A.A.D. theorists

in a strong position to unify electrodynamics. The analysis leaves

open the mechanism of flow in ordinary circuits, excepting that

conductors carrying voltaic currents have to be electrostatically

neutral. Fechner did some further theoretical work using one of the

three possible assumptions: the voltaic currents consist of equal

and opposite flows of positive and negative electrical fluids.

3' arises from the attempt to unify static and current

electricity. I discuss it in Section 2.

4' was developed by Gauss, Weber's fellow researcher at

Gottingen, and Ri~mann, who was Gauss's student. One point to note

135

is that the retardation of forces also suggests a revision in the

Newtonian central force assumption. If a force takes time to travel

across space, then it becomes an open question as to whether the force

should act along the line joining the particles when the forces set out,

or along the resultant of the directions of the retarded forces, or

along some other direction. This important area of retarded forces is

considered in Sections 3 and 7.

5' is the outcome of Gauss's and Weber's approach to electro­

dynamics using a force law between electrical atoms. It is discussed

in Sections 3 and 4.

The major problem facing electrodynamics in the early 1830's

was that of explaining electrodynamic induction. This new effect was

unexpected, except under the metaphysical view that all forces were

inter-convertible, and it manifested itself in a myriad of forms

including Arago's disc, dynamos, and self and mutual induction.

The problem, being new, was not on the agenda of either the

Field o~ the A.A.D. programmes. However the A.A.D. programme did have

Page 136: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

1%

a pressing problem -- that of unifying static and current electricity

by combining Coulomb's and Ampere's laws -- and it did have a

prescription for a solution -- analyse current elements, then combine

with charge fluids.

Weber solved this problem by deducing a force law from

, Ampere's law and a reasonable analysis of currents -- as I shall show

in Section 4. ,

Weber's law superceded Ampere's and Coulomb's laws. It

also predicted that there should be electrodynamic induction so, if

Faraday had not discovered induction, Weber would have done so. The

existence of induction was good evidence for Weber's law, and in turn

the A.A.D. programme. The most conservative claim that I make here is

that Weber's law, when it was proposed in 1846, accounted for all known

electrodynamic phenomena.

Far from being well received, Weber's law was subjected to

severe criticism which apparently damned it for once and for all. I

will show in Section 5 that not only was this criticism without foundation

but also that either it was known to be false or should have been known

to be false when first offered.

The A.A.D. heuristic suggested that Weber's law should be

replaced by a retarded force law. This line was followed by Riemann

and is discussed in Section 7.

Page 137: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

2. Sources and Receivers of Force :

The thesis 3' -- that the forces acting operate directly

between electrical atoms and not between conductors -- was naturally

, 1 assumed to be necessary for relating the laws of Coulomb and Ampere.

And as a result of 3', the A.A.D. programme took a new view of a

standard distinction. It was usual to distinguish ponderomotive

137

forces, which act between current carrying conductors, from electromotive

(which were often inductive) forces, which act on a current in a

conductor. The A.A.D. theorists regarded this distinction as spurious

only the one 'electric' force was needed.

Maxwell, on behalf of the Field programme, specifically

denied 3'

It must be carefully remembered, that the mechanical force which urges a conductor carrying a current across the lines of magnetic force, acts, not on 2he electric current, but on the conductor which carries it.

However, 3' was a theory which was consistent with the known

properties of electro-mechanical interaction and which steadily produced

novel facts in the years following its proposal. Everyone knew that

conductors are the receivers of magnetic force only if they are

bearing currents, and that a conductor bearing a current is affected in

direct proportion to the strength of that current while the size and

material of the conductor is a matter of indifference. And the bending

3 of a spark discharge by a magnetic field, and the properties of

1. See, for example, Weber (1848), 'On the Measurement of Electrodynamic Forces', page 511.

2. J.C.Maxwe11 (1873), A Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism, § 501.

3. Davy discovered this in 1821 -- see Phil. Trans. cxi, (1821), page 425.

Page 138: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

) 38

fluorescent discharge -- both known to Faraday -- become clearer under 3'.

Then there were the truly novel discoveries such as the Hall effect.

Let me quote again from Maxwell :

[the distribution of currents in conductors is independent of magnetic forcesJ

The only iorce which acts on electric currents is electromotive force •••

To this J.J.Thomson added in 1891 the editorial revision:

Mr. Hall has discovered •••• in [1880] .•• a steady magnetic field does slightly alter the distribution of cu~rents in most conductors, so the ~tatement ••• must be regarded as only approximately true.

In real English, 'only approximately true' means 'false'.

Hall himself describes the matter :

Sometime during the last University year, while I was reading Maxwell's 'Electricity and Magnetism' in connection with Professor Rowland's lectures, my attention was particularly attracted by the following passage in vol ii p. 144 :-

'It must be carefully remembered ••• [etc ~ •••• This statement seemed to me to be contrary to the most natural supposition in the case considered ••••

Soon after reading the above statement in Maxwell I read ••• in which the author evidently assumes that a magnet acts upon a current in a fixed conductor •••

Finding these two authorities at variance, I brought the question to Prof. Rowland. He told me he doubted the truth of Maxwell's statement •.•

I ••• hit up~n a method that seemed to promise a solution to the problem •••

A.A.D. electrodynamics, even in the form it was with Weber in the 1840's,

predicts the Hall effect.

1. Maxwell (l873), J 501. My italics.

2. Maxwell (l873) , § 501.

3. E.H.Hall (1879), 'On a New Action of the Magnet on Electric Currents'.

Page 139: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

The analysis 1'-3' as a whole predicted novel results, such

as the outcome of Rowland's convection current experiments. Rowland

explains

The experiments described in this paper were made with a view of determining whether or not an electrified body in motion produces magnetic effects. There seems to be no 1theoretical ground upon which we can settle the question ••••

Rowland was mistaken -- the A.A.D. programme predicted that there

would be 'magnetic' effects. But Helmholtz -- ever the vigourous

critic of A.A.D. electrodynamics -- was aware of the theoretical

relations

139

I understand by electric convection the conveyance of electricity by the motion of its ponderable bearers. In my last memoir on the theory of electrodynamics, I proposed some experiments (which were then carried out by Herr N.Schiller) in which the question came into consideration whether electric convection is dynamically equivalent to the flow of electricity in a conductor, as W.Weber's theory assumes. Those experiments might possibly have been decisive against the existence of such an action. They were not so; but, on the other hand, through this negative result the existence of the action in question remained unproved. Mr.Rowland has now carried out a series of direct experiments, in the physical laboratory of the University here, which give positive proof that the motion of electrified p~nderable substances is also electro­magnetically operative.

And he sums up :

As regards the signification of these experiments for the theory of electrodynamics, they correspond to the hypotheses of the theory of W.Weber; but they can also be referred to Maxwell's or to the potential-theory which tak~s account of the dielectric polarization of the insulators.

That is : the convection current experiments start life as an

intended crucial experiment against Weber's theory, but when the theory

1. H.A.Rowland (1878), 'On the Magnetic Effect of Electric Convection'.

2. H.Helmholtz (1876), 'On the Electromagnetic Action of Electric Convection', page 233.

3. Helmholtz (1876), page 237.

Page 140: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

passed the test Helmholtz argued that the Field theories can be

modified so as to entail the result. He concluded that the

convection current experiments become confirming instances of the

Field theories also. The M.S.R.P. imposes an entirely different

appraisal on the same theoretical relations the experiments are

evidence for the A.A.D. view but they are not evidence for the

Field view.

There were also genuine experimental difficulties which

appeared to beset 1'-3'. These too resulted in the discovery of

novel facts. Maxwell pointed out that the entire analysis faced

anomalies : accelerating conductors should exhibit inertial effects

such as 'inertial currents', but no such effects were known.l

However, mere anomalies do not affect the appraisal of a research

programme, and even Maxwell acknowledged that the expected effects

were small. Later, as experimental methods became more refined,

all of Maxwell's predictions, derived from A.A.D. views, were

2 discovered to occur.

3 instances.

The anomalies became triumphant confirming

1. Maxwell (1873) § 574-577.

140

2. See S.J.Barnett (1933), 'Gyromagnetic Effects Experiments'.

History, Theory, and

3. 3' also led to fruitful research outside the strict domain of electrodynamics. Weber worked extensively on the magnetic, electrical, and thermal properties of materials. In particular he tried to explain electrical resistance in terms of lattice molecular models. Weber's own research was not notably successful, but Weber's assistant Eduard Riecke developed the electron theory of metals and this approach led to the Drude-Lorentz electron gas models of conduction.

Page 141: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

141

3. Gauss -- The Unification of Electrodynamics and the Retardation

of Forces:

Gauss developed one key suggestion of the A.A.D. heuristic

and he highlighted another. The first was to unify electrodynamics by

rationally guessing a force law between electrical particles which ,

would link Coulomb's and Ampere's laws. Gauss produced such a force

law in 1835. 1 The law, in addition to providing the link, explained

some but not all the cases of electrodynamic induction -- so it

predicted novel facts. Gauss, though, regarded the law as provisional

and to be replaced. He thought it temporary because of the second

key idea: that A.A.D. inverse distance forces should propagate in

space and not be instantaneous:

I would doubtless have published my research long ago, if only, at the time I interrupted my work, what I considered to be the cornerstone had not still been missing.

Nil actum reputans si Quid superesset agendum [unfinished work counts for nothing]

And by that I mean the derivation of the additional forces (which are in addition to the reciprocal effect of passive electric particles, when they are in relative motion) from the effect which is not immediate, but (in a similar manner as with light) which propagates in time. I did not manage to do this then: but as far as I remember, I turned away from the investigation at th~t time not entirely without hope, that I would perhaps be successful later, although -if my memory is correct -- with the subjective conviction, that it would be first necessary to arrive at a construct­ible representation how this propagation takes place. 2

1. Gauss (1867), Werke,

F ... Q1Q2 -2-

r where u is the relative distance apart.

Vol. ~, page 616. The law was:

[ 1 + !2 [u2 - ~ (:~n]

velocity of the two 'charges' and r their

2. Letter to Weber, Werke, ~, page 629. Translated by Professor E.W. Herd. The German is convoluted. The Latin is a misquote of Lucan's description of Julius Caesar which emphasizes his demonic energy. It means literally: considering that nothing had been done, if anything remained to be done.

Page 142: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Gauss devoted most of his work in electrodynamics to appraising the

consequences of a propagated force.

It is fair to say that the A.A.D. heuristic did not

originally contain the strict instruction to retard the forces so

that they propagated. But all A.A.D. theorists -- working on gravity

or on electrodynamics -- thought that instantaneous propagation was

impossible. l All that was required was for someone to transform the

underlying assumption 'instantaneous propagation is impossible'

into the heuristic hint 'evaluate the consequences of a finite

propagation'. It was Gauss who provided that service for electro-

dynamics.

Gauss's ideas were to remain unpublished. In his eyes

they were incomplete he was an essentialist and regarded the

fact that he had not been able to explain the propagation itself

2 as a shortcoming. However, published or not, Gauss's ideas were

influential. Weber, Riemann, and others knew both that Gauss

regarded electrodynamics as being governed by a propagated force

acting between particles, and that Gauss had been to some extent

successful in these researches.

Gauss's deduction of his law was the pattern that Weber

followed in making his derivation. I give a full account of Weber's

derivation in Section 4, and point out there the alterations

needed to obtain Gauss's law.

1. In connection with this, see also my arguments in Chapter 1 Section 2.

2. See the letter to Weber quoted parlier.

142

Page 143: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Gauss did one other important piece of research in electro-

dynamics. He showed in 1835 that the phenomena of electrodynamic

induction could be described mathematically in terms of the rate of

change of a (nowadays the) vector potential A. This result is

generally attributed to Franz Neumann who published it in 1845. 1

This mathematical description enables us to see that Weber's law

does indeed yield all the types of electrodynamic induction -- this

is discussed further in Section 5.

1. Berlin Abhandlungen. (1845) page 1. F.E. Neumann produced several mathematical results of value to the A.A.D. programme -- the most important one was the connecting induction with variation in a vector potential. He first used Lenz's law to arrive at a flux­cutting description of electromagnetic induction for the case of a conductor moving in a magnetic field. He then considered the electrodynamic potential of two closed circuits under Amperian forces and found that the variations of this potential would yield an account of induction. In turn, this closed circuit potential could be split up into a 'vector potential' at a point of one circuit due to the other circuit. Thus mathematically induction was a function of variations in vector potential. Neumann was an A.A.D. theorist -- for him electrodynamics was about direct action at a distance -- but yet his work was away from the main line of development. He analyzed complete circuits, yet microanalysis of currents or current elements was required to link the laws of , Coulomb and Ampere.

14 '3

Page 144: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

4. Weber's Deduction of His Law:

My aim in this section is to show that, given the problem

situation and the problem solving techniques, A.A.D. naturally led

to Weber's law:

where r is the distance between charges, c is a constant of

1 proportionality, ql and q2 are the charge magnitudes, and Coulomb's

law for static charges has been added. Weber's theory was the

third and most complete in a sequence of A.A.D. attempts to solve

the problem by substituting for the trigonometrical functions in

Amp~re's law. Gauss's law of 1835 was the first. Fechner's

theory of 1845 was the second. 2 And both of these predicted

some, but not all, cases of induction.

" The heuristic generation starts with Ampere's law and

144

Fechner's account of currents and proceeds by deduction. At one point

an obvious guess has to be made -- so that while not logically

inevitable the process may be described as being heuristically

inevitable. Weber himself claims a necessary and sufficient link

" 3 between his law and Ampere's law. This claim is false, but could

justifiably have been thought to be true in the days before modern logic.

1. c appears because the force law combines Coulomb's force law for static charges, which uses one system of units, with Amp~re's law for moving charges, which uses a different system. c, the ratio of one unit to the other, was known to have the dimensions of a velocity. There is the further inessential complication that there were two units for currents, one being fi as big as the other. The result is that many of the historical equations have apparently mysterious factors of 2 which appear due to the units being switched. It was important for Weber to determine c but there were technical difficulties which prevented him (and Kohlrausch) from succeeding until 1855. Their value for c was J2 times the speed of light.

2. G.T. Fechner, Ann de Phys & Chim, 64 (1845), PR337-345.

3. I quote this claim at the end of my account of Weber's derivation.

Page 145: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

The deduction puns as follo~sl

Weber starts ~ith Amp~re's law for the aase ~here the

2 elements are in the same plane:

dF :: ids i 'ds' --,.-2-- 1 [sin a sin a' - 2 aos a aos a']

using the notation of Chapter 2.

Partial derivativ~B are substituted for the trigonometriaal

funations

_I ~~~ ____________ ~~~~, aj r r \"W

cos a ::

cos 8' =

(()r) ()s s'

=

sin e sin a' = r ()2r (because ()S dS' .

() - cos a' = -dS

sin e ,~' dS

so that:

dF =

r 0 a' = os sin a, therefore

,. l (ar ) == _ sin a' sin a). as as'

ids i 'ds [1 ar ar r 2 "2 as as'

(1)

and

(2)

1. I reconstruct Weber (1848) 'On the Measurement of Electrodynamic Forces'. I have changed and modernized notation for clarity -- any more substantial alterations are indicated in footnotes. Weber (1848) is a translation of his German (1848), which in turn is a short version of his (1846).

2. Actually Weber uses: - ids i 'ds'

dF :II - S r [cos t - ~ cos e cos 8 'J

t here is the angle of intersection flow of the current elements. That

, S' h e cos e + sin e sin ,so t e two

of the extension of the positive is, t .. (e - 8') and cos t - cos expressions are identical.

145

Page 146: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

146

TheFe aFe two '~uFFents' in eaah wiFe; if A and A'

aFe the lineaF ahaFge densities and v and v, the veloaities of

the aharges, then:

il = AV

i .. :r:t -A'V'

TheFe aFe four aurFent paiFs between the wiFes whi~h

pFovide fOF~es name the fOFaes dP l , dF2 , dP3 and dP.. .

The line elements ds and ds' now become split in half:

dSI and dSl' aFe the positive CUFrent line elements and dS 2 and

dS2' aFe the negative current line elements.

Applying equation (2) to each fOFce paiF:

aPl AV ,,"v' dSI dBI' [2. ~PI d:r>l a~rl ] = - 1'12 2, as} dB\ ' - F}

aSl as}' • •• (3)

dP2 = + AV :xv' dS I dB2' [2. dr2 d:r>2 a2r2 J 1'2 2 2, dS l dB2' - 1'2 aBl aS2'

• •• (4)

dF3 :Xv :Xv' dB2 dB2' [1- dr3 ar3 a~r3 J - - 1'3 2 2 aB2 dS2 - 1'3

aS2 dS 2 ' • •. (5)

dE = + AV ,,"v' dB2 dBI' [1- ~r ... dP,+ a~r .. J 1' .. 2 2 dB2 dSl - 1' ..

t- aB 1 de2' • •• (6)

At the moment the electrical masseB Fefe:r>Fed to are all in

dB and dB',

1'1 = 1'2 = :r>3 = 1',,(= 1')

eo the total for~e ie, from adding (3) - (6)

d - ~v ~v' as dB' [1:. Rl'l arl aF2 01'2 F - - 41'2 2 ae} as l' - as} aB2'

- l' • •• (7)

Page 147: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

N01J)~ 1'1 is a function of

S, II I

drl _ arl BO dt - aSI

but dSI is V at

therefore drl crt

and simi lar ly

dr2 dt

Fu.rther

dSl

at

and

=v

d2r~l. = 2 ~ dt v aSI

d2r2 v2 chr2 df'E"" = ~

1:~ = v2 a2r3

aS2 2

~:~ = v2 a2r 4

dS2 2

NoUJ,

r,

+ arl aB l'

as 1' at

dSl' is v, at

, 01'1 + v, arl dBI as l'

+ 2vv' a~rl as 1 dB l'

+ 2vv' chI" 2 aSI aB2'

+ 2vv' a2r~ a8 2a82'

+ 2vv' a2r 4

as 2 as l'

Bl and Sl'

-\\5 1

t

· .. (8)

• •. (9)

• •• (10)

• •• (11)

+ V,2 d2 r l dBI' 2 • •• (12)

+ V,2 c}ar2 OS2' 2

• •• (13)

+ V,2 a2r~ aS2' 2 • •• (14)

+ V,2 i}zr .. aSI' ~ • •• (15)

because they depend merely on the position and form of the first

147

Page 148: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

conducting wire.

Therefore f~m (12) - (15)

d2rl _ d2r~ + ~ ~ dt 2"" dt (It2 - dt 2

and squaring (8) - (11)

dr2 2 ar2 2 ar2 ar2 + V,2 ar 2 = v2 + 2vv' dt aS1 aSl as 2' aS2'

dr3 2 ar 3 2 arg arg + arg = v 2 + 2vv' V,2

dt as 2 aS2 as 2' as 2'

dr .. 2 ar .. 2 ar .. ar .. + ,2 ar .. = v 2 + 2vv'

dt aS2 aS2 as l' v aSl'

arl 2 ar2 2 ara 2 ar .. 2

(= ~ 2) Now aS I = aS I = aS2 = aS 2 as

arl 2 ar2 2 ar, 2 ar .. 2

(= k-2

) and = aSI' = aS2' aS2' a~ l' as'

beaause of their dependenae on the aonduating wires.

Therefore, from (17) - (20)

drl 2 dt

-1-2

2 -1_ 2 c.u" + ~ dt dt

ar 2 --!!.. dt

148

• •• (16)

• •• (17)

• •• (18)

• •• (19)

• •• (20)

Page 149: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Substituting (16) and (21) into (7)

A ds A ds' j-/ dro 1 2 dF = - 16r2 ( at dr2 2 + dr3 2 _ dr,. 2 )

dt dt dt /

- 2" (1;r - '1;/ + '1;" - '1;,,) )

Rewriting Qlq2[ ~ 2

dF = -~ dt _ 2rl d2 r 1 ]

dt 2

• •• (22)

••• (23)

Eaah of the four members in this expression refers exclusively to

~ of the four electric masses e.g. the first to the two positive

masses forming the positive CUlTents

Weber then continues :

Hence it is evident tbat if the entiN expression of the electrodynamic force of ~ elements of a current be considered as the sum of the forces, which each ttJo of the foW' electric masses they contain exert upon .• iJdh othe1', this swn wouUi be decomposed into its o~inal constituents, the four above members representing l ividualiy the four f01'ces which the foUl' electric masses in the two elements exert in pairs upon each other.

Hence also the force with which any positive or negative mass E acts upon any other positive or negative ~9f. s E', at the distance R, with a reZative velocity of ~ and acce leration ~ may be expressed j

0. ct. E£:. / /rJl. ) ~ _ 2 /l PI .. A! - W ~A.. lc..;cy ~

for this fundamental principle is necessary and at the same time sufficient to allow of the deduction of Amp~re's eZectro­dynamic laws ••• 1

1Weber (1848) page 518

149

Page 150: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

The addition of Coulomb's law gives the total result:

[To derive GaUSS'8 law~ veloaities and relative

veloaities (not partial derivatives) are sUb8tituted for aos t: ,

in Ampere's law (see 145 footnote 2) :

u=v-v'

u2 = v 2 _ 2vv' aos t + V,2

v 2 + V12

- u2

aos t = 2vv' Then the derivation

proaeeds as before~ but aonalude8

F = ~[1 + ~ [u 2 - ~ (drdt/]]] r a 2

I will now run over the strategy of the proof, make some

remarks on the assumptions, and refute Weber's claim of a ,

necessary and sufficient link between his law and Ampere's. ,

The proof opens with Ampere's law used ina plane.

This is not a special case since Amp~rian forces exist only for

coplanar elements. (Non-coplanar elements are projected onto

planes and non-coplanar projectio.ns exert no forces.)

An assumption is made about 'macro' currents being twin

'micro' currents. This Fechner's idea -- seems perfectly

reasonable. Equal quantities of positive and negative electricity

150

must be assumed, then the question 'is 'which of them move?' Both is

the best answer, since, at this time, there were no known

asymmetries between the electricities.

Then the force between macro-currents is taken to be

the sum of four forces between micro-currents. ,

Then Ampere's law is applied to each micro-current pair.

This step is a guess. And it is a little unusual in that micro-

Page 151: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

, currents have a resultant charge and so one would expect Ampere's

law not to apply. .. However, there was no other law -- Ampere's

was the only known current element law. The rational stance here ,

is to use Ampere's law and to expect that it needed correcting. ,

Notice that Weber's law cannot be proved from Ampere's law in its

micro-current form.

Amp~re's micro law

dP 2

and (d;)

For example, [1 arl

dF1 = 1"2 aSl

+

. tiF1 -- I' [(drdt

)2 - 2 .... 1 and Weber's law ~s L

\ so Ampere's = Weber's iff

V ,2 (arl )2 aS1'

which in general it will not.

V,2

Then the four micro forces are summed to obtain the macro

force.

The macro force is manifestly separable into four micro

components of identical form each linked to a micro-current pair.

The natural guess here is that each micro-current pair is governed

by a law of that form (Weber's law, in fact). There is no proof

at this point and Weber is mistaken in claiming that there is.

(Justification of my statement: ,

Amperian micro-current forces

are consistent with the macro force but inconsistent with Weber's

151

Page 152: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

law, hence Weber's law cannot be a logical consequence of the

macro force expression.) However, even though Weber's law is not

provable from the macro-force expression it is the most rational

guess as to an explanation of the macro force.

Notice that the rational guessing here is genuinely

content increasing. It starts with the special case of currents

in wires, and ends with a law that is intended to apply to all

moving charges whether, or not they are confined to wires.

152

Page 153: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

5. The Significance of the Law for the A.A.D. Programme :

Weber's law united the laws of Coulomb and Amp~re, and it

was not heuristically ad hoc. Further, it predicted the stunning

1 novel fact that there should be electrodynamic induction.

Electrodynamic induction phenomena, say between two wires,

may be considered as combinations of two basic types : where there is

only relative motion between the wires ('motional action'), and where

there is only variation in current ('transformer action').

Qualitatively, Weber's law accounts for these as follows.

The positive and negative electricities in the current carrying wire

153

move in opposite directions in the conductor and so, when the relative

motions between conductors is added on, do not move equal and oppositely

relative to the initially stationary positive (or negative) electricity

in the current-less wire; this means that there is a resultant force

on the positive (and negative) electricities in the initially current-

less conductor and so a current is induced. With transformer action,

it is the acceleration terms that lead to a resultant force. When

the current increases in the first wire the positive electricity accel-

erates in one direction and the negative electricity accelerates in

the opposite direction -- consequently, as the force depends both on

the sign of the charge and the first power of the acceleration, there

is a resultant force on the electricities in the second wire.

Quantitatively, Weber's law was shown to predict that induction

2 would be fully described by the rate of change of a vector potential.

1. 'Novel fact' is used here in the sense of Zahar. 'Why did Einstein's Programme Supersede Lorentz's 1', 'Logical Versus Historical Theories of Confirmation'.

See E.G.Zahar (1973), and A.E.Musgrave (1974),

2. See Weber (1848) pages 521-9, and Maxwell (1873) §856 and f.

Page 154: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

This means that Weber's law exactly accounts for all electrodynamic

induction phenomena.

To emphasize the strength of the A.A.D. programme here, I

will quote, then analyse, a section from Maxwell :

856.} After deducing from Ampere's formula for the action between the elements of currents, his own formula for the action between moving electrical particles, Weber proceeded to apply his formula to the explanation of the production of electric currents by magneto-electric induction. In this he was eminently successful, and we shall indicate the method

154

by which the laws of induced currents may be deduced from Weber's formula. But we must observe, that the circumstances that , a law deduced from the phenomena discovered by Ampere is able also to account for the phenomena afterwards discovered by Faraday does not give so much additional weight to the evidence for the physical truth of the law as we might at first suppose.

For it has been shown by Helmholtz and Thomson (see Art. , 543), that if the phenomena of Ampere are true, and if the principle of the conservation of energy is admitted, then the phenomena of induction discovered by Faraday follow of necessity. Now Weber's law, with the various assumptions about the nature of electric currents which it involves, leads by mathematical transformations , to the formula of Ampere. Weber's law is also consistent with the principle of the conservation of energy in so far that a potential exists, and this is all that is required for the application of the principle by Helmholtz and Thomson. Hence we may assert, even before making any calculations on the subject, that Weber's law will explain the induction of electric currents. The fact, therefore, that it is found by calculation to explain the induction of currents, leaves the evidtnce for the physical truth of the law exactly where it was.

The suggestions here are twofold: (a) that, ceteris paribus, the fact

that Weber's predicts induction constitutes good evidence for its truth,

and (b) that the ceteris paribus clause in (a) is violated because any ,

law 'equivalent' to Ampere's and consistent with the conservation of

energy must explain induction and so no special merit attaches to

1. Maxwell (1873) f 856.

Page 155: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

155

Weber's law by virtue of this feature. And many secondary sources

share this view; Woodruff, for example, writes:

With this law of force, Weber proceeded to explain the phenomenon of electromagnetic induction, and thereby to unify the treatment of all the electrostatic and electromagnetic effects known in his day. However, Helmholtz, •.• and William Thomson demonstrated the intimate connection , between the Amperian force, the conservation of energy and electromagnetic induction, by deriving the last (with some restrictions) from the first two. Thus any theory which satisfied the energy principle, and yielded the ponderomotive force expressed in Amp~re'y law, would be expected to imply the inductive effects.

I maintain that the suggestion (b) is false. and that Maxwell

should have been aware of the insufficiency of his argument. ,

Induction cannot be explained by'Ampere's law' and the

conservation of energy because induction generally involves two or

more circuits, and thus the division of energy between two circuits,

and the conservation of energy imposes only one constraint. No

predictions can be made, and thus no satisfactory explanations can

3 be offered.

Maxwell should have known this -- he was the most accomplished

mathematical physicist of his day and would have known full well the

analGgous triviality that the conservation of energy alone cannot

2 determine the equations of motion of a system with two degrees of freedom.

Maxwell must have had some misgivings about his argument. He

appeals in the quoted passage to papers by Helmholtz and Thomson.

1. A.E.Woodruff (1962), 'Action at a Distance in Nineteenth Century Electrodynamics', page 445, his italics; and see also C.W.F.Everitt's 'J.C.Maxwell' article in the Diet.Sci.Biog., page 206.

2. It seems that Maxwell had a blind spot here. On the one hand, he must have known that the conservation of energy alone would not determine the behaviour of simple systems like colliding billiard balls. But see his (1877), Matter and Motion IX, 9, and Larmor's Appendix II to that volume, especially page 158 and f.

3. See also A.O'Rahilly (1965), Electromagnetic Theory, Ch.4, Section 4.

Page 156: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

156

These papers offer energy equations to account for induction, but

these are successful only if all the forms of energy that are involved

are known and can be summed. In this application some of the types

of energy were newly discovered: the chemical energy of the batteries,

and the heat energy from the wires, for example. It is easy to

produce an energy equation to 'account for' induction, once induction

is known; in contrast, it is formidable to sum over types of energy

and to predict, and thus genuinely explain, that energy re-appears

as the energy of induced currents. Take, as an illustration of the

difficulties, the theory of the electric cell as it was in 1855 :

the cell loses energy and the circuit gains energy but the one does

not equal the other; the cell is a heat pump and works, using energy,

to pump energy from the surroundings into the circuit. Maxwell would

have been aware of the problems. And he would have known that Thomson,

in his paper, proves that Helmholtz's paper is fallacious as Helmholtz

1 2 had omitted the energy stored in the magnetic field. '

The rational scientist of the mid-nineteenth century should have

been wary of the connection between energy arguments and induction; and

he should have appreciated that Weber's force law operates from first

principles to predict all the effects.

1. Thomson's reasoning -- which approximates to the modern theory -- appears in four main papers which are reprinted in W.Thomson (1872), Papers on Electrostatics and Magnetism.

2. Helmholtz himself was later to describe the electrodynamic section of his paper as follows : 'The chapter on electro-dynamics in my treatise was written under great difficulties. At that time I scarcely had access to any mathematical and physical literature [He had seen only isolated portions of the works of Poisson, Green, and Gauss] , and was almost wholly confined to what 1 could discover for myself.' Quoted from L. Koenigsberger (1906), Hermann von Helmholtz., page 119. .

Page 157: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

157

6. Criticisms of the Law and Their Evaluation :-

The M.S.R.P. evaluates merit primarily by the presence of

positive success and not by the absence of failure, anomaly, or

inconsistency it directs the historian's attention away from

criticisms of laws or programmes. However, I wish to leave the

direction of the M.S.R.P. for a moment. I have the view that the

A.A.D. programme has been harshly treated and in further defence of

that thesis I will now look at criticisms of Weber's law.

The law was not well received. Helmholtz stated that the

1 law violated the conservation of energy, and this allegation was

2 used by Field theorists (and many historians) as a damning criticism

of A.A.D. electrodynamics. In 1855 Maxwell wrote :

There are objections to making any ultimate force in nature depend on the velocity ••• the principle of Conservation of 3 Force requires that these forces .•. be functions of distance only.

and in 1864 he wrote :

••• apparatus may be constructed to generate any amount of work from its own resources ••• I think that these remarkable deductions from ••• Weber['~theory ••• can only be avoided ~y recognizing the action of the medium in electrical phenomena.

Similar statements can be found in the publications of most of the

1. H.Helmholtz (1847), 'On the Conservation of Force', page 114.

2. For example, Berkson in his (1974), Fields of Force, writes on page 131 : 'One of the chief difficulties of the action-at-a-distance theories was their violation of the conservation of energy'.

3. Scientific Papers, v.l, page 208. It took a long while for Maxwell to change his mind over the question of whether Weber's law contradicted the conservation of energy. That is why these early passages are incons­istent with the later passage that I quoted in the last section.

4. I have quoted this from 0'Rahi11y (1965), page 529. Actually O'Rahilly has misquoted and concatenated two sections. In 1864 Maxwell tells us that Weber's law faces mechanical difficulties (Scientific Papers, v.1, page 527), and in 1868 Maxwell tells us that these mechanical difficulties are in fact those of leading to a perpetual motion machine (Scientific Papers, v.2, page 137). See also Scientific Papers,v.I, page 488.

Page 158: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

1 English Field theorists.

I will expose much of this for the nonsense that it is.

I will show:

a) that Helmholtz's refuting principle is false and his argument for it invalid;

b) that Weber's argument for the consistency of his law with the conservation of energy is a good argument;

158

c) that Weber's argument can no longer be taken as being persuasive; d) that Whittaker's (and O'Rahilly's) modern proof that the law

and the conservation of energy are consistent is again a good argument;·.

e) that Whittaker's (and O'Rahilly's) proof is faulty.

The clearest approach is the one used by Maxwell in the last

2 quote : discuss perpetual motion machines and their impossibility.

Perpetual motion machines may be roughly characterized as isolated systems

which start in one state, produce work, and yet return to exactly that

state; then the system can be repeatedly run through the cycle to

produce work ad infinitum. Isolation prevents the system from doing

work at the expense of energy that it obtains from elsewhere; cyclical

operation prevents the system from working indefinitely by virtue of

special initial conditions.

Now let us consider the arguments.

Helmholtz based. his on the principle 'All velocity dependent

forces must violate the conservation of energy' which he claimed to

1. See O'Rahilly (1965), page 530.

2. I do this because in the mid-nineteenth Century the Conservation of Force was a mechanical principle without direct application to electrodynamics, and the Conservation of Energy was a new principle which, in a manner of speaking, was regularly being refuted with the discovery of new forms of energy. What lay behind these conservation laws was the thesis that there could be no perpetual motion machine.

Page 159: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

159

1 have the backing of his 'Conservation of Force' paper. But Helmholtz's

principle is false -- a trivial counter-example occurs when the force

is always perpendicular to the velocity, such a force can do no work

and thus cannot form the basis of a perpetual motion machine. If

the English Field theorists Maxwell and Thomson had considered whether

Helmholtz's principle was true, they could have hardly failed to see

2 that it was false. It was even not at all unusual to argue that the

velocity dependent frictional forces were consistent with the conservation

of energy. What about Helmholtz's proof? In the 'Conservation of

Force'paper he shows that from assumption A 'all forces depend only

on distance' conclusion B 'the Conservation of Force' follows. He

then triU ~ a'a"e. that from not-A 'not all forces depend only on distance'

(for example, there are velocity dependent forces) not-B 'violation of

the Conservation of Force' follows ! Maxwell's later reconstruction of

this reads :

••• in establishing by mathematical reasoning the well-known principle of the conservation of energy, it is generally assumed that the force acting between the two particles is a function of the distance only, and it is commonly stated that if it is a function of anything else, such as the time, or the velocity of the particles, the proof would not hold.

Hence a law of electrical action, involving the velocity of the particles, has sometimes been supposed to ~e inconsistent with the principle of the conservation of energy.

In short, the condemnation of Weber's law rested on the logical blunder

'If A, then B' therefore 'If not-A, then not-B'.

1. Helmholtz (1847).

2. The case is more complex than I have suggested. Maxwell and Thomson may have assumed that the forces are central and acting between two particles if so the F x v counter-example would have been obscured. However, Weber himself 'refuted' the principle, as I show in the next paragraph of the text, and Maxwell and Thomson must have known this.

3. Maxwell (1873), f852.

Page 160: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

160

Weber's response to Helmholtz's attack was to publish

immediately -- in 1848 -- the spatial integral for his force :

1 r [ 1 - ~2

c

The existence of this potential is a strong argument that the law

cannot lead to a perpetual motion machine. The work done by this

force on a charged particle is linked to the particle's position and

velocity in such a way that if a particle starts in one state (presumably

here this means that the particle has a specific charge, position, and

momentum (velocity» and finishes in the same state, there is no

change in potential. The kinetic energy and the potential energy

of the particle sum to a constant. Once this potential was known

in the absence of other arguments -- all criticism concerning violation ,

of conservation of energy should have stopped. But it took nearly

1 thirty years for the Field theorists to acknowledge their errors.

Looking briefly at the problem in modern terms. If we

consider path integrals of force laws in a distance, velocity, acceleration

phase-space, then the existence of a scalar"Y' such that F .. - grad 1/1 is neither necessary nor sufficient for the work done by F around an

arbitrary loop to be zero. This seems to mean that in absolute terms

Weber's argument is not strong enough. But there are many subtleties

here. Whittaker and O'Rahilly have proved that the law does not violate

the conservation of energy, using Lagrangian and variational methods.

1. The English Field theorists presumably learned of Weber's law from the 1852 translation of his paper. This paper contains the spatial integral (on page 520) -- yet the Field theorists still alleged that there was violation of the conservation of energy. Secondary sources also go astray here. For instance, Everitt holds that Weber did not refute the energy arguments until 1869 and by then Maxwell had produced a better theory of electromagnetism; see his 'Maxwell' article in the Dict.Sci.Biog., page 205.

Page 161: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Their proofs too are not strong enough. In essence the method is to

show that there is a precisely analogous mechanical system for which

1 the conservation of energy holds. This means that a system of

particles moving in the phase space in any closed path available to

16 t

them under Weber's law do no work. But this is insufficient. There

may be other closed loops in the phase space around which work may be

done. Let me explain. A force must be used to make a particle travel,

and in general the assumption is made that there is a suitable driving

force to give access to all paths in the phase space. But if restrictions

are imposed on the driving force, certain paths may become inaccessible.

For example, if there were only two particles and they were governed

by a purely repulsive force, then if one is released it will travel to

infinity and will not return under its own force -- there will be no closed

path in the phase space, and so no path around which work is done; but

the particle may be brought back n-o,.tt Cl\ clc..st-t1AtCL to its original position,

momentum, and acceleration using another type of driving force, and then

it becomes an open question as to whether the repulsive force does work

around the loop. Whittaker's and O'Rahilly's proof restricts the

driving forces to Weberian forces, and this is too much of a special case.

Their proof shows that if there are only Weberian forces, then no perpetual

motion machine can be constructed on the basis of Weber's force law.

But the A.A.D. theorists always assumed that gravitational forces could

1. The proofs appear in Sir E.T.Whittaker (1951), A History of Theories of Aether and Electricity, page 203 and O'Rahilly (1965), page 530 and f.

Page 162: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

162

be used on the electrical fluids, either directly, by virtue of the

fluids having mass, or indirectly, by virtue of the fluids being able

to attach to ponderable bodies. Whittaker's and O'Rahilly's proof is

insufficient. And in fact, if one particle is fixed at the origin,

and another travels from x - 1 to x c 2 and back under Weber's law,

then conservation of CD4' w.. 1

energy ;.... violated. (Whittaker's proof shows

that there is no way that Weberian forces could produce such a motion.)

To return to the history. Helmholtz continued and diversified

his opposition to Weber's law. He blindly carried on asserting that

physicS allowed of no velocity dependent forces, and he offered the new

objection that Weber's law led to absurd instabilities. 2 This had little

influence historically as it was always in the shadow of the major objection

that conservation of energy was violated. But it is worthwhile to

consider it briefly. Helmholtz put forward a sequence of thought-experimental

absurdities. In the main these consisted of initial conditions which

would provide a large (possibly infinite) amount of energy, usually by

virtue of the negative term in Weber's force law which can lead to a particle

having apparently negative mass and thus accelerating itself in a

resisting medium. (As a parenthetical remark, the last paragraph mo.~

clarif~ an apparent inconsistency in Helmholtz's position : by this time

he accepted Weber's proof that no perpetual motion machine could be

constructed from the law, and yet he was offering thought-experimental

1. Such violations are not always significant. Accelerating electrons radiate energy and so driving an electron around a loop should be inconsistent with the conservation of energy, but any inconsistencies should be accounted for by the radiated energy. I think that Weber's law is still deficient here (unless, of course, there is a new type of radiated energy which has not yet been discovered.)

2. See A.E.Woodruff (1968), 'The Contributions of Hermann von Helmholtz to Electrodynamics', pages 304-6, and references therein.

Page 163: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

163

perpetual motion machines relying on the law -- these latter machines

used forces in addition to the Weberian one.) Weber objected to

the initial conditions in some of these examples -- one required

sub-atomic dimensions and speeds over half that of light. I suggest

that mere absurdities are not sufficient, they should be converted

into failed experiments. I offer two arguments. It is one of the

glories of science that many 'absurdities' have actually occurred,

so theories should not be ruled out simply because they suggest

new effects our limited imagination should not act as a constraint

on a theory. Listen to Ritz discussing Relativity

The result is that it has been found necessary to abandon the classical concept of universal time, to make simultaneity a quite relative notion, to suppress the concept of the inva~iability of mass as well as that of rigid bodies, to abandon the axioms of kinematics and the parallelogram of velocities, It is curious and worth noting that a few years ago it would have been thought sufficient, in order to refute a theory, to show that it entyiled only one or other of the consequences here enumerated.

Secondly, the attempt at realizing an absurdity may disarm it. For

example, Coulomb's law on its own leads to 'absurd' instabilities

there can be no stable equilibrium in a charge-free electric field,

2 so a charge released there may pr~duce an infinite amount of energy.

(But, to realize the situation experimentally charges must be used to

produce the field and then the roaming charge will not deliver an

infinite amount of energy.)

1. W.Ritz (1908b), 'A Critical Investigation of Maxwell's and Lorentz's Electrodynamic Theories'.

2. For stability, displacement must produce a restoring force. That flux E over a surface containing the pOint cannot be zero; so div E cannot be zero, which is impossible in a charge-free region.

is.

Page 164: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

lh4

~:.-I<.jemann's Attempt to Deduce Weber's Law from a Propagated Force Law

The history of Riemann's contribution to electrodynamics is

briefly told. In 1858 he offered the world his 'discovery of the

1 connection between electricity and light' , and this consisted of

the retardation of the Coulomb scalar potential ~ .2 But no sooner

had he submitted the paper to the Gottingen Royal Society than he

withdrew it, possibly because he realized that it contained a mathematical

error. The paper was published posthumously in 1867 and was then

criticized by Clausius for the mathematically incorrect permutation

3 of two integrals. In the same year -- 1867 -- Ludwig Lorenz presented

his theory in which both the scalar potential f and the vector potential A

4 are retarded.

Riemann's theories were inadequate. He retarded the Coulomb

potential and incorrectly derived from this a force law similar to

Weber's force law. The Riemann force law made no successful predictions

to make it preferable to that of Weber.

However, Riemann's paper is still important. Its value

lies as an easily understood piece of evidence for the objective

problem situation and the techniques that would be used for solving

1. B.Riemann, Letter to his Sister, quoted from Rosenfeld (1957), page 1634.

2. See B.Riemann (1867), 'A Contribution to Electrodynamics'.

3. R.Clausius (1869), 'Upon the New Conception of Electrodynamic Phenomena Suggested by Gauss'. A distance integral and a time integral are permuted and in this case, with a moving particle, the order of integration is important.

4. L.Lorenz (1867), 'On the Identity of the Vibrations of Light and Electrical Currents'.

Page 165: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

165

that problem. Of course, one swallow does not a summer make -- but

Riemann was not alone. Gauss tried to retard forces, Carl Neumann

retarded potentials to obtain his father's vector potential induction

laws, Betti retarded potentials, and Ludwig Lorenz retarded the scalar

1 and vector potential. And Weber himself wrote to Gauss in 1845

••• the nicest solution to the puzzle [of electrodynamic action-at-a-distance] would be its exp~anation on the basis of a gradual propagation of the force.

The problem was to produce a retarded force law which would

yield Weber's law or an approximation to it. Such a theory might be

expected to provide an electric or 'electromagnetic' theory of light.

A remark is called for here on the relationship between electricity

and light. I think that it was virtually part of background knowledge

at this time that the two would be connected, for such a link opens

up the possibility of an explanation of Faraday's results of the 1840's

3 on the magnetic rotation of the plane of polarization of light.

Light was known to be propagated with speed c, electrical action was

1. C.Neumann (1868), Betti (1868)~ and Lorenz (1867).

2. This letter of the 31 March 1845 is quoted on page 68 of Karl Heinrich Wiederkehr. Wilhelm Webers Stellung in der Entwichlung der Elektrizitatslehre. (diss. University of Hamburg, 1961). I read it in K.L.Caneva (1978), 'From Galvanism to Electrodynamics: The Transformation of German Physics and Its Social Context'. page 100; but so late as to prevent checking with the original source.

3. Note, for instance, the Riemann quote on the previous page, the Gauss passage quoted in Section 4.3. and the Thomson passage quoted in Section 1.8.

Page 166: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

thought to be propagated -- a reasonable guess was that the latter

1 also travelled at speed c and that light was electrical in nature.

166

Instantaneous and retarded functions can often be integrally

transformed one to another -- for example, if the present position

of a particle is given as an explicit function of its past position

and its acceleration as a function of time. In these cases, A.A.D.

theorists would regard the retarded law as the physically significant

one -- that is, the one in need of further explanation. In the 1840's

Weber's instantaneous law should have been taken as an approximation to

the truth about electrodynamic phenomena -- the search was for a more

fundamental retarded law that would underpin it.

I suggest that Riemann's idea was this. Weber's law is

merely Coulomb's law with additional velocity and acceleration terms,

and these terms are significant only if there is relative motion between

the particles. Further, there must be relative motion or change to

distinguish between an instantaneous and a retarded force function

an instantaneous signal and a signal taking time can be told apart only

if a signal is sent. Riemann's idea was that Coulomb's law required

the additional velocity and acceleration terms because it was instantaneous

whereas it should have been retarded.

Riemann took Coulomb's law stated in the scalar potential form

governed by Laplace's equation:

Vl--4n-o-and retarded

1. The constant c appears as the velocity of light, it also appears in Weber's law and similar laws as a ratio of dynamic and static electrical units having the dimensions of a velocity -- that the two 'c's' were identical (except for, perhaps JT factors) becomes apparent only with the work of Riemann, Weber, and Kirchoff.

Page 167: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

it at speed c, substituting a D'Alembertian for the Laplacian

Riemann then incorrectly derived from this D'Alembertian equation an

1 approximation to Weber's law.

167

In heuristic reconstruction the history would have developed

as follows. Sound derivation would have shown that an electric

current or charge in uniform motion produces forces over and above

a retarded Coulomb force -- Riemann's error in supposing that a

retarded scalar potential, was equivalent to an instantaneous scalar

potential+ together with an instantaneous vector potential A, which

were then assumed to be the complete basis of electrodynamics, would

have been uncovered. Some vector potential or remnants of a vector

potential would have to be used. The second step would be to extend

the retardation to the existing vector potential A so that it too

propagated in space th1s would yield all the known results, and in

addition would have predicted the full electromagnetic theory of light.

The actual history is slightly deviant. Ludwig Lorenz

omitted one of the intermediate steps. He sought an electromagnetic

theory of light and a desideratum he imposed was that such a theory

should yield the Fresnel formulas for reflection and refraction, which

he had described by means of a vector equation governing the boundary

conditions of the light vector. He then asked, 'How can the Weber-

Kirchoff equations be modified to yield that vector equation ?' and

1. These mathematical equations introduce an extra physical solution. The idea of retarding forces is that the force propagates outward from a source, but a D'Alembertian has advanced solutions as well as retarded ones and so ia not true to the physical ideas. That 1s, it is not ad hoc for A.A.D. theorists to discard the advanced solutions.

Page 168: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

he noticed that this question had a unique answer -- by retarding + and! at speed c. A retarded + and A are consequences of knowledge

on reflection and refraction and A.A.D. background knowledge on

electrodynamics.

168

Page 169: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

8. Electrical Actions Propagated at the Speed of Light :-

During the 1850's Weber and Kirchoff developed the theory

1 of transmission lines. Their approach is similar to the modern

treatment except that Weber's force law and vector potential are

1~9

used to eliminate self-induction and capacitance from the calculations.

The outcome was a set of equations, depending on Weber's theory,

which predicted the velocity of an electrical disturbance down

a wire. These equations constitute part of the

problem situation for Ludwig Lorenz's theory of light and they will

be discussed further in that context in Chapter 6.

What has to be noted is that Weber and Kirchoff knew that

the velocity of current waves (and so on) in suitable wires was that

of light, and they also pointed out that under their theory this

2 velocity' was the ratio of the electrical units.

1. This appears in Kirchoff (1857a), 'Uber die Bewegung der Electricitat in Drahten', Kirchoff (1857b), 'Uber die Bewegung der Electricitat in Leitern', and Weber (1864), Electrodynamische MaasBbestimmungen, IV, page 105.

2. Some idea of the subtlety of Weber's investigations may be gained from his suggestions for determining a link between charge and mass of electrons. For him a current disturbance was akin to a wave in a plasma and its velocity of propagation was damped by a factor of frequency related to the charge and mass of ions.

Page 170: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

9. Summary :

In this Chapter I have :

a) shown that the A.A.D. views on the sources and receivers of force

were superior to those of the rival Field programme,

b) argued that the A.A.D. programme united Amp~re's and Coulomb's

170

laws by a process akin to deduction to yield Weber's law -- the objective

problem situation and the problem-solving techniques were such that

A.A.D. theorists would arrive at Weber's law or a law similar to it,

c) concluded that since Weber's law was produced in this way and it

predicted electrodynamic induction, it constituted good evidence for

the A.A.D. programme,

d) refuted Maxwell, Woodruff, and Everitt on the evidential relationship

between electrodynamic induction, Weber's law, and the conservation

of energy,

e) refuted Maxwell, Helmholtz, Berkson, and others over their arguments

concerning Weber's law and the conservation of energy,

and

f) argued that the A.A.D. programme would lead to a retarded potential

approach to electrodynamics, independently of developments elsewhere.

Page 171: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

17 J

Chapter 5 Maxwell's Theories of Electromagnetism.

1. Introduction.

2. The Early Theory of 'On Physical Lines of Force'.

3. A Critical Appraisal of 'On Physical Lines of Force' and of the

Theses of Hejmann and Bromberg Concerning It.

4. The Later Theory.

5. A Critical Appraisal of the Later Theory.

6. Summary.

Page 172: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

1. Introduction:

By 1860 the Field programme had acquired the ability to

solve problems. But did it ever surpass its rival? The key issue

here is the electromagnetic theory of light. Most commentators

would regard the thesis that the A.A.D. programme was the better one

as somewhat unusual but on reflection, and perhaps on consideration

of my arguments, they would admit that the thesis was sound until

1860. But they would qualify their admission. Surely, they would

add, the electromagnetic theory of light, developed during the 1860's

gave the Field programme its decisive victory?

172

I think not, and I argue the point in the next two Chapters.

It was Maxwell who developed the Field theories of light,

and he did so in four publications: 'On Physical Lines of Force'

(1862), 'A Dynamical Theory of the Electromagnetic Field' (1865), 'On

a Method of Making a Direct Comparison of Electrostatic with Electro­

magnetic Force: with a Note on the Electromagnetic Theory of Light'

(1868), and the Treatise on Electricity' and Magnetism (1873). I

regard the theories here as being in two groups. There is what I

will call the early theory of 'On Physical Lines of Force', and

there is the later theory which was proposed and refined in the other

publications. The theories will be assessed carefully in this

Chapter using the M.S.R.P. -- particular attention will be paid to

the questions of whether the theories were heuristically integrated

to the Field programme, and whether they predicted novel facts.

My approach -- that of assessing Maxwell's theories in

their own terms -- may be contrasted with the method used by most

historians. Many writers are led by excessive hindsight into

insoluble problems. The modern theory of electrodynamics yields

an electromagnetic theory of light and it does so by virtue of the

Page 173: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

term involving the time variation of the electric field (the 'dis-

placement current'). Some historians search for the discoverer of

the displacement current and think their venture is satisfied by

Maxwell. But Maxwell's 'displacement current', which was not much

more than the aether stepping sideways, has very different properties

to the modern 'displacement current'. At this point these writers

either do an injustice to Maxwell or retreat into such empty phrases

as 'the germ of the modern idea' or the 'glimmer of the displacement

current' • And they invent stories as to why Maxwell introduced the

'displacement current'. Two such myths can be briefly disposed of.

He did not realize that the equations:

curl B = .1 (Ampere's equation relating magnetic force and

current)

div 1.' = - ~ (Continuity) Ot:

were inconsistent and seek to remedy this by adding the displacement

1 current term. And it was not a desire for symmetry that led him

to introduce the displacement current.2

The truth is -- as we shall

see -- that there is nothing original to Maxwell that is closely

related to the modern 'displacement current'.

1. The inconsistency is that div curl!!. = 0 so div i. = - 4 ;t o. (j.E... Physicists offer the r~ional reconstruction that Maxwelf~added e'~ so that curl ~ = (1 + a ) • This is historically incorrect. See J. Bromberg (1967), 'Maxwell's Displacement CUrrent and His Theory of Light'.

2. In a charge and current free region the pre-Maxwell versions of 'MaxWell's equations' were: a-

div E = 0 curl E = - ,,~

Div B .. 0 curl B ". 0 dffs. and so, it has been said, Maxwell made curl B = + ~ to obtain symmetry. This is mistaken. See A.M. Bark (1963), 'Maxwell, Displacement Current, and Synnetry', and J. Bromberg ( 1967) •

173

Page 174: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

174

Maxwell's theories -- especially the later one -- are easier

to understand if viewed in the light of three theses which I maintain

form the skeleton of his ideas

i) that all charge is polarization charge,

ii) that polarization is a mechanical stress in the aether,

and

iii) that the vacuum is a polarizable dielectric.

Thesis (iii) is the Helmholtz A.A.D. interpretation of

1 Maxwell's theories. It enables the Maxwell view to be expressed in

terms of the then existing A.A.D. electrodynamics. and in fact most

scientists of the period understood Maxwell's theories in this way.

(That is why Hertz's experiments on radiated electromagnetic waves

2 3 were taken as a proof that the vacuum is a polarizable dielectric. ' )

One consequence of the A.A.D. theories using source fluids. which was

presumably unknown until Maxwell derived it in his (1865). is that there

can be transverse electromagnetic (e.m.) waves in dielectrics. For

Maxwell these waves should also occur in the vacuum, since the vacuum

is a polarizable dielectric. This consequence, although previously

unknown, was in harmony with background knowledge. No scientist

acquainted with the then standard result that conductors support longitudinal

current waves propagating at the speed of light would have been surprised

to be told ~hat dielectrics should support transverse current waves

propagating at the speed of light.

1. See Helmholtz (1870). 'Ueber die Theorie der Elektrodynamik'.

2. Historians, with hindsight sharpened by relativity theory, have re-written this story.

3. See, for instance. C.F.Fitzgerald's opening address to the annual meeting of the British Association for the Advancement of Science, 1888. reprinted in Fitzgerald (1902) pages 229 and f.

Page 175: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

But thesis (iii) does not do full justice to Maxwell's

views. Maxwell did not hold merely that the vacuum was polarizable.

Had he done so there would still be the source charges to cause this

polarization and then, for instance, a charged capacitor with empty

space between its plates would carry both a free charge and a

polarization charge. No, polarization was not to be the result of

free charges acting on a vacuum, it was instead to replace free

charges. Electrical sources such as fluids or electrons were not

to be permitted. As Maxwell put it, in a revealing passage:

Bodies .•• are said to be electrified, or charged with electricity. These words are mere names given to a peculiar condition of matter

In speaking of a quantity of electricity, we need not conceive of it as a separate thing, or entity distinct from ponderable matter, any more than in speaking of sound we conceive it as having a distinct existence. Still it is convenient to speak of the intensity or velocity of sound, to avoid tedious circumlocution: and quite similarly we may speak of electricity, withoyt for a moment imagining that any real electric fluid exists.

It should be noted that this was written in a British Association

for the Advancement of Science Report and consequently represents

Maxwell's judgement as to the objective truth and not merely a

speculation that he thought merited public attention. For Maxwell,

apparent sources were the outcome of a mechanical 'displacement' in

the medium. Polarization currents, in one direction, then become

displacement currents, possibly in the opposite direction.2

Some

1. J.C. MaxWell and Fleeming Jenkin (1863), 'On the Elementary Relations between Electrical Measurements', page 136. Fleeming Jenkin was one of Maxwell's students.

175

2. See also my Chapter 1 Section 6. Passages expressing this may be found in all of Maxwell's later publications on electromagnetism -­see for instance, his (1868) page 139 or his (1873) J 62, A Ill. , ,:r And see also J. Bromberg (1968), 'Maxwell s Electrostatics'.

Page 176: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

deficiencies in his theory originate here. For example, Maxwell

never derived the Fresnel formulas for the reflection and refraction

of light: this is no accident -- he was unable to: all three

components of a 'displacement' strain must be continuous across the

boundary of two media or else the two media lose contact with each

other; with this condition the Fresnel formulas are unavailable; one

might say that the Fresnel formulas 'refute' Maxwell's electro­

mechanical theory of light.l

Another instance is the persistent

difficulty with signs -- his (1862) has two complementing errors of

sign, his (1865) contains a formal contradiction, and his subsequent

publications inherit the ghost of this contradiction. These all

arise as follows. The displacement strain, or polarization, or

displacement must be in the same direction as the electric force,

that is D~+ ~, then for charge to be the result of displacement div

Q~- f, but the standard Coulomb law of electrostatics makes div

E~+ p; and these three conditions are incompatible.

It is often stated that Maxwell's novel contribution was

his postula~ion of a displacement current which was akin to the

conduction current in producing magnetic effects. In this vein

Simpson writes:

•• it is bold hypothesis to assert, as Maxwell did without empirical evidence even at the t~e of the Treatise, that these hypothetical momentary currents would produce the same magnetic effects as conduction currents in wires. 2,3

176

1. See Sir E.T. Whittaker (1951), A History of Theories of Aether and Electricity, page 266.

2. T.K. Simpson (1966), 'Maxwell and the Direct Experimental Test of His Electromagnetic Theory', page 413.

3. See also, for example, J.J. Thomson (1893), Notes on Recent Researches in Electricity and Magnetism, page vii.

Page 177: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

1 This is not true. For Maxwell the displacement current is a

polarization current and polarization currents -- as transient flows

of electrical fluids -- had been part of A.A.D. background for at

2 least twenty years. That these polarization currents should

produce magnetic effects was also part of background. Simpson is

completely mistaken when he writes:

••. it would be the tru1y crucial evidence for Maxwell's displacement current, namely, the direct demonstration of a magnetic fi~ld produced by varying polarization of a dielectric.

All A.A.D. theorists regarded polarization currents and conduction

currents as being identical; and specifically under Weber's force

law conduction currents, polarization currents, and equal and

opposite convection currents, all merited the same treatment. I

must emphasize that the A.A.D. view was not one account among many

. 4 it was the only common V1ew.

More sophisticated authors argue that Maxwell's contrib-

ution was in identifying the static electrical force with the induced

electrical force in so far as both were able to cause polarization

in a dielectric. This also is not true. 5 A.A.D. theorists had

been identifying ponderomotive, inductive, and electromotive electric

1. See also H. Hertz (1884), 'On the Relations between Maxwell's Fundamental Electromagnetic Equations and the Fundamental Equations of the Opposing Electromagnetics'.

2. The twenty years run back to Weber and Fechner -- it can be argued that the figure should be forty years, which run back to Poisson.

3. T.K. Simpson (1966), page 429.

177

4. See my Chapter 1 Section 6. Maxwell and Faraday remained silent on the questions of the nature of conduction current and of how dielectrics work. In contrast, the A.A.D. theorists explained conduction currents as a flow of electrical fluids, and they explained the surface charge of dielectrics as the outcome of a momentary flow of electrical fluids.

5. See H. Hertz (1884).

Page 178: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

I forces for again at least twenty years.

What is novel to Maxwell, or to the Faraday-Maxwell trad­

ition, is the thesis that the vacuum is a dielectric.4

The views that I have expressed in the last paragraphs

are not entirely new. Hertz argued them in 1891. He mentions

three hypotheses:

1. that changes of dielectric polarization produce the same electromagnetic forces as do the currents which are equivalent to them;

2. that electromagnetic [electrodynamic] forces as well as electrostatic are able to produce

2dielectric polarizations;

3. that the vacuum is a dielectric;

and he writes:

But while I was at work it struck me that the center of interest in ••• [Maxwell's] theory did not lie in the consequences of the two hypotheses. If it were shown that these were correct for any given insulator, it would follow that waves of the kind expected by Maxwell could be propagated in this insulator, with a finite velocity which might perhaps differ widely from that of light. These however could not be very surprising, not more than the circumstance, known long since then, that in wires electric perturbations propagate with a great but finite velocity. I felt that the third hypothesis contained the gist and special significance of Faraday's and therefore Maxwell's view, and3that it would thus be a more worthy goal for me to aim at.

Not many English readers are aware that Hertz thought this. The

translator, after assuring us that he has made only minor changes

only to the title and some footnotes, omits the entire sentence

that starts 'These however could not be very surprising ••.. '.

1. See also my Chapter 4, Section 2.

2. H. Hertz (1891), Electric Waves, Introduction, page 6.

3. See S.D'Agostino (1975), 'Hertz's Researches on Electromagnetic Waves', page 310. I should explain the reference to varying velocities. In wires, the velocity of transmission can be that

178

of light or can differ widely from it -- depending on the properties of the wire; dlelectries are similar.

4. See also P.Drude (1897), 'Ueber Fernwirkungen', page xxiv.

Page 179: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

2. 'On Physical Lines of Force' (1862) :

At first glance this paper achieves the following. It

sets out to solve the problem of electromagnetic induction using an

extremely natural mechanical model which filled the intervening

space with a mechanism. This model has the independent and

unexpected consequence that it supports transverse waves and further

these waves travel at the speed of light, so that:

we can scarcely avoid the inference that light consists in the transverse undu~ations of th: same medium1which is the cause ofelectr1c and magnet1c phenomena.

Thus the model solves the outstanding problem of the Field progr~e

while predicting a rudimentary electromagnetic theory of light.

As Everitt writes:

Maxwell's •.• paper ••. began as an attempt to devise a medium occupying space which would account for the stresses associated by Faraday with lines of magnetic force. It ended with the stunning discovery that vibra2ions of the medium have properties identical with light.

Such an achievement would be an impressive victory indeed

for the Field programme. And some think it so. Pearce Williams

writes:

[the model] had an amazing ability to account for observed electrical and magnetic phen~mena. Using this model as a starting point for his mathematics, Maxwell was able to explain a host of facts. Magnetic attractions and repulsions could be derived by some elementary mathematical operations from the assumed tension and hydrostatic lateral pressure of the rotating vortices. More dramatically, the electrical effects of the disturbance of ma~netic lines of force followed so naturally from his model ••.•

179

I, of course, will argue that the achievement is not real, but I will

1. Maxwell (1862), page 500, his italics.

2. C.W.F. Everitt (1975), James Clerk Maxwell, page 93.

3. L. pearce Williams, (1966), The Origins of Field Theory, pages 131-2.

Page 180: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

give a more detailed account before offering criticism.

We may take it that the problem was that of explaining

induction for that was the major unsolved one of the Field programme,

and also Maxwell tells us of the unfinished task of his previous

paper:

The idea of the electro-tonic state, however, has not yet presented itself to my mind in such a form that its nature and properties may be clearly explained without reference to mere symbols ••• By a careful study of the laws of elastic solids and of the motions of viscous fluids, I hope to discover a method of forming a mechanical conception of this electro-tonic state adapted to general reasoning.

Induction involves the magnetic field so that heuristically the first

task is to model magnetism. Faraday had argued in 1852 that the

behaviour of magnetic lines of force could be described completely

by supposing that they were trying to shorten in length and expand

laterally away from each other. Tubes of rotating fluid have

exactly the property of shortening longitudinally and expanding

laterally, and further the Field theorists had always supposed that

magnetism was rotatory or vortex in character. In short:

'The explanation which most readily occurs to the mind

was that of using vortex filaments to model magnetism. The fila-

ments or tubes of force run through space as a SUbstitute for lines

of force. Thomso~ treated magnetic energy as an all space integral

of the magnetic energy density 82

• With vortex filaments, the total

2 energy is an all space integral of d.v where d is the density of

the fluid (which we can set on one side for th~ moment) and v 2 is

the square of the tangential velocity of the fluid.) Maxwell made

1. Maxwell (1857), pages 187-8.

2. Maxwell (1862), page 455.

3. I am presenting here a simplified r~construction. I will in general use modern vector notation throughout this dissertation, and discuss the primary fields of E and !, not D and H.

180

Page 181: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

the obvious identification of magnetic force and tangential velocity

so that the tangential velocity v mimics the axial magnetic force B.

There is a mechanical difficulty in filling space with these

vortices. Adjacent filaments cannot move in the same sense and

maintain mechanical contact:

TO overcome this Maxwell introduced idler particles, which he

called particles of 'electricity'. These electric 'ball-bearings'

are distributed throughout space -- they are free to rotate, and they

can also have translatory motion. Flow of these particles

being flow of 'electricity' -- constitutes a current. And if an

electric force produces such a flow, say in a conductor, it will set

the vortices in motion; in this wayan electric current creates a

magnetic field. Also, if there is a variation in current, this

alters the speeds of rotation of the adjacent vortices, and the

disturbance is passed from vortex to vortex by the idler particles

until it encounters particles in a conductor, which are free to move

in translation, and then a current is induced. Now the model

needed to be adapted to account for static electricity. As Maxwell

states it

If we can now explain the condition of a body with respect to the surrounding medium when it is said to be 'charged' with electricity, and account for the forces acting between electrified bodies, we shall have established a connexion 1 between all the principal phenomena of electrical science.

And he did so by permitting the aether cells to distort and using a

1. Maxwell (1862), page 490.

181

Page 182: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

displacement of the aether. The attempt here is at a mechanical

interpretation of the existing A.A.D. theory of dielectrics:

In a dielectric under induction, we may conceive that the electricity in each molecule is so displaced that one side is rendered positively, and the other negatively electrical ..•

The effect of this action on the whole dielectric mass is to produce a general displacement of electricity in a certain direction •.• These relations are independent of any theory about the internal mechanism of dielectrics, but when we find electric displacement in a dielectric •.• we cannot help regarding the phenomenalas those of an elastic body, yielding to a pressure.

Such a distortion enables one to introduce a coefficient of rigidity

m of the medium, and this can be evaluated in terms of electrical

.. 2 quantl.tl.es. Maxwell then calculates the velocity of a transverse

182

wave in the medium using the formula v =~ where v is the velocity,

m the coefficient of rigidity, and d the density of the medium

(mentioned earlier) . And the velocity had the value of the ratio of

the electrical units, which is numerically equal to the speed of

light.

There is one further consequence. In 'genuine'

dielectrics like glass or paraffin the coefficient rigidity m' is

proportional to the dielectric constant of the substance. This

means that the velocity of the disturbance in dielectrics (and hence

the refractive index) is proportional to the square root of the

dielectric constant. Thus electrical and optical quantities are

related and genuine tests of the theory may be performed.

1. Maxwell (1862), pages 491-2. See also my explanations in Chapter 1 section 6, and Chapter 5 Section 1.

2. Berkson's long explanation of this in his (1974) Fields of Force has it that the idler particles of electricity distort, not the aether cells. This account of Maxwell's theory is simply mistaken.

Page 183: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

3. A Critical Appraisal of 'On Physical Lines of Force' and of the

Theses of H~ann and Bromberg Concerning It:

The achievement of 'On Physical Lines' is illusory.

I will drive a logical wedge between the independent test

and the model, and a heuristic and historical wedge between the wave

model and the induction model.

Maxwell employs what was known to be an incorrect formula

for the velocity of a transverse wave -- the correct formula is

~l v =..!;l.t:I(, • It is a logical consequence of his model that the

velocity of a transverse wave be the speed of light divided by ~,

not the speed of light. The model fails the independent test.

This mistake has occasioned much comment. Scientists

usually manage to make omissions from the penultimate line of a

183

calculation only when they know exactly what they are trying to obtain

for the last line. Certainly Maxwell has been accused of decept-

. 2 1on. My concern, though, is solely with the logical and heuristic

structure of his paper. I suggest that the model was designed to

ensure the existence of a transverse wave, and that there was enough

openness in the determination of the parameters to ensure the right

value for the velocity. There were no novel predictions.

How might we explain Maxwell's mistake? If the use of the

wrong velocity formula was a chance error, then either the model is

just false -- as above -- or if basically sound there must be a

compensatory error of FelseWhere. Some commentators favour this

1. See P. Duhem (1902), Les Th~ries Electriques de J.C. Maxwell, page 62.

2. See, for example, P. Duhem (1905), The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory, page 98.

Page 184: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

I story of compensating errors. But did Maxwell insert a J2 by

chance, then later omit a fi by chance, to obtain the right answer?

I can think of two better explanations and both suggest that the

objective problem was to model the propagation of light. Maxwell

was familiar with the work of Kohlrausch, Kirchoff, and Weber. And

in 1857 Kirchoff and Weber predicted the existence of electrical

actions travelling at the speed of light, and that this speed was

° 1 h to f th 1 ° 1 ° 2 proportl.ona to t e ral.O 0 e e ectrl.ca unl.ts. Bu t they used

electrodynamic units of current, whereas Maxwell used electromagnetic

units of current, and there is a conversion factor of~ between

these two units. Had Maxwell been trying to model light, and had

he used Weber's numerical relationships as a pattern, he could easily

have overlooked a ~ My other idea concerns waves. The

appropriate formula for speeds of waves depends on how many types

of wave the medium will support -- if a medium has two degrees of

freedom and permits longitudinal as well as transverse waves then a

factor of~ can appear in the velocity expression. Had Maxwell

been aiming at a theory of light which would have to allow only

transverse waves -- then his use of an elastic solid, which permits

both longitudinal and transverse waves, leaves him open to making a

184

mistake of a~ in a velocity. Either way here one mistake is made,

and an ad hoc adjustment is made elsewhere to ensure that the correct

speed is obtained. There is no genuine test.

My view does not stand unopposed. There is a body

1. See, for example, L. Rosenfeld (1957), 'The Velocity of Light and the Evolution of Electrodynamics', page 1658.

2. See, for instance, G. Kirchoff (laS7), 'On the Motion of Electricity in Wires'.

Page 185: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

of historical folk lore that the model must have been genuinely

predictive. because there could have been no 'fudging'. The

argument is that Maxwell did not know anything about the ratio of

the electrical units and the connection between this ratio and the

velocity of light. HeLmann sums up this evidence:

Maxwell formulated his theory of light without being aware of a paper by W. Weber and R. Kohlrausch, ••. in which the ratio .•• was determined ••.• That Maxwell was unaware of this paper is clear from a letter to Faraday of 19 October 1861 in which he stated that 'I have determined the velocity of transverse vibrations •••• The coincidence between velocities is not merely numerical. I worked out the formulae in the country before seeing Weber's number ••• and I think we have now strong reason to believe, whether my theory is a fact or not, that the luminiferous and electromagnetic medium are one' .•• This statement, and the way in which his wave-equation was derived from the model, clearly show the unexpectedness of the result. See also a letter to Thomson of 10 December 1861 where he repeated this statement: 'I made out the equations in the country before I had any suspicion of the nearness between the two values of the velocity of propagation of magnetic effects and that of light' The first indication of the numerical equivalence of the velocities of propagation of light and electricity was by G. Kirchoff in 1857, ••• Maxwell seems to have been unaware of this paper, in which litile significance is attached to the numerical equivalence ••••

But this is not the full story. There is a paper of

Maxwell's that few historians know of-- his (1863) 'On the

Elementary Relations between Electrical Measurements'. This paper

is usually overlooked because it was omitted from the collected

)85

edition of Maxwell's scientific papers. In it Maxwell discusses the

determination of the ratio of electrical units, and in particular he

refers to an attempt by Thomson in 1860 to determine this quantity.

Thomson read a paper to the Royal Society on the topic and the paper

was published in the 1860 Proceedings of the Royal Society.2

1. P.M. Hetmann (1970), 'Maxwell and the Modes of Consistent Representation I, footnote 130.

2. W. Thomson (1860), 'Measurement of the Electrostatic Force Produced by a Daniell's Battery'.

In turn,

Page 186: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Thomson in his paper refers to Weber's determination of the ratio

of the units. I say that Maxwell knew of Weber's calculations

before he started to write 'On Physical Lines'. What about

Kirchoff's paper? Heimann does not offer any evidence here -- he

merely states that Maxwell 'seems unaware' of it. Kirchoff's paper

was reprinted in English, being published in the widely read

Philosophical Magazine, and part of it reads

The velocity ofepropagation of an electric wave is here found to be = ~ , ••••• : its value is 41950 German miles in a second'lhence very nearly equal to the velocity of light in vacuo.

The paper was not some obscure work. Its subject was transmission

lines, and the major research area in electrodynamics at this time

was the application of the theory of transmission lines to cable

telegraphy. And Maxwell does tell us in 1854 that he has read

Kirchoff's earlier papers on currents in conductors. 2 Further, it

is clear from the references that Maxwell makes throughout his work

186

3 that he read all the publications of the Continental A.A.D. school --

are we to believe that he omitted from his readings a paper of

Kirchoff published in English in the Philosophical Magazine? The

balance of evidence is that Maxwell knew of Weber's and Kohlrausch's

determination of the ratio of the units, that he knew that this ratio

had the dimensions of a velocity, that he knew of Kirchoff's

prediction of electrical actions travelling at the speed of light,

and that he knew of the connection between this speed and the ratio

of the units. I think that Maxwell may not have known, or had total

1. G. Kirchoff (1857), page 406.

2. See page 10 of his November 1854 letter to Thomson in Larmor (1937) •

3. And see also L.Campbe11 and W.Garnet (1884), The Life of James Clerk Maxwell.

Page 187: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

187

recall, of the exact figure (and experimental error) that Weber and

Kohlrausch arrived at.

What about HQ!mann's other assertion that 'the way in

which his wave-equation was derived from the model, clearly show[s]

the unexpectedness of the resul t '? I maintain that HeLmann is

mistaken. Looking more closely at the 'On Physical Lines' paper.

It is in four parts. Part 1 is introductory, and part IV is on

the rotation of the plane of polarization of light -- neither concern

us. Part II is on the vortex induction model and Part III is on

the static electricity-transverse wave model. Maxwell intended

the paper to end with Part II. He wrote, completed, and published

that much of it before he had the afterthought of writing a

1 Part III. This historical division is reflected heuristically.

The induction model is hydrodynamical, whereas the static electricity

one is an elastic solid. It is true that Maxwell links one to the

other -- he stops the vortices rotating and assumes that they have

'elasticity of figure' so that they may distort. Why does Maxwell

do this? He tells us:

it is necessary to suppose, in order to account for the transmission of rotation from the exterior to the interior parts of each cell, that the SUbstance in the cells possesses elastic~ty of figure, similar •.• to that observed in solid bodies.

It is unlikely that this is the real reason for the velocity

1. He wrote Part III while in Scotland during the summer of 1861. (See, for instance, Maxwell's 1861 letter to Thomson in Larmor (1937) page 34.) Six months elapsed between his writing Part II and Part III.

2. Maxwell (1862), page 489

Page 188: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

distribution within a vortex is of no interest. Maxwell continues:

The undulatory theory of light requires us to admit this kind of elasticity in the luminiferous medium, in order to account for transverse vibrations. We need not then be surprised if the magneto-electric medium possesses the same property.

That is, the model was heuristically ad hoc relative to the induction

model, and the speed of propagation was not a genuine prediction.

188

One expert Joan Bromberg -- tries to rescue Maxwell thus.

She suggests that it was supposed that there were two elastic solid

aethers -- one optical and one electromagnetic -- and the novel

prediction was that the two were identical. She writes:

[in this early section] there is no mention of the optical ether. Were it the case that MAXWELL wanted to offer a physical theory of electromagnetism, one would expect the optical ether to enter. For then his task would have been to look at that medium already thought to fill space, and to investigate whether it had, or could be given, properties which would also give rise to electromagnetic effects. In this case, the identity of the optical and electromagnetic ethers would not have been the final and unexpected result, but the starting assumption for "On Physical Lines". As it was, however, the theory developed differently. Maxwell first invented a mechanical electro-magnetic medium, and subsequently discovered it could be identified with the optical ether.

When we come to the pages of Part III of "Physical Lines", we see, as the argument is developed, a gradual growth of a conviction of this identity. The first mention of the optical ether is on the first page •••. After he endows the electro­magnetic ether with the addit~onal property of elasticity of figure, MAXWELL brings in the optical medium to support the plausibility of this idea •••• Now the sense here is of the electromagnetic and optical ether as two similar but distinct media. In his next mention of the light-bearing medium, however, three pages later, MAXWELL reports he has shown its elasticity to be the same as that of his electromagnetic ether, and strongly raises the question whether "these two coexistent, coextensive, and equally elastic media are not rather one medium" ••• Finally, ••• at the end of the ve~ocity computation, he concludes, ••• that the two are identical.

This is grossly implausible. How could a scientist

mindful of Faraday's discovery that magnetism rotates polarized light

1. Maxwell (1862), page 489

2. Bromberg (1967), page 226.

Page 189: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

have supposed that there were two similar but distinct media?l And

Maxwell was mindful of the discovery -- he devotes Part IV of

'Physical Lines' to rotation of polarization, he tells in it that the

vortex approach is developed from Thomson's and Faraday's ideas on

the subject, and he re-affirms this in letters to Thomson.2

Maxwell set out in Part III to investigate whether the one

aether had, or could be given, properties to produce electromagnetic

effects, and there is no independent way to test the construction he

produced.

The relationship between refractive index and dielectric

constant remains to be discussed. The problem for Maxwell here is

that this relationship failed badly for all the substances that were

considered.

Maxwell later wrote:

The only dielectric of which the capacity has been hitherto determined with sufficient accuracy is paraffin, for which

K = 1.975 ••• the index of refraction ••• would be about 1.422.

The square root of K is 1.405. The difference between these numbers is greater than can be accounted for by errors of observation, and shews that our theories of the structure of bodies must be much improved before we c~n deduce their optical from their electrical properties.

So if the model had genuinely entailed this relationship, the model

would have been refuted by it.4

Both of Maxwell's models have numerous difficulties of

their own. Even at the qualitative level the induction model is

1. See also my Chapter I Section 8.

2. See, for instance, the 1861 letter to Thomson in Larmer (1937), page 34.

3. Maxwell (1873) f789.

189

4. Maxwell was unlucky. The relationship is accepted nowadays. The difficulty results from the static dielectric constant not being the same as the high frequency dielectric constant.

Page 190: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

190

baffling. The magnetic field around a current carrying wire is not

uniform, so the peripheral velocities of the vortices must not be

uniform, so the idler electrical particles must travel in space --

does this mean that a steady current induces a current in space?

Also the idler particles cannot travel freely in space for otherwise

the vortex motion would not penetrate the surrounding space -- there

must be resistance to translatory motion. TUrning now to a second

conductor. There must in it be resisted translatory motion -- if

there was no translation there would be no induction, if there was no

resistance a steady current in the first wire would induce a current

in the second. How then is the conductor to be distinguished from

the space so that all the phenomena occur where they should? Maxwell

1 does not tell us. And what are these 'electrical particles' whose

motion constitutes a current but which themselves are electrically

neutral. Maxwell writes of their role:

I do not bring it forward as a mode of connexion existing in nature, or even as that which I would willingly assent to as an electrical hypothesis. It is, ho~ever, a mode of connexion which is mechanically conceivable, and easily investigated, and it serves to bring out the actual mechanical connexions between the known electromagnetic phenomena; so that I venture to say that anyone who understands the provisional and temporary character of this hypothesis, will find himself rather helped than hindered by it ~n his search after the true interpretation of the phenomena.

Finally, the wave model seems to suggest that a transverse wave could

be initiated merely by moving an uncharged, current free, conductor,

and such a wave could presumably be detected by any other conductor --

no such sympathetic vibrations were known.

1. But Everitt does, on page 96 of his (1975) -- there is resistance in space, and none in the conductor. This interpretation cannot be right.

2. Maxwell (1862), page 486.

Page 191: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

191

4. The Later Theory :

Many historians relate that Maxwell was dissatisfied with some

of the mechanical details of the theory of 'On Physical Lines of Force'

for instance, those of the particulate electricity -- and that he

wished to restructure the theory on a firmer base. The result

was the later theory, which on this account becomes a sophisticated

1 version of the early theory and a natural heuristic development of it.

I disagree with this view. The later theory does not have the

early theory as an ancestor -- it is instead descended from accepted

electrical science. The early theory is a mechanical model which is

heuristically faithful to the aims of the Field Programme; in contrast,

the later theory is axiomatic and has as its main feature a phenomenological

and electrical derivation of the existence of transverse e-m waves in

dielectrics. The derivation -- essentially the one used today --

required exceptional mathematical and physical skills on Maxwell's

part; but I must emphasize that its deductive base was A.A.D. background.

Maxwell then tried to impose on the electromagnetic postulates a mechanical

interpretation -- on some occasions he insisted that the equations were

2 known to be about certain definite mechanical properties of a medium,

and on other occasions he applied the Lagrangian methods of generalized

coordinates to electromagnetism and inferred from this application that

3 electromagnetism concerned a mechanical aether.

1. See, for example, L.P.Williams (1966) or R.A.R.Tricker (1966), The Contributions of Faraday and Maxwell to Electrical Science.

2. See, for instance, Maxwell (1873) .f831.

3. See Maxwell (1873) or Maxwell (1873b), 'Electromagnetism'.

Page 192: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

192

Maxwell offered several alternative derivations of travelling

waves from 1865 through to 1873. He first found that a transverse

magnetic field could be propagated, later he was able to show that

a transverse electrical field could travel, and also (after some

1 difficulties with the gauge condition ) that the vector potential

2 could be propagated. I will explain the postulates and show how the

first derivation was made.

The theory and derivation occur first in his (1865) 'A Dynamical

Theory of the Electromagnetic Field'. I will quote a section of that

paper in full, then, as I discuss the equations, translate the component

notation into modern vector notation.

In these equations of the electromagnetic field we have assumed twenty variable quantities, namely,

For Electromagnetic Momentum •••••••••••••••••••.• F G H " Magnetic Intensity •.••••••••••••••••••••••••• ol ~ lJ " Electromotive Force •••••.•••••••••••••••••••• P Q R " Current due to true Conduction •••••••••••••.• p q r " Electric Displacement •••••••••••••••••••••••• f g h " Total Current (including variation of

displacement) •••••••••••••••••• p'q'r' " Quantity of Free Electricity ••••••••••••••••• e " Electric Potential •••••••••.••••••••••••••••• y

Between these twenty quantities we have found twenty equations, viz. Three equations of Magnetic Force •••••••••••••••• (B)

" Electric Currents ••••••••••••• (C) " Electromotive Force .•••••••••• (D) " Electric Elasticity ••••••••••• (E) " Electric Resistance .••••••.••• (F) " Total Currents •••••••••••••••• (A)

One equation:'of Free Electicity ••••••••••••.••••• (G) " Con tinui ty ••••••••••••••••••••••• (H)

These equations are therefore sufficient to determine all the quantities which occur in them, provided we know the conditions of the problem. 3 In many questions, however, only a few of the equations are required.

1. Maxwell found that a Coulomb gauge, in which div A = 0, suited his deriv­ations, but he was not satisfied with his own physical arguments for the truth of this condition. See P.F.Cranefie1d (1954), 'Clerk Maxwell's corrections to the page proofs of "A dynamical theory of the electromagnetic field'" • 2. For a discussion, see A.M.Bork (1967), 'Maxwell and the Electromagnetic Wave Equation'. 3. Maxwell (l865)§ 70.

Page 193: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

193

Equation B relates Magnetic Intensity -- H -- to the

Electromagnetic Momentum (the vector potential), it is

pH - curl A B'

where J.I is the coefficient of magnetic induction of the particular

1 circuit. This equation is a particular case of a standard mathematical

, result related to a consequence of Ampere's law that div H = o.

Equation C connects Magnetic Intensity H to Total Current

curl H • 4lT'-4otal C'

This postulate, which was discussed in the Introduction, is part of the

, Ampere-Weber A.A.D. background, if the Total Current is understood to

mean all flows of electrical fluids.

Equation D relates Electric Force E found in a moving

conductor to the sum of the induced e.m.f.,arising (a) from its

movement and (b) from change of magnetic field ('transformer action'),

and the static electric field :

E" p(Y1<H) - ~: - V1f ....... D'

Here the rate of change of vector potential has been taken as

an unanalysed description of Faraday's results on electromagnetic

induction and it has, by mathematical manipulation for a particular case,

been divided up into motional action and transformer action. Finally the

static electric field has been added.

1. I have used the standard modern symbols which I consider portray most aptly the quantities of Maxwell.

Page 194: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

194

Equation E equates Electromotive Force and Electric Displacement

E - k 0 ..................................... E'

Equation F is Ohm's law for isotropic substances

E • -f~onduction •••••••••.••••.•••.•••••••••. F'

Equation A governs total motion of electricity as a source of

magnetic intensity and relates total current to conduction current and

'displacement current'

of + 'JR. itotal - -Conduction Be .................... A'

Equation G relates free positive electricity e to Displacement

div 0 - - e

Equation H

dA. div 1. - - ~

.............................. G'

is the continuity equation for conduction current

.............................. H'

The first derivation of the wave equation is carried out in

Sections 93-5 of the (1865) paper. The two assumptions made are that

the medium is a perfect dielectric in which there are no true conduction

currents, and that there are no conductors or motions of conductors.

The relevant equations then become :

- curl A ................................ B'

curl H • 41T"~otal' • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • C'

E - - b~

E - k 0

- '\l'VI ........•.....................

()! itotal - 8e

................................. ................................

0"

E'

A"

Page 195: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

t 95

B, C, and A" combine to give :

f! 4"'-;f = V V, A - V"'!1 (1)

Differentiating the combination of D" and E' yields :

~ ~ [- ;~~ rJ $lJ (2)

(1) and (2) combine to give

j/tf-7i [t;~ + V ttl -I- k[rrr;.11 _Ql~] ...... (3)

Curl of (3) provides :

p 47r [f)f!.-jl.~ ] -I- k [- ~fl-r;~!!..J = 0 (4)

then substituting from B'

f/41r ~ ~ fll.~ /I ) ==0

which is a standard wave equation for~H, ( and Maxwell showed also

that the wave is purely transversal). The velocity of such a wave

is ~ ; this retains the connection with Weber and Kohlrausch's Jiii;

velocity figure, and the relationship between refractive index and

dielectric constant.

Page 196: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

196

5. A Critical Appraisal of the Later Theory :

I will argue that the later theory was heuristically ad hoc,

and that it did not predict novel facts. Thus, the advent of the

later theory did not make the Field programme progressive.

There are two unsatisfactory heuristic aspects to the later

theory. The theory was not directed at explaining induction, which was

the unsolved problem of the early theory; instead the later theory

postulated the rate of change of the vector potential as an unanalysed

1 description of induction. Secondly, the later theory was not the

byproduct of the search for the properties of a single mechanical aether;

the heuristic path to it used purely electrical arguments and only

later was an aether interpretation applied to it. As Chalmers states,

in my view correctly :

Maxwell's successful innovations in electromagnetism were not occasioned by his desire to reduce that branch of science to mechanics. The displacement current did not emerge as a result of his attempts to cast electromagnetism in the framework of Lagrangian mechanics, nor did it emerge as an inevitable consequence of his attempts to construct a mechanical model. Its introduction was ~upported by electrical rather than mechanical arguments. ,

Maxwell's much admired use of Lagrange'. equations needs further

discussion. 3 Some argue that Maxwell's electrodynamic equations were

4 derived from a Lagrangian application of general dynamics. If

indeed there was a mechanical aether, then it would be governed by

1.And actually the Field programme was never able to explain induction.

2. For 'the sixty page argument that Chalmers uses in support of his thesis, see A.F.Chalmers (197~, 'Maxwell's Methodology and His Application of It to Electromagnetism'.

, 3. The admirers include H.Poincare in his (190S), Science and Hypothesis, pages 216, 222, and 223 and R.T.Glazebrook in his (1896), J.C.Maxwell and Modern Physics, page 179.

4. See, for example, T.K.Simpson (1970), 'Some Observations on Maxwell's Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism', page 249.

Page 197: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Lagrange's equations -- which is to say that if Maxwell's discoveries

resulted from the use of Lagrange's equations then the discoveries

would be evidence for the Field programme's thesis that there was

a mechanical aether, and furthermore Maxwell's theories would be

acceptable heuristically.

197

I maintain that as a matter of fact Maxwell's equations were

not the outcome of a Lagrangian analysis -- Maxwell first produced the

electromagnetic equations and then cast them in a Lagrangian form.

And I suggest also that Lagrangian analysis is not a powerful heuristic

aid in this type of case.

Lagrange's equations, in their original role in analytical

dynamics, are useful transformations of Newton's equations for systems

of particles. The transformation is usually made from Cartesian

coordinates to generalized coordinates, and in most cases of interest

there are constraints which enable the number of generalized coordinates

to be reduced to the number of degrees of freedom of the system.

Page 198: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

198

For example, a wheel free to rotate on a fixed axle has only one

1 degree of freedom and is thus governed by one Lagrange equation ;

whereas many Newtonian equations are required to describe the

dynamics of the vast number of particles which constitute the wheel.

In addition to the generalized coordinates of Lagrange there are

generalized velocities, generalized forces, and generalized momenta

these concepts are given purely analytical definition, for example the

time derivative of a generalized coordinate is a generalized velocity.

The final component of the Lagrangian method is energy. There is

the kinetic energy of the system which is the sum of the kinetic

energies of the individual particles, and of lesser importance is

the potentialtnergy (if there is one) which, when differentiated

with respect to the appropriate generalized coordinate, yields the

generalized forces. Lagrange's equations relate the generalized

forces to derivatives of the kinetic energy, and they are sufficient

to predict the time development of the system of particles. From a

mathematical point of view the equations achieve no more and no less

than Newton's equations, if the focus of interest is total information

about all the individual particles. But often the focus of interest

is limited, and then Lagrange's equations may have an advantage. A

typical case is where the behaviour of the generalized coordinates is

all important, and where there are known constraints. Maxwell's

.1. I assume here that the intetest 1s confined to rotatory motion of the_· wheel. Engineers may be co~erned whether flywheels disintegrate, and to calculate forces of constraint larger numbers of Lagrangian equations would have to be used. (In these cases the number of generalized coordinates is larger than the number of degrees of freedom of the system.)

Page 199: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

199

1 favourite example was that of church bells -- in his example there is

a bell mechanism which is inaccessible in the bellfry, and there are

exposed bell ropes which operate the mechanism; the investigator's concern

is solely with the behaviour of the ropes -- how they respond to forces

and displacements -- and Lagrangian analysis is used to yield all the

information that can be known about the behaviour of the ropes.

This type of problem is one where there is a hidden Newtonian

mechanism with observable parameters, and the interest is confined to the

observables. Lagrangian analysis will apply to these cases if the

observables determine the state of the mechanism, and if the kinetic

energy of the hidden machinery can be evaluated.

Maxwell's wish was to analyse electromagnetism in this fashion.

Electromagnetic effects were the observable epiphenomena of the aether

and thus for him played the role of the observable parameters of a

hidden Newtonian mechanism. Accordingly Lagrange's equations should be

able to yield all the information that can be known about electromagnetic

effects.

I maintain that there is no rational procedure for applying

Lagrangian techniques to the aether to produce descriptions or explanations

of electromagnetic effects or to make discoveries about electromagnetic

effects. Consequently Maxwell's el~tromagnetic postulates could not

have had their origins in rational application of Lagrange's equations.

I offer three arguments; these concern the observable-unobservable

1. Maxwell (1868b), 'Thomson and Tait's Natural Philosophy', page 783.

Page 200: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

distinction, the generalized coordinates, and the kinetic energy.

Maxwell's bell example is unfairly favourable to his

enterprise -- in it there is a clear distinction between the hidden

mechanism and the observable ropes. Such clarity does not in

200

general exist and does not exist in the case of the aether. With the

aether, it is not obvioua what the candidates for the observables are.

For example, Maxwell takes electric current (and even displacement current)

as an observable parameter partially determining the state of the aether,

but electric current was discovered only around 1800, prior to that

date it was an unobserved observable; there may yet be undiscovered

observables. The appropriate bell analogy would be the following.

There is a hidden bell-mechanism and there are some observable bell-ropes

in the bell-ringer$~ room; furthermore, there may be other undiscovered

bell-ropes perhaps in another unlocked, but as of yet unopened, bell­

ringers' room. The investigator must make a conjecture as to the

candidates for observables, but -- as I shall show -- Lagrangian techniques

offer no rational way of refining such conjectures.

Maxwell's bell example is also unfairly favourable over the

constitution of the generalized coordinates. In that example the

coordinates of the ropes are guess'ed to be the generalized coordinates,

the velocities of the ropes then become the generalized velocities, and the

forces on the ropes are guessed to be the generalized forces.

Page 201: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

But mathematically the generalized concepts are given a purely

analytical definition and usually these generalized concepts will

not have the same dimensions as the ordinary concepts; for instance,

generalized forces will often not have the dimensions of a force.

The investigator must make a conjecture as to the constitution of the

generalized coordinates, and it is not permissable for him to assume

that these must be positions or that the generalized velocities are

the velocities of moving objects or that the generalized forces are

pushes or pulls.

201

Of crucial importance in Lagrange's equations is the kinetic

energy of the hidden mechanism. In standard applications, where the

mechanism is not hidden, the kinetic energy can be determined with

the spinning wheel example there is a Newtonian formula for the kinetic

energy of a wheel. In these cases, where the kinetic energy is known,

there can be a independent check of the ongoing Lagrangian analysis of

generalized coordinates, and certain types of errors can be rectified.

And in other cases, where there is a hidden mechanism with known

generalized coordinates and unknown kinetic energy -- as in Maxwell's

bell example -- the kinetic energy of the hidden mechanism can be

operationally defined in terms of the behaviour of the generalized

observables, and again certain types of false conjectures can be improved

upon. But with the aether, both the generalized coordinates and

Page 202: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

202

the kinetic energy are unknown. The investigator must make a

conjecture about the kinetic energy of the hidden mechanism of the

aether, and since he is unsure of the generalized coordinates he has no

independent test of his conjecture.

A failed Lagrangian analysis of the aether would not indicate

whether the conjectured generalized coordinates were incorrect, whether

they were incomplete, or whether the conjectured formula for the kinetic

energy of the aether was false.

Simpson completely misleads his audience when he writes

The relevance of {Lagrangian analysis) to the problem of electromagnetism is i~mediately apparent : if indeed the field is to be regarde~as a connected mechanical system, the positions and velocities of the conductors, together with the currents and integral-currents associated with them, constitute the generalized coordinaies, and determine the configuration of the field at any moment.

Maxwell's electrodynamic equations and the existence of

Maxwell's displacement current were not produced by means of Lagrangian

2 analysis, and from a mathematical point of view could not have been

produced effectively in this way.

The later theory was thus heuristically ad hoc. But was it

testable ? Did it predict novel facts ? The postulates that Maxwell

favoured had several disadvantages. 3 They were formally inconsistent;

4 they did not explain electromagnetic induction; and -- with the

1. Simpson (1970) page 253.

2. The displacement current was always included at the beginning of the analysis, not discovered by virtue of the analysis. See, for example, Maxwell (1873)~604.

3. The derivation is given in Chalmers (1973~pages 141 and f.

4. See also my Chapter 4 Section 10.

Page 203: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

203

interpretation of the vacuum as a dielectric -- they abandonned a

satisfactory theory of dielectrics. In compensation, the postulates

offered a unified view of travelling electromagnetic waves. These

elegant theoretical results were to the effect that there would be

transverse but no longitudinal electromagnetic waves in dielectrics,

including the vacuum. Light was suggested to be such a wave.

The obvious direct test of the electrical axioms is to produce

and detect a travelling wave. Maxwell never tried this, and there is

good evidence that he had no idea of how it might be done, even as

an in principle thought experiment. His postulates obscured the

nature of the sources and receivers of the waves; his derivations

being plane-wave solutions with sources and receivers at infinity

left him in ignorance. • Furthermore the theory was directed at the

electromagnetic band around visible light, which has a relatively high

frequency -- it seems that Maxwell judged that the frequency of the

travelling waves was so high as to defy artificial production in the

laboratory. The whole question of a Maxwellian direct test of the

existence of travelling waves is curious. Many scientists had produced,

observed, and reported non-optical electromagnetic radiation before

Maxwell's time. They did not know what it was that they were observing

neither, it seems, did Maxwell know. Furthermore, all the technological

and technical materials needed for a test were available to Maxwell,

1 but he did not use them. .

1. See C.Susskind (1964), 'Observations of Electromagnetic-Wave Radiation before Hertz', T.K.Simpson (1966), 'Maxwell and the Direct Test of His Electromagnetic Theory' and A.F.Chalmers (1973~h 'The Limitations of Maxwell's Electromagnetic Theory'.

Page 204: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

204

Maxwell did propose two tests -- the first his theory failed,

and the second, though not attempted, would not have distinguished

his theory from background knowledge. The first test was to evaluate

the relationship between dielectric constant and refractive index -- the

1 equations failed this test, as Maxwell admitted. The second test

was to construct a sensitive galvanometer and to try to detect a current

within a genuine 'dielectric' such as solid paraffin

According to this view l:Maxwell's own] , the current produced in discharging a condenser is a complete circuit, and might be traced within the dielectric itself by a galvanometer properly constructed. I am not aware that this has been done, so that this part of the theory, though apparently a natural consequence of the former, has not been verified by direct experiment. The

2 experiment would certainly be a very delicate and difficult one.

This is a poor suggestion. All the background theories asserted the

existence of polarization currents in dielectrics. So the mere

deflection of a galvanometer needle in these circumstances -- had it

been produced was hardly a novel fact predicted by Maxwell's theory.

Maxwell seems to have been unable to suggest demanding tests of his

theory. The second unperformed experiment could have been developed

into two reasonable tests. It should have been tried in a vacuum,

since a vacuum current is a peculiarity of Maxwell's theory. And

attention should have been directed to the magnitude of these currents

__ Maxwell's currents into dielectrics are circuital, whereas the

background theories' polarization and conduction currents are not

1. See Section 3 of this Chapter.

2. Maxwell (1868), page 139.

Page 205: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

so the important factor is the magnitude of the current within the

dielectric, not its mere existence.

And there is a third test that Maxwell could easily have

thought of. For him, displacement currents were exactly the same

as transient conduction currents. He writes

Whatever electricity may be and whatever we may understand by movement of electricity, the phenomenon which we have called electric displacement is a movement of electricity in the same sense as the transference of a definite quantity of electricity through a wire is a movement of electricity; the only difference being that in the dip.lectric there is a force which we have called electric elasticity, which acts against the electric displacement ••••

In which case, since conduction currents -- even transient ones

produce heat, so should displacement currents. A capacitor in a

vacuum should generate heat while being charged. This test is

simple to perform (and Maxwell's theory would have failed it).

1. Maxwell (1873) ! 62.

205

Page 206: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

6. Summary

In this Chapter I have

a) argued that Maxwell's 'early' theory of electromagnetism, while

initially heuristically acceptable, became heuristically ad hoc and

simply ad hoc as it was developed into a theory of light,

b) concluded that Maxwell's 'later' theory of electromagnetism

was heuristically ad hoc and made no successful novel predictions,

c) pointed out that the originality in Maxwell's theories lies in

their suggestion that the vacuum is a dielectric,

d) shown that Maxwell's use of Lagrangian Mechanics did not make his

later theory heuristically acceptable,

206

e) made suggestions regarding the source of the J':2 error in his early

theory,

f) refuted two theses of Simpson -- one concerning polarization currents

producing ~gnetic effects and the other concerning Lagrangian analysis,

g) refuted the standard view, as expressed by Heimann, that there

could have been no'fudging' in the case of Maxwell's derivation in

his early theory,

h) refuted Bromberg's thesis that the novel outcome of the early theory

was the discovery that the electromagnetic and optical aethers were

one and the same,

and

i) refuted minor theses of Everitt, Pearce Williams, Tricker, and

others.

Page 207: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Chapter 6 The A.A.D. Theory of Light.

I. Introduction.

2. Ludwig Lorenz's Theory of Light.

3. Hertz's 1884 Paper, 'On the Relations Between Maxwell's

Fundamental Equations and The Fundamental Equations of

the Opposing Electromagnetics'.

4. A Comparison of the A.A.D. Theory of Light and Maxwell's

Theory of Light.

5. The Theory of Helmholtz.

207

Page 208: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

I. Introduction:

The question of whether the electromagnetic theory of

light gave the Field programme a decisive victory has still to be

given a final answer. This will involve discussing the A.A.D.

electromagnetic theory of light, and the development of the two

programmes after 1860. The A.A.D. electromagnetic theory of

light is that of postulating retarded potentials emanating

from electron sources. The theory receives partial expression

in Ludwig Lorenz's theory of light, but from the point of view

of the A.A.D. programme Lorenz's theory must be incorrect and

incomplete. The necessary refinements are indicated in

Hertz's theoretical paper of 1884. I

It was Ludwig Lorenz who proposed the prototype of the

A.A.D. theory of light, and his problem situation and the solutions

he offered, in terms of retarding- the scalar potential 4> and the

vector potential !, are discussed in Section 2.

Little research was carried out 1n the pure forms of

either of the two programmes between 1870 and 1900. Instead new

hybrid programmes arose. Helmholtz developed a general potential

theory which he maintained encompassed both Maxwell's and Weber's

theories. Indeed it did so, but at the cost of disfiguring them

Maxwell's theory became an A.A.D. theory with genuine sources, and

Weber's theory became endowed with current element sources as a

208

I. H.Hertz (J884), 'On the Relations Between Maxwell's Fundamental Equations and the Fundamental Equations of the Opposing Electromagnetics'.

Page 209: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

209

replacement for the atomic ones. Helmholtz favoured his own variant

of Maxwell's theory. His preference was based in part on good

reasons; and it was also based in part on bad reasons (as we have seen

in Chapter 4). There was a bitter dispute between Helmholtz and

Weber -- which extended as far as Helmholtz opposing the proposal,

made at the First International Congress on Electricity, to use

the name 'weber' to denote a unit of current. I The core of the

intellectual disagreement was that Weber's force law used velocity

dependent forces and Helmholtz held as a basic principle that

physics allowed of no such forces. Helmholtz writes in 1872 that

Maxwell's theory

proves that there is nothing in electrodynamic phenomena to compel us to attribute them to an entirely anomalous sort of natural forces, to forces depending not merely on the.situa~ion2of the masses in question, but also on the1r mot10n.

and he writes in 1873

all the known effects of electro-dynamic action are subject to the great principle of conservation of energy, although a theoretical deduction of this universal principle of nature ~ be given onjY for forces .•.•• which are independent of motion.

and in 1881 he writes

Nobody can deny that this new theory of electricity and magnetism, originated by Faraday and developed by Maxwell, is in itself well consistent, in perfect and exact harmony with all the known facts of experience,

I. See A.E. Woodruff (1968), 'The Contributions of Hermann von Helmholtz to Electrodynamics', footnote 20.

2. H. Helmholtz (1872), 'Ueber die Theorie der Elektrodynamic, II', page 532.

3. H. Helmholtz (1873), 'On Later Views of the Connection of Electricity and Magnetism', page 248, my italics.

Page 210: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

and does not contradict anyone of the general axioms of dynamics ••.•. Other eminent men have tried to reduce electromagnetic phenomena to forces acting directly between distant quantities of hypothetical electric fluids, with an intensity which depends not only on distance, but also on the velocities and accelerations All these theories explain very satisfactorily the phenomena of closed galvanic currents. But applied to other electric motions, they all com, into contradiction with the general axioms of dynamics.

210

Helmholtz should have given Weber's law a fairer hearing -- Helmholtz's

principle is false, and in the mid-19th. century there were many good

arguments for thinking it false and none for thinking it true.

Helmholtz's papers were extremely influential and in my view had a

detrimental effect on the perception of many scientists of

electrodynamics, for example on that of Hertz. The theory of Helmholtz

is considered in Section s.

The younger continental scientists -- notably Hertz and

H.A. Lorentz -- used Helmholtz's theory as a starting point. Hertz

was one of Helmholtz's students2

; and H.A. Lorentz's doctoral

dissertation was directed at the electromagnetic boundary conditions

between media, a problem that he had learned of from a footnote to

3 one of Helmholtz's papers.

Hertz's research is important. Its significance lies not

with his well know experimental production of finitely propagating

electromagnetic waves in space, but instead with the lesser known

theoretical paper of 1884. The experiments are of value, they

1. H.Helmholtz (1881), 'On the Modern Development of Faraday's Conception of Electricity', pages 280-1.

2. For the Helmholtz-Hertz relationship see S.D'Agostino (1975). 'Hertz's Researches on Electromagnetic Waves', section 2.

3. H. Helmholtz (1870). 'Ueber die Theorie der Elektrodynamic' footnote to page 558.

Page 211: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

did show the direct production of travelling electromagnetic

waves. But they are of limited value because their outcome did

not serve to confirm a novel prediction of a theory -- theories

in both the A.A.D. and Field programmes anticipated the result.

The experiments, which compared a wave in space with one in a ,

wire, also had shortcomings. Poincare observed immediately

that Hertz had used the incorrect theoretical value for the velocity

of propagation in a wire and so there was a missing factor of J2;

Hertz himself knew that his results were awry due to the spatial

wave reflecting off objects in his laboratory; and he freely

admitted to falsifying the values he obtained, selecting those

J that theory demanded. In the 1884 theoretical paper Hertz

proves the equivalence of the retarded potentials of Ludwig

Lorenz and the equations of Maxwell. This meant that the elegant

mathematical derivations of Maxwell were available to A.A.D.

theoreticiams for the vacuum case. The 1884 paper received a

hostile reception from Helmholtz and his followers, and it was

. . d· . b H 2 never aga1n ment10ne 1n pr1nt y ertz.

H.A.Lorentz's Electron Research Programme was a hybrid

programme which employed both atomic sources and a rest aether.

In the years around the turn of the century Lorentz's programme

was more popular than either the Field or the A.A.D. programmes.

Discussing the intellectual merits of Lorentz's programme is

I. See Hertz (1892), Electric Waves. p. 2. See D'Agostino (1975), pages 293 and 295.

21 J

Page 212: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

not within the province of this dissertation, but I should remark

that Lorentz's programme can be seen naturally as a continuation

1 and development of the A.A.D. programme. Lorentz would have

described his own work as being initially in the A.A.D. tradition

and then later in the Field programme (and he meant by the Field

programme: Helmholtz's version of it). What caused him to transfer

allegiance was his feeling that electrical actions should have

a finite velocity of propagation and that this required contiguous

. 2 act~on. Lorentz writes :

I have tried to reduce all the phenomena to one, the simplest of all: the motion of an electrified body ..• We see then that Maxwell's theory, in the new form I am about to give it, approaches the old ideas ...• [The]simple formulae regulating the motion of charged particles ••. (can be regarded] as expressing a fundamental law comparable with those of Weber and Clausius. But these equations continue to bear the impress of Maxwell's principles •••• In general terms we can say that [ electrical actions] are propagated with a velocity equal to that of light. Thus we return to an idea already expressed by Gauss in 1845, according to which the electrodynamic actions require a certain time to propagate themselves from the asting particle to the par·ticle which experiences their effects.

Lorentz's characterization of the difference between the programmes

is inappropriate -- as I argued in Chapter 1 Section 2 -- and

212

1. H.A.Lorentz's research is described in H.A.Lorentz (1909), Theory of Electrons, T.Hirosige (1962), 'Lorentz's Theory of Electrons and the Development of the Concept of Electromagnetic Field', T.Hirosige (1966), 'Electrodynamics before the Theory of Relativity 1890-1905', T.Hirosige (1969), 'Origins of Lorentz's Theory of Electrons and the Concept of the Electromagnetic Field', and R.McCormmach (1970), 'H.A.Lorentz and the Electromagnetic View of Nature'.

2. See Hirosige (1962), Section 6.

3. H.A.Lorentz (1892), 'La Theorie Electromagnetique de Maxwell et son Application aux Corps Mouvants', page 432 and f. And McCormmach, for example, writes on page 462 of his (1970) : ' In his [Lorentz's] view electrodynamics should return to the theories of Weber ... while at the same time retaining the core of Maxwell's theory -- the finite propagation of electrical action'.

Page 213: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

thus it indicates a false conseiouRness on Lorentz's part.

The affinity between Lorentz's theories and the A.A.D. programme

is shown by Lorentz's use of electron sources and of the key

unifying idea that static and dynamic electrical phenomena were

the outcome of electrons interacting under the one force law.

Lorentz solved an important problem for the A.A.D. programme.

Forty years earlier the A.A.D. electrodynamics of sources and

empty space had apparently been questioned by the existence of

dielectrics, but it had been shown that empty space and sources

governed by Coulomb's law were sufficient to explain the behaviour

. 1 1 of materla s. Now a similar problem had arisen. It appeared

that the A.A.D. view of sources, empty space, and one finite

velocity of propagation cannot explain the fact that light has

a different velocity in a dielectric to its velocity in a vacuum.

Lorentz showed that sequences of charged harmonic oscillators

respond to an impinging electromagnetic wave so that the manifold

resultant wave travels with a different velocity to its component

members. Dielectrics contain sequences of electron sources.

Thus Lorentz gave an explanation of why light travels slower in

a dielectric than it does in a'vacuum and furthermore Lorentz's

explanation was independently testable, and actually confirmed,

as it related the velocity to the frequency of light and the

density of the dielectric. The aether that Lorentz invoked in his

1. See my Chapter 1 Section 6 and Chapter 3 Section 3.

213

Page 214: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

theories was imponderable and at rest -- in contrast to that of

1 Maxwell and as such was little more than a picturesque rep-

resentation of the electric and magnetic forces in space. Lorentz

did allow for the propagation of energy across space and thus

his aether was akin to Maxwell's in being a seat of energy, but

for Maxwell the energy was strictly mechanical energy whereas for

214

Lorentz the energy was non-mechanical. This feature of the location

of energy in space prevents Lorentz's work from being classified

as part of the A.A.D. programme. It perhaps should be mentioned

that Lorentz incurred Helmholtz's ire for using a velocity

2 dependent force -- the Lorentz force law.

I.He defined aether as a material substance, see his 'Aether' article in Niven (ed.) (1965) ,and for him the relationship between aether and moving matter was always problematic.

2. Heaviside used velocity dependent forces as a natural part of the Field programme -- such forces were in use in the A.A.D. programme, the Field programme, and Lorentz's hybrid programme.

Page 215: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

2. Ludwig Lorenz's Theory of Light:

Ludwig Lorenz has never been widely known. This fact

has often been lamented, mainly by those few historians sympathetic

to the A.A.D. programme -- they claim that Lorenz proposed an

electromagnetic theory of light equivalent, or superior, to that

1 of Maxwell. They support their view by pointing out that Lorenz

suggested that the scalar and vector potentials be retarded and

that this idea is the full modern electromagnetic theory of light.

Lorenz's obscurity is explained by the fact that he was Danish

and had :

'great difficulties in presenting hi~ ideas and calculations in an accessible form.'

This simple view and its subsidiary explanation are

unacceptable -- it contains too much hindsight. Lorenz's own

theory was bound to an interpretation in terms of contiguous action

in a full space; and this means that as it stood it was not an

A.A.D. theory. And the subsidiary explanation is just false.

Lorenz wrote only one major paper in electrodynamics 3, and it was

clear and it was published in German and in English in the major

physics periodicals.

Lorenz's work is important, but not because he proposed

a theory of light superior to that of Maxwell for neither Lorenz's

215

1. See A.O'Rahilly (1965), M.Pihl (1962), 'The Scientific Achievements of L.V.Lorenz', and R.W.P.King (1949), 'Review of Mogens Pihl : Der Physiker L.V.Lorenz ••• '

2. Pihl (1962), page xxi.

3. L.Lorenz (1867), 'On the Identity of the Vibrations of Light and Electrical Currents'.

Page 216: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

216

theory nor Maxwell's contributed to progression in a research

programme. Lorenz's theory has to be considered in the context

of the A.A.D. programme. Two aspects of Lorenz's research are

isolated by the A.A.D. programme as it was in the 1860's: that

he invented a new heuristic tool" and that he emphasized the

connections between retarded potentials and the theory of light

especially those relating to the boundary conditions between media

and to the velocity of light.

Ludwig Lorenz almost certainly knew nothing of Maxwell's

papers in electrodynamics or of the equivalence between their two

sets of equations. (Most scientists, both on the Continent and in

England, did not become aware of Maxwell's work until Helmholtz

drew attention to it, and Hertz 'proved' the existence of Maxwell's

mechanical aether.) Lorenz took as electrodynamic background

. f . I h' h b . . the Weber-K1rchof equat1ons, w 1C can e wr1tten 1n modern

notation :

.i -ll E ..... (A localized Ohm's law for a conducting medium, 1 is the current density vector, a the conductivity, and E the electric force.)

E • ~l + E. d -1n

Eel - - grad'

I. See my Chapter 4 Section 8.

2

3

(The total electric force is the sum of the induced electric force and the electric force due to the static charge.)

(. is the scalar potential)

Page 217: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

217

div grad + f' 4 ( p is the charge densi ty and ... e.

~, a cons tan t . )

E. d = 1 lUi. 5 (A is the vector potential -In C2 ~I: and c is the ratio of the electrical units.)

div grad ~ ... - p.l 6 (}4 is a constant.)

div.i li 7 (Conti nui ty.) ~t:;

div A + it ... 0 8 (This was an auxiliary condi tion for Kirchoff.)

Earlier Lorenz had considered the question of the boundary

conditions between media needed to yield the Fresnel formulas for

reflection and refraction of light. He, in common with many other

scientists, became convinced that no elastic solid aether could

yield the Fresnel formulas (because of difficulties, mainly with the

longitudinal wave); and so he sought as an intermediate step a

condition on the light vector. The differential equation he

proposed was

curl curl u 1 ~A = 2- ~I:'L ••••• * (where u is the light vector and a Is the velocity of light.)

and he showed that this equation guaranteed transverse waves and

that the Fresnel formulas would hold at an interface. I The equation

was a desideratum for a theory of light.

He -- also in common with many other scientists -- assumed that

light wou:tlbe electrical in nature and involve propagated

I. This had been shown independently by MacCullagh in 1863.

Page 218: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

1 effects • He writes

.•• the entire action between the free electricity and the electrical currents requires time to propagate itself -- an assumption not strange in science, and which may in 2 itself be assumed to have a certain degree of probability.

In his earlier research in elasticity he had described propagated

effects by retarded potentials and he emphasized that a propagated

force func tion can be expanded as 'a Taylor series which, given

a reasonably high velocity of propagation, would remain consistent

with its experimental base of quasi-stationary phenomena. He

had drawn attention here to a new heuristic tool. He writes

It is at once obvious that the equations .••• are not necessarily the exact expression of the actual law; and it will always be permissable to add several members~ or to give the equations another form, always provided these changes acquire no perceptible influence on the results which are established by experiment. We shall begin by considering the two members on the right-hand 3 side of the equation as the first members of a series .•.

Equations 4 and 6 thus can be modified to . . div grad .., I ~+

v'" "t"~ = f 4 ' (where v is the

218

6-, , g~8. velocity of propagation) div grad A V.z.m2. .. -"",.J. "

Such a modification is conservative in the sense that if v is infinite

the original equations are obtained, and if v is high the resulting

equations are not contradicted by experimental data.

Lorenz's problem is now in view. How is an equation with

the form of * obtained from 1, 2, 3,4',5,6', 7, and 8 ? What

1. See my Chapter 4 Section 7, especially page 165.

2. Lorenz (1867), page 291.

3. Lorenz (1867), page 289, his italics.

Page 219: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

has to be identified with~, the light vector, and what with a, the

velocity of light ? Such a problem is to be solved by evaluating

curl curl x for each of the vectors x which occur in the modified , ~

equations I - 8' and seeing if the form Q~ ~~ can be obtained.

Lorenz starts on this path but, as we will see, encounters an

unfortunate success.

He shows that

curl curl 1 =

provided that he makes the heuristically determined identification

of the velocity of propagation v of the retarded potentials and the

value of the ratio of the electrical units c. And he emphasizes

that if c, v, and a (the velocity of light) are all identified

then

curl curl 1 = ** is obtained, and ** is similar to * but not identical to it.

At this point the problem solver's strategy is clear: he

either discards ** as not having identical form to * and proceeds to

evaluate curl curl ~, curl curl !, and so on, or he scrutinizes the

c9~ addi tional term CT af: and ponders on its significance. The bes t

move is to do both -- Lorenz did only the latter.

The factor ~ is the conductivity and Lorenz realized

immediately first that in free space cr would be low and thus **

219

Page 220: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

220

would approach the form :

~~ curl curl.J. :: - 0..2. ~~a

~ and second that the c::T 8f=r term is a damping term which if tT 1S not

low rapidly removes a sinusoidal 1 solution with the result that

good conductors cannot support this type of transverse wave. And

Lorenz knew that good conductors like metals are opaque to light,

and that transparent materials like glass are poor conductors.

Lorenz simply identified the current density vector 1 with the

light vector ~ and concluded

'the vibrations of light are themselves electrical currents'

Lorenz's theory may be summarized:

i) the potentials + and A are retarded so that they propagate

at the velocity of light (which is the equivalent to the ratio of the

electrical units);

ii) the light vector is identified with the current density

vector;

iii) the problem of the boundary conditions for the reflection

and refraction of light are solved by means of (i) and (ii);

iv) in a laboratory vacuum (or interstellar space) the current

density vector must be non-zero and so the vacuum cannot be empty

there must be in it electrons or conducting matter, light is

propagated through a vacuum by virtue of the contiguous action

1. Lorenz (1867), page 228.

Page 221: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

of conducting matter, Lorenz writes

..• there is scarcely any reason for adhering to the hypothesis of an aether; for it may well be assumed that in the so-called vacuum there is sufficient matter to form an adequate substratum for the motion [electric current]

Lorenz's theory fits well into the A.A.D. programme. For

some time the task of the programme had been to find a retarded

force conservation generalization of the Weber-Kirchoff equations.2

And Lorenz had done just that, and in addition he had given the

boundary conditions for an electromagnetic theory of light. But

what has to be rejected by A.A.D. theoreticians is the suggestion

that the vacuum contains electrons. The vacuum is just empty

space and this means that the current density vector 1 has to be

zero, and so the light vector cannot be the current density vector

221

Lorenz's identification might hold in conducting matter, but it could

not hold in empty space. But since 1 :: fT ~, by the Weber-Kirchoff

equation I, the light vector could have been identified with E

and E does not have to be zero in empty space.

I. Lorenz (1867), page 301.

2. See my Chapter 4 Section 7.

Page 222: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

222

3. Hertz's 1884 Paper, 'On the Relations Between Maxwell's Fundamental

Equations and The Fundamental Equations of the Opposing Electro-

magnetics' :

The thesis of Hertz's 1884 paper is that Maxwell's

equations of electromagnetism are the best available. I The thesis

develops from a premise in two stages, by means of a subsidiary

argument and a separate proof. The premise is that the only two

rival equations of electromagnetism are those of the instantaneous

force law of Weber and those of the equations of Maxwell. The

subsidiary argument is that Weber's law, when properly applied,

leads to the retarded potentials of Riemann and Lorenz, and the

separate proof is that the retarded potentials of Riemann and Lorenz

are identical to the equations of Maxwell. Thus, Maxwell's equations

follow from Weber's law, and Maxwell's equations follow from Maxwell's

equations, therefore Maxwell's equations are the best available.

The merits of the subsidiary argument need not he discussed.

The desire of A.A.D. theoreticians to replace instantaneous forces

with retarded ones had been prominent for some time -- further

motivation, whether persuas"ive or not, was unnecessary.

The proof of the equivalence of Maxwell's equations and

the retarded potentials of Lorenz and Riemann is important. It

means that the elegant mathematical derivations of Maxwell are

available to the A.A.D. theoreticians for the vacuum case.

I. Hertz actually argues the stronger claim that Maxwell's equations are necessarily true.

Page 223: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

223

Maxwell had shown that his axioms had as a consequence that there

should be propagated transverse electric and magnetic waves;

the retarded potentials of Lorenz and Riemann, which travel across

empty space, also predict the existence of transverse electric and

magnetic waves. It was now manifestly clear that for the A.A.D.

theory the light vector has to be identified with the electric

vector and not, as Lorenz had done, with the current density

vector.

An unusual feature of Hertz's paper is that he does not

compare the equations of Lorenz and Riemann with those of Maxwell.

It is true that the two sets of equations are formally equivalent,

and so have the same consequences; but they are embedded in separate

programmes and have different interpretations -- as we shall see in

the next section. I think that the reasons for this are that

Hertz did not understand Maxwell's theory) his knowledge of it

was from Helmholtz's generalized potential theory which transmogrified

Maxwell's research; and Hertz seemed to believe .in the strict

identification of theories which had formally equivalent equations

he writes :

To the question 'What is Maxwell's Theory l' I know of no shorter or more definite answer than the following: Maxwell's theory is Maxwell's system of equations. Every theory which leads to the same system of equations and therefore comprises the same possible phenomena, I would cons~der as being a form or special case of Maxwell's theory ..•..

1. For the demands that Maxwell's theory places on the comprehension, see my Chapter 1 Section 6.

2. H.Hertz (1891), Electric Waves, page 21.

. .

Page 224: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

224

4. A Comparison of the A.A.D. Theory of Light and Maxwell's Theory

of Light

In this section I summarize the two theories of light.

The M.S.R.P. does not provide the means of appraising individual

theories from different programmes -- theories have to be considered

as components of programmes and programmes are appraised. It is

my contention that there was no decisive victory to the Field

programme by virtue of its theory of light.

Maxwell's theories of light have already been explained

at some length in Chapter 5. The theory is in essence that of

transverse medhanical stresses in an all pervading medium. As

J.J.Thomson, a British scientist sympathetic to the Field programme,

writes in his B.A. report on Electrical Theories :

This theory [Maxwell's] , which is called the electro-magnetic theory of light, might almost as justly be 1 called the mechanical theory of dielectric polarization.

The theory has no genuine electrical sources or receivers, and

there was some indefiniteness over the questions of how to produce

electromagnetic waves and how to obtain the Fresnel formulas for

reflection and refraction of light. The prominent attraction

of the theory was its unified approach no distinction was made

between the vacuum and dielectrics and in consequence one theory applied

directly to both.

Theories of the A.A.D. programme had acknowledged the

existence of current waves in dielectrics long before the advent

1. J.J.Thomson (1885), Report on Electrical Theories, pagp 132.

Page 225: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

of Maxwell's ideas. What was denied was the existence of this

type of wave in a vacuum, since the vacuum was not a dielectric.

The theory of retarded potentials constituted an account of

electric waves in a vacuum (and it also produced a revision of the

theory of current waves in dielectrics). The means of producing

and detecting such waves was manifest -- Lorenz had given sine wave

solutions for oscillating currents and charges -- and the problem

of the Fresnel boundary conditions had been solved. The theory

was heuristically acceptable as it was the end result of a thirty

225

year search for an account in terms of retarded forces; but the theory,

like Maxwell's, did not predict any novel facts.

In the late 1880's Hertz detected propagated electromagnetic

waves. There were flaws in his experiments, but these need not

concern us. The question is : does Hertz's result constitute

a decisive victory for the Field programme? Hertz and many

other scientists thought so -- they all thought that the existence

of a mechanical aether had been proved. But what are the objective

relations between the experiments and the programmes ? Propagated

waves were predicted by both programmes -- the experiments were a

decisive victory to neither.

Page 226: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

5. The Theory of Helmholtz:

Helmholtz's generalized potential theory has been mentioned

several times. and it is to be explained further in this section.

1 Helmholtz saw his own paper as a survey paper -- a'tour d'horizon'

of the 'pathless wilderness' of competing electromagnetic theories.

In this role the paper was hailed by later scientists -- like Hertz

and by historians -- like Berkson.2

Many researchers did learn

electrodynamics from Helmholtz's paper. it was the only discussion

of Maxwell's theories available on the Continent. And undeniably

the paper was a stimulus to Hertz and to his experimental production

of travelling electromagnetic waves. But Helmholtz's theory was

not a good theory -- it did not provide a fair representation of

the rivals -- and the scientists who learned electrodynamics from it

were misled as to the characteristic features of the theories.

Helmholtz's theory was a general Neumann-type A.A.D.

potential theory, using current element sources and a dielectric

with parameters that could be varied to yield Weber's theory,

Maxwell's theory, or the other theories. This dielectric was shown

to support transverse and longi tud,inal current waves, the nature of

which depended on the value of the parameters.

Philosophical considerations of the M.S.R.P. warn against

the effectiveness of this. Weber's theory and Maxwell's theory are

226

in separate research programmes -- a theory cou,ld encompass both only

1. Helmholtz (1870). There is an accessible account of Helmholtz's theory in Woodruff (1968).

2. W.Berkson (1974), Fields of Force.

Page 227: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

by some misrepresentation. And indeed this is what occurs.

Maxwell's theory is a unified no-source contiguous action

mechanical theory. Helmholtz endows it with electrical sources

1 and makes it into a non-unified A.A.D. theory. The Field

theorists explicitly rejected Helmholtz's account of their views.

Heaviside writes :

I made acquaintance with it in about 1886, and concluded that it would not do, ~eing fundamentally in conflict with Maxwell's theory.

And Larmor writes :

[Helmholtz's] so-called extension of Maxwell's theory •.• being based on distance actions is in conception entir~ly foreign to Maxwell's view of transmission by a medium.

And the secondary source Rosenfeld writes:

[Helmholtz's theory was not only) entirely alien to its [Maxwell's theory's] spirit, but it tended to obscure its characteristic features and to make th~ theory appear as a somewhat limiting case of the scheme.

Weber's theory loses its atomic sources and gains as

a replacement current element sources. One key idea that runs

through the A.A.D. approach is that electrostatics and

electrodynamics are to be united by means of one force law applied

to atomic sources. And it is this that leads to an

explanation of electrodynamic induction and to the dissolution

of the distinction between inductive and ponderomotive electric

I. See also my Chapter 5 Section I.

2. O.Heaviside (1912), Electromagnetic Theory, v.3, page 504.

3. J.Larmor (1900), Aether and Matter, page 274.

4. L.Rosenfeld (1957), 'The Velocity of Light and the Evolution of Electrodynamics', page 1665.

227

Page 228: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

forces. The Helmholtz version of Weber's theory obliterates

that idea -- the Helmholtz variant does not explain induction,

does not explain why Coulomb's law holds between charged bodies,

and re-introduces the distinction between inductive and ponderomotive

forces. No A.A.D. theoretician should have accepted Helmholtz's

generalized view, and none did so.

228

Page 229: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

APPENDIX 1 : History and Philosophy of Saienae

1. Introduotion.

2. Induativist versus Hypothetiao-Deduotivist Historiography : The

Problem of Seleation.

229

3. The Growth of Saientifio Knowledge : The Problem of the History of

Saienae.

4. Methodologies of Saienae : The ~obZem of Appraisal.

s. Methodologiaal Bias : The Probtem of Objeativity.

6. Lakatos's Suggestion: History of Saienae as a Test of its Methodology.

7. Rejeation of Lakatos's Views.

8. Conalusion.

Page 230: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

1. Introduction:

What does the M.S.R.P. '8 appraisal indicate? I maintain

that it measures three properties. First it shows the epistemo-

logical superiority of one theory in the series over its predecessor

-- if one of two more or less similar theories makes a successful

prediction which the other cannot account for~ then that prediction

can serve as objective grounds for preferring one theory. Thus,

with a good developing progPamme, one can say that knowledge is grow-

ing. Second~ and probably the most controversially~ often it can

show t~e epistemological superiority of one prog~e over its rival

at a given time. Lakatos regarded this question as a major pro-

blem. The diffiaulty is that under the M.S.R.P. science seems to

become a trivial game with good and bad moves, but what we 1Al~ is

for science to give us knowledge, so there is the problem of

arguing that good moves actually mean increase in knowledge.

Lakatos's own answer was to postulate an inductive principle stating,

roughly, 'good moves increase knowledge'. Postulation is not

argument, though; but what is worse is that Lakatos states that only

postulation can solve the problem. Let me quote him on this issue:

We should here at least refer to the main epistemological problem of the methodology of scientific research programmes. As it stands, like Popper's methodological falsificationism, it represents a very radical version of conventionalism. One needs to posit some extra-methodological inductive principle to relate - even if tenuously - the scientific gambit of pragmatic acceptances and rejections to verisimilitude. Only such an 'inductive principle' can turn science from a mere game into an epistemologically rational exercise; from a set of lighthearted sceptical gambits pursued for intellectual fun into a - more serious - f~llibilist venture of approximating the Truth about the Universe.

I maintain that Lakatos is wrong here. I will propose, without

postulating, an answer using one of Popper's and MUsgrave's ideas.

1. Lakatos (1971) 'po 101.

230

Page 231: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

FinallY3 it irulicates the heuy·istic power of a whole programme -­

for the continuing discoveries are good evidence for the potential

to discQver.

And there is another outstanding problem. Any author of

a case-study ought to face the questions: Why should the case-study

be done? and How should the case-study be done? These questions

give rise to Appendix 1. This case-study is done because it des­

cribes the growth of a sector of k~ledge and such accounts are

important. (One can jokingly~ but not entirely inoorrectly~ claim

that classioal electrodynamics is one third of all knowledge.) It

may also have value as a weapon for critioizing philosophies of

science3 if Lakatos's thesis on the function of case-studies is

correct. I will explain Lakatos's ideas on this later -- sadly I

think that there is not rrruch in them. The second question

occupies most of this Appendix. The answer proposed is that the

histoPy rrrust be approached theoretically and fallibly and -- given

this -- it is preferable to do so from a methodologioally advanced

standpoint which i8 expli~ly stated.

(As further methodological remarks:- I consider that the

positions advocated throughout this dissertation ~ere defended, and

should be defended by argume"ltS. And the bept arguments are those

which are valid and have tP'!,e premises. Ensuring that arguments

are valid is not difficult3 :zZthough many of my arguments lA1ere en­

thymemia forms and thus had to be understood as though they have

theil' hidden premises made expliai"t. Ensuring that pl"emises are

true is another matter. If the pl'emiees are LogicalLy true, then

in the main theil' truth aan be recognised without fUrther ado. But

if the premises are intend~d to be true ~-logiaaZly, then usually

more apgument is needed. And thus thel'e is the possibility of an

23 )

Page 232: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

infinite pegpess. MY way out of this was to pegaPd all the

positions advocated as conjectupes to solve ppoblems. Then my

concepn was only that of showing that conjectuPes wepe bettep than

othep known OP easily imaginable conjectupes to solve the same PFO-

blem. Generally this ppocess involved a sepies of valid aPguments

leading eventually to one op mope ppemise8 tentatively accepted by

all paP ties to the debate -- then, hopefully, the8e ppemi8e8 settled

the mattep. This mean8 that the pegpe88 was taken back only a8 faP

as the supp08ed cammon gFOUnd, so all claims that wepe defended hepe

wepe guessed to be uncontpovepsial OP wepe depived fPOrn ppemises

guessed to be uncontpovepsial. Anothep point on aPguments is that

stating the identity of the onginal, pFOposep of an apgument -- if

such a pepson can be found -- adds nothing to an aPgument'8 stpength;

it i8 mepe appeal to authoPity. Consequently in generol I gave

onl,y the aPgU11Ient and did not try to pe-inforee it by stating its

'80upce' . Of coupse, when I expound~d o~ cpiticized existing

intepppetations, I fipst made cleaP the objective claims, which

stood OP fell on theip own, and I then heLd that these objective

claims wepe my sympathetic ckaPacterisations of the authop's views.)

2. Inductivist vepSU8 Hypothetico-DedUctivi8t Histopiography: The

Problem of Selection: 1

How should one write history of science?

At first sight the answep is obvious: write a true and complete

description of the histopical events. Sadly the quick answep

faces a devasting cPiticism: its design is Utopian because the end

1. The contents of my brief introdUct"~on to some pFObl-ems in historiography are dealt 1Jith at gpeatt-!' length in the standaPd texts on hypothetico-deductivism and hittoriography. See, for exampZe, J. Agassi (1963), Towards em liistol'irJgraphy of Science, and p. 10f. of C.G. Hempel (1966) Philosophy of Na~l Science.

232

Page 233: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

~s impossible to achieve.

There have been men that have attempted to 'tell it like

it !.Jas'. A famous one was Tristram Shandy. 1 He resolved to write

in his diazy everything that happened to him each day so that there

would be a comprehensive and true description of his life. The

trouble was that it took him a year to write up each individual day!

And thus his diary was neVer finished. There is a lot to be learn-

ed from Tristram Shandy (but little from his diary). The key point

is that the quantity of possible infoPmation far excedes the amount

that can be written in a book.

Authors must therefore choose what is deemed to be the use-

ful true information and include it, and they must omit the useless

true information. This choice might be made in one of two styles:

at random or under some principle.

A ro.nd.om choice amongst histoM,oal faotB wou~d 'Lead to a

'shopping-list' history. What of value oould come of this? What

could emerge from a hotch-potch of facts about ThaleB, the Battle of

Trafalgar, and MazuJelZ's displacement CUFrent? The main argument for

this Inductivist Historiography is a criticism of the alternative

idea that the selection should be made undeF some principle. It

Fests on the indUctivist theory of error under which errol'S are the

result of prejudice or preconception. The argument runs as follows.

If the historian made a choice under some principle then he would be

bringing some antecedently adopted point of view to bear on the hist­

ory and this would mean that the histoJY~an's approach was biased and

thus, as likeZy as not, that the h~story itse~f was error-ridden.

But the criticism is unsound. The fau It with this argument is that

233

the adoption of a point of "ie1l) does y,)t have to mean bias. If the points

1. See the noveZ by Sterne. This, ard SWift's Gv:?-Ziver '8 T1tavels, are, in part, criticisms of the indluJt-,?}ist orient'lted Royal Society.

Page 234: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

of view are made explicit ar~ thus criticizable and the historian

is permitted to choose which of the alternativeB he adOptB~ there

is no bias. The historian may be under the directives of hiB

point of view but he iB not enBlaved by it -- one is not a slave if 1 one can chooBe a master.

Making a choice under a principle requireB a principle

which divideB the world of facts up into one manageable portion

which can be uBed and into another which can be discarded: it must

lay down what iB relevant. Excellent candidates for principleB are

hypotheses. A hypothesiB partitions the world of facts into those

which it pemzits or forbids Cl!'d to those which are irrelevant to it.

Pacts can be said to be relevant only in respect of hypotheses and

hypotheses can then do the job of selection procedures. Con­

sequences can be drawn from a hypothesis and then the historical

facts consulted to see if the conjecture is cOP.roborated or refUted.

And history books would consist of reports of such tests.

In a sense, this Hypothetico.Deduotivist Historiography has

a difficulty which is only one stage removed from the difficulty of

selecting facts. How are hypo theBes chose-? Where db hypotheses

come from? In answer to these questions. A finite~ and usually

small~ number of hypotheseB are proposed as 'happy guesses' to solve

probl,ems, and in respect of one probl,em that hypothesis is defended

which critical, scrutiny reveal,s to be the best among the avaiLable

1. Por a ful,ler version of this ~ounter see H. Poinc~e (1905), Science and Hypothesis (Dover reprint 1952) pG.ge 14J.

234

Page 235: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

7·· 7 • 1 expt-1.-cn.t ac.-terrtat1.-Ves. As critical sorutiny consists largely in

subjecting a hypothesis to the trial by historical facts, the best

hypothesis can be l·ecognized often only after the history has been

done. In whioh oase a history book should consist of a problem,

several tentative solutions to it, and a report of the test of the

solutions.

3. The Growth of Scientifio Knowleqge: The Problem of the History

of Soience:

The Hypothetico-Deductivist historiogPaphy favoured here

requires one more item: problems for the historian.

Whioh problems shou,ld the history of soience address it-

self to?

This is a difficult question to anmver for in general it

is impossible to judge the value of a problem without solving it.2

Thus, the historian seems to be oonfronted with an e~stentialist

choice -- he must just pick a problem and hope that it leads to

something valuable. However, while this is POughZy correct, there

is one exception and this will provide our answer. There is one

problem that is important and should be of conoern to all historians

of science: it is the problem of the growth of scientific knowledge.

1. At first sight facts can be relevant direotly to problems; for example, the question 'Did Napoleon win the battle of Borodino?' immediately points to the appropriate facts. However, this sort of problem dOes so only because it incorpo~tes all the hypotheses whioh can be used to solve it. Most pPOblems do not do this. Take 'w1y-P1'Oblems' -- for e:r:ample, 'Why did Napoleon win?' -- these do not have hypotheses attaohed and therefore do not indicate relevant facts.

2. And we cannot prediot fUture solutions, 01' else we would have them nOW. A fuller argument is available in Prefaoe v of K.R.Poppero (1957 ), The Poverot 0 Historicism. Of oourse, theroe can be a rational e ate as to the poss~ble value of open problems. But it is as well to remember that these can go hopelessly awry. Kepler's problem, foro instance, 1.UaS''ihy are thsl'€ six ,Jlanets?' (see I.B. Cohen (1960), The Birtf: of a __ NBW Physios., page J.%) -- but theroe are not six planets.

235

Page 236: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

236

In turn this generates the histor>ian's pr>oblem agenda and fur>ther actually

provides a host of types of solution to theBe problems. 1 For

example, say we hold that the growth of Bcientific knowledge con-

sists of conjectures and exper>imental refutations, then 80me -- at

least -- of the components of the agenda will be: Who put fOI'UJaru

which conjecture and why and when waB it proposed? Who r>efuted it

and when and how did they do it? And~ a8 an example of a 80lution

type: Bay scientists abandoned a conjecture and we wished to explain

this, the trial answer must be that the conjecture was refuted and

so we Bear>ch for> an expe:roimental refutation.

The problem of scientific knowledge is important for two

reasons. It is interesting on philosophical groundS. Epistemol-

ogy is the cent~lissue of philosophy; many epistemological

theories asser>t that CUrl'ent knowledge is so only in so fa!' as it

bea!'s the correct r>elation to past view~ so a knowledge claim re-

quir>es an investigation of pedigree to see if the title is war~nted.

In shor>t~ epistemology needs hi8tory; the philosopher would like the

historian to chart the development of views. The second reason is

that Bcientific knowledge i8 uBed as a basis for technology, actions,

and deci8ion making. Thi8 mean8 ,that a historian will be able to

explain past technology, past actions, and past decision making only

if he appreciates what was known at the time. A history of know-

ledge will thus be pr>eBUpposed by other histories.

There have been two types of hypotheses as to the nature

and growth of knowledge: dogmatic and fallibiUst. The first type

1. See page 173f. of J. WO."Tall (l976)~ 'Thomas Young and the 'refutation' of Newtonian Optics' in C. Howson (ed.) (1976).

Page 237: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

1 will be pejected and the seeor~ defended.

Dogmatist epistemologies analyse 'P is known' as 'P is a

proven certain truth'. For this view knowled,ge tends to be a

black or white affair -- either P is or is not a proven certain

truth; there is no middle ground~ for there are no degrees of

proven certainty.

The sceptic accepts the analyses and tenets of dogmatism

but shows that when these are combined with his standard arguments

they lead to the stunning conclusion: There is no knowledge. My

position is that the sceptic's attack cannot be repulsed: there is

no certain knowledge. The ~ceptic always uses the same strategy

he takes a knowledge cZaim~ say 'P is known', and then frustrates

attempts at certain justifications of P; he does not criticise P,

he criticises only putative proofs of P. The weapons used are the

infinite regress argument,the invalidity of indUction, the unreli­

ability of authorities~ and the possibility of perceptual or

intellectual error. The sceptic asks 'Where is the proof of the

certainty of P?'; and in reply he usually receives a justification

237

of P on the basis of other statements; he then switches his attention

to the other statements 'How are these known?' or 'Where is the

proof of the certainty of these?'; thus either there is an infinite

regress and no proof of certainty or the chain is stopped by a

proven certain truth which is somehow guaranteed and needs no justi-

fication by other statements. Finally, the last door is closed.

Typical candidates for proven certain truths not in need of justi­

fication by other statements are truths of tradition, the senses,

1. Of value here is LaklWS's e:r;tl:3nsive clasC'ification and argument as used in I.Lakatos (J.962J, 'Infi".1ite Regress and the Foundations of Mathematics', Secti~n 1.

Page 238: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

or the intelleot. All three are debarred by the possibility of

error -- the existenoe of error dOBS not mean that these alleged

truths have to be false, but it does mean that these alleged truths

are not oertain truths. For example, on oooasions the senses are

mistaken, this is not to say that they are always mistaken, but it

does imply that there is nothing intrinsio to the peroeptual

situation whioh allows you to tell when they are mistaken and when

they are not -- so any truth of sense is not going to be aezatain.

Similarly authorities, books, tradition, and intelleotual intuitions

can be in error; so there is no oertainty. Usually the dogmatist

takes a wrong step as he is chased up the ladder of proofs -- he

deoreases content in the hope of increasing certainty. Thus, if

he justifies P by Q, he aims to give Q less content and more oertain-

ty than P -- for instance, perceptual. statements about physical

objeots which are general.ly taken to be pretty uncertain are often

justified by statements about sense-data whioh say l.ess and are

presumably more oertain. The troubl.e here is that the steps have

to be reversed for Q to justify P and so a content-increasing logio

is needed. But induotion and all suoh oontent-inoreasers are

invalid; we have only to reoall. that Descartes required both God and

238

IndUotion to reverse the steps trom Physios to the Cogito.

under dogmatist standards there is no oertain knowledge.

In short,

AU views are thus on a par in so far as they are aU not

proven certain truths. Does this mean that all views are on a par

full-stop? Does this mean that aU views are equaZl.y good? Some

have thought so. BusseU teZl.s the tale of Pyrrho, the founder

of soeptioism:

He maintained that we never know enough to be sure that one oourse of aotion is wiser than another. In his youth, when he was taking his constitutional one afternoon, he saw his teaoher in philosophy (from whom he had imbibed his principles)

Page 239: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

with his head stuck in a ditch, unable to get out. After contemplating him for some time, he walked on, maintaining that there was no suffioient ground for thinking that he would do any good by pulling the old man out. Others, less soeptioal, effeoted a rescue~ and blamed Pyrrho for his heartlessness. But his teaoger, true to his prinoiples, praised him for his oonsistency.

But Pyrrho and his teacher were mistaken.

The question 'Are all views equally good?' is wrongly put

for it is ambiguous; it covers 'Are all views equally good as des-

criptions of the world?', 'Are views equally good as guides for

action?', 'Are all views equally good for making the one who holds

them happy?', 'Are aU views equally good as bases for e:r:planation?',

and so on. The ambiguity is. removed only if we reformulate the

question as: 'Are all views equally good for pUrPose Z?' and fill

in the end 'Z'. It is a general tenet of mine that any system for

appraising theories or views should grade relative to an end. I

see no point in merely labelling theories 'good' or 'bad'; instead

I feel that philosophers should argue that theories are better or

worse for achieving a specified end, then others seeking that end

1. B. Russell, (1941), 'On the Value of Sceptioism', page 1.

239

Page 240: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

receive helpfuL advice. 1

What ~e the goals or purposes that I intend some views to

achieve? Well, they ~e similar to those ends that the dogmatist

~aB trying to attain with his notion of certain kn~ledGe: to tell

us what the world is like, to be a basis for explanation in science,

to be a guide for action in daily life, and suchlike. Unfortunate-

ly these ends a~ incompatible. A theorry stands a better chance

of describing the world if it is timid and commits itself to little

-- for instance, 'Some animats are co toured ' is more likely to be

true than 'A l l stJans observed un ti l n~ are whi te' which is in turn

more like ly to be true than 'A t l swans are whi te ' ; whereas for a

1. In no~ative ethics it is common to distinguish intrinsic value and instrumental value: one is good in itself and the other good-in­so-far-as-it-fulfils-its-intended-purpose. Items which have a definite and manifest function naturatty tend themsetves to the second sense; fol' instance, a screwdPiver just ~ould not be a goqd screwdriver if it could not be used for d:ttiving in screws. Bet'tefs, though, do not have a single definite and manifest function -- they can be used for all sorts of ~oses -- and consequentty there is no one obvious meaning to statements like 'some beliefs are better than others'. H~ever, the force of these assertions can be recog­nized by choosing a goal or goals and l'elativizing the claims to these goals. This is ~hat I do. One result is that whenever I ~gue that one vie~ is better than another my conclusion has minimal commendatory content -- it is just a l'oundabout way of saying that one belief fulfils the function. The situation is similar in logic; the wore 'valid' has pl'imarity the descriptive meaning that an ~gument transfel's truth; the recormrendatorry meaning of 'valid' is minimal, -- logicians wish neithel' to praise nol' to ~hort; how­ever if anyone shal'es the goat of using an argument to tItansfer trouth then he ought to use valid apguments since they are best for that purpose; so we can say that the vatid ~guments are the good ones so long as we remember that 'good' here has a hidden purpose­opera tal'. There is the further point that theories do have at least one function, for theories are atways theories as to what something is like; this means that it is easier to suggest an appropriate end fol' theol'ies than it is fol' beliefs, nameLy to be like what they intend to be like.

240

Page 241: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

theuY'Y to serve as an explanation it has to maintain that one

property rrrust be cormected with another property~ that is -- it has

to be bold and commit itself to rrruch by attempting to describe the

structure of the world 1; again~ to serve as a guide to action a

theory rrrust make assertions about the future -- it must be bold.

to reconcile these differences~ I propose that the primary pUrPose

of scientific views is to describe the structural properties of the

world. Some views are better than others for fulfilling this role.

For a staPt~ some views are true and some are false. Of course"

the dogmatist and the sceptic would retort that we are not helped

by this as we do not know for certain which is which. But not

knowing for certain need not prevent us from being inspired by the

existence of the ideal to argue about the merits of rival views.

If this can be done satisfactorily -- and I will aPgue in the next

section that it can -- then what will emerge is the idea of a

criticaUy prefelTed view or a rational view. And we can label any

1. By this I mean only that the theories should be true unrestricted universal statements. There is fierce debate at this point con­cerning acciden ta l and nomic universa li ty . It wou Ld take me too far afield to enter it -- however" I will state my views. I place myself firmly in the Hume" Frege" Witt,genstein" Popper tradition of claiming that the only necessity is logical necessity (See K.R.

241

Popper (1934 -- English edition 1959)" £0 ic 0 Scienti ic Discove " page 438). If'A is B' is explained by 'All A's B'" then we can say that A must be B (in virtue of the universal truth 'AU A's are B') -- the statement 'A is B is" if you Zike~ physically necessary. However" the statement 'AU A's aNL E r is not itself physically (or nomicaUy) necessary. If 'AU A's are B' is in turn e:cplained by a deeper generali2ation~ ~ay 'All A's or C's and B and D' then we can say" if you like" it NUSt be the case that 'All A's are B. '. But then the deeper gene'l'cliaation iteelf is not in any sense nec­essary. For an example -- imagine OUl'selves b0.ck in Newtonian days. Bodies ~ faU as they dt:;. and planets must o"'ebit as they do (in virtue of Newton's L(Jh) of Gravity). But Newtor:'s law of Gravity" which is at the top of the explanator,: tree, is jU8t true; it i8 not" in any 8ense" necesf1arily true. (It is defini,:ely not logically true" then all it appears to be is 't."ue i~ the 2ctual world and true in aU pos8ible worl.ds ir. ',)hich ·:t i8 true' whi, h gives it the same statu8 a8 any other true k ~tem€r. t.)

Page 242: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

theory so favoured at time t the scientific baakground at time t and

scientific knowledge is composed of the modern background. 1

Finally, to return to an earlier point, each epistemology

te lls the historian what to do: he must find the theories and track

the critical discussion. These are the primarry aims, but there

2 are also secondary problems. Say the scientist's behaviour is at

odds with the epistemologist-historians account -- maybe the

saientists said that A !Vas better than B, aated as if B was better

than A, and the historian assesses B as better than A; then the

saientist's utterances pose a problem: why didn't the scientists

admit e:r:pUcitly what actual7,y was the oase and what they aated as

if were the case?, were they subjeot to external pressures?, did the

state or the ohuroh intimidate them?, and so on. To oonolude, the

historian should taokle the problem of knowledge and the problems

generated thereby.

1. I was tempted to call the theories so favoured at t the soient­ific knowledge at time t. This would mean that, for example, the ptolemaists knew that the earth !Vas stationary and the Coperniaans knew that the earth moved, and it might even mean that oertain modern primitives know that the earth is flat. Nothing turns on woms, but this tezrminology gives oredenoe to a relativism to whioh I am opposed -- therefore it ZJaS not adopted.

2. These considerations lay behind Lakatos's re-defining 'internal' and 'external' history. See T.S. Kuhn, 'Soienoe: History of Soienae', artiole in the International Enoyclopaedia of Sooial Saienae,Lakatos (1971), and the oritioism and Lakatos's 'Replies to critios' in the last mentioned volume.

242

Page 243: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

243

4. Methodologies oj'Science: The Problem of Appraisal:-

Thus far the sceptic has taught us that any attempt to

prove the certainty of a theory will be in vain.

Where does that leave the status of tlwo;ries r There are two

views on this: Pyrrho's -- that~ no matter what the end~ all theor-

ies have the same status~ and the optimist's -- that some theories

are better than others for achieving same ends.

The second view encompasses the rational tradition of

optimistic epistemologies. These assert that under explicit

standards some theories are better than others. I will mention

four such methodologies to appraise theories: probabilism~ con­

ventionalism~ falsificationism~ and research programmiam. 1 I

advocate the last tAJo to solve our problem of finding a rational

view as to the stpucture of the world. The first pail' enter only

to illustrate two points: that often the goals of different systems

of appraisal are different -- this means that were you to attempt

the ar~us task of evaluating systems of appmisal you must first A

argue as to whether the ends are appropriate and then consider if

the methodology achieves those ends~ and that the key terms like

'science' and 'evidence' have a methodological content which varies

with system. I need both results later -- the first to criticize

Lakatos's suggestion on evaluating systeme of appraisal~ and the

second to argue that a methodology fundamentally coloUl's the history

1. These are names for objective philosophical positions which are third wor~ objects. The Popper-MUsgrave theory of objective knowledge is presupposed in thi8 the8is. (See K.R. Popper, 'Epi8temology Without a Knowing Subject' c:.1'ld 'On the Theory of the Objective Mind' reprinted in K.R. Popper <.1.9'12) and A.E. Mu8grave (1968) ~ Impersonal K:1owledge

The named objects are chcaoacteY"'.,zed sufficiently for my purposes in the text, for a fuller treatment see Lakatos (19'10)~ (1971) ~ and I. Lakatos '1968), 'ChanfJesin the problem of Inductive Logic'

Page 244: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

fOl' which it is used.

Probabilism peplaces the dogmatist's aim of certainty by

the weakep l'equirements of probability. Usually this probability

is understood as being in the sense of the mathemati~al calculus of

probabilities~ although probabilism can be set up with other con-

firmation functions. In effect~ then~ the probabilist takes the

primaPy end of science to be that of being right -- ~lanation,

and action become subsidiary. Some theories are better than others

in so far as they have a higher probability. Presumably 'science'

is composed of all statements with probability over OM half, and

the 'evidence' for a statement are all those things whiah rtaiseits

probabi li ty .

Conventionalism is not really an epistemology in the same

manner as the other three -- generally its aim is not to say which

theories tell us what the world is like -- but nonetheless it is a

grading system for theories. It arose not to solve the problems

of epistemology, action~ and e:x:planation, but instead to ansl.c1er a

sub-problem of these -- the invalidity of induction. EXperimental

reports cannot prove theories because induction is invalid; the

conventionalist sidesteps this by arguing that theories are not in­

tended to be proven anyway. Their purpose~ it is said, is solely

to order~ summariae~ classify~ 01' aot as inference zoules be1AJeen

e:cpel'imental 1'eports. Observations are taken for granted and the

goal of science is that of producing theoreticaZ frometUOrks to

systematiae these. The JPading arises in that simple theories

order well and that means that the best theol'ies are the simple

ones. Conventionalism has nc notion of e:x:pe~iments being evidence

for theories -- the sole -:'tem .~avou1'abll'c to a theory is its

elegance. Also there i8 no propel' definit7:on of science -- any

244

Page 245: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

attempt to link up the data wouZd be 'science'.

Falsificationism, and its sophisticated variant the theory

of research proerammes, result trom consideration of one important

feature of the sceptic-dogmatist debate. The sceptic does not

criticize a statement, he criticizes only attempted proofs of a

statement. Toeether with the simple fact of logic that the con-

clusion of a valid or invalid argument can be true even if the

premises are false, this means that even if the dogmatist's premises

are false his conclusion may be true. ~ng doubt on proofs of

T, say, therefore does not throw doubt on T. The falsificationist

recorrrnends that instead of tpYing to prove T we should criticize T.

Take T for granted, in other words, unless we can prove it false.

There seems to be a difficulty here, for proving T false

is e:r:actZy the same as proving not-T true so we are apparently back

to squaPe one.

It is at this point that the decisive break with dogmatic

justificationism is made. The dogmatist distorts the problem and

as a result cannot answer it -- he thinks that, for instance, action

is possible only if what the agent intendS to do is certainly

justifiable. But this warps the set up -- the agent is actuaUy

aware of only a small number of courses of action, he can act only

in the light of the alternatives before him, and so action is poss­

ible if he can make a rational choice among the alternatives; in

other words, he does not have to justify the view that he chooses,

he has to justify only his choice. Where scientific background

and explanation are concerned, there are never more than a few rival

theories as to the structure of the lc,co,rld -- our problem is to say

which is the best, not ';0 attempt the -•. TtposFible by trying to show

that one theory trut.y and ,,;ith certainty reoresents the state of

245

Page 246: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

affail's. The problem of action can then be solved if the agent

uses the scientific background to decide which is the best choice

among the aZternatives.1 What Pyrrho should have ar-gued Was:

Eithe1' I will walk off down the road, 01' I wiU stand here mesmerized by my philosophical predicament, 01' I will pull the old man out. MY guesses as to the world's structure provide sufficient ground for thinking that the last course of action is best so I will pull the old man out. It is true that there is no guarantee that good will result, but that does not W01'1'y me for I know that equally there is no guarantee that good will result frCfT/ my walking off 01' that good will result frCfT/ my twiddling my thumbs. The onus on me is merely to establish a preference -- there is no requirement that I should be awed because no guarantees are given.

1. The problem of action is formidable and here is not the place to go into it in depth. But f feel that science is the anSlJJer, for if the problem is formulated in terms of instances then it is insoluble. My approach wiU be to use past ezperience to weed out unsound theories -- this is logically impeccable in that if a theory has a false past consequence then it is false and that means false for the past, present, and future. But for action an agent can maintain that he is not interested in whether 01' not a theory is false but rather that his concern is whether 01' not the very n~t intended exemplification of the theory will occur. Given that theories can have instrumental value -- that is, false theories can have true consequences -- there seems to be no reason why the agent should opt for the conjecturo.l theory over a theory which has been falsified. For example, the theory 'The sun always rises' is conjectural where­as the theory 'The sun never rises'is false, but the second may be right in predicting that the sun will not rise tomorrow and the first may be wrong in predicting that it wiU - so why shy away frCfT/ the second theory for the next instance prediction unless for the inductive reason that false in the past means false in the future? I think that there is no answer to this if one sticks to instances, for aU experience is past ezperience and thus is consistent with any future instances. But one should not stick to instances, for rational action is possible only if the World is law-governed -­random and c~tic action would be the only policy for a randOm and chaotic unive1'8e. Why not use OUI' best guesses as to tJhat the laws are as guides fOl" action? If we demand that each of the two state­ments be deduced f1'am purported scientific "LahJs, then past ezpenence

246

may be able to settle the matter. This will also mean that, for example, that the Bun has aways 1'isBn is not the only evidence for its rising tom01'1'OlJJ, f01) we know why the sun appears to rise and there is much past evidence for our explanation. I regard the fact that past pendulums have 8lJJUn~ J3lowero at the equator than at the pole (due to the oblatenes8 J.

r the spinni:1.f] earth) as evidence for the view that the sun wi l l I'I se tomor1'Otc].

Page 247: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

In short, a theory T cannot be absolutely justified, but there is no

need for it to be; T has only to be preferable to its rivals.

This answer is a variant of the Popper-Musgrove approach,

Musgrave explains it thus:

Popper swns up aU this in the foUowing fOlWlUla: 'We cannot justify our theories but we may, by considering the present state of the critical debate about them, be able to justify our preference for one theory over some others. '

One can say this only with the full realisation that (aJ to have made a justified choice of a theory does nothing to justify the theory itself, so that (b) we oan justifiably choose a theory which is false, and which we may have good reason to think is false, and finally that (0) the8e ohoioes are not so important because the state of the oritical disoU8sion maY1 change tomorrow and an opp08ite choioe beoome rea8onable.

What should not be accepted for e8pistemoZogy i8 oZause (b). In

the case where we have good reason to think that the oritioally

preferred view is false, we must withhoLd judgement and modestly

state that we do not know. There cannot be good grounds for

supposing that the critioally preferred view de8cribes the world if

there are good grounds for supposing that it does not. For ex-

ample, around the turn of the oentury the Rayleigh-Jeans account

was the best theory of radiation but in view of the behaviour of

blaok bodies no knowledge claims could be made.

The ideal method for establishing a preference is that of

choosing the best corroborated hypothesis. 2 In the clearest oase

this will involve logically-crucial experiments in which two the 01'-

ies make oontradiotory empirioal predictions one of which experiment

wi II show to be mistaken. There is nothing oertain about this

procedure becau8e the empirioal test is not oertain, but the method

1. A.E. Musgrave (1968, page 302. Popper ~e8 this line in 'Con­jeotural Knowledge: My Solution to the ProbLem of Induotion' in Popper (1972) -- see espeoially page 21.

2. The basio Popperian theory of oOProboration -- whioh i8 the one adopted here -- is expi~ined in K.R. POPI- er (1963): Conjeoture8 and Refutations.

247

Page 248: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

is sufficient to give the agent reason for preferring one theory

over the other. If a theory fails a test then~ as far as the

agent k~wws~ it cannot be a law; whereas if another passes the same

test it might well be a law so~ from the agents point of view the

second theory is preferable to t1e fipst. In a case of moderote

clarity we have to look at potential logically-crucial experiments.

It may be that the theories concePned make theip predictions only

when conjoined with a:w:iUapY theories~ and it may be that one

theory makes a successful ppediction whereas the othep lacks suit-

able auxiliapY theories to link it with the phenomena -- so that the

second theory says nothing about the phenomena rather than is mis-

taken about it. Hepe~ the first theory should be prefe~ed; it

exp lains the phenomena whepeas were the second to attempt an 8X-

planation it would fail. Finally~ there is a bi2~e case which

apparently can bring the whole progpamme to a halt. It arises

from the curve fitting problem: no mattep how well any particulaP

hypothesis is corroboroted in the above senses it is always possible

to devise an infinite number of hypotheses which are equally well

corroboroted and thus to pendep empty the instruction to choose the

best corroborated one. This aPises because any theopY can be

represented as a (generolly continuous) curve in an infinite dimen­

sional space~ and the finite knot.m datIL points in that space can be

used to choose be~een ~es which fopbid or fail to predict

particulap points~ but what the data points cannot do is to distin­

guish be~een cupves which account fop them all and -- as evepY

mathematician k~s -- an infinite numrer of curves can be drawn

h f ·· b • 1 throug any ~n~te num er of po~nt8, The Pop~)<~rian theopy of

1. The much vaunted 'Nell) Riddle of Induf'!tion' i·9 actually only this old as the hills cupve-fi+.ting pr~blem

248

Page 249: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

aOP.robopation p~vides a pepjeat answep hepe: only genuine tests

should aount. If a curve ppediats a point, then that point

aor~bopates the (]UPVe; but if a (]UPVe is droaLJr/. mePely post hoa

through a point then -- since that point aannot potentially falsify

and thus genuinely test the aurve -- that point does not aOP.roborate

This is an exaeUent theoPy of evidence in that it

solves the key p~blems in aonfi~ation theory -- namely, the

parado:ces of aonfirmation, the (]UPVe- fi tting prob lem, and the p~­

blem of aation 1 -- and it aaaopds with oup intuitions on evidence.

But it does not satisfy oup epistemologiaal qualms. On the faae of

it, the extent to whiah a theory desaPibes the wopld will be mepely

a timeless relation between the theory and the wOPld; whepeas this

aaaount of aOP.roboration embodies a time variable. 2 This, then, is

3 a ppoblem to be solved. I aan say in mitigation only that all

the ' (]upves' in saienJe that I wi U aonsidep lJi II be non-bizaP.re:

thepe b1ill be aatual OP potential aruaial ezpeztiments between them.

In this lJXJ:y, e:r:perience -- that is, past ezperienae

aan be used to make a pational ahoiae between (J(]f1f[>eting views on

the bJOptd's st7tuatuPe.

How might the debates about merit develop?

1. See J.W.N. Watkins (1964), 'Confirmation, the Paradoxes, and Positivism' . and A.E. Musgrove (19'14), 'Logiaal vepsus Historiaal Theories of confirmation' •

2. This time variable may be a pseudo variable -- the ppediation testing the theory may be known befope the theory is ppoposed. Fop the intriaaaies of this, see A.E. Musgrave (1974).

3. In my opinion the p~blem hepe aannot be ovepstated. I feel that 'ppediation-orientated' aOP.roboration theory is requiped to solve aonfirmation p~blems, yet my intuitions on tputh and verisimilitude have it that they aPe not 'ppediation-orientated' so how aan we link ao~boPation and verisimilitude in these diffiault aases?

249

Page 250: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

I will disC1UsB tuJo cases -- wheroe T has roival theor'ies and

wheroe T does not -- and will apgue that the dialogue proceeds in much

the same way. All that has to be invoked is the suggestion that we

use cororoboration to estabZish a roanking among the views between us.

But beforoe that I will explain the re~tion between fallibilism and

the logical models that I adopt. This is an important issue to

settle because Lakatos uses an arogument here as the main foundation

foro the M.S.R.P. and if the aPgW11ent is sound aZl of Popper'ian

falsificationism (and much of lAJhat I intend to do) 7JOuld be incororect.

Poppero, foro instance, lAJPitss of it:

if [it] were true, then my [Popper's] philosophy of science would not only be ccmpletelY1mistaken, but would turn out to be ccmpletely uninteresting.

My view is that the argwnent is faulty and thus falsificationism

supvives.

Ohm's LaLJ, to sta1't with an e:cample, for-bids cer-tain com-

binations of voltage current and r-esistance. Scientists can deter-­

mine, fallibly, these types of combination in the labor-atory, so the

logic of a test can be a monotheoroetical one with one fallible

theory and one fallibZe ~erimental reporot about Voltage, C1Ur'rent,

. ' and roelJ,.s tanae • Equally well, one could be more ~licit about

expereimental technique by saying that when a scientist measures

voltage, aurreent, and resistance, all he does is to determine,

fallibly, pointer- r-eadings and these requiroe obserevation theor'ies

for their intezrpreetation. Then the logic of the test becomes a

multitheoroetical one with many fallible theor'ies including Ohm's

law, and theoPies on ammeters, voltmeter-s, & c., and one fallible

1. K.R. Popper- (1974), The Philosophy of Karol Popper-, page 1005.

Page 251: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

expepimental ~epo~T about p~inter peadings. Then the question

arises: shouZd the Logiaal rnodel for the testing of, say, Ohm's law,

be a monotheoretia ~ne or a multitheoretia one?

There have been two firm ahampions of multitheoretia

mode ls: Duhem and Lakatos. Duhem's case aPises beaause he was not

a faUibiZist -- his aPgument was that in a refuting situation you

have to reZy on theories other than the one under test, nameZy those

governing voltmeters and the Zike, and so there are these extpa

possibilities of errop which should be listed in the test model. 1

This in itself, though, does not fopce the adoption of a multi-

theopetic model. If you are a faUibilist -- as I am -- many, and

pephaps all, of Duhem's possibilities of e~or can be swallowed up.

Intuitively speaking, saientists can dete~ine voltages at least as

weZZ as, to take a philosophical chestnut, human beings can deter-

mine that the tab les in their rooms are rectangu lar and brown. So,

we can forget about pointers and hoUl that scientists measure,

fallibly, voltage. Lakatos, though, goes one step further than

Duhem. He takes the view that even with fallibilism a multi~

theoretic model is mandatory. Then falsificationism fails because

nothing can be learned, even tentatively and conjecturally, fram

tests. With multiple premises, the failure of the test itself

cannot isolate a guilty premise and the success of a test may be

fortui tous . Lakatos's position is expressed in the assertion:

torbi any

1. See P. Duhem (1905), The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory (P.P. Weiner translation 1954) especially pages 180 ff.

2. Page 100, Lakatos (1970), italics throughout in the original.

251

Page 252: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

252

and the peasoning behind it is t~t ajmiped scientific theopies have

to be conjoined lJJith athep theories to entail ppedictions. Lakatos

. f h' .,. 1 g~ves no aPgument UP ~s a~a~. Ho,.:evep, I will give a countep-

example to it. Th~ fipst poiy,t to l'e cleaPed up is a terminolog-

ical one. Lakatos wPites of 'obseT1Jable states of affaips' and

takes fallibilism to be ~he view that 'obs8PVations' do not with

ceptainty peppesent the ' obserovabl,e states of affaips ' •

1. The argument seems to be that aU theopies must be conjoined with ceteris paribus clauses -- see page 101, Lakatos (19'10). But then thepe is a footnote which peads:

[Added in ppess]: Th-,:s 'cetepis paPibus' must not norrnaUy be interppeted as a sepa!'ate ppemise. Fop a discussion, cf. below, page. 186.

And on page 186 thepe is a muddle and the claim is made, in footnote 2, that the defect in the aPgument is 'easil,y pepairabl,e'. The 'easy pepaip' shows a subtl,e change of emphasis. In his (19'11) he states on pqges 111 and 112:

'What kind of obseroation would pefute to the satisfaction of the Newtonian not mepel,y a paPticu"lar Newtonian explanation but Newtonian dynamics and gravitational, theoPy itsel,f? And have such criteria evep been discussed op agreed upon by Newtonians?' The Newtonian wil,l" a"las, sCaPcel,y be able to give a positive answer.

(And this same passage appears verbatim in ppetty well all, of Lakatos's latep papers; for exampl,e, in his paper in the Popper (19'14) Schilpp volume). The reformulation makes an entirel,y diffepent point to the aPchetype. Fipst let us distinguish between observations and obseroable states of affairs. Lakatos's original states categorically that Newtonian theory fails to fopbid any observable states of affaips. The 'improvement' states that Newtonian theory fails to fopbid obsepvations specifiable in advance. The original is false, as I will shOlJJ; the improvement is possibly fal,se. It is a statement about the minds of Newtonians: it says that they are so dogmatic about their theory that they aPe willing to take advantage of the fallibility of any experimental pepopt. What arguments aPe thepe that Newtonians aPe as dogmatic as this? Lakatos does not resopt to psycho-sociological evidence, he simpl,y pefers us back to the original (now pefuted) argument!!! (See footnote 83 of Lakatos (19'11)). What arguments aPe thepe that Newtonians ape not as dogmatic as this. One can name a lapge number of people who hel,d Newton's theory and gave it up. Or one can pepforrn a thought experiment: wake Newton from the dead" in­struct him in relativity theopy, Eclipse experiments and the like, and ask him 'What obsepvation would refute to your satisfaction your dynamics and gravitational theopy?'J woul,d he not say 'The precession of Mercury's perihelion, when I see it, wil,l satisfy me'?

Page 253: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

But I have not dwelled on the word 'observation'; to me, it is too

anthropocentric and I feel that for science 'measupable' 0'1' 'deter-

minable' are better -- in other words, I put the limits of obser-

vation with the limits of measUPement. Then Lakatos is wrong in the

following way.1 Most of the most admired scientific theories in­

volve fundamental constants; one aspect that fundamental constants

have is that they are measUPable (how else do scientists determine

them to so many significant figures?); then the theories alone will

forbid measurable states of affairs involving these constants. For

example, Newton's theory rules out the measurable state of affairs

that there exist two one kilogram masses one metre apart which

attract each other with a force of 0.5 G Newtons. Then, to turn

this around. Newton's theory on its own predicts that all pairs

of kilogram masses a metre apart attract each other with a force of

G Newtons. So, Lakatos's arguments do not force the adoption of a

253

multitheoretic model: we still have the choice. Which choice shou ld

we make?

There is one advantage in multitheoretic models -- they

make more of the fallibility explicit and thus identify targets for

criticism. Bu t there are l imi ts . As the model ~pands the

additions to it have less content. Many 'observation theories'

have never been articulated and do not amount to much more than the

assumptions 'The instl'W1lent works', 0'1' 'The observations mean what

we think they do', or 'Our eyes are not deceiving us'.

'theories' are not specific enough to help criticism.

These

To sum up. Generally either monotheoretical or multi-

theoretical models can be used: one talks of more 'theoretical'

1. Popper rebuts Lakatos in an alternative way in the Popper (1974) volume -- I feel that my argument is stronger than Popper '8.

Page 254: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

notions like voltage and j?rce, the other of more 'observational'

notions like pointer readings. There is an advantage in expanding

a model, but not without limit. A recipe for producing a model is

as fo llO!JJs . Choose the type of statement that, for these pUl"poses,

is regarded as being dete~nable by experimental technique. See

if the theory under discussion yields that type of statement. If

not, add in all the observation theories, initial conditions,

ceteris paribus clauses, and the like, which are necessary for the

derivation to go through. The result is one of the many suitable

logical models -- usually we will be able to expand or contract the

model, if we wish to. I tend to use minimal models to discuss

logic and expanded models to discuss the dynamics of criticism.

254

To return to the main theme. Say T has no rival theories.

Even in this null case, T has so to speak one rival: not-T, although

not-T will not be a universal theory. Should we try to prove T true

or should we try to prove not-T true? My view is that this depends

on the fo~ of T; in science, where T is universal, we should try to

prove not-T true -- that is, we should criticiae T by trying to shO!JJ

that it is false. I argue this for two reasons. First from a

desire to make observation an arbiter -- I feel that if we want to

find out bJhat the bJorld is 'like bJe ought to have a look at it to see.

And secondLy from considering the forrm of theories and observations;

the scientific theories that we are trying to assess are universal

in form bJhereas any observations we make are of particular pLaces

and times, therefore bJe can neJer prove a theory but we might refute

Page 255: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

255

't 1 1.- •

To take the argument further let us assume that a theory

T has been put forward and criticized successfully in that an experi-

mental consequence of it, say P, has apparently failed. There is

noW a refuting situation and some decision will have to be made be­

tween two logically incompatible conjectures: one the guess that the

theory is true and the other the guess that the experimental con-

sequence is false. No simple directive can be given; the rule al-

ways trust the experimental test contravenes faZlibilism; on the

other hand, always overruling the test contravenes eMpiricism.

Let us look at the possibilities of relinquishing the

observation.

What arguments can be used here? Of the many, two types

are prominent: from initial conditions, and fraom instruments. The

first arises as follows. Most scientific theories are expressed

as differentiaZ equations; a differential equation connects the

value of a function at one point in space or time with the value at

the n~t point in space or time: it connects initial conditions

with predictions or causes with effects. The e:x:perimental conse-

quence P that has been referred to' therefore actually consists of

two components which are connected by a conditional: If the initial

1. Much of what has been argued about dogmatism and faZZibilism cou ld have been e:r:pressed as theses abou t language. Language is a system of conventional signs and it is a fact that the community of speakers do use the same of similar linguistic units to apply to (presumably similar) aspects of different situations. Thus, in a way, an aspect of the situation itself justifies or motivates, in the light of the community's conventions, the use of the linguistic unit to describe it. Then, all fallibilism amounts to is the ack­nowledgement that the labels are not sacrosanct and that they may even, for one reason or another, be retroactively changed. And the importance of observation as an arbiter is that it is here that the t:Jonventions are the most widespread, uniform, and entrenched.

Mary Hesse in her (1974), The Structure of St:Jientific Inferent:Je, makes rapid and deep advances which throw light on this line.

Page 256: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

(Jonditions hold, then the praediction must OCCUl'. And the guess

that the consequence fails is actually a double guess: that the

initial conditions hold~ and the praediction fails. The falsifica-

tionist thus has the opporatunity to aI'gue against the initial cond-

itions. He cannot meraely say that the initial conditions may be

false; 7JJe kYlO'lJ that alraeady, fora 7JJe kn07JJ that therae is no ceratainty.

What he must do is to devise and praesent a raival vie7JJ on the initial

conditions 7JJhich, 7JJhen 7JJe come to judge between the alternatives,

tu.ms out to be bettera cOlToboroated than the original vie7JJ. Take

the example of LevePTiera. At fira8t it 7JJaS the o~bit of Uraanus

that 7JJOPTied him; in 1846 he announced:

I have dernonstraated ••• a f01'lTlal incompatibility between the obseravations of Uranus [the praediction] and the hypothesis that this planet is subject only to the actions of the sun and of the other planets [the initial conditions] acting in accoradance 7JJith the princ}ple of univerasal gravitation. [the theory undera test.]

He offeraed a rival vie7JJ on the initial conditions by postulating

the existence and position of a ne7JJ planet the actions of 7JJhich

affected Uraanus. It took the obseraveras just one houra to find

Neptune, and thus the argument against the initial conditions 7JJas

successful. LeveraPiera then move4 on to the ne:ct great astronomical

problem: the obseraved perihelion of Merouray 7JJaS incompatible 7JJ£th

the supposed initial conditions and Ne7JJton's theory of gravity.

Again LevePTiera offered an argument against the initial conditions

by postulating a ne7JJ pZanet 'Vulcan' 7JJhich affected MeracuPy. But

therae is no 'Vulcan' and consequently the original vie7JJ raemained the

best corraoborated one. The second type of aragument oonoerns

1. See N.R. Hanson (1962), 'LevelTier: The Zenith and Nadira of Ne7JJtonian Mechanics', page 381. This article praovides the historaical background fora the example.

256

Page 257: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

instrwnentb. Few pf'edi~tions of sa{eutifia theories aan be tested

without th6 use oj" measu~~~ deviaes or experimental appaf'atus, but

suah instruments ~itly pFesuppose theories in addition to the one

under test, and so there is opportunity to take issue with these

obseFVation theories. FOF insbanae, Galileo alaimed to have ob-

1 seFVed the phases of Venus by means of a telesaope. If Venus

shines solely by the light of the BUn then, under the Ptolemaia

system, its faae should neveF by fully lit up; to the naked eye,

though, Venus appe~s to be a shapeless point; howevef', Galileo

assef'ted that he has seen with his telesaope the aompletely

illuminated disc of Venus and that consequently the Ptolemaia system

was f'efuted. As you would expect, the ptolemaists tried to direct

the arrow of modus tollens into the obseFVation theof'ies. Galileo

said that his telesaope was a 'superiof' and better sense' than the

eye, but this seems to have been a bluff for the weight of the

arguments were against Galiteo. To start wi th, he had no idea how

his telesaope worked: there was no obseFVation theory available to

him under whiah it oould have been subsumed. The instrument itself

did not perform very well on the earth -- prod:uoing ohromatio and

other abel"I"ations; and it seemed riot to wOFk at all when used on

the heavens -- it magnified the planets, but diminished the size of

the stars; the image produoed by the telescope appeaf'ed to be with­

in the telesoope and so, in the absence of a satisfaatory optical

theory, it was reasonable to assume that some, if not all, of the

obseFVed images, dOuble-images, and triple-images, were produoed by

the telescope itself; finally, through Galileo's telescope the

1. The histoFical basis for this example is proVided in P.X. Feyera­bend (19'10), 'Problems of Empirioism, Part II'.

257

Page 258: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

planets appeared to be coloured squares. Clearly the Ptolemaists

had some grounds for- questionirl] UJhether a co loured square reaUy oos

the fully illuminated disc of a spherieal Venus. But again, this

debate aan be Oflnduc ted aatisfac :;orily within the framework that we

have adopted. Let uS look anew at this test. What the ptolemaic

theory aatually forbad was Venus being further away from the Earth

than the Sun was, and at that time measuring the Earth-Sun and Earth­

Venus distances was a taring pFOblem at the fFOntiers of saienae.

GaUleo alaimed to have done it qualitatively UJith his 'coloured

squares' observation, alearly the onus is on Galileo to produce the

back up arguments as to why the observation meant what it did. And

it is at this point that the Ptolemaists can offer a rival, and

presumably better corroborated, interpretation of the 'aoZoured

squares'. As time goes by the task of overthrowing the observation

theory becomes more arduous. Nowadays we aan measure these distan­

ae8 it a thousand-and-one ways and so faulting a partiaular observ­

ation theory achieves nothing; instead a reinterpretation of a factor

aommon to all these theories is required; this is not impossible

(look at relativity, for example) but it is dif/iault. To sum up,

then, the observation aan be overthrown -- all that is needed is an

explanation of what is UJrong UJith it.

There is nothing final about the overthrow of the observ­

ation -- overthrows aan be overthrown, and so on. But what is final

and generally u~biguous is the state of the aritiaal disaussion at

258

a partiaular time: usually there is no doubt at all as to UJhiah is the

best guess about the observation at a particular time. As an

illustration, there is an embellishment to the Leverrier story.

Several people aatually did 'find' the predicted 'Vulcan'; in faat,

one Dr. Lesaarbault was awarded the Legion of Honour by the French

Page 259: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

Academy for discovering it. At this point, then, it may have been

that the best view was that the initial conditions of the Mercury

prediction were at fault; but eventually good arguments arose that

Lescarbault was mistaken and so the debate 8tcJUng the other way. So

much for the case where T has no rivals.

The same approach can be adopted when T does have rivals.

All we have to do is to look at how well the various views are

corroborated. If necessary we can carry out a series of crucial

experiments, this will establish a ranking and the grading obtained

will be absolute for a particular time, although it will usually

vary through time. 1

To find out what adviae follOWS from this appraisal, we

have only to recall the end for which the app~isal was made. With

these in mind, my thesis is that a scientist should maintain of the

best theory, 'This is what the world is like. This is the explan-

ation of such-and-such a phenomena. And this is what to use as a

1. I have devised an objection to my account. If we assume that all scientific theories are false -- an assumption that I for one am happy to make -- then if a logiaally crucial e:cperiment favours T over T' there will be other cruaial experiments that favour T' over T. So what advan tage is there in being victorious in com­petitive tests? The proof goes through as follOWS: if T/-p and T' I­-p and p is true, then T f (p & f) and T' I- - (p & f) where f is any false consequence of T and, of course, (p & f) is false and -(p & f) is true.

r do not know the answer to this and consequently regard the objection as a problem to be solved. BUt it does not look too seriouS. There is something a little strange about regarding ( -p v -f) for all f as genuine predictions of a theory which pre-dicts -po Consider relativity and Newtonian science and say gravitational red shift did not occur -- then relativity predicts Mercury's perihelion correctly and the conjunction Mercury's peri­helion and red shift incorrectly, whereas Newtonian science is wrong about Mercury but right about the disjunction Mercury does not pre­cess or gravitational red-shift does not occur. But does Newtonian science reaUy have anything to say about gravitational red shift?

259

Page 260: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

guide to action'. I must stress that on this account no advice

follows on other matters such as which theory or group of theories

a scientist or community of scientists should work on. 1 If I wish-

ed to offer advice on, say, this I wou ld consider first what ends

1. It was at this point that another wrong turn was made in the developnent of the M.S.R.P. Lakatos was challenged to say what the consequences of his appraisals were -- what were the repercussions for scientists of their hearing that a theory or research programme was 'good'? He, following a suggestion by John Worrall, then made a distinction between appraisal and advice and claimed that his evaluations were appraisal only and that, more or lesB, no advice foztowed from them (Bee page 174 of Lakatos (1971) -- 'Replies to critics' section). ThiB cauBed uproar. Among the first to bring the obviouB into the open was J.J.C. Smart in his (1972) Review of Lakatos's paperB, "Science, History, and Methodology',

He wrote on p. 269: What is the point of appraisal as such? Surely appraisal is valuable only if it is a guide to decision. In footnote 18 to Chapter 5 of his en Societ and its Enemies Popper remarkB: 'But it is clear that moral'u ents are solutely irrelevant. Only a scandalmonger iB intereste in judging people on their actions ••. ' AnalogouBly, if Lakatos's methodological prin­ciples are not meant as heuristics, what is the point of them? What is the point of saying that a scientific research pro­gramme is a l00d one if this is not meant as advice to follow it or to do ikewise?

And thus Lakatosians were faced with putting some bite into the appraisals. One suggestion came from A.E. MUsgrave -- that the advice should be not to individual scientists but instead to the community of scientists, that they should work on programmes in accordance with the programme's worth, that a division of labour should be effected guided by the appraisals (see Section 3 of A.E. MUsgrave (1976), 'Method or Madness'.

260

This is completely lJJ1'OnfJ. If a theory is 'good', the advice that fo llows is simply this: scientists should advocate the theory as an e:x:pZanation of the appropriate phenomena (and, in'turn, there is much advice which follows from that instruction). To be fair to Musgrave, (a) he does offer arguments fol' his suggestion -- I have not considel'ed these; (b) he is not the only one to make this sort of mistake, indeed, I myself in my (1976) 'The Rejection of Avogadro's Hypotheses' tended to use appl'aisals to e:x:plain why scientists ignored (i.e., l'efused to work on) theol'ies, whel'eas now I would use appraisals to explain why scientists ignol'ed (i.e., refused to advocate as e:x:pZanations) theol'ies.

John WOl'rall now advocates explicit~ the view that I hoZd -­see Section 5 d' J. Worrall (1976).

Page 261: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

the scientist ~as trying to achieve by ~rking on a theory -- ~s he

tpYing to find out what the ~orld was like? was he trying to make a

contribution and become famous? was he trying to make money by pro­

ducing a technological innovation? and so on. I do not do this here

because I consider such issues not to be in the province of

epistemology.

To re turn to the key terms 'science' and 'evidence'. For

a falsificationist, 'science' consists of those theories which are

falsifiable, and the 'evidence' for a theory is simply the set of

those items ~hich corroborate it.

The M.S.R.P. -- oW" final methodology is an extension of

falsificationism and consequently has a similar vi~ on 'science' and

261

'evidence'. It is enough for my purposes to say that falsification-

ism appFaises only a theory ~hereas the M.S.R.P. appFaises a theory

together with its heW"istic.

large differences in emphasis.

This seemingly small change causes

Lakatos suggested that scientific

theories should be considered not merely as abst~ct logical systems,

instead they shou~ be looked upon as systems plus associated re­

search policies or 'local logics of discovery! and thus there arose

the notion of a research programme which consists of a deep theory

together with a heuristic.

Earlier I discussed clashes between theory and observation

and the possibility of abandonning an observation in favour of a

rival interpretation and the possibility of relinquishing the theory

in favour of a better rival theory. But I did not discuss ~hat is

to be made of the clash before the rivals have been proposed. It

is important to deal with this because of the empirical fact aU

theories have difficulties in so far as they all have (real or

Page 262: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

262

apparent) exceptions or (real or apparent) inconsistencies. 1 This

means that we are always in the circumstance of having clashes with-

out rivals. If corroboration is to be used, it needs to be

supplemented by some guide as to which evidence is merely apparent.

Which 'e::cceptions' can be ignored and which not? How are the 'ex-

ceptions' to be weig~d? Lakatos has given an answer. He argues

that all major theories have accompanying problem-solving techniques

which consist of mathematical methods, planned simulation by

sequences of models, and overall research policies for exposing

'exceptions' and other matters. These heuristics weight the

, excep tions ' • If the heuristic is powerful, it in itself constit-

utes a good argument that an objectiVely sound case will be made that

'exceptions' of a fcuniliar type and merely apparent for it actua7:ly

provides the means for showing them to be so. A good e::camp7..e of a theory If...t"J.5

facing up to its anomalies is that of~mechanics, as described by

Hertz:

At first it might have appeared that the fundamental law was far from sufficient to embrace the whole extent of facts which nature offers us and the representation of which is alreadY contained in the ordinary system of mechanics. For while the fundamental law assumes continuous and normal connections, the common applications of mechanics bring us face to face with discontinuous and abno~aL connections as well. And while the fundamental law expressLy refers to free systems only, we are aLso oompelLed to investigate unfree systems. Even aLl the normal continuous, and free systems of nature do not conform immediately to the law, but seem to be partly in contradiction to it. We saw, however, that we could also investigate abnormal and discontinuous systems if we regarded their abnor­malities and discontinuities as only apparent; that we could also follow the motion of unfree systems if we conceived them as portions of free systems; that, finally, even systems apparently contradicting the fundamental law could be rendered confo~able to it by admitting the possibility of concealed masses in them. Although we have associated with the

1. As Lakatos often wrote 'aU theories are born refuted' or 'aZZ theories are submerged in an ocean of anomalies'. See, for example, Lakatos (1970) page 133.

Page 263: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

fundamental law neither additional experiential facts nor arbitrary assumption8~ yet we have been able 10 range over the whole domain covered by mechanics in general.

~~ If we assessed~echanics~ or any other theory~ merely by looking at

its prima facie corroboration~ we wouU evaluate it as being very

263

poor for it is massively refuted; but once we take its problem-solving

power into account it fares reasonably well for much of its troubles

can be branded 'apparent'.

Heuristics themselves are graded in accordance with how

well they are functioning. A research programne has a p Zan and is

good at a given point in time in so far as it is solving its problems

according to the plan and bad in so far as it either is not solving

its problems or is solving the problems but not according to the plan~

and heuristics are good in so far as they are associated with good

2 programmes. Lakatos's appraisals have epistemological import for

isolated programme: a good programme is likely~ at that time~ to

develop into a defensible view on the world's structure. For rival

programnes~ the oose is more involved.

The natural. way within rrry approach to argue the epistemo-

logical. superiority of one programne over another one is to hope for

a l,ogicaZZy crucial e3:periment bettueen the two. But there are

difficulties. The M.S.R.P. was intended as a theory of super

science: of the deepest and most profound theories only. With

these crucial, experiments become ineffective beoouse the theories

under test are each embedded in a plethora of other theories -- mere

1. H. Hertz (1899)~ Principles of Mechanics~ Book II~ page 735.

2. MY view is that there is more to the evaluation of heuristics than this. One tactic in science is to improve heuristics so as to im­prove a programme. This seems to 8uggest that the heuristics can be appraised independently of the programme.

Page 264: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

mention of initial conditions or observation theories fails to do

justice, for auxiliary theories and ceteris paribus clauses abound

1 and so multitheoretioal logical models are necessary. The most

that can be counted on is the existence of potential crucial

experiments between programmes: that one predicts novel facts which

the other cannot satisfactorily explain. Sound judgements on

potential crucial experiments oan be made only if the heuristics

are taken into account for what has to be defended is the assertion

that a programme cannot solve a given problem and that requires an

assessment of the programmes's ideas and its problem solving tech-

niques. To sum up. Actual and potential crucial experiments are

still able to establish the epistemological superiority of one pro-

gramme over its rival, and these 'experiments; are an expression of

Lakatos's appraisals (that a progranme is good if and only if it pre­

dicts novel facts and these are facts which are unexplained or

forbidden by a rival prograrrrne).

1. This point comes out in most of the existing case-studies, and in I.Lakatos (1974), 'The Role of Crucial Experiments in Science',

Lakatos was alliJays 7J?O.l'Y of interprogrcurrnatic cri t­icism (see the 'Replies to Critics' in his (1971», to the extent of virtually forbidding major crucial experiments between programmes.

264

It is true that major crucial experiments are not easy to perform for the people attempting it wou~ have to be masters of the scientific and mathematical techniques of both programmes; and even then the outcome may be inconclusive. Most ordinary mortals would be better to exploit an alternative pattern of growth by rapidly producing novel facts in one programme which, hopefully, the rival will not be able to ezplain. Even so, I think that the methodologist shou~ not restrict any fonn of criticism. Many scientists make good use of interprograrrrnatic debate. For example, talented scientists often explain their allegianace to one programme by claiming that the rival together with its heuristic cannot solve a particular key problem. This is extremely valuable for, if sound,it tells the workers on the rival that they must produce a 'creative shift' in heuristic. (See Lakatos (1971) page 176 and references in footnote 9 for an account of this technical term.)

Page 265: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

5. MethodoZogiaaZ Bias: The ProbZem of Objeativity:

History must be taakZed theoretiaaZZy and phiZosophiaally.

In partiaular a historian should be looking at the growth of saient-

ifia knowledge; and he aan hardly do that without some views of what

constitutes scientific knowledge and what constitutes evidenae for a

saientifia theory; and finaZly philosophiaal theories intpude into

those aoncepts. The historian will use more tainted terms than

'saienae' and 'evidenae' ~ but these key ones are sufficient for my

purpose.

This seems to leave us with radiaal methodologiaal bias

and relativism. A sentenae like 'Faraday's saientifia theory was

supported by such-and-suah experiments' means different things to

different philosophers and some would judge it tpue where others

would alaim it to be false.

To avoid this~ the historilan should (a) declare his

interests by being expliait about the phil080phiaaZ stance he adopts

and (b) use an adVanced philosophy.

P~thetiaally, it may be remarked that these methodolog-

ical bias aonsiderations indicate that testing historiaal theses may

be extremely difficult. It is only artefaats that ahance has per-

mitted to survive that aan be used;1 and doauments of these might be

ruled out on the groundS of methodologically biased design -- for

example, Faraday's own statement 'These experiments support my

scientific theory' might be no evidenae at all for the historians

claim that those same experiments supported Faraday's scientific

theory.

1 See page 797 of H. Guerlac (1963)~ 'Some Historiaal Assumptions of the History of Saience'.

2f)5

Page 266: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

266

We are left then with the p~oblem of dete~ning whiah

philosophies of saienae should be ppeferTed. The~e are logiao-

epistemologiaal aPguments between the va~ous philosophies, but it is

not in the provinae of this thesis to go into these. I simply asse~t

that the~e are objeative arguments to defend the view that falsi­

fiaationism and ~esearah programmism are the best among the avail­

able expliait philos~hies.l There iSJhoweve~, Lakatos's suggestion )c:

that there is a acmpletely new style of argument using history that

will grade philosophies, and that be~s on the possible value of any

aase study -- I will aonsider this in the next two seations.

6. Lakatos's suggestion: History of Saienae as a Test of its Methodology:

I have fo llowed Lakatos in arguing the thesis that method-

ologies grade saientifia theo~es and steps made in saientifia

debate. Further, we all know that saientists themselves grade

saientifia theo~ies and steps made in saientifia debate; they make

basi a value judgements like 'Newton's theory was good'.

Given this, Lakatos has made a proposal whiah is ~eally

part of a general theory of norms. 2 He suggests that the grading

theory should explain the grading j~gements of the experts; here

this means that the methodology should explain the basia value judge-

ments of the saientists. The value judgements whiah are explained

by a methodology aount in its favour, and those whiah it fails to

expLain are ~guments against it.

Three points about explanation should be made. To explain

a vaLue judgement means merely to be able to derive it fraTI the

1. Lakatos and Popper argue to this end. (19'10) .

See, for instanae, Lakatos

2. This is the main thesis of Lakatos's (19'11).

Page 267: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

methodology and the appropriate facts about the scientific gambit.

An explanation is a good one if it is independently testable -- so a

good methodology should predict unmade or unexpected judgements.

Finally, and this is most important, in an explanation the explican­

dum is a statement and it is possible that this does not correspond

with the world and thus is false; indeed, the explanation itself may

267

highlight the falsehood by correcting the explicandum while explain­

ing it; what this implies is that there is no assumption that the

experts have to be right, they are fallible -- they may judge a theory

bad, the methodology may con8titute an argument that the same theory

i8 good and the argument may win them over, in which ca8e the method­

ology corrects their juagement while explaining it.

As an example, I U8e Lakatos's favourite one. According

to the 8cientists, Newton's theory was good; anco~ing to falsi-

fica tioni sm, any unfalsifiable theory is bad; according to Lakatos,

Newton'8 theory i8 a matter of fact unfalsifiable1 -- as a result,

Lakatos argues that either the scientists should revise their judge-

ment or fal8ificationism is inadequate at this point.

History of science is thus used, in conjunction with the

scientists' value judgements, to test the methodo'Logy used to gener-

ate it.

'1. ~ejection of Lakatos's View:-

My thesis in this section is that Lakatos's new critical

weapon has limited strength. All criticism, even weak criticism,

1·,8 valuable; but it is as well to be aware that not much can be

achieved with this new approach. The argument proceeds in two

stages:

a) to the conclusion that the introduction of norms and value

1. This assertion, as we have seen, is mistaken.

Page 268: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

judgements leadR to a blind alley, for in this sort of

grading there is a hidden purpose operator and the judge­

ments and grades can and should be translated back into

ordi~ descriptive language.

and b) to the conclusion that there are vicious feedback loops and

that these vitiate the whole enterprise;l one might expect

that sane circularity would arise in using philosophy to

produce the hi~toroy which testis that phi Zosophy; however the

loops becane manifest only when it is reaZised that scient­

ist's value judgements are required and that phiZosophy is

aZso used to identify who the 'scientists' reaUy are.

Lakatos does have a point. Taken in the widest possibZe

sense, scientists know much better than anyone else what the worZd is

Zike, but this must be baZanced against the possibiZity that part-

icuZar scientis18, particular scientific groups, or even particuZar

periods of aZl science are degenepate. The philosopher must retain

his role as a critic -- he must be able to a~e that some science

just is not knowledge; for exampZe, a philosopher in the middle ages

should haVl:~ been able to point out that much of what ws done in the

name of science was without value. So, experts know better than

philosophers, but experts are fallible and their judgements shouZd

be open to cri ticism. What can be made of this?

Not much, I am afpaid. Lakatos maintains:

What the scientists tell us is 'good' is, fatlibly, good.

1. T.S. KuAn in his (1971) 'Notes on Lakatos' in the Lakatos (1971) Volume makes this sort of charge, but in a less explicit and exten-sive fashion. John WorraZl produces a reply to this on page 164

268

of WorraZZ (1976), his response ultimately amounts to testing methodologies against 'general opinion' -- but then do we need history and all of Lakatos's complex suggestions concerning it?

Page 269: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

This type of statement has characteristic diffi(JULties -- of i,Jfllf.e-

fication, of unanimity, and of correctness -- not aU of which

Lakatos's view anawen We have to identify the scientists -- for

the view to be useful one has to know who the scientists are.

GeneraLly this has to be done phiLosophically -- the scientists are

the people who do 'science' and a philosophicaL theory lays down what

'science' is. Again, for the view to be useful, the scientists

must agree, otherwise a statement might end up being both good and

bad. Finally, even if the scientists do agree, We still must know

why it is that they are right.

Taking these diffi(JUlties in reverse order, Lakatos's view

starts to founder with the second one. The probLem of correctness

is answered satisfactorily: there is no assumption of correctness,

all there is is the reasonabLe cLaim that the experts guess better

than ordinary people. As to the second difficuLty, there certainLy

is no unanimity over the basic normative judgements. This is be-

cause the no~tive juagements have a hidden purpose operator and

consequently should be unravelled so their meaning is exposed. A

scientist might teLL you in the one sentence that Newtonian mechan­

ics ws bad and good and bad, and mean that Newtonian mechanics is a

poor description of the world, is good for calauZating how to put a

man on the moon, and is a poor bet for a research student to devote

his life to. The prospects of real comparison deteriorate even

fUrther when my earlier result that different philosphies grade

relative to varying goals is brought in -- conventionalism and

faLsificationism, say, just do not make the same cLaim by calLing

269

a theory 'good'. To compare scientists' judgements we have first to

translate back into the descriptive mode. This means here that

Lakatos's assertion becomes:

What the scientists tell us is 'scientific knowledge' is,

Page 270: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

fallibly, saientifia knowledge.

Is thepe now unanimity or near unanimity? Well, there

might be. But thepe are two feedbaak loops that aause ppoblems.

First, the saientist would apply some prior (and usually unsound and

out of date) theopy of saientifia method in omep to make his judge-

ment on 'saientifia knowledge'. Seaondly, we -- the philosopheps

__ would use our philosophiaal theopies to identify who the

'saientists' wepe; nameLy, those who espoused and proaatiaed our

philosophy. And thus theroe would be two bootstrap lifts. A

typiaaZ pesult might be: an induativist would define a saientist as

being a membero of the Royal Soaiety (sinae the pules of that body

demand adherenae to induativism), in tuFn a typic al membero would

judge Ampepe's wopk to be saientifia knowledge sinae Amp~roe had

expliaitl, used the induative method; finally induativism apppaises

Ampere'S work as knowledge thus the grading theory fits the

judgements of the expepts. Clearoly this is a aheap victory.

8. SU11!TlCl!"Y

The imporotant consequenaes of the proevious seven sections

270

(a) History of scienae should' be aonaeroned primarily with the

problem of knowledge and then with any other questions which

that proobZem generoates.

(b) An advanaed philosophy of science should be made explicit

and used -- in this case it will be the M.S.R.P.

and (c) A aase study will have value as historoy of scienae and it

may have value for criticizing philosophies of scienae.

and the subsidiary achievements of this t'lf'/,J'ld( ~ t'~ ;

(a) to make a aase fop methodoZogieR (in papticulap the M.S.R.P.J

being app1'Oproiate fop grading epistemological ventupes and

for not being confined to being fancy labeUing systems for

Page 271: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

past socia-psychological tpends in what is commonly called

'science'.

(b) to stpess that gpading hepe is gpading relative to an end

and thus to make some sort of sense of the app~isal/advice

distinction and its associated flocculent lite~ture.

(c) to refute the linch-pin aPgument for the M.S.R.P.

This is the argument of page 100-101 of Lakatos (1970)

which is cited~ in every Lakatos methodological paper~ as

being the basis for the MSRP. (Need I add that refuting

the aPgument fop the M.S.R.P. does not pefute the M.S.R.P.)

(d) to refute the main tenets of Lakatos (1971) -- for example~

that history tests the philosophy which generates it.

271

Page 272: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

APPENDIX 2 : Fallibilist Realism versus Instpumentalism.

R.A.R.TPicker, the major secondary source on Amp~~e

and the earlier scientists reseapching in electrodynamics, urges

an instrumentalist interpretation of scientific theories. This

was discussed briefly in Chapter 2, here I defend at g~eate~ length

the view that scientific theoPies can and should be interpreted

realistically. 1

272

Instrumentalism has t~ditionally had as its rival dogmatic

realism which is the view that : a) scientific theories should aim

to be tpue, and b) the true ones are known, or can be knoum, to

be so. Then clause (b), and with it dogmatic ~ealism, is defeated

by means of the arguments outlined in Appendix 1; and consequently

instrumentalism has been dominant in this two-cornered fight.

But Popper introduced a thi~d category -- fallibilist

real'lsm -- under which : a) scientific theo~ies should aim to be

true, and b) we can never know for certain that a true one is so.

It is this view that I cont~st with instrumentalism.

The standard arguments in favour of instrumentalism, and

my replies may be reviewed as follows. Economv· Putting the

argument as a question : if we can never know that a theory is true,

then why make the unnecessary and superflUOUS demand that it should

1. This issue was brought into prominence by K.R.Poppe~ in his 1956 paper 'Three Views Concerning Human Knowledge' which is reprinted in his (1963), Conjectures and Refutations. The basic arguments are there; but the paper suffers from ruo defects : that of identifying dogmatic realism with essentialism, and that of using some weak arguments (for instance, the major argument against instrumentalism is that it does not account for the actual scientific p~ctice of testing -- in other words, our philosophy is to be ruled by what scientists do.)

Page 273: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

be so? The counter is that other benefits outweigh the loss

of economy. The Lewis Carroll argument. Lewis Carl'oLZ showed

that genuine !'Utes of inference cannot be conjoined as e;ctro

descriptive premises in a deductive argument; hence -- it is said -­

scientific theories must not be taken as descriptive major premises

~n the hypothetico-deductive explanatory model, they must instead

by understood as rules of inference. This argument is invalid.

Indeed if scientific theories actually were !'Ules of inference,

they could not be interpreted as descriptive major premises; but

the question is whether they are rules of inference, and this

invalid argument throws no light on that. Craig's Theorem and

Ramsey Sentences. These technical results in logic show that

the theoretical terms in some artificial idealized theories are

273

for certain purposes eliminable. Thus -- it is argued -- theoretical

terms are not necessary, they are merely a convenience and a

fictional convenience at that. With Cmig's theorem, a formal

theory with a recursively enumeroble set of theorems and ~o

recursive categories of predicate or term (theoretical and observable,

say) can be converted into another axiomatized theory which yields

a LZ and only the pure observa tion terms of the firs t theory. Therefore,

as far as the observational consequences are concerned, the theoretical

component is superfluous. The theorem is not profound. It takes

an existing result that a recursively enumeroble set (of a;cioms or

Page 274: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

theorems) can be recursively axiomatiaed~ and then adds a filter

h h l h b . l . 1 to let t roug on y teo servat'l-ona ax?-oms. Usually the

resulting observational theory will have an infinite number of

axioms -- one axiom for each observational consequence of the

firs t theory. To sum up~ if the interest is solely in observational

predictions and certain artificial conditions obtain~ the theoretical

terms are superfluous. But our interest should not be solely in

observational predictions -- our theories should aim to describe

the structual properties of the world so that they explain why

certain things happen. The Craigiaed ob8ervational theory doe8

not explain why its consequences occur. For inBtance~ Newtonian

physics explains why the moon and an apple fall with the same

acceleration~ whereas the conjunction 'the moon and an apple fall

with the same acceleration and the moon and an apple fall with the

same acceleration and the moon and an apple fall with the .•.• , does

not explain that observation. Consequently~ if explanation be our

aim~ Craig's theorem does not show that theoretical terms are

eZiminable. With Ramsey sentences the theoretical properties

1. The existing result is prove« as follows. (I use here Church's thesis to make the theorem more acce8sable.) Given an effectively enume~ble set of theorems~ the axioms are taken to be the formulas which (a) are repeated conjunctions of a given formula~ say A~

274

and (b) the number of oc~enaes of '&' in the conjunct is the code number of the theorem A in the enumeration of theorems. For example~ say B is the second enumerated theorem~ then B & B & B is an axiom~ whereas B & B or B & B & B & B or C & C & C are not. Clearly~ i) the axioms are decidable~ ii) a formula is one of the effectively enume~ble theorems if and only if it is a consequence of the axioms. For Craig's theorem~ we add (c) A must contain only observable predicates/terms. Then the second theory will still be decidable and have as its theorems all and only the observational theorems of the first theory.

Page 275: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

are existentially quantified over in second order logic and

are thus apparently eliminated. But they disappear only in so

far as they either lose or change their name~ and this is not

enough to eliminate theories. In first order logic the inference

from Fa to J x F ( x) is va lid~ bu t the inference 3 x F (x) to Fa

is not (were it so then ~x F(x) & - Fa would be inconsistent);

but clearly an existential quantifier can be instantiated, all that

is required is the use ofa suitable instantiating constant (usually

this demand is made in the fom that the constant be ~) 80:]X F(x)

does entail Fb for suitable b; now~ say F is the only property we

have to discuss the world~ and the world has certain objeats in it

which we name by our constants a~ b~ c and one object has the

275

property F so we commence with Fa from which we validly infer 3 x F(x)

from which in turn we validly infer Fb; all that has happened here

is that the object in the world which first had the name 'a' now

has the name 'b' so the real situation would be best expressed by

saying that if we forget about name8~ 3 x F(x) and Fa are logiaaUy

equivalent in this case. On now to second order logic and to

Ramsey sentences : at the local level these work as follOWS. Say

we have a theorry that 'a is a red magnet' symbolised as 3 x ( x-= a &

M(x) & R(x))~ and here We take being red as an observational property

and being magnetic as theoretical; this theory has one infomative

observational aonsequenae~ namely Ra fa is red); the Ramsey trick

Page 276: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

is to existentially quantify over the theoretioal property~

thus 3 f 3 x{ x: a & t a & R{x)), so that the trunsfofflled

theopY reads 'There is a property whioh a has and also a is red';

this Ramsey sentenoe has the same observational oonsequenoe as

the original theory; and, by existential instantiation, it also

has an informative non-observational oonsequenoe, namely a has a

property, N say, so that Na follows from the Ramsey sentence.

Ramsey sentenoes do not eliminate theoretioal properties while

retaining the observational ones -- they mere~refuse to name the

theoretioal properties. There are two oases -- looal and global

Ramseyfication. With local.Ramsey sentences a theoretieal property

(say magnetism) in one theory (the above one, for example) is

eliminated by quantifioation. But that property also appears in

other theories (for instance, 'All magnetie substances align

themselves along a line of force when treely suspended above the

Earth'); in whieh case the Ram8ey sentence loses observational

infoffllation over its original (for example, the original with

baokground knowledge has the eonsequenoe 'a points to the North'

whereas the oorresponding Ramsey sentenoe laok8 this.) So looal

Ram8ey sentenees are not striotly observationally equivalent to

276

their arohetypes. With global Ramsey sentenees every single accepted

theopY in which the given theoretical property appears are eonjoined,

and then the oonjunction is Ramseyfied. In this case the global

Page 277: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

theory and the Ramsey sentence have identical obsepvatior~l

consequences. But -- I maintain -- the relation between them is

stronger : they are now logically equivaZent except for the

change of name. Consequently the theoretical p~perties have

not disappeared -- we are mereZy refusing to call them what they

ape. For these purposes let us say that the meaning of a term

is fUlly known if a procedure exists which yields a 'Yes/No'

answer to those situations in which the term does 01' does not apply,

and also that the meaning of a term is to some extent known if

a procedure exists to answer 'Yes' to some of those cases in which

the term applies or to answep 'No' to some of those cases in which

the terrm does not apply. Then take a global Ramsey sentence for,

say, the p~perty 'magnetic'. The name'magnetic' disappears with

277

the existential quantification, but the quantifier can be instantiated

to give the p~perty instance, say N. N and 'magnetic' name the

same property, so that Ramseyfication at best changes or hides

names in much the same manner as what happened in the given example

in first-order logic. Every 'Yes/No' or 'Yes' or 'No' procedure

for 'magnetic' has the identical procedure for N so to at least

some degree their meanings coincide; but the 'magnetic' sentence,

the corresponding Ramsey sentence, and the N sentence are all global,

so there can be no extra meaning left over. In short, Ramsey

sentences do not both eliminate theoretical terms and fail to lose

Page 278: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

278

observational consequences. Local Ramsey sentences lOBe observational

consequences, and global Ramsey sentences merely hide the terms

and do not eliminate them. Duhem's fruitfulness. Duhem argues

that (dogmatic) realism is not as fruitful as instrumentalism. He

claims that realists have dogmatic (usually metaphysical) views

about the world and are thus prevented from expounding possibly

fruitfUL scientific theories which conflict with these prejudices.

For example, a realist might hold that 'God does not throw dice'

and thus refuse to entertain fruitful scientific theories which are

probabilistic. Duhem's objection does not hit fallibilist realists.

For these, any view on the world is just a guess and so they have to be

to lero.n t of riva l views. Quan twn the0:J/. Modern science -­

especially quantum theory (Q.T.) -- seems to favour instrumentalism.

In Q.T. a complex wave contains all the information which is possibly

knowable about a system or systems. This wave is u8ually manipulated

in a highly mathematical fashion -- it i8 governed by the

schrodinger Equation and is generally considered to develop not in

our ordinary physical space but instead in an abstract Hilbert

space. Information is extracted from the wave by subjecting

it to the appropriate mathematical operations. Any other attempts

at extro.cting knowledge, or asking how the process works, will

aLmost certainly lead to contradictions. To sum up, the theory is

mathematics only and these yield the experimental or observable

Page 279: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

pr'ed1:~t-i01'lS, and the mathematics apparently cannot be further

e:.L'P ~ahled or taken l'ea Lis tica ZZy. What is the fallibilist realist's

I make thl'ee points. The argument, although good,

is not a knock-out one in favour of instrumentalism; Q.T. is

mel'ely a theory as such, it may well be mistaken and be replaced

by a theory not inimical to realism. Point two. FaUibilis t

l'ealism seeks evel' deeper explanations : it wants explanations,

then explanations of those explanations, and so on. Whereas

with instl'Umentalism the quest for theories is satisfied at the

fil'st leveL In ovher words, realism is question amplifying

and instrumentalism is question damping. Q.T. as presented above

seems to halt all further questions and is instrumentalist. But

actually the above presentation is not entirely accurate. Q.T.

does not bar all questions : some are permitted both without and

within Q.T. Certain will lead to contradictions, but these can

still be asked and answered consistently if the interrogator is

willing to abandon some current interpretations of Q.T. For

example, with some 'hidden val'iable' theories all of Q.T. is

retained within its empirical limits but Heisenberg Uncertainty

is held to be false in its extrapolated and untested domains,

the result is Qn aitl",rt "t Consi.1t,,,t explanation of 'empirical'

279

Q.T. itself. Other questions can still be asked without contradiction

within Q.T. -- the difficulty hel'e is that the sensible physical

Page 280: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

280

questions become obscured by the current mathematics. In short,

Q.T. does not have to be instrumentalist. Point three. No

realist denies that theories are subjected to mathematicaL

manipulation or that they have purely mathematical portions. However,

he wilL wish to separate the mathematics fPOm the physicaL theory,

to make the theory as extensive as possible, to interpret it reaListicaLly,

and to claim that there are advantages in doing all this. Look

at the exampLe of the interpretation of Fourier Analysis. Often

a complicated electromagnetic wave can be Fourier analysed into a

sum of a fundamental wave and harmonics. One should ask in each

case : is this mereLy mathematics or is it indicative of the

physical situation. The answer matters. Electromagnetic waves

have causes, so if the compLicated wave reaLly is composed of a

fundamentaL and harmonics then it may weLL have originated in a

set of oscillators behaving in a specific fashion. As a piece

of physics, Fourier analysis has further ramifications. With

Q.T., there is an abundance Of mathematics, but much of it --

Hilbert spaces, complex waves, and mathematical operators -­"'11ft

ftc. -1 is fashionable rather than essential. There ... be a realist Q.T.

Thus there appears to be no compeLling argument to

regard scientific theories instrumentally.

But there are good arguments for interpreting theories

Page 281: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

281

reali~ltically -- these have been described in Chapter 2 and Appendix 1.

In bri(!f~ science should be conceived of as an epistemological

venture aimed at discovering ever deeper explanationa~ and the

problem agenda of science should not be restricted.

Page 282: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

APPENDIX 3 : Weber's Law and the Conservation o[ Energv.

For an argument'that Weber's l~ violates the conservation

of energy consider the following motion in one dimension.

Take any curve ~ (t) such that :

lJ (0) • 1

~ (1) ~ 2

• ~ (0) 1& 0

• I (1) = 0

that is, a particle following the curve would go

from 1 to 2 with initial and final velocities zero.

Let the particle fdllow t~jectory r(t) such that :

r(t) :. { Uc) O~ t-~I

<1(2-&) I ~ t-~1.

The particle goes from 1 to 1 with initial and final velocities

zero -- it t~verses a closed loop in the phase space.

The limits are :

t = 0 ~ ~ s 1 =:!p r :: 1

t = 1 =;> l$ :. 2 9 r ::: 2

t - 2 =7 r :. 1

282

Weber's law is F :: ~[I I [ (;.)2. - ~ r ;: J ] - -,.2. ,,1

Work done: JF. dr.

Page 283: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

283

_ I c~2..

c-. 2.. J {J.fl :: 1,t~[-j1i{ (~r- -tir G-~ r r 2-

(;-:0 C:/

Page 284: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

284

Bibliography

ACHINSTEIN P. (1968), Concepts of Science.

AGASSI J. (1963), Towards an Historiography of Science.

AGASSI J. (1964), 'Scientific Problems and Their Roots in Metaphysics'.

in M.Bunge (ed.) (1964), The Critical Approach to Science

and Philosophy.

AGASSI J. (1968), The Continuing Revolution A History of Physics

from the Greeks to Einstein.

AGASSI J. (1971), Faraday as a Natural Philosopher.

AGASSI J. (1975), Science in Flux.

D'AGOSTINO S. (1975). 'Hertz's Researches on Electromagnetic Waves',

in R.McCormmach (ed.) (1975), Historical Studies in the

Physical Sciences. Vol. 6.

AMPERE A.M. (1826.7), Th~orie Math~matique des Phenom~nes E1ectrodyn-,

amiques Uniquement Deduit de L'Experience, Paris 1826, Tenth

Edition Paris 1883. and republished with foreword by E.Bauer

Paris 1958.

ARAGO D.F.J. (1825). 'L'Action Que Les Corps Aimantes . . . . • Ann.Chim •

Phys •• ~. (1825). p.325. and in Quart. J. Sci., 19, (1825),

p.336. ,

ARAGO D.F.J. (1854). Oeuvres Completes, Paris 1854. ,

ARAGO D.F.J. (1872), 'Eulogy on Ampere', Reports of the Smithsonian

Institute. (1872). p.141.

Page 285: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

BABBAGE C. and J.F.W.HERSCHEL (1825). 'Account of the Repetition

of M.Arago's Experiments ••••• '. Phi1.Trans.18. (1825).

p.484.

BARNETT S.J. (1933). 'Gyromagnetic Effects: History. Theory. and

Experiments'. Physica, 13, (1933). p.241.

BENJAMIN P. (1898). A History of Electricity from Antiquity to the

Days of Benjamin Franklin.

285

BERKSON W. (1974). Fields of Force -- The Development of a World View

from Faraday to Einstein.

BETTI E. (1868), ' •••• '. Nuovo Cimento.l!. (The paper's reference

is missing from the Royal Society Catalogue of Scientific

Papers. and the Nuovo Cimento volume is difficult to obtain

the paper is referred to in C1ausiua (1869) and Maxwell (1873).)

BORK A.M. (1963). 'Maxwell, Displacement Current. and Symmetry',

Amer.J.Phys., 31, (1963), p.854.

BORK A.M. (1967), 'Maxwell and the Electromagnetic Wave Equation',

Amer.J.Phys •• 35, (1967), p.844.

BORK A.M. (1967b), 'Maxwell and the Vector Potentia1'.Isis. 2!. (1967).

p. 210.

BROMBERG J. (1967). 'Maxwell's Displacement Current and His Theory

of Light'. Archives for the Bist. of Exact Sci., i. (1967).

p.218.

BROMBERG J. (1968). 'Maxwell's Electrostatics'. Amer.J.Phys •• 36. (1968).

p. 142.

BROMBERG J. (1976). 'Review of W.Berkson's Fields of Force'. l!!!. ir.

(1976). p. 132.

Page 286: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

286

BRUSH S.G. and C.W.F.EVERITT (1962). 'Maxwell. Osborne Reynolds, and

the Radiometer'. in R.McCormmach (ed.), Hist.Stud.in the Phys.

Sci., Vol.l.

BUCHWALD J.Z. (1977), 'William Thomson and the Mathematization of

Faraday's Electrostatics'. in R.McCormaach and L.Pyenson (eds.),

Hist.Stud.in the Phys.Sci., Vo1.S.

CAMPBELL L. and W.GARNETT (1884), The Life of James Clerk Maxwell.

CAMPBELL N.R. (1953), What is Science?

CANBY C. (ed.) (1963), History of Electricity.

CANEVA K.L. (1978), 'From Galvanism to Electrodynamics: The Transformation

of German Physics and Its Social Context', in R.McCormmach

et al.(eds.), Hist.Stud.in the Phys.Sci., Vol. 9.

CARR M.E.J. (1949), The Development of Mathematical Theories of Elect­

ricity Prior to Maxwell with Special Reference to the Concept

Potential., Thesis, M.lc., London.

CHALMERS A.F. (1971), The Electromagnetic 'l1leory of J .C.Maxwell and

Some Aspects of its Subsequent Development., Thesis, Ph.D.,

London.

CHALMERS A.F. (1973a), 'Maxwell's Methodology and His Application of

It to Electromagnetism', Studies in Hist. and Phil. of Sci.,

~, (1973), p.107.

CHALMERS A.F. (1973b), 'The Limitations of Maxwell's Electromagnetic

'l1leory', Isis, 64, (1973). p.469.

CLAUSIUS R. (l869). 'Upon the New Conception of Electromagnetic

Phenomena Suggested by Gauss', Phil.Mag., 11, (1869), p.44S.

Page 287: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

287

COHEN 1. B • (l9 56), Frankl in and Newton.

COHEN I.B. (1960), The Birth of a New Physics.

CRANEFIELD P.F. (1954), 'Clerk Maxwell's Corrections to the Page

Proofs of "A Dynamical Theory of the Electromagnetic

Field"', Ann. Sci. , 10, (1954), p.359.

CROWTHER J.G. (1935), British Scientists of the Nineteenth Century,

Pelican Ed., 1940-41, 2v.

DAVY H. (1821), 'Further Researches on the Magnetic Phenomena Produced

By Electricity , . . .. , Phi1.Trans., 111, (1821), p.425.

DESCARTES R. (1634), 'Letter to Beeckman', in Oeuvres, ed. Tannery-Adam,

!, p.307.

DIBNER B. (1961), Oersted and the Discovery of Electromagnetism.

DICTIONARY OF SCIENTIFIC BIOGRAPHY.

DOHB C. (ed.) (1963), Clerk Maxwell and Modern Science.

DORAN B.G. (1975), 'Origins and Consolidation of Field Theory in

Nineteenth-Century Britain : From the Mechanical to the

Electromagnetic View of Nature', in R.McCormmach (ed.),

Hist.Stud.in the Phys.Sci., Vol.6.

DORLING J. (1973), 'Demonstrative Induction Its Significant Role in

the History of Physics', Phil. of Sci., 40, (1973), p.360.

DORLING J. (1978), 'On Explanations in Physics: Sketch of an

Alternative to Hempel's Account of the Explanation of Laws',

Phil. of Sci., 45, (1978), p.136.

DRUDE P. (1897), 'Ueber Fernwirkungen', Ann.der Phys.,!!, (1897), p.i.

Page 288: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

, DUHEM P. (1902) • Les Theories E1ectrigues de J.C .Maxwe1l.

DUHEM P. (1905) • The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory. (tr.

P.P.Wiener. 1962).

DUHEK P. (1969). To Save the Phenomena.

EVERITT C.W.F. (1975). James Clerk Maxwell.

FARADAY M. (1821, 2). 'Historical Sketch of Electro-Magnetism',

Annals of Phil., 1. (1821), p.195, p.274, and 1. (1822),

p.l07.

FARADAY M. (1832-6), Diary.

FARADAY M. (1839-55). Experimental Researches in Electricity. 3v.

FECHNER G.T. (1831), Haassbestimmungen Uber Die Galvanische Kette.

FECHNER G.T. (1845). 'Ueber die Verknupfung der Faraday'-schen

Inductions •••• '. Ann.der Phys •• 64. (1845). p.337.

FEYERABEND P.K. (1968). 'How to be a Good Empiricist -- A Plea

for Tolerance in Matters Epistemological', in P.H.Nidditch

(ed.), (1968), The Philosophy of Science.

FEYERABEND P.K. (1970), 'Problems of Empiricism. Part II', in R.G.

288

Co1odny (ed.) (1970). The Nature and Function of Scientific

Theory.

FEYNMANN R.P. (1964), Lectures on PhYSiCS, 3v.

FITZGERALD G.F. (1902), The Scientific Writings of G.F.Fitzgerald,

ed. J.Larmor.

FRICKE M. (1976). 'The Rejection of Avogadro's Hypotheses', in C.

Howson (ed.) (1976). , ,

GARDINER K.R. and D.L. (1965), 'Andre-Marie Ampere and His English

Acquaintances'. B.J.Hist.Sci., 1, (1965), p.235.

Page 289: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

289

GAUSS C.F. (1877), Werke, 1.

GILLISPIE C.C. (1960), The Edge of Objectivity.

GLAZEBROOK R.T. (1896), James Clerk Maxwell and Modern Physics.

GREEN G. (1828), 'An Essay on the Application of Mathematical Analysis

to the Theories of Electricity and Magnetism', rep. in

The Mathematical Papers of the Late Gearge Green.

GROVE W. (1867), The Correlation of Physical Forces, 5th.Ed.

GUERLAC H. (1963), 'Some Historical Assumptions of the History of

Science', in A.C.Crombie (ed.), (1963), Scientific Change.

GUILLEHIN E.A. (1932), 'Early Developments in Electromagnetic Theory',

!!!!, 18, (1932), p.118.

HAAS-LORENTZ G.L. De (ed.) (1957), B.A. Lorentz -- Impressions of His

Life and Work.

HALL E.H. (1879), 'On a New Action of the Magnet on Electric Currents',·

Amer.J.Math., !, (1879), p.287.

HANSON N.R. (1962), 'Leverrier : The Zenith and Nadir of Newtonian

Mechanics'~ Isis, 21, (1962), p.359.

HANS TEEN (1857), Letter to Michael Faraday. 3Oth.Dec.1857, in B.

Bence Jones, Life and Letters of Faraday, !, p.395.

HARE R. (1840), 'A Letter to Prof.Faraday, on Certain Theoretical

Opinions', rep. in Phi1.Hag., 17, (1840), p.44.

HEAVISIDE o. (1893-1912), Electromagnetic Theory, 3v., Dover reprint

1950, lv.

HEIMANN P.M. (1970), 'Maxwell and the Hodes of Consistent Representation',

Archive. for History of Exact Sciences, 6, (1970), p.17l.

Page 290: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

HEIMANN P.M. (1971), 'Maxwell, Hertz, and the Nature of Electricity',

Isis, ~, (1971), p.149.

HEIMANN P.M. (197lb), 'Faraday's Theories of Matter and Electricity',

B.J.Hist.Sci.,1, (1971), p.235.

HELMHOLTZ H. (1847), 'On the Conservation of Force', in R.Taylor,

Scientific Memoirs,S, (1853), p.114.

HELMHOLTZ H. (1870), 'Ueber die Theorie der Elektrodynamik, I',

Wissenschaftliche Abhandlungen, 1, (1882), p.545.

HELMHOLTZ H. (1872), 'Ueber die Tneorie der Elecktrodynamik, II',

rep. in English in Phil,Mag., 44, (1872), p.530.

290

HELMHOLTZ H. (1873), 'On Later Views of the Connection of Electricity

and Magnetism', Smithsonian Repo~t8, (1873), p.246.

HELMHOLTZ H. (1876), 'On the Electromagnetic Action of Electric'

Convection', Phil.Mag.,!, (1876), p.233.

HELMHOLTZ H. (1881), 'On the MOdern Development of Faraday's Con­

ception of Electricity', J. of the Chem.Soc., 39, (1881),

p.

HEMPEL C.G. (1966), Philosophy of Natural Science.

HERTZ H. (1884), 'On the Relations Between Maxwell's Fundamental

Electromagnetic Equations and The Fundamental Equations of

the Opposing Electromagnetics', rep. in Hertz (1896).

HERTZ H. (1892), Electric Waves.

HERTZ H. (1896), Miscellaneous Papers, Landmarks of Science Micro-card.

HERTZ H. (1899). The Principles of Mechanics.

Page 291: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

HESSE M.B. (1953), 'Models in Physics', B.J.P.S •• !. (1953). p.198.

HESSE M.B. (1955) • 'Action at a Distance in Classical Physics',

!!!!.' 46. (1955). p.337.

HESSE M.B.

HESSE M.B.

HESSE M.B.

(1961) • Forces and Fields.

(1963) • Models and Analogies in Science.

(1973) • 'Logic of Discovery in Maxye11's Electromagnetic

Theory', in R.N.Giere and R.S.Westfa11 (eds.) (1973)

Foundations of Scientific Method : The Nineteenth Century.

HESSE M.B. (1974), The Structure of Scientific Inference.

291

HIROSIGE T. (1962), 'Lorentz's Theory of Electrons and the Development

of the Concept of the E1ec~omagnetic Field', Jap.Stud.Hist.

Sci,. 1. (1962). p.101.

HIROSIGE T. (1966), 'Electrodynamics before the Theory of Relativity.

1890-1905'. Jap.Stud.Hist.Sci •• 1. (1966). p.1.

HlROSlGE T. (1969), 'Origins of Lorentz's Theory of Electrons and the

Concept of the Electromagnetic Field', in R.McCormmach (ed.).

Hist.Stud.in the Phys.Sci •• Vo1.1.

HOPLEY 1.B. (1959), 'Maxwell's Determination of the Number of Elect­

rostatic Units in One Electromagnetic Unit of Electricity',

Ann.Sci., 15, (1959), p.91.

HOSPERS J. (1956). 'What is Explanation?'. reprinted in A.G.N.F1ew,

(ed.). (1956). Essays in Conceptual Analysis.

HOVGAARD W. (1932). 'Ritz's Electrodynamic Theory'. Stud. in Applied

~ •• (1932). p.2l8.

HOWSON C. (ed.) (1976), Method and Appraisal in the Physical Sciences.

Page 292: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

HUMPHREYS A.W. (1937), 'The Development of the Conception and

Measurement of Electric Current', Ann.Sci., 2, (1937),

p.164.

HUTTEN E.H. (1948), 'On Semantics and Physics', Proc.Arist.Soc., 49,

(1948), p.ll5.

HUTTEN E.H. (1953), 'The Role of Models in Physics', B.J.P.S., 4,

(1953), p.284.

JONES R.V. (1973), 'James Clerk Maxwell at Aberdeen 1856-60', Notes

and Records of the Royal Society of London, 28, (1973),

p.S7.

KANT I. (1786), Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science,

translated by J.Ellington (1970).

KARGON R. (1969), 'Model and Analogy in Victorian SCience, Ma~ell's

292

Critique of the French Physicists', Journal of the Bist. of

Ideas, 30, (1969), p.423.

KING R.W.P. (1949), 'Review of Mogens Pihl : Der Physiker L.V.Lorenz.

Eine Kritische Untersuchung', !!!!, 40,(1949), p.64.

KIRCHOFF G. (1849), 'Ueber eine Ableitung der Ohm'schen Gesetze

Ann.der Phys., 1!, (1849). p.S06, and reprinted in

Phil.Mag •• 11.. (1850), p.463.

, . .. ,

KIRCHOFF G. (1857), 'On the Motion of Electricity in Wires', Phil.

Mag •• 88, (1857), p.393.

KIRCHOFF G. (1857&), 'Uber die Bewegung der Electricitat in Drahten',

this i8 the German original of his (1857).

Page 293: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

2~3

KIRCHOFF G. (1857b), 'Uber die Bewegung der Electricitat in Leitern'.

Ann.der Phys., 102, (1857), p.529.

KOENIGSBERGER L. (1906), Hermann von Helmholtz, translated by F.A.

Welby.

KUHN T.S. (1971), 'Notes on Lakatos', in R.C.Buck and R.S.Cohen

(eds.), Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol.8.

LAKATOS I. (1962). 'Infinite Regress and the Foundations of Mathematics',

Arist.Soc.Supp.Vol •• 36. (1962). p.155.

LAKATOS I. (1968), 'Changes in the Problem of Inductive Logic'. in

I.Lakatos (ed.). The Problem of Inductive Logic.

LAKATOS I. (1970). 'Falsificationism and the Methodology of Scientific

Research Programmes'. in I.Lakatos and A.E.Muagrave (eds.)

(1970). Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge.

LAKATOS I. (1971), 'History of Science and Its Rational Reconstructions'.

reprinted in Howson (1976).

LAKATOS I. (1974). 'The Role of Crucial Experiments in Science', Studies

in the History and Philosophy of Science, i. (1974). p.3S7.

LAKATOS I. and A.E. MUSGRAVE (eds.) (1970), Criticism and the Growth

of Knowledge. ~ ,

LAPLACE P.S. (1829-39). Mechanique Celeste.

LARHOR J. (ed.) (1937), Origins of Clerk Kazwe11's Electric Idea..

LENZ E. (1834). 'Ueber die Bestimmung der Richtung •••• '. Ann.der Phys ••

31, (1834), p.483.

LODGE O.J. (1892), Modern Views on Electricity, 2nd.Ed.

LORENTZ H.A. (1909), Theory of Electrons.

Page 294: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

LORENTZ H.A. (1923), Clerk Maxwell's Electromagnetic Theory, The

Rede Lecture for 1923.

LORENZ L. (1867), 'On the Identity of the Vibrations of Light and

Electrical Currents', Phil.Mag., 34, (1867), p.287.

HAGlE W.F. (1935), A Source Book in Physics.

McCORHMACH R. (1970), 'H.A.Lorentz and the Electromagnetic View of

Nature', Isis, 61, (1970), p.459.

McGUIRE I.E. (1968), 'The Origin of Newton's Doctrine of Essential

Qualities', Centaurus, 12, (1968), p.233.

MAXWELL J.C. (1855), 'Letter to William Thomson', in Larmer (ed.),

(1937), p.17.

HAXWELL J.C. (1856), 'On Faraday's Lines of Force', reprinted in

Niven (ed.) (1965), The Scientific Papers of James

C1erk-Haxwe11.

MAXWELL J.C. (1862), 'On Physical Lines of Force', reprinted in

Niven (ed.) (1965).

MAXWELL J.C. (1865), 'A Dynamical Theory of the Electromagnetic

Field', reprinted in Niven (ed.) (1965).

MAXWELL J.C. (1868), 'On a Method of Making a Direct Comparison

of Electrostatic with Electromagnetic Force; with a Note

on the Electromagnetic Theory of Light', reprinted in

Niven (ed.) (1965).

MAXWELL J.C. (1868b), 'Thomson and Tait's Natural Philosophy',

reprinted in Niven (ed.) (1965).

294

Page 295: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

MAXWELL J.C. (1873), A Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism, in

general I have used the 1891 3rd. edition which is

available in a 1954 Dover reprint.

MAXWELL J.C. (1873b), 'Electromagnetism', English Cyclopaedia, Arts

and Sciences Supplement, (1873), p.854.

MAXWELL J.C. (1877), Matter and MOtion.

MAXWELL J.C. (1881), An Elementary Treatise on Electricity.

MAXWELL J.C., 'On Action at a Distance' reprinted in Niven (ed.)

(1965).

MAXWELL J.C. (1931), James Clerk Maxwell: a Commemorative Volume

1831-1931, (Essays by J.J.Thomson, Planck, Einstein, etc.)

MAXWELL J.C. and FLEEMING JENKIN (1863),'00 the Elementary Relations

between Electrical Measurements', App.C to the 2nd. B.A.

Report on Electrical Standards, (1863), p.l30.

MEIER H.W. (1971), A History of Electricity and Magnetism.

MEYER K. (1920), H.C.Oersted,Scientific Papers, 3v.

MOTTELAY P.F. (1922), Bibliographical History of Electricity and

Magnetism, Chronologically Arranged.

295

MURPHY R. (1833), Elementary Principles of the Theories of Electricity,

Heat. and Molecular Actions.

MUSGRAVE A.E. (1968), Impersonal Knowledge, Thesis, Ph.D., London.

MUSGRAVE A.E. (1974), 'Logical Versus Historical Theories of Confirmation',

B.J.P.S., li, (1974), p.l.

MUSGRAVE A.E. (1976), 'Method or Madness', in R.S.Cohen et.al.(eds.),

Essays in Memory of Imre Lakatos, (Boston Stud. in the P. of S.).

Page 296: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

NEUMANN C. (1868), 'Die Principien der Elektrodynamik', Math.

Annalen, 70, (1880), p.400.

NIDDITCH P.H. (ed.) (1968), The Philosophy of Science.

NIVEN W.D. (ed.) (1965), The Scientific Papers of James Clerk-

Maxwell, Dover reprint.

OERSTED H.C. (1813), 'Ansicht der Chemischen Naturgesetze ,

translated into 'Recherches sur l'ldentite ••• ',

Fahie, Hist. of Electric Teleg., (1884), p.270.

OERSTED H.C. (1820), 'Experimenta Circa Effectum Conflictus

Electrici in Acum Magneticam', Ann.Phil., ~, (1820),

p.273.

OERSTED H.C. (1821), 'On Electromagnetism (A) The History of My

Previous Researches on this Subject', new translation

1n R.C.Stauffer (1957).

OERSTED H.C. (1830), 'Thermoelectricity', article in The Edinburgh

Encyclopaedia (1830).

OHM G.S. (1827), 'Die Galvanische Kette . . .. , translated in vol.2

of R.Taylor, Scientific Memoirs.

PEIERLS R.E. (1963},'Field Theory since Maxwell', in Doub (ed.)

(1963).

PIHL H. (1962), 'The Scientific Achievements of L.V.Lorenz', in

E.C.Jordan (ed.) (1963), Electromagnetic Theory and

Antennas; Proceedings .

. . , POINCARE H. (1901), Electrlclte et Optique, 2nd ed., 2v.

296

Page 297: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

POINCARE H. and F.K.VREELAND (1904), Maxwell's Theory and Wireless

Telegraphy.

POISSON S.D. (1812), 'M~moire sur la Distribution de l'Electricit:

~ la Surface des Corps Conducteurs', Mem. de l'lnst.,

(1811), p.1.

POISSON S.D. (1821-7), 'M~moire sur la Theorie du Magnetisme', Mem.

Acad. Sci., ~, (1823), p.441.

POLYA G. (1954), Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning, 2v.

POPPER K.R. (1934) , Logic of Scientific Discovery.

POPPER K.R. (1945) , The Open Society and Its Enemies, 2v.

POPPER K.R. (J957), The Poverty of Historicism.

pOPPER K.R. (1963), Conjectures and Refutations.

POPPER K.R. (1972), Objective Knowled~e.

POPPER K.R. (1974), The Philosophy of Karl Popper.

O'RAHILLY A. (1965), Electromagnetic Theory, Dover reprint, 2v.,

first published in 1938 as Electromagnetics.

RANDALL Sir J. (1963), 'Aspects of the Life and Work of James Clerk

Maxwell', in Domb Ced.) (1963).

RIEMANN G.F.B. (1867), 'A Contribution to Electrodyna~cs', Phil.

Mag., 34, (1867), p.368.

RITZ W. (1908a), 'Recherches Critique sur l'Electrodyn~que , ,

Generale', Ann.Chim.Phys., 8 Series, ll, (1908), p.145.

RITZ W. (1908b), 'A Critical Investigation of Maxwell's and Lorentz's

Electrodynamic Theories', translated in Hovgaard (1932),

p.225 and f.

297

Page 298: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

RIVE A. de la (1853), Treatise on Electricity, 2v.

ROLLER D. and D.H.D.ROLLER (1954), The Development of the Concept

Electric Charge.

ROMER A. (1942a), 'The Speculative History of Atomic Charges 1873-

1895', Isis, 33, (1942), p.671.

ROMER A. (1942b), 'The Experimental History of Atomic Charges. 1895-

1903', Isis, 34, (1942), p.150.

ROSENFELD L. (1957), 'The Velocity of Light and the Evolution of

Electrodynamics', II Nuouvo Cimento, 1, Supp. Vol.4 Series

10, (1957), p.1630.

298

ROWLAND H.A. (1878), 'On the Magnetic Effect of Electric Convection'.

Amer.J.Sci., 11 (1878), p.30.

RUSSELL B. (1941), 'On the Value of Scepticism', in Let the People

Think.

SCHAEFER W. (1931), 'Gauss's Investigations On Electrodyna~cs',

Nature, 128, (1931), p.339.

SCHAGRIN H. (1963), 'The Resistance to Ohm's Law', Amer.J.Phys., li,

(1963), p.536.

SCHUSTER A. (1910), 'The Clerk-Maxwell Period' in A History of the

Cavendish Laboratory, 1871-1910.

SCOTT W.T. (1963), 'Resource Letter FC-I on the Evolution of the

Electromagnetic Field Concept', Amer.J.Phys., 1!, (1963),

p.819.

SHADOWITZ A. (1975), The Electromagnetic Field.

Page 299: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

SIMPSON 1.K. (1966), 'Maxwell and the Direct Test of his Electro­

magnetic Theory', Isis, 1l, (1966), p.411.

SIMPSON T.K. (1970), 'Some Observations on Maxwell's Treatise on

Electricity and Magnetism', Stud. in Hist. and Phil. of

Sci., l, (1970), p.244.

SMART J.J.C. (1972), 'Science, History, and Methodology', Brit.J.

Phil.Sci., 23, (1972), p.266.

SMITH-ROSE R.L. (1948), James Clerk Maxwell, F.R.S. 1831-1879.

SNOW HARRIS Sir W. (1849), Rudimentary Electricit~.

SNOW HARRIS Sir W. (1867), A Treatise on Frictional Electricity.

SPENCER J.BROOKES (1967), 'B6scovich's Theory and its Relation to

Faraday's Researches: An Analytic Approach', Archive

for History of Exact Sciences, ~, (1967), p.184.

STAUFFER R.C. (1953), 'Persistent Errors Regarding Oersted's

Discovery of Electromagnetism', Isis, 44, (1953), p.307

STAUFFER R.C. (1957), 'Speculation and Experiment in the Background

of Oersted's Discovery of Electromagnetism', Isis, 48,

(1957), p.33.

STINE W.M. (1903), 'The Contribution of H.F.E.Lenz to the Science

299

of Electromagnetism', Journal of the Franklin Institute, ISS,

(April-May 1903), p.301 and p.363.

SUSSKIND C. (1964), 'Observations of Electromagnetic-Wave Radiation

Before Hertz', Isis, ~, (1964), p.32.

TAYLOR R. (1837), Scientific Memoirs, Vol.l.

Page 300: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

TAYLOR R. (1841), Scientific Memoirs, Vol.2.

THOMPSON S.P. (1895), 'Mirrors of Magnetism', Phil.Mag., ~, (1895),

p.213.

THOMPSON S.P. (1910), The Life of William Thomson.

THOMSON J.J. (1885), 'Report on Electrical Theories', Report of the

55th. Meeting of the British Association, (1885), p.97.

THOMSON J.J. (1893), Notes on Recent Researches in Electricity and

Magnetism.

THOMSON W. (1846), 'On the Mathematical Theory of Electricity in

Equilibrium', Camb. and Dublin Math. J., l, (1846), p.75.

THOMSON w. (1860), 'Measurement of the Electrostatic Force Produced

300

by a Daniell's Battery', Proc.Roy.Soc., ~, (1860), p.319

THOMSON W. (1872), Reprint of Papers on Electrostatics and Magnetism.

THOMSON W. (1882), Mathematical and Physical Papers.

TRICKER R.A.R. (1955), 'On the Teaching of Electricity -- Ill',

School Science Review, ~, (1955), p.213. ,

TRICKER R.A.R. (1962), 'Ampere as a Contemporary Physicist',

Contemporary Physics, 1,(1962), p.453.

TRICKER R.A.R. (1965), Early Electrodynamics.

TRICKER R.A.R. (1966), The Contributions of Faraday and Maxwell to

Electrical Science.

TURNER D.M. (1927), Makers of Science: Electricity and Magnetism.

TURNER J. (1955a), 'Maxwell on the Method of Physical Analogy', Brit.

J.Phil.Sci., ~, (1955), p.226.

Page 301: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

~I

TURNER J. (1955b), 'A Note on Maxwell's Interpretation of Some

Attempts at Dynamical Explanation', Annals of Science,

l, (1955), p.238.

TURNER J. (1956), 'Maxwell on the Logic of Dynamical Explanation',

Phil. of Sci., ~, (1956), p.36.

TYNDALL J. (1868), Faraday as a Discoverer.

VAIHINGER H. (1924), The Philosophy of 'As If'.

WATKINS J.W.N. (1964), 'Confirmation, the Paradoxes, and Positivism',

in M.Bunge (ed.), The Critical Approach to Science and

Philosophy.

WEBER W. (1846), Electrodynamische Maassbestimmungen, partial reprint

in Ann.der Phys., 11, (1848), p.193, and this is translated

in R.Taylor, Scientific Memoirs~ Vol.S, p.489.

WEBER W. (1848), 'On the Measurement of Electrodynamic Forces', this

is the partial reprint referred to in the previous entry.

WEBER W. (1864), Electrodynamische Maassbestimmungen, Vol.IV.

WHITTAKER Sir E.T. (1951), A History of Theories of Aether and

Electricity.

WILLIAMS L.PEARCE (1960), 'Michael Faraday and the Evolution of the

Concept of the Electric and Magnetic Field', Proc.Roy.

~., 38, (1960), p.235. ,

WILLIAMS L.PEARCE (1962a), 'Ampere's Electrodynaudc Molecular

Model', Contemporary Physics, i, (1962), p.113.

Page 302: TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th. CENTURY CLASSICAL ...etheses.lse.ac.uk/3430/1/Fricke_two_rival_programmes.pdf · TWO RIVAL PROGRAMMES IN 19th.CENTURY CLASSICAL ELECTRODYNAMICS ACTION-AT-A-DISTANCE

WILLIAMS L.PEARCE (1962b), 'The Physical Sciences in the First Half

of the Nil1t!teenth Century: Problems and Sources',

History of Science,~, (1962), p.l.

WILLIAMS L.PEARCE (1965), Michael Faraday.

WILLIAMS L.PEARCE (1966), The Origins of Field Theory.

WILLIAMS L.PEARCE (1975), 'Should Philosophers be Allowed to Write

History', Brit.J.Phil.Sci., 11. (1975), p.241.

WINDRED G. (1932), 'The Relation Between Pure and Appli.ed Electrical

Theory: with Special Reference to Mathematical Methods',

Isis, ...!!, p.184.

WINTER H.J.J. (1944), 'The Reception of Ohm's Electrical Researches

by His Contemporaries', Phil.Mag., ~, (J944), p.371

WOODRUFF A.E. (1962), 'Action at a Distance in Nineteenth Century

Electrodynamics', Isis, 2l, (1962), p.439.

WOODRUFF A.E. (1968), 'The Contribution of Hermann von Helmholtz to

Electrodynamics', !!i!, ~, (J968), p.300.

WORRALL J. (J976), 'Thomas Young and the 'Refutation' of Newtonian

Optics', in C.Howson (ed.) (1976).

ZAHAR E.G. (J973), 'Why did Einstein's Programme Supercede Lorentz's

reprinted in C.Howson (ed.) (J976).

302

?' . ,