two visions one democracy

33
TWO ‘VISIONS’, ONE DEMOCRACY: DO ‘MAJORITARIANISM’ AND ‘PROPORTIONALITY’ SIMULTANEOUSLY GUIDE DEMOCRATIC POLICY-MAKING? Ian Budge* University of Essex Colchester, UK Email: [email protected] Michael D. McDonald Binghamton University SUNY Binghamton, NY, USA [email protected] *corresponding author

Upload: mladen-mrdalj

Post on 16-Apr-2017

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Two Visions One Democracy

TWO ‘VISIONS’, ONE DEMOCRACY: DO

‘MAJORITARIANISM’ AND ‘PROPORTIONALITY’

SIMULTANEOUSLY GUIDE DEMOCRATIC

POLICY-MAKING?

Ian Budge* University of Essex Colchester, UK Email: [email protected]

Michael D. McDonald Binghamton University SUNY Binghamton, NY, USA [email protected]

*corresponding author

Page 2: Two Visions One Democracy

2

TWO ‘VISIONS’, ONE DEMOCRACY: DO ‘MAJORITARIANISM’

AND ‘PROPORTIONALITY’ SIMULTANEOUSLY GUIDE

DEMOCRATIC POLICY-MAKING?

ABSTRACT

Democracy is supposed to effect the popular will. But is this best expressed by the party

with the largest vote or by compromise among all parties? Median-sensitive ‘proportionality’

as opposed to plurality-based ‘majoritarianism’ has been seen as distinguishing ‘proportional

democracies’ from ‘majoritarian democracies’. Both however have representational claims

which can be made within any one democracy. Dilemmas about which ‘vision’ to follow are

in practice eased by joint participation of plurality and median parties in government – but

even more by their policy preferences generally pointing in the same direction anyway,

facilitating a common response in terms of government policy. This article examines policy

relationships between plurality parties, median parties and governments inside 16 post-war

democracies, uncovering practical bases for accommodation between ‘majoritarian’ and

‘proportional’ visions.

Page 3: Two Visions One Democracy

3

TWO ‘VISIONS’, ONE DEMOCRACY: DO ‘MAJORITARIANISM’ AND

‘PROPORTIONALITY’ SIMULTANEOUSLY GUIDE DEMOCRATIC

POLICY-MAKING?

THE POPULAR WILL: MAJORITARIAN, PROPORTIONAL – OR BOTH?

Classical political theorists assumed that the popular will emerges unproblematically

from general discussion and voting (Schattschneider, 1942, 14). The actual failure of

elections to produce clear majorities has long been known – less than 10 per cent do

(McDonald & Budge, 2005, 22-3). However, it took Bingham Powell’s seminal exploration of

‘Elections as Instruments of Democracy’ (2000), to focus scholarly attention on the

consequences of such failure..

These lead in most democracies to manufacturing the missing majority through

election rules which give the plurality party (with the largest individual vote) a majority of

Parliamentary seats: or to creating a majority through legislative negotiations between

potential coalition partners which will then form a government. These procedures were put

on an equal footing in Powell’s ‘two visions of democracy’. Election systems which habitually

produced a clear mandate for one party were characterized as ‘majoritarian democracies’

and multi-party systems with coalition governments as ‘proportional democracies’. While the

first had obvious advantages of coherence and accountability, proportional democracies – in

line with Lijphart’s (1968, 1984, 1999) arguments for consensus and negotiation – produced

greater policy congruence between citizens and governments.

Powell (2000, 77-81) notes that single party governments usually rest on plurality

votes rather than genuine electoral majorities. The government majority is purely legislative,

created by the tendency of single member constituency systems with plurality winners

(SMDP) to translate a popular plurality into a legislative majority. However, the ready

identifiability of the plurality winner and the mandate conferred by plurality status justify the

procedure. Where no party is clearly identified by the election as the leading contender,

Page 4: Two Visions One Democracy

4

coalition negotiations and policy compromises are necessary to produce a government.

This, as a matter of fact, often takes policy stands closer to those of the median citizen than

does a plurality-based one (Powell, 2000, 221-2). What emerges are two distinct types of

modern democracy which work in different ways and produce rather different results.

McDonald et al (2004) seek to bridge this gap by presenting a unified account of

democracy at work in their theory of the median mandate (see also McDonald & Budge,

2005). Their argument is that elections can be seen as expressing a majority preference

indicated by the position of the median voter. All democracies, in order to qualify as such,

have to make ‘a necessary connection between acts of governance and the equally weighted

felt interests of citizens with respect to these acts’ (May, 1978: Saward, 1998, 51). Thus

‘majoritarian’ as well as ‘proportional’ democracies ought to bring government policy as close

as possible to the median voters preference and can all be assessed on their ability to do so.

On this comparison, proportional systems perform better than majoritarian or plurality ones

(confirming Powell, 2000, 221-2 – who however did not so explicitly set up conformity to the

median preference as a general standard).

The median mandate approach has a consistent logic behind it, which given its

premises seem to provide both the desired unified approach to democracy and a rationale for

Lijphart’s advocacy of ‘consensus democracy’ - and incidentally for Powell’s findings in

favour of proportional democracy. The premises the median mandate thesis rests on are

however very strong and probably unrealistic. In particular it assumes that all voters decide

between parties on policy grounds. This surely flies in the face of evidence from voting

studies from all over the world in the tradition of The American Voter (Campbell et al, 1960).

Even if we learned nothing else from these, they conclusively demonstrate that party

attachments, government competence, candidate appeals and many situational factors apart

from issues have a strong – even major – influence on the popular vote.

If we allow for an electorate that votes with mixed motives, not just in terms of policy

(or even more narrowly, in terms of policy proximity) we have got to step back towards

Powell’s position and reconsider the conflicting claims of the plurality voter and the median

Page 5: Two Visions One Democracy

5

voter to represent majority opinion. We are not going back entirely to Powell however as

recent evidence suggests that both plurality-based majoritarianism and proportionality can be

seen as entering into electoral and governmental processes in all democracies, not just as

distinguishing one type of democracy from another.

This evidence comes from a series of studies (Wlezien, 1996: Wlezien & Soroka,

2009: Soroka & Wlezien, 2004: 2005) of the ‘majoritarian’ democracies of Britain, Canada

and the US, which show government policy initiatives as extremely sensitive to movements

of public opinion. Such movements are often based on an adverse reaction of electors to the

proposed policies themselves, which the government then modifies to improve its standing in

the next election. The Macro Polity (Erikson, MacKuen & Stimson, 2002, 282-326) also sees

these ‘thermostatic’ interplays as being at work between US elections.

If plurality parties in these ‘majoritarian’ democracies habitually accommodate public

opinion (representing in part the other parties’ policy preferences) then clearly some kind of

‘proportional’ negotiation and compromise with other political groupings is taking place. The

US of course is well known for the continuing negotiations and policy compromises which the

division of powers forces on all parties. Canada has frequent minority governments whose

survival depends on effective compromise. Wlezien & Soroka’s evidence demonstrates

however that even Britain’s ‘elective dictatorship’ cannot simply steamroll its policies through

and has to take opposition into account.

This is hardly surprising – even elective dictatorships have to concern themselves

with votes in the next election. But the findings indicate that ‘majoritarianism’ can and does

co-exist with ‘proportionality’, rather than substituting for it as an exclusive form of decision-

making in one democracy as opposed to another. On the other side evidence from

proportional systems indicates that plurality status gives parties considerable advantages

over the others they negotiate with in the formation of coalition governments (Muller & Strøm,

2000), share of cabinet seats (Browne & Franklin, 1973) and policy-making (see below).

Quite apart from the detailed evidence one can recognise generally that in the

absence of an electoral majority, both the largest party and all the parties have claims to

Page 6: Two Visions One Democracy

6

represent the popular will. In the absence of any clear criterion to decide between their

claims, surely most democracies have to try to accommodate both, at any rate to some

extent. Below we check comparative evidence to see to what extent they can be, and are,

mutually accommodated. First however we have to consider how to identify the carriers of

the majoritarian and proportional ‘visions’ in practice. We argue below that the plurality party

is the one with the commanding numerical basis whether in a multi-party legislature or in one

where SMDP gives it the majority of seats. It thus represents the concept of majoritarianism

in democratic decision-making. The median party position is the one that would probably be

arrived at by all-party negotiation and compromise. It thus embodies the concept of

proportionality.

OPERATIONALISING MAJORITARIANISM AND PROPORTIONALITY: PLURALITIES AND

MEDIANS.

Since Downs (1957) and Black (1948, 1958) independently demonstrated the ‘Power

of the Median’, the median position on a one-dimensional policy continuum (usually the

overarching Left-Right dimension) has generally been taken to represent the popular

preference (cf Powell, 2000, 175-229: Adams et al 2004: Ezrow, 2005). From Figure 1 it is

easy to see why. If all actors prefer positions closer to their own

[FIGURE 1 ABOUT HERE]

to ones further away they will not leapfrog to form majority coalitions with actors on the other

extreme (A with G for example). A would always prefer to be in the majority ABCDE.

Similarly G would always prefer the combination GFE to any other majority. These

preferences make E, at the median, crucial in deciding which majority will form, as it is

essential to both. E is also assumed to be policy-motivated so will favour the majority which

adopts the policy position closest to its own. Successive bargaining rounds will thus end up

with a majority position close to that of the median. Hence the median position is the one

which proportional bargaining and negotiation between all parties will produce as the majority

preference.

Page 7: Two Visions One Democracy

7

The logic is very strong – if the assumptions on which it is based are appropriate.

That is to say, it will only hold if all the actors are purely policy-motivated and if they array all

their policy-preferences along a one-dimensional continuum, as shown in Figure 1. In

practice the only cleavage which could sustain such an overarching policy continuum is Left-

Right.

Figure 1 probably gives a good picture of the way legislative voting proceeds if we

take the percentage distribution as referring to shares of Parliamentary seats. Parties do

seem to divide along Left-Right lines and favour positions closer to their own (Axelrod, 1970

165-85: Budge et al 2001, 20-45). Even at legislative level however other considerations

may enter. Where policies far removed from Left-Right concerns are voted on separately

they may produce a different ordering of the parties. Moreover a legislature may have non-

policy-based concerns about having stable and effective government in the face of external

threats and crises which would favour having a large plurality party as its basis. The Nordic

countries are a good case in point where the social democrats have often been favoured in

government formation through being the single largest party.

Even in a multi-party legislative situation therefore considerations other than Left-

Right policy positions may surface, favouring a large plurality party over the Left-Right

median position. This is even truer and more relevant at electoral level when we take the

percentage distribution in Figure 1 as referring to election votes. General Elections put

voters in the position of having to express both policy preferences and choose a government

at the same time. Some votes therefore will inevitably be cast on non-policy based

considerations – which may even sway a majority of voters. When the dominant concern

can often be government effectiveness, stability, and clear accountability, there is then

considerable justification for the tendency of the SMDP rules to translate a popular plurality

into a majority of legislative seats.

Even when we try to evaluatet the vote distribution in pure policy terms, the seeming

median party which emerges from it may not actually be at the genuine median policy

position. This discrepancy would occur if any vote was affected by non-policy

Page 8: Two Visions One Democracy

8

considerations. In that case discounting non-policy votes could lead to the seeming median

being displaced to Left or Right. Given uncertainty about the median’s true position, voters

for the plurality party might well claim to bestow a more convincing policy mandate by

arguing that their votes had more policy content than the others.

However, the median position cannot be totally written off as uninformative, even

where the legislative majority goes to the plurality party. The distribution of votes emerging

from the General Election is the most authoritative expression of overall policy preferences

that we have, even if we have some doubts about it. Under the declared distribution of

preferences the revealed median is the only one common to all vote-based majorities. The

median position therefore is the one such majorities would tend to endorse after any process

of negotiation. This means that the median position emanates from the preferences of all

electors, not just from one (perhaps extreme) group, as might be the case with the plurality

position. This is particularly true as it is the declared preference which is closest in

aggregate to all declared individual preferences and thus minimizes dissatisfaction if

adopted.

These considerations all lend the median position some standing even where SMDP

rules give the popular plurality the legislative majority. Arguments about the popular majority

basis of the median and the plurality positions can go on endlessly however as we lack the

crucial information about what mix of motivation went into the votes and whether therefore

the median is the ‘real’ policy median or the plurality party is the ‘real’ policy majority. Their

contrasting claims are summarized in Table 1.

[Table 1 about here]

What the Table makes clear is that neither the median nor the plurality positions can

be decisively dismissed as carriers of the popular majority preference under representative

democracy. The median position is the one that would probably be arrived at by party

negotiation and compromise and thus operationalizes the concept of ‘proportionality’ in

democratic decision-making. The plurality position is the one with a commanding numerical

Page 9: Two Visions One Democracy

9

basis whether in a multi-party legislature or in one where SMDP gives it the majority of seats.

It thus represents the concept of majoritarianism in democratic decision-making. Does this –

given the claims of median-based proportionality – always prevail however, even in

democracies we would regard as generally majoritarian? And does plurality-based

majoritarianism always lose its force even where decision-making is more proportional? (in

practice under coalition Governments under PR with multi-parties). Now that we have

investigated the general claims for representing the popular majority that can be made on

both sides we can examine actual democratic practices empirically and comparatively, by

seeing how government formation and policy-making respond to ‘proportional’ median and

‘majoritarian’ plurality preferences in 16 post-war democracies.

GOVERNMENT FORMATION AND COMPOSITION

We take our information about government composition from Woldendorp, Keman

and Budge (2000) and use the vote distributions reported in Volkens, Schnapp & Lass (1992)

with updates to 1995, our end year, from the specialist reports in the European Journal of

Political Research. To characterize the party supported by the median voter we additionally

rely on the Comparative Manifesto Project’s (CMP) Left-Right scorings of parties in the 16

democracies for each post-war election 1945-1995 (Budge et al, 2001, 19-46). Details of

how the Left-Right scale has been constructed are given below when we come to analyse

party policy positions more directly. Here we concentrate on government formation as such,

against the background of the election results and the declared preferences of electors for

the parties’ overarching positions on the left-right scale.

Table 2 reports the relative and absolute frequencies of being in government

[Table 2 about here]

or not, for the plurality and median electoral parties, for the first governments forming

immediately after each of 215 elections – covering sixteen nations from the early 1950s

through 1995 (not including France’s government after its unique PR election, in 1986). The

Page 10: Two Visions One Democracy

10

fourfold classification shows whether the median electoral party, 1 the plurality electoral party,

both, or neither are in government. The top cross-classification covers all nations; the two

tables underneath separate out elections conducted under SMDP rules (N = 81) from those

conducted under PR (N = 135).2

The main message of the sixteen-nation cross-classification is that the plurality party

holds a privileged position. It is included in about four out of five governments. The party

closest to the median voter (i.e., the electoral median party) holds office in just under two-

thirds of these first governments after an election3 and most of those cases are situations

when the plurality party is also in government – 122 out of 140 cases. Going one step

further, of these 122 cases, ninety five are situations when one party is both the plurality and

median. The conjunction of median voter and plurality voter endorsement all but guarantees

inclusion in government. All ninety-five times it occurs, the party is in office. But, when one

but not the other is included, the plurality party is three times more likely than the electoral

median party to be there.

The cross-classifications for SMDP and PR systems are remarkably similar. The

marginal relative frequencies are virtually the same – including the median party in about

65% of governments while including the plurality party in about 85% of governments under

SMDP and 79% under PR (not a statistically significant difference). A more notable

difference comes from PR systems’ slightly greater tendency to include the median party in a

government when it does not also include the plurality party. By implication, these

governments display a slightly lesser tendency to include the plurality party, and a slightly

lesser tendency to include both the median and plurality. This difference, we suppose,

1 A median electoral party is the party with a Left-Right score closest to the position of the median voter. This may or may not be the same as the median parliamentary party as such. For the calculation of the Left-Right score see below. 2 Elections in six nations are classified as SMDP: Australia, Canada, France Fifth Republic (excluding 1986), New Zealand (its post-1995 mixed-PR elections are not in the data set), the United Kingdom, and the United States (presidential elections). 3 The two-thirds fraction is lower than the three-fourths reported in Müller and Strøm, (2000, 564). Part of the difference relates to the fact that we are dealing with the median electoral party and not the median parliamentary party; part relates to coverage of different nations; and part, in comparison to Müller and Strøm, relates to Left-Right party locations based on expert survey data versus the MRG-CMP data used here.

Page 11: Two Visions One Democracy

11

comes from SMDP elections encouraging voting that attaches the median and plurality

designation to the same party – 58% of elections under SMDPs (with Britain and France the

notable exceptions) versus 36% of elections under PR.4

Going back to our general concerns, the main point that emerges from comparing

government participation is surely the absence of any real difference between proportional

and majoritarian (SMDP) systems in privileging the plurality over median as the expression of

majority support. Certainly there remains a difference between the systems - which we

investigate below for its policy effects – in terms of whether the plurality party is the leading

or the only member of the government. In terms of the policy centrality accorded to the

median and plurality parties there does however seem little difference in democratic practice

across the board. All democracies seem ‘majoritarian’ rather than ‘proportional’ in emphasis,

so far as government formation and confrontation are concerned.

DOES PLURALITY VS MEDIAN ENDORSEMENT MAKE A DIFFERENCE IN POLICY

TERMS?

Features of government beyond the inclusion of particular types of parties are

important to governing positions. Perhaps, for example, the electoral plurality party tends

more often to go it alone in government, whereas the electoral median party tends to join in a

coalition. If so, the electoral plurality party would have more weight in policy-making than the

numbers on its presence or absence indicate by themselves. Alternatively, when the plurality

and median parties are not one and the same, they may take similar policy positions, and

thus a seemingly clear-cut distinction in terms of relative government participation is not

vastly important in terms of the policy being adopted.

In addition to taking account of party characteristics, the fact that median and plurality

voter positions are correlated has to be considered. The correlation is not a necessary

(definitional) matter. But logic tells us that it is likely to emerge empirically. On the ‘not

4 There is a tendency for the plurality voter party to gain advantage from having a vote percentage approaching 50 and for the median to gain an advantage from a close vote split between the two largest parties. We do not pursue more detailed analyses of those tendencies, as such pursuit is more likely to cloud than to make clear the main message that a plurality voter’s preferred party is relatively privileged in comparison to a median voter’s preferred party.

Page 12: Two Visions One Democracy

12

necessarily so’ side of various possibilities, imagine a right-leaning party at the next election.

Imagine also, because its vote splits with another right wing party, that the right-leaning party

loses its plurality status to a party on the left. This combination of changes has the median

voter moving rightward (the Right vote increases in total) while the plurality party moves

leftward. On the correlated side of the possibilities, however, imagine that a right-leaning

party in a two-party system loses one election by a 45-55 voter percentage split and wins the

next election by a 54-46 split. The median voter moves to the Right between these elections

and so does the plurality voter. As party systems generally remain stable between

successive elections we suspect that the correlated movements predominate. But this needs

further investigation. One clear relationship does emerge however. If support for the party

alternatives remains broadly the same from election to election, a marginal shift in the

plurality voter position will go in the same direction as a shift in the median position.

We examine the practical possibilities for co-ordinated movement between the two in

policy terms, using a Left-Right measure. We are not bound to the idea that all of policy is

necessarily contained in the Left-Right distinction. However, for a comparative analysis such

as this it is the one type of conflict which crops up in all countries and time periods, rendering

it possible to place all parties, wherever located, within the same policy framework (Budge,

Robertson & Hearl eds, 1987: Huber & Inglehart, 1995: Klingemann et al, 2006).

Possibly because of the universality of the Left-Right cleavage, there is the further

constraint on our investigation that the only measure on which one can trace party policy

movement over time, in a number of countries, is the Left-Right scale devised by the

Manifesto Research Group/Comparative Manifestos Project (MRG-CMP) (Klingemann et al,

2006, 5-9). This has the additional advantage of drawing on all the policy information

contained in the parties’ authoritative statements of election policy, as specified below.

Page 13: Two Visions One Democracy

13

The CMP has coded each quasi-sentence5 of the election programs of significant

parties in over 50 countries for the post-war period into one of 56 categories covering the full

range of public policy. The overall distribution resulting from this is converted into

percentages to control for varying length of the text. The main resulting policy measure is a

Left-Right scale which groups 13 of the original categories to the Right and 13 to the Left, on

largely a priori grounds. Percentaged references to ‘Left’ topics are summed and subtracted

from the summed percentages of ‘Right’ topics. This gives a scale running in theory from

-100 (totally Left) to +100 (totally Right). In practice parties rarely move beyond ±50.

Essentially the Left-Right scale contrasts support for order and security at home and

abroad; traditional morality; and ‘freedom’ on the Right, to support for government planning

and intervention; welfare and social security; and peaceful internationalism, on the Left. It

thus gives an overall summary of policy stances across the whole of the party platform in

each election year.6 So we feel that the analyses below do give a pretty comprehensive

picture of policy in the countries concerned.

Figures 2 and 3 trace median and plurality voter positions in each of 16 nation’s

elections from 1950 through 1995, with Figure 2 displaying the traces for ten PR nations and

Figure 3 displaying the traces for the six SMDP nations. Table 3 reports a set of summary

statistics, by nation, to help describe the details.

[Figure 2 about here]

[Figure 3 about here]

[Table 3 about here]

5 A quasi-sentence can be either a grammatical sentence or ‘an argument or phrase which is the verbal expression of one idea or meaning. It is often marked off in a text by commas or (semi)-colons. Long sentences may contain more than one argument so that they need to be broken up into quasi-sentences’ Klingemann et al (2006) xxiii 6 Incidentally the median elector position we used to identify the electoral median party above, also derives from combining information about party positions on the Left-Right scale with their vote as suggested by Kim & Fording (1998, 2001) and reported in Budge et al (2001, 160-6). We have modified the calculation slightly by assuming that the distribution of votes for parties at each end of the array is symmetrical rather than running right out to the end of the continuum. But this produces a substantive difference in estimates only in the US case.

Page 14: Two Visions One Democracy

14

But for France, Switzerland, and the Netherlands, the median and plurality positions

trace one another reliably enough to record a statistically significant positive relationship.

Generally the median voter’s position is more centrist and less volatile than the plurality

voter’s. This centrism is reflected in the graphs inasmuch as median voter scores tend to

stay closer to zero than the plurality voter scores; the lower volatility is apparent from the

smoother traces for the median voter with the exceptions of Denmark and Norway. This

centrism and lower volatility are also reflected in the statistical summaries, by the slope

values exceeding 1.0; a one-unit movement by the median voter is associated with more

than a one-unit movement by the plurality voter.

The trace of the Austrian plurality voter shows oversteering relative to the median

position in the 1950s and to the early 1960s, and then the two traces mostly move in tandem.

Tandem movements are also visible in other PR systems except for Switzerland throughout

and except for one or two large deviations during the 1970s or 1980s in Belgium, Germany,

Ireland, Italy, and the Netherlands. Other than Switzerland, the most remarkable

mismatches among PR nations are in Denmark and Norway, where the plurality social

democratic parties (the Danish Social Democratic Party, SD, and the Norwegian Labour

Party, DN) stood almost persistently to the left of the median voter position. This creates the

leftward bias of the plurality voter to the left of the median voter as indicated in Table 3 by the

statistically significant negative intercepts. The other noticeable but less remarkable

mismatches are the rightward bias in Germany and the leftward bias in the Netherlands.

These, unlike Denmark and Norway, are nations where once-in-a-while large deviations tend

to go just one way. Finally, in regard to PR nations, the Swiss median and plurality voter

positions are consistently out of step. From the 1950s through 1980 the Swiss median voter

drifted gradually leftward and the plurality voter, a supporter of the SPS/PSS, stood farther

Left. Then from 1983 through 1991, while the median voter positions continued their gradual

leftward drift, the Swiss liberals, FDP//PRD, took the plurality spot. All of this happened while

three of the four major Swiss parties – Social Democrats, Liberals, and Christians

(CVP/PDC) – vied in close competition for the plurality position, each with a vote typically in

Page 15: Two Visions One Democracy

15

the 20 and 25% range. Close competition among the major left and right parties in the

presence of a centrist alternative (in Switzerland, the CVP/PCD) are circumstances where

reading a majority electoral position from the median versus the plurality can be, and as we

are reporting for Switzerland sometimes is, likely to be very different. In addition to the

consistent mismatch in Switzerland, close competition between Left and Right parties and a

centrist alternative also contributes to the occasional mismatches in Germany, the

Netherlands, and Belgium.

Mismatches aside, though they are potentially a problem, the relationships between

the voter positions, other than in Switzerland, are not statistically significantly different from

one-to-one among PR nations. In nine out of ten PR nations, slopes are a little higher or a

little lower than 1.0, and with fairly large standard errors. Generalizing, the matches through

time wander about in a not terribly reliable but general pattern not too much out of line with

one another.

The generalization holds reasonably well for SMDP nations, too, with the exception of

France. The slopes are roughly in the neighborhood of 1.0 - even less reliable than PR

nation slopes. In the United States we see persistent oversteering of the plurality relative to

median positions and almost as much in the United Kingdom. From the oversteering come

relatively large slopes (Table 3, b > 1.4). For Australia and New Zealand, we see loosely

consistent tracking of the median positions by the plurality positions. In Canada, especially

through 1979, we see mostly consistent tracking.

France is a different case. It shows no relationship between the median and plurality

positions to speak of. It is similar in this to Switzerland, except that the median voter position

does not show such a consistent leftward drift. As in Switzerland, however, a major party on

the right (Gaullists and their progeny) was the plurality winner of middling size from the start

of the Fifth Republic until 1980, after which the major opposition party, the Socialists, PS,

emerged as the middling size plurality winner – (the vote percentages refer to the first ballot).

And, just as PS fortunes rose, the median voter moved rightward. In the series of elections

Page 16: Two Visions One Democracy

16

of the Fifth Republic, through 1993, all of this produces essentially no relationship between

electoral median and plurality positions.

Usually the median and plurality voter positions give correlated readings of which

direction, Left versus Right, an electorate signals the parliament and government to go. In a

few cases – Switzerland and France throughout, along with Belgium, Germany, Ireland, Italy,

and the Netherlands once in a while – movements of the plurality and median voter positions

give very different readings.7 When this is the case, the elections give ambiguous messages

about whether it is plausible to consider the median or plurality voter position as carrying the

electoral majority preference. The ambiguity arises most seriously when two parties are in

close competition for a plurality vote e.g. the German case, where two parties generally

receive vote percentages above 40 and a small party (vote <10%) is at the electoral median.

Here it is arguable which large party to empower. Thus it is reasonable to think about

empowering either or both. An alternative which tempers this choice is to hand over power

to the median party or to include the median party in government along with one of the large

parties. All of these post-election responses have emerged in Germany, and all are

reasonable and ‘democratic’, accommodating both ‘majoritarian’ and ‘proportional’

responses. When the close competitors for the plurality spot receive middling size vote

shares, it also makes sense, arguably, to empower the median position, alone or in addition

to the plurality position, as in Belgium and the Netherlands.

Government participation is one thing but what government decides to do is not

wholly determined by this especially under coalitions. Our next step in the analysis asks

what government policy positions emerge from the election results.

WHAT DIFFERENCE DOES PLURALITY OR MEDIAN ENDORSEMENT MAKE TO

GOVERNMENT POLICY?

7 In Switzerland this may not matter too much given that the federal government is formed by a permanent coalition of the four large parties and much policy is delegated to cantons. Frequent referendums and initiatives also supplement the policy messages given by general elections.

Page 17: Two Visions One Democracy

17

Democracies tend to privilege the electoral plurality over the median in forming

governments. Reading electoral majorities in terms of forming around the median or plurality

electoral party shows a loose but consistent relationship between the policy directions they

point towards in most countries most of the time. In countries where the loose connection

breaks down for a short series of elections (Belgium, Germany, Ireland, and Italy) and in two

where the relationship breaks down completely (Switzerland and France, and perhaps three,

if we include the Netherlands) governments usually form as coalitions. Coalitions hold the

potential of splitting a difference and thereby saving the balance of representation. With that

possibility in mind, we put our government and voter findings together and enquire whether

government policy positions follow the direction indicated by either the median or plurality

voter.

Perhaps the strongest empirical generalization in political science is that

parliamentary seat proportions among parties in government relate very closely to the

proportion of cabinet portfolios held by the parties (Browne and Franklin 1973; see Warwick

and Druckman 2006 for a recent review). With Kim and Fording (2002) we rely on this oft-

repeated finding to score government policy positions, Left-Right, as seat-weighted policy

positions of parties in government. Thus, when two parties are in government, one with 25

seats and scoring 0 on the Left-Right metric and the other with 75 seats and scoring +20 on

the Left-Right metric, the government’s position is +15 (i.e., 25*0 + .75*20). And, when a

plurality party holds all the cabinet portfolios, as it often does in SMDP systems with single-

party majority governments, the government policy score is equal to that one party’s Left-

Right score.

Table 4 reports the relationships, by country, between government policy positions,

estimated in this way, and the plurality voter’s position. For comparison purposes, to see

how well government positions also align through time with median voter positions, Table 5

reports that set of relationships by country.8 So far as Table 4 goes, nine out of ten PR

8 The relationships are weighted by the proportion of time governments held office. A government that holds office for four years receives four times the weight of a government holding

Page 18: Two Visions One Democracy

18

country slopes and five out of six SMDP country slopes are less than 1.0, (often statistically

significantly lower than 1.0 under PR). This indicates a near uniform tendency for

governments’ policy positions to be more centrist than would be the case were governments

to follow the plurality voter position on a one-to-one basis. Importantly, because we have

seen that the median voter is more centrist than the plurality voter, it also indicates erring on

the side of median-based ‘proportionality’ on policy.

[Table 4 about here]

[Table 5 about here]

The results in Table 5 show that six out of ten PR nations display a centrism which is

not quite so centrist as to match the median voter positions, however. The relationship is

statistically significantly greater than 1.0 in two cases (Italy and Sweden, using a one-tail

test). Among SMDP systems, the relationship between government and median voter

positions is significantly different from 1.0 only in the United States. And it must be noted

that it fails to produce a significant difference for France largely because government

positions are so unreliably associated with median voter positions there – indeed so

unreliably so that the slope value is not significantly different from zero either! In most

countries, government positions loosely but consistently track median voter positions (nearly

one-to-one).

Finally, we can compare the degree to which governments track plurality or median

voter positions more faithfully. The correlations show that all SMDP nations have

government positions more consistently fitted to the plurality voter position – even though, as

we have seen, they are not much at variance with median voter positions either. The PR

comparisons are more mixed. The Irish and Swiss governments do not track their plurality

voter positions even to a statistically significant degree, while in both nations there are

statistically significant relationships with median voter positions – in Switzerland with b = 1.0.

office for just one year. The weights are calculated as the proportion of total time from the first government forming after the first election in the 1950s through the end of 1995. Time in government is taken from Woldendorp, Keman, and Budge (2000). So that the number of cases for each country equals the number of governments that formed during the period in that country, the time proportions have been multiplied by the number of governments.

Page 19: Two Visions One Democracy

19

Running in the opposite direction are the results for Norway. There the relationship between

government and median voter positions is essentially nonexistent, at least reliably so, while

Norwegian government positions are reasonably strongly associated with plurality voter

positions.

With a few exceptions therefore governments follow the policy tracks set by both the

plurality and median voter. Indeed, in several countries it is as if governments split the

difference in the long run, somewhat more centrist than the plurality voter position and

somewhat more extreme than the median voter position. We suspect, therefore that the

theoretical ambiguity over whether electoral majorities are best indicated by the plurality or

median voter position is not often going to be of great moment in practical terms. Either or

both would lead to the same policy decisions being taken.

REVIEW AND CONCLUSIONS

This discussion has brought together theoretical concerns about majority

representation under democratic rules with comparative evidence, in the tradition of Lijphart’s

(1968, 1984, 1999) analyses and particularly Powell’s own (2000) and collaborative (1994,

2001) work. It has hopefully extended and deepened these authors’ concerns by suggesting

that ‘two visions’ of how to respond to majority wishes – or even to conceive of a majority –

coexist within every democracy rather than distinguishing one type of democracy from

another. (Though, as we have just seen, a slight tendency to favour the plurality under

SMDP still remains.)

Both the ‘proportional’ and ‘majoritarian’ visions are embedded within the very

structure of representative general elections, where voters are asked to decide on a number

of questions, only some of them bearing directly on policy: which government do they want?

which candidate do they prefer? which party do they like best? We cannot therefore assume

that voters simply choose the party closest to them on policy, which would lead to the party

preferred by the median voter being the obvious carrier of majority preferences (and possibly

becoming the plurality party too cf Downs, 1957, 118). On the other hand, we cannot

Page 20: Two Visions One Democracy

20

dismiss the possibility that policy voting occurs. But whether in a general election it favours

the median or plurality party is obscure.

Since elections overwhelmingly fail to produce a spontaneous majority in practice,

there is no guarantee that the median based ‘proportional’ and plurality based ‘majoritarian’

positions coincide (though they do in 44% of the cases we examined). Even where they are

different however both have claims to represent popular opinion, and neither claim can be

convincingly denied in the absence of pure policy-voting.

The horns of this dilemma are nonetheless blunted for most democracies by the fact

that, under a stable party system, both median and plurality shift marginally from election to

election in the same policy direction. Their actual policy positions may diverge but they

generally give the same indications of what the popular majority wants in the way of change.

In this sense governments – regardless of whether plurality or median parties form them –

can claim popular support for their policy innovations, conforming as they do to both

‘proportional’ and ‘majoritarian’ messages from the election.

In terms of government participation its clear identifiability (Powell, 2000, 61-80) gives

the plurality party an advantage, even under proportional rules and coalition-formation.

Balancing this, government policy for the most part seems to cater both for median and

plurality positions even under single-party governments. This is not surprising, given the

similarities we have identified between the policy messages they provide.

Superficially, our finding that election-messages tend to point in the same direction

resembles Soroka & Wlezien’s (2008) conclusion that there is little difference between the

preferences of various ‘sub-constituencies’ in the United States (rich and poor, voters and

non-voters, with some exceptions in regard to specific policy areas and perhaps levels of

education). This is in contrast to the findings of Gilens (2009) that there are wide variations

between different groups, a view supported by the comparative findings of Adams & Ezrow

(2009) on European opinion leaders. These are both left-leaning and disproportionately

influential in parties and on governments.

Page 21: Two Visions One Democracy

21

It would be nice if our findings contributed to this important debate. However we have

to point out that they are quite tangentle to the questions at issue in it. The positions

identified by election results could be those favoured by any demographic group and there is

nothing to say whether plurality or median policy positions favour Right or Left, rich or poor.

Indeed it is quite likely that over time the balance of opinion, as indicated by the election

results, shifts between all of these groups.

Our findings therefore relate more to the functioning of the central democratic

institution of elections than to their substantive impact. Whichever way one looks at them,

from a median or plurality point of view, elections tend to relay the same message about

majority preferences. Why should this be so?

We have already pointed out that the similarity between the median and plurality

preference is neither necessary nor logical in nature. It depends on the broad overall stability

of the party system at the electoral level. Where sequential elections simply transfer votes

between existing parties, even though the transfers may be relatively large, we can expect

that a plurality shift between Left and Right parties for example will be accompanied by a

shift in the median – probably between Centre-Left and Centre-Right. This is because the

median position, being estimated from the distribution of voters over the party alternatives,

will also register the movement of support from Left to Right.

Party systems in established democracies such as the ones examined here are

reasonably stable most of the time. Hence only limited transfers of votes occur between

election and election, median and plurality move in the same policy direction, and so

governments can be responsive to both. Where however a challenger suddenly takes

support from an established party on either Right or Left, splitting that ideological grouping,

the plurality position may be taken by an unchallenged party on the other wing. The median

however will still reflect the balance of votes between the ideological groupings rather than

between the parties as such. If the new challenger and the targeted party between them

have increased or retained their overall support the median will stay stable or shift towards

them. In that case the messages governments take from the election results will differ. This

Page 22: Two Visions One Democracy

22

simply reflects the general political upheaval that is taking place in that election however,

signalled by divisions in established parties or by new entrants to the electoral arena. When

the election situation stabilizes the median and plurality will again send the same message to

governments about the policy direction to take.

What our evidence reveals therefore, for the 16 post-war democracies we have

examined, is that elections organized by parties generally provide loose but consistent

representation of electoral preferences whether these are aggregated in ‘proportional’ or

‘majoritarian’ terms. This holds true whether, operationally, the majority is taken to be

represented by either the median or plurality voter positions, thus resolving the problems of

choice which open up in theory between the two. The two ‘visions’ of democracy, rather than

competing or distinguishing one type of democracy sharply from another, in practice

generally complement each other within the established framework of most democratic

systems.

Page 23: Two Visions One Democracy

23

Table 1

Arguments for the median or plurality positions to be taken as

representing the majority position under mixed motive voting

Arguments for the median position as representing the majority preference:-

Arguments for the plurality position as representing the majority preference:-

1. The median voter is essential to creating a majority under the declared distribution of votes so her position is the only one common to all majorities and can be taken as the one they would arrive at by negotiation and discussion

1. The plurality grouping only failed to become the majority by accident, possibly owing to non-policy based factors affecting voting

2. The median position is defined by the voting preferences of all electors, not an extreme group as could be the case with the plurality

2. The plurality emerges spontaneously as a result of voting. It is not artificially calculated from the final distribution of votes and is thus readily identified and held accountable

3. The median minimizes the overall distance between individual declared preferences and the majority position endorsed by the election.

3. The plurality position is the single revealed preference most representative of majority opinion, particularly if it clearly has more support than the next largest party grouping

4. There is always a plurality party1 but it is not always easy to identify the ‘true’ and ‘unique’ policy median

1 Of course two parties might be returned with the same plurality. In this case both have to be regarded as having its attributes.

Page 24: Two Visions One Democracy

24

Page 25: Two Visions One Democracy

25

Page 26: Two Visions One Democracy

26

Page 27: Two Visions One Democracy

27

Page 28: Two Visions One Democracy

28

FIGURE 1

The Median Position E and Plurality Position G in a

One-dimensional Policy Space

Parties A B C D E F G

Left Right % Seats/Votes 10% 20% 7% 6% 10% 6% 41%

Page 29: Two Visions One Democracy

29

Page 30: Two Visions One Democracy

30

Page 31: Two Visions One Democracy

31

REFERENCES

Adams, James, Michael Clark, Lawrence Ezrow, and Garrett Glasgow. 2004. “Understanding Change and Stability in Party Ideologies: Do Parties Respond to Public Opinion or Past Election Results?” British Journal of Political Science 34: 589-610.

Adams, James and Lawrence Ezrow. 2009. Who Do European Parties Represent? How Western European Parties Represent the Policy Preferences of Opinion Leaders. Journal of Politics 71, 206-223.

Axelrod, Robert. 1970. Conflict of Interest. Chicago, Markham.

Black, Duncan. 1958. The Theory of Committees and Elections, (Cambridge, CUP)

Black, Duncan. 1948. “On the Rationale of Group Decision Making.” Journal of Political Economy 56: 23-34

Blais, André and Marc André Bodet. 2006. “Does Proportional Representation Foster Closer Congruence between Citizens and Policymakers?” Comparative Political Studies 39: 1243-62.

Browne, Eric and Mark Franklin. 1973. Aspects of Coalition Payoffs in European Parliamentary Democracies. American Political Science Review 67: 453-69.

Budge, Ian, Hans-Dieter Klingemann, Andrea Volkens, Judith Bara, Eric Tannenbaum, et al. 2001. Mapping Policy Preferences: Estimates for Parties, Voters and Governments 1945-1998. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Campbell, Angus, Philip Converse, Warren Miller, Donald E. Stokes. 1960. The American Voter. New York, Wiley.

Downs,Anthony. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York, NY: Harper and Row.

Erikson, Robert S., Michael B. MacKuen, and James A. Stimson. 2002. The Macro Polity. Cambridge, UK, and New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

Ezrow, Lawrence. 2005. Are Moderate Parties Rewarded in Multi-Party Systems? A Pooled Analysis of Western European Elections1984-1998. European Journal of Political Research, 44, 881-898.

Gilens, Martin. 2009. “Preference Gaps and Inequality in Representations.” PS, 319-327.

Golder, Matt and Jacek Strmski. 2007. “Ideological Congruence and Two Visions of Democracy.” Unpublished manuscript, Florida State University (July 23 version).

Huber, John D. and Ronald Inglehart. 1995. “Expert Interpretations of Party Space and Party Locations in 42 Societies.” Party Politics 1: 73-111.

Huber, John D. and G. Bingham Powell. 1994. “Congruence between Citizens and Policymakers in Two Visions of Liberal Democracy.” World Politics 46: 291-326.

Kim, HeeMin and Richard Fording. 1998. “Voter Ideology in Western Democracies, 1946-1989.” European Journal of Political Research 33: 73-97.

Kim, HeeMin and Richard Fording. 2002. Government Partisanship in Western Democracies, 1945-1998. European Journal of Political Research 41:187-206.

Page 32: Two Visions One Democracy

32

Klingemann, Hans-Dieter, Andrea Volkens, Judith Bara, Ian Budge, and Michael D. McDonald. 2006. Mapping Policy Preferences II: Estimates for Parties, Voters and Governments in Eastern Europe, European Union and OECD 1990-2003. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Lijphart, Arend. 1968. The Politics of Accommodation. New Haven, CT: Yale.

Lijphart, Arend. 1977. Democracy in Plural Societies: A Comparative Exploration. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Lijphart, Arend. 1984. Democracies: Patterns of Majoritarian and Consensus Government. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Lijphart, Arend. 1994. Electoral Systems and Party Systems: A Study of Twenty-Seven Democracies, 1945-1990. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Lijphart, Arend. 1999. Patterns of Democracy: Government Forms and Performance in Thirty-Six Countries. New Haven. CT: Yale University Press.

McDonald, Michael D., Silvia M. Mendes, and Ian Budge. 2004. “What Are Elections For? Conferring the Median Mandate.” British Journal of Political Science. 34: 1-26.

McDonald, Michael D. and Ian Budge. 2005. Elections, Parties, Democracy: Conferring the Median Mandate. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

May, John D. 1978. ‘Defining Democracy: A Bid for Coherence & Consensus’. Political Studies 26: 1-14.

Müller, Wolfgang C. and Kaare Strom. 2000. Coalition Government in Western Europe. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Powell, G. Bingham, Jr. 1982. Contemporary Democracies: Participation, Stability, and Violence. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Powell, G. Bingham, Jr. 2000. Elections as Instrument of Democracy: Majoritarian and Proportional Visions. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Powell, G. Bingham and Georg Vanberg. 2000. “Election Laws, Disproportionality, and Median Correspondence: Implications for Two Visions of Democracy.” British Journal of Political Science 30: 383-411.

Saward, Michael. 1998. The Terms of Democracy. Cambridge: Polity.

Schattschneider, E.E. 1942. Party Government. New York, NY: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

Schattschneider, E.E. 1960. Semi-Sovereign People: A Realist;s View of Democracy in America. New York, NY: Holt,Rinehart and Winston.

Soroka, Stuart and Christopher Wlezien. 2004. Opinion representation and policy feedback: Canada in Comparative Perspective. Canadian Journal of Political Science 37: 531-60.

Soroka, Stuart and Christopher Wlezien. 2005. Opinion-Policy Dynamics: Public Preferences and Public Expenditure in the UK. British Journal of Political Science 35: 665-89.

Soroka, Stuart and Christopher Wlezien. 2008. ‘On the Limits to Inequality in Representation’. PS 319-327.

Page 33: Two Visions One Democracy

33

Schumpeter, Joseph A. 1950 [1942]. Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy. 3rd ed. New York: Harper & Brothers.

Volkens, Andrea, Kai-Uwe Schnapp and Jürgen Lass. 1992. Data Handbook on Election Results and Seats in the National Parliaments of 26 Contemporary Democracies, 1945-1990. Berlin: WZB.

Warwick, Paul V. and James N. Druckman. 2001. Portfolio Salience and the Proportionality of Payoffs in Coalition Governments. British Journal of Political Science 398: 627-649.

Warwick, Paul and James N. Druckman. 2006. The Portfolio Allocation Paradox: An Investigation into the Nature of a Very Strong but Puzzling Relationship. European Journal of Political Research 45: 635-665.

Wlezien, Christopher. 1996. Dynamics of Representation: The Case of US Spending on

Defense. British Journal of Political Science 26: 81-103. Wlezien,Christopher and Stuart N. Soroka. 2009. ‘The Relationship between Public Opinion

and Policy’, Chap. 43 of Dalton, Russell and H-D Klingemann. Oxford Handbook of Political Behaviour. Oxford, OUP.

Woldendorp, Jaap, Hans Keman and Ian Budge. 2000. Party Government in 48

Democracies (1945-1998). Amsterdam: Kluwer Academic.