value of hedging

203
THE VALUE OF HEDGING A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE DEPARTMENT OF MANAGEMENT SCIENCE & ENGINEERING AND THE COMMITTEE ON GRADUATE STUDIES OF STANFORD UNIVERSITY IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Thomas C. Seyller March 2008

Upload: sean-k-mehra

Post on 22-Nov-2014

205 views

Category:

Documents


6 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Value of Hedging

THE VALUE OF HEDGING

A DISSERTATION

SUBMITTED TO THE DEPARTMENT OF

MANAGEMENT SCIENCE & ENGINEERING

AND THE COMMITTEE ON GRADUATE STUDIES

OF STANFORD UNIVERSITY

IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

FOR THE DEGREE OF

DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY

Thomas C. Seyller

March 2008

Page 2: Value of Hedging

UMI Number: 3302870

Copyright 2008 by

Seyller, Thomas C.

All rights reserved.

INFORMATION TO USERS

The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy

submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and

photographs, print bleed-through, substandard margins, and improper

alignment can adversely affect reproduction.

In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript

and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized

copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion.

®

UMI UMI Microform 3302870

Copyright 2008 by ProQuest LLC.

All rights reserved. This microform edition is protected against

unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code.

ProQuest LLC 789 E. Eisenhower Parkway

PO Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346

Page 3: Value of Hedging

© Copyright by Thomas Seyller 2008

All rights reserved

Page 4: Value of Hedging

I certify that I have read this dissertation and that, in my opinion, it is fully adequate in

scope and quality as a dissertation for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy.

(Ronald A. Howard) Principal Adviser

I certify that I have read this dissertation and that, in my opinion, it is fully adequate in

scope and quality as a dissertation for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy.

(Ali E. Abbas)

I certify that I have read this dissertation and that, in my opinion, it is fully adequate in

scope and quality as a dissertation for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy.

j T ^ i \ y L A A x y t \j7 M A / ^

(Samuel S. Chiu)

Approved for the Stanford University Committee on Graduate Studies.

in

Page 5: Value of Hedging

Abstract

In this dissertation I introduce a definition of hedging which is based on the comparison

of two indifferent buying prices. With that definition, it then becomes possible to ascribe

a monetary value to the hedging provided by a specific deal with respect to the decision­

maker's existing portfolio. The value of hedging concept can also be used to identify

within a list of several deals the ones that best complement the portfolio.

Next, I present some fundamental properties of the value of hedging, including some

which only arise if the decision-maker's u-curve satisfies the delta property. I also shed

some light on the probabilistic phenomena which are at the source of hedging: in that part

of the thesis, I show that hedging can be thought of as moment reengineering, in other

words, as an opportunity to favorably reshape the moments of the decision-maker's

portfolio by adding other deals to it.

The last concept I introduce is that of the value of perfect hedging. While the value of

hedging captures how well a specific deal would fit within the existing portfolio, the

value of perfect hedging captures the decision-maker's willingness to pay for the best

hedges one can construct to complement his portfolio, based on a specific uncertainty.

Such an analysis provides three significant benefits to the decision-maker: first, it enables

him to decide how much of his resources he should devote to searching for hedges;

secondly, it allows him to identify the uncertainties on which it is most valuable to hedge,

and therefore to focus his search on the most promising classes of deals; and finally, the

value of perfect hedging can help him establish an upper bound on his personal

indifferent buying price for any uncertain deal which he might be considering acquiring.

Throughout the dissertation, I illustrate the approach through practical examples and

applications.

IV

Page 6: Value of Hedging

Acknowledgements

I believe that few experiences in someone's life can be as instructive and transforming as

working on a doctoral thesis. My deepest gratitude goes to the wonderful people who

made this experience even more enjoyable than I imagined it would be; I especially wish

to thank my wife Aditi for her love, patience and constant encouragements, and my

parents, my sister and my brother for their support and for all they have taught me.

I am very much indebted to my dissertation advisor, Ronald Howard, for his teachings

and his friendship. From him I have learnt the importance of clarity in thought and

communication, and the efficiency and elegance of simple solutions. I would also like to

thank Ross Shachter, Ali Abbas, Daphne Koller, Samuel Chiu and Jim Matheson for their

guidance and for many thought-provoking classes and discussions. Their love of and

dedication to teaching has been an inspiring example for me.

I finally wish to thank my friends and colleagues Ibrahim Al Mojel, Somik Raha,

Debarun Bhattacharjya, Ram Duriseti and Christopher Han for their support and for

numerous suggestions on this research. My years at Stanford University have been

especially enriched by my experiences as a teaching assistant for decision analysis at

their side. Never let it be said that it is impossible to conciliate an efficient work ethic

with the desire to have fun.

v

Page 7: Value of Hedging

Table of Contents

Abstract iv

Acknowledgements v

Table of Contents vi

Index of Tables & Figures ix

List of Notations Used xi

Chapter 1 - Introduction 1

1. Dissertation Overview 1

2. Motivation 2

3. Research Questions 5

4. Elements of Decision Analysis 7

a) The Six Elements of Decision Quality 8

b) The Five Rules of Actional Thought 9

c) U-curves, Indifferent Buying and Selling Prices, and Delta Property 11

d) The Decision Analysis Cycle 15

5. Hedging in the Financial Literature 32

a) Traditional Definitions of Hedging 33

b) Mean-Variances Approaches 35

c) Utility-Based Approaches 39

Chapter 2 -Definition & Valuation of Hedging 41

1. Definition of Hedging 42

2. Definition of the Value of Hedging 49

a) The Value of Hedging as a Difference of Two PIBPs 50

b) The Value of Hedging as the PIBP of a Translated Deal 52

3. Influence Diagram Representation 56

4. Basic Properties of the Value of Hedging 59

vi

Page 8: Value of Hedging

a) Hedging in the Risk-neutral Case 59

b) Existence of Negative Hedging 61

c) Sign and Monotonicity of the Value of Hedging in the Risk-Averse Case.. 62

d) Value of Hedging for Two Deals Which Differ by a Constant 65

e) PIBPfor an Uncertain Deal and Value of Hedging 68

5. Extension of the Value of Hedging Concept to the Sale of Deals 69

Chapter 3 - Value of Hedging in the Delta Case 72

1. A Simpler Formula to Compute the Value of Hedging 73

2. Special Properties of the Value of Hedging in the Delta Case 76

a) Symmetry 76

b) Upper Bound on the Value of Hedging 77

c) Value of Hedging for Multiples of a Deal with Respect to Itself 83

d) Value of Hedging and Irrelevance 91

3. The Chain Rule for the Value of Hedging and its Implications 95

a) Chain Rule 95

b) Toward an Irrelevance-Based Value of Hedging A Igebra 101

Chapter 4 - Hedging as Moment Reengineering 106

1. General Principle 107

2. Variance Reengineering 109

3. Reengineering Moments of Higher Order 116

Chapter 5 - The Value of Perfect Hedging 120

1. Definition 121

2. Basic Properties 126

a) Risk Attitude and Sign of the Value of Perfect Hedging 126

b) PIBPfor an Uncertain Deal and Value of Perfect Hedging 127

c) Joint Value of Perfect Hedging 130

3. Impact of Relevance on the Value of Perfect Hedging 134

a) Complete Relevance 135

b) Irrelevance 139

c) Incomplete Relevance 142

d) Relevance-Based Dominance of one Hedge over Another 146

vn

Page 9: Value of Hedging

e) Summary - Impact of Relevance on the Value of Perfect Hedging 150

f) Influence of the U-Curve on the Choice of a Perfect Hedge 151

4. General Upper Bound on the PIBP of an Uncertain Deal 153

5. Approximation of the Value of Perfect Hedging in the Delta Case 156

6. Similarities between Value of Perfect Hedging and Value of Clairvoyance 166

7. The Value of Perfect Hedging as a New Appraisal Tool 168

Chapter 6 - Conclusions & Future Work 172

1. Contributions 172

2. Limitations 174

3. Directions for Future Work 177

List of References 179

Probability, Bayesian Methods and Decision Analysis: 179

Finance and Hedging: 184

Index of Terms 188

Vlll

Page 10: Value of Hedging

Index of Tables & Figures

Figure 1.1 - Our valuation of Yean be greatly impacted by X. 2

Figure 1.2 - The six elements of decision quality 8

Table 1.1 - Common u-curves and some of their characteristics 13

Figure 1.3 - The decision analysis cycle 15

Figure 1.4 - A decision hierarchy 16

Table 1.2 - Influence diagram semantics -possible nodes and their meanings 17

Table 1.3 — Influence diagram semantics - possible arrows and their meanings 18

Figure 1.5 - An influence diagram 19

Figure 1.6 - A tornado diagram 21

Figure 1.7 — Cumulative distribution functions for two alternatives 23

Figure 1.8 - Sensitivity to the risk-aversion coefficient 26

Figure 1.9 - Open loop and closed loop sensitivity analyses 28

Figure 1.10 - Minimum-variance hedging for foreign currency 36

Figure II. 1 - Hedging as the comparison of two PIBPs 43

Figure II. 2 - Hedging with complete relevance between X and Y. 44

Figure II. 3 — Hedging with partial relevance between X and Y 46

Figure II. 4 - An equivalent definition of the value of hedging 52

Figure II. 5 - Hedging with partial relevance between Xand Y 55

Figure II. 6 — Using influence diagrams to compute the value of hedging 56

Figure II. 7 -An example for which VoHfY | w, X) is not monotonic in y 63

Figure II. 8 - Sensitivity of VoH(Y \ w, X) to y 63

Figure 11.9 - Hedging provided by a deal which differs from Y by a constant 67

Figure III. 1 - Best hedge for X 79

Figure III.2 - Computation of an upper bound on the PIBP ofY 82

Figure III.3 - Sensitivity ofVoHflX \ X) to k 90

Figure III.4 - Value of hedging for two irrelevant deals 94

Figure III. 5 - Mnemonic for the chain rule for the value of hedging 98

IX

Page 11: Value of Hedging

Figure 111.6 - A chain rule example 99

Figure 111. 7 - Applying the contraction property for the value of hedging 104

Figure IV.1 - Example of variance reengineering 109

Table IV. 1 - Decomposition of certain equivalents along the first two cumulants I l l

Table IV.2 — Decomposition of certain equivalents along the first three cumulants 112

Figure IV.2 — Accuracy of approximation depending on the number of cumulants 113

Figure IV. 3 - Hedging as reengineering of moments of order 3 and above 116

Table TV.3 - Decomposition of certain equivalents along the first five cumulants 117

Figure IV.4 - Accuracy of approximation depending on the number of cumulants 117

Figure IV.5 - Probability mass functions ofX and (X u Y) 118

Figure V.l - The value of perfect hedging: an example 123

Figure V.2- Upper bound on the PIBPfor Y based on the value of perfect hedging.... 128

Figure V. 3 - Joint perfect hedging on Oil Price and Volume 132

Figure V.4- Gold Price is only relevant to the value through Oil Price 144

Figure V.5 - Impact of the relevance between S and S' on VoPHfS"1 \ X, w) 150

Table V.l - Impact of the risk tolerance on the selection of a perfect hedge 152

Figure V.6 - Distribution over profit for the second oilfield. 155

Figure V. 7 -Accuracy of our value of perfect hedging approximation: an example .... 160

Figure V.8 - Influence of risk-aversion on the accuracy of the approximation 162

Figure V.9 — Influence of risk-aversion on the accuracy of the approximation (2) 163

Table V.2- Comparison of value of clairvoyance and value of perfect hedging 167

Figure V.10- The value of perfect hedging in the decision analysis cycle 168

Figure V.l I -Example for the use of perfect hedging as an appraisal tool 170

Figure VI. 1 - Hedging with negative side effects 175

Figure VI.2 - Equivalent probability of clairvoyance 177

x

Page 12: Value of Hedging

List of Notations Used

{A | B, &} Probability assigned to A given B and the background state of

information & of the individual.

A J_ B | C, & A is irrelevant to (or some might say "probabilistically

independent of) B given C and the background state of

information & of the person. This means that in the opinion of the

person making the statement, {A | B = b;, C, &} = {A | B = bj, C,

&} for any possible outcomes bj and bj of B. Relevance statements,

just like probability assignments, are matters of information and

not matters of logic - two individuals might disagree as to whether

two uncertainties are relevant or irrelevant given a third.

X= {(pi, Xj)je[i,n]} The uncertain deal X comprises n prospects x;, with their

associated probabilities p;.

<Y | &> Mean of Y given &.

V(Y | &> Variance of Y given &.

~(Y | w, X) The decision-maker's PISP for deal Y given that he also owns

wealth w and a portfolio of deals denoted by X. In the delta case,

we will use the notation S~(X | 0) to refer to S~(X | w), since w does

not have any effect on the value of certain equivalents.

RPs(Y | w, X) The decision-maker's selling risk premium for deal Y given that he

also owns wealth w and a portfolio of deals denoted by X. It is

defined as <Y | &> - S~<Y | w, X>.

XI

Page 13: Value of Hedging

~(Y | w, X) The decision-maker's PIBP for deal Y given that he already owns

wealth w and a portfolio of deals denoted by X. In the delta case,

we will use the notation S~(X | 0) to refer to B~(X | w), since w does

not have any impact on the value of certain equivalents and since

the PIBP for any deal is equal to the PISP for the same deal.

RPB(Y I w, X) The decision-maker's buying risk premium for deal Y given that

he already owns wealth w and a portfolio of deals denoted by X. It

is defined as <Y | &> - B~(Y | w, X).

xn

Page 14: Value of Hedging

Chapter 1 - Introduction

"Humanity is constantly struggling with two contradictory processes.

One of these tends to promote unification, while the other aims at

maintaining or re-establishing diversification. "

Claude Levi-Strauss (b. 1908),

Race et Histoire

1. Dissertation Overview

In this dissertation we will study hedging through a decision analytic lens.

I will first introduce a definition of hedging which is entirely grounded on the principles

of personal indifferent buying and selling prices. This will also allow me to establish a

method through which we can assign a monetary value to the hedging that a deal

provides with respect to the decision-maker's existing portfolio. Many of the properties

of the so-defined value of hedging will be presented and illustrated through practical

examples.

In the later parts of the dissertation, I will present a concept which provides further

insights to the decision-maker: the value of perfect hedging. Given a specific portfolio,

the value of perfect hedging is the amount that the decision-maker should be willing to

pay for the most favorable deal that can be constructed by hedging on some particular

uncertainty or set of uncertainties. The value of perfect hedging thus helps us place an

upper bound on the resources that should be devoted to hedging the existing portfolio.

1

Page 15: Value of Hedging

2. Motivation

In decision analysis, we often observe that our valuation of uncertain deals can be greatly

affected by the existence of other deals we own. It is a common oversight to

underestimate how pervasive the phenomenon actually is; many students in decision

analysis, including some who have received training in the discipline for several quarters,

often believe that it does not hold for decision-makers who follow the delta property. The

students' intuition is that since the certain equivalents of such decision-makers for

uncertain deals do not depend on their initial wealth, they should not depend on the

unresolved deals which they own either.

A simple example such as the one presented in the next figure is enough for those

students to become aware of their mistake. In that example, the decision-maker, who

follows the delta property, owns deal X and has a certain equivalent of $2,000 for it. The

decision-maker is then offered deal Y for a fee. At first it might be tempting to reason

that the decision-maker should be willing to pay up to $2,000 for Y, because it comprises

the same probabilities of the same prospects as X.

r ^ — $10,000 -$5,000 0.5

O

—— -$5,000 $10,000

Figure 1.1 — Our valuation of Y can be greatly impacted by X

However, such logic is flawed; it does not take into account the fact that deals X and Y

are probabilistically relevant. In fact, by combining X and Y into the same portfolio, the

decision-maker is assured of a profit of $5,000 once both deals are resolved, irrespective

2

Page 16: Value of Hedging

of whether si or S2 is realized. The decision-maker should thus be willing to pay as much

as $3,000 for deal Y, since it can help him transition from a situation worth $2,000 to one

worth $5,000.

The difference between the two possible answers, the erroneous one ($2,000) and the

correct one ($3,000), is sizable. It should remind us that, just like information and control,

hedging can be regarded as an alternative which might significantly affect the value of

the decision-maker's portfolio.

Another element which should make that alternative worthy of our consideration is its

availability. Many financial instruments have been used extensively and for several

decades for hedging purposes, from insurance contracts to derivatives such as forwards or

swaps. Hedging instruments have even been gaining in accessibility in recent years, be it

for organizations or private investors; for instance, companies such as HedgeStreet have

started offering financial derivatives which are designed to give individuals more

flexibility as they try to manage the risk of their portfolio.

The primary ambition of this dissertation is to raise our sensitivity as decision analysts to

the value that hedging can bring to decision-makers. I will strive to present enough

evidence for the reader to be able to decide whether he wants to apply those views on

hedging in his professional practice; but it is not one of my intentions to dissect the

ideological differences between the approach to hedging presented here and that which

can be found in most of the traditional finance literature. It is true that philosophical

differences between the decision analytic framework and the financial framework abound,

the treatment of uncertainty being one of the most notable examples; but I share the

opinion of Edwin T. Jaynes [Jaynes, E.T., 1976], who argued that the true test of the

merits of two competing statistical theories should consist in applying them to the same

examples and deciding which one provides the most sensible results:

Let me make what, I fear, will seem to some a radical, shocking suggestion: the

merits of any statistical method are not determined by the ideology which led to

it. For, many different, violently opposed ideologies may all lead to the same

final 'working equations' for dealing with real problems. Apparently, this

phenomenon is something new in statistics; but it is so commonplace in physics

that we have long since learned how to live with it. Today, when a physicist says,

3

Page 17: Value of Hedging

"Theory A is better than theory B", he does not have in mind any ideological

considerations; he means simply, 'There is at least one specific application

where theory A leads to a better result than theory B".

I suggest that we apply the same criterion in statistics: the merits of any

statistical method are determined by the results it gives when applied to specific

problems. The Court of Last Resort in statistics is simply our commonsense

judgment of those results.

I thus hope to provide a sufficiently ample number of practical examples throughout this

dissertation for the reader to get a solid grasp of the decision analytic approach to

hedging I am advocating, and of its possible benefits and drawbacks.

4

Page 18: Value of Hedging

3. Research Questions

The fundamental research questions which I intend to address in this dissertation are

congruent with the motivation and objectives I exposed above:

[ 1 ] What is hedging? What is a clarity-test definition of hedging?

[2] How can I measure the value of hedging?

[2.a] Given the decision-maker's current portfolio, and given a specific

deal which he does not own but is considering buying, how can I

ascribe a monetary value to the hedging that the deal provides with

respect to the portfolio?

[2.b] How can I extend the value of hedging concept to the case of a

specific deal which he owns but is considering selling?

[2.c] What remarkable properties does the value of hedging have? Does

it have any special properties in the case in which the decision­

maker's u-curve satisfies the delta property?

[3] Which probabilistic phenomena are at work in hedging? How can the

existence of hedging be explained?

[4] Given the decision-maker's portfolio, how can I help him identify the

kinds of deals which best complement it?

[4.a] How can I detect the uncertainties on which it is most valuable to

perform hedging?

[4.b] Is there a way to quantify the decision-maker's willingness to pay

for the ability to perform hedging on a given uncertainty or set of

uncertainties?

[5] How can analyses related to hedging be incorporated into the existing

decision analysis process? How can decision analysts best apply those

tools and methods to practical situations?

5

Page 19: Value of Hedging

I will now give an overview of some of the existing research which will help us answer

those questions. I will start with a short introduction to decision analysis, the engineering

discipline whose principles and techniques will serve as a foundation for this dissertation.

After that, I will provide a succinct account of the works on hedging which can be found

in the finance literature.

6

Page 20: Value of Hedging

4. Elements of Decision Analysis

The term "decision analysis" was coined by Ronald A. Howard [1966a] and refers to

"applied decision theory". The objective of a decision analysis is to help the decision­

maker achieve clarity of action - in other words, to help him identify what is the best

course of action given the information he has, given his preferences, and given the

alternatives that are available to him.

Decision analysis is a normative discipline, and not a descriptive discipline; as such, its

sole intent is to provide axioms and norms for how people should make decisions, and

not to identify the intellectual and psychological processes which account for how people

actually make decisions.

Over the next few pages, I will provide an overview of some of the most fundamental

concepts of decision analysis, with an emphasis on the concepts which will be most

critical to understanding this dissertation. I recommend to the readers who are least

familiar with the field that they consult the works which are cited in the list of references,

in particular those of Ronald A. Howard [1964, 1965, 1966a, 1966b, 1968, 1992, 2004],

Peter C. Fishburn [1964], or Howard Raiffa [1968].

7

Page 21: Value of Hedging

a) The Six Elements of Decision Quality

It is difficult to articulate what constitutes a good decision in no more than a sentence.

In decision analysis, we consider that there are six elements to decision quality

[Matheson, D., and Matheson, J. E., 1998]. They are enumerated on the figure below.

Any decision or decision process can be rated along those six dimensions, from 0% to

100%. 100% indicates the point at which trying to do better on that specific dimension

would yield an improvement which would not be worth the additional expense of

resources required to obtain it.

Three of the six elements of decision quality, namely the alternatives, information and

preferences of the decision-maker, are also collectively referred to as the "decision basis".

Meaningful, Reliable Information

Creative, Doable

Alternatives

Appropriate Frame

Clear Values & Trade-offs

Commitment To Action

Logically Correct

Reasoning

Figure 1.2 - The six elements of decision quality

Page 22: Value of Hedging

b) The Five Rules of Actional Thought

Like any other normative system, decision analysis is entirely based on a few principles

which serve as axioms. There are five of them [Howard, R. A., 1992], and they are

commonly known as the "five rules of actional thought":

• The probability rule requires the decision-maker to be able to characterize every

alternative he faces by a possibility tree - that is, a tree showing the different

scenarios which might unfold following the selection of that particular alternative.

The decision-maker should also be able to assign probabilities to all branches of

the tree, and he may or may not choose to assign value measures to characterize

the quality of all of the corresponding possible futures. Once the probability rule

has been applied, the decision-maker obtains a list of prospects, in other words a

list of all of the possible futures he might face as a result of the decision situation.

• The order rule requires the decision-maker to order every prospect in the list from

best to worst, according to his own preference. Ties are allowed: the decision­

maker might declare that he is indifferent between several prospects.

• The equivalence rule states that for any triplet of prospects which are at different

levels in the ordered list, A, B and C where A > B > C (">" denotes the

preference order), the decision-maker should be able to assign a number p,

comprised between 0 and 1, such that he would be just indifferent between

receiving B for sure and an uncertain deal in which he would receive A with

probability/) and C with probability 1 -p. Such a number/? is called a preference

probability.

• The substitution rule states that for any triplet of prospects A, B and C where A >

B > C, if the decision-maker faces an uncertain deal in which he assigns a

probability p to his receiving A versus 1 — p of his receiving C, where p is also

equal to his preference probability for B in terms of A versus C, then the decision­

maker should be indifferent between keeping the uncertain deal and exchanging it

forB.

9

Page 23: Value of Hedging

• Finally, let us suppose that there are two prospects A and B at different levels in

the ordered list of prospects, and that A >B; let us also suppose that the decision­

maker needs to choose one of two uncertain deals: in the first, he will receive

either A with probability r or B with probability \ - r, while in the other deal he

will receive either A with a different probability s or B with a probability 1 - s.

Then, the choice rule requires that the decision-maker choose the deal which

offers the better chance of the prospect he likes better, namely A: he should select

the first deal if r > s, the second if r < s.

Decision analysis can only be of help to decision-makers who choose to subscribe to the

five rules of actional thought. By successively and carefully applying the rules, one after

the other, to a particular decision situation, a decision analyst can help a decision-maker

infer what the best alternative available to him is. Conversely, to the decision-maker who

does not subscribe to at least one of the five rules, counsel from a decision analyst is of as

little use as are the theorems of Euclidian geometry to someone who rejects one of its

postulates.

10

Page 24: Value of Hedging

c) U-curves, Indifferent Buying and Selling Prices, and Delta Property

It would be a tedious process to repeatedly apply the equivalence rule to elicit from the

decision-maker a preference probability for each prospect of a large-scale decision

situation: if there are JV> 3 prospects {Pi}ie[i,AG, Pi being the best and PN the worst, one

would need at least N- 2 assessments, one for each prospect within the list {Pi}ie[2, jv-i] in

terms of Pi and PN- Fortunately, it is possible to greatly simplify the assessment process

by introducing a few more basic concepts.

Let us first observe that in any decision situation, the course of action which is

recommended by the five rules of actional thought does not change if all preference

probabilities are arbitrarily multiplied by the same positive constant, or if any real

number is added to all of them. We can thus lift the requirement that preference

probabilities should be contained within the interval [0, 1], All we need to do is introduce

a new term to refer to those unrestricted preference probabilities, as the analogy with a

probability is lost once we allow those numbers to dwell outside of [0, 1]; we will call

them u-values instead [Howard, R. A., 1998].

We can then simplify the assessment process for preference probabilities by assuming

that the u-values all follow a particular functional form, which we will call u-curve. If the

value measure which the decision-maker cares about is his wealth, w, we can denote the

u-curve by u(w). If in addition the decision-maker prefers more money to less, u(.) should

be an increasing function.

Once it is assessed from the decision-maker, the u-curve can be used to solve decision

situations without resorting to preference probabilities anymore: it can be shown that

subscribing to the five rules of actional thought is equivalent to making decisions by

selecting the alternative which yields the highest expected u-value.

With u-curves, it also becomes possible to compute the decision-maker's Personal

Indifferent Buying Price (PIBP) for something he does not own, or his Personal

Indifferent Selling Price (PISP) for something he owns [Howard, R. A., 1998]. The PIBP

for an item is defined as the sum of money such that the decision-maker is just indifferent

between not acquiring the item at all and acquiring the item at that price; more formally,

if we consider a deal X with probabilities pj and prospects x;, ie[l , n], which the

11

Page 25: Value of Hedging

decision-maker is considering acquiring, and if we denote his present wealth by w and his

PIBP for X by b, the indifference statement can be translated into the following equation:

u(w) = X PiUCw + Xj-b) ie[l,n]

Similarly, the PISP for an item is defined as the sum of money such that the decision­

maker is just indifferent between retaining the item and selling the item at that price. The

PISP for an uncertain deal is also called certain equivalent. For an uncertain deal with

probabilities q* and prospects y\, ie[l, m] which the decision-maker owns and is

considering selling, if we denote his PISP for Y by s, then:

u(w + s)= 2 9 , u ( w + yi) ie[l,m]

The decision-maker's risk attitude is directly reflected in the shape of his u-curve, and

more specifically in its concavity or convexity. We will call risk-neutral a decision-maker

who assigns to an uncertain deal a certain equivalent which is exactly equal to the

probability-weighted average of its monetary prospects (an amount usually referred to as

"the e-value of the monetary prospects" of the deal). A risk-averse decision-maker is

defined as one whose certain equivalent for an uncertain deal is inferior to the e-value of

the monetary prospects of the deal; for example, a decision-maker who has a certain

equivalent of $450 for an uncertain deal in which he assigns a 50% chance to receiving

$1,000 and a 50% chance to receiving nothing is risk-averse. Such a decision-maker has a

concave u-curve. In contrast, a risk-seeking decision-maker is one who assigns to an

uncertain deal a certain equivalent which is greater than the e-value of the monetary

prospects of the deal; his u-curve is convex.

It is important to understand that nothing in the five rules of actional thought prohibits u-

curves which are concave on some intervals but convex on others. A decision-maker

using such a u-curve would exhibit a risk-averse behavior for some deals and a risk-

seeking behavior for others. Piecewise concave and convex u-curves are seldom used in

practice, however; it is not surprising if we consider that very few decision-makers, once

they understand what the term risk-seeking truly means in decision analysis, would want

to adopt that sort of risk attitude in an actual decision situation.

12

Page 26: Value of Hedging

The next table shows some of the u-curves which can be most commonly found in the

literature [Bickel, E. J., 1999]:

Table 1.1 — Common u-curves and some of their characteristics

Among the u-curves listed above, two of them, the linear and exponential form u-curves,

possess a fascinating characteristic called the delta property [Howard, R. A., 1998]:

consider a decision-maker who has a certain equivalent s for an uncertain deal X = {(p;, x0ie[i,n]}; what will be his certain equivalent s' for an uncertain deal X' = {(pi, Xj + §)ie[i,

n]}, in other words, for a deal which differs from X by a constant 8? It is a natural

desideratum for many decision-makers, especially if they regard the magnitude of the

monetary prospects involved as relatively small compared to their total wealth, to declare

that s' should be equal to s + 8. If that is the case, the decision-maker's u-curve is said to

satisfy the delta property.

13

Page 27: Value of Hedging

What makes the delta property particularly remarkable is the fact that it entails many

additional properties for the decision-maker:

• The decision-maker's valuation of any uncertain deal remains the same whether

he includes his initial wealth in his characterization of the deal's monetary

prospects or not. Therefore, it is not necessary to take initial wealth into account

when computing his PIBP or PISP for a deal.

• For any uncertain deal, the decision-maker's PIBP and PISP for it are equal.

• The decision-maker's u-curve can only be of one of two forms: linear or

exponential. Because u-curves are unique up to a positive linear transformation,

as mentioned earlier, this also implies that the only number which needs to be

assessed to determine the decision-maker's u-curve in its entirety is y, which is

often called the decision-maker's risk-aversion coefficient. A y of zero

corresponds to a risk-neutral decision-maker, a positive y to a risk-averse

decision-maker, and a negative y to a risk-seeking decision-maker.

Therefore, one question is all decision analysts need to ask in order to assess y and

thereby the whole u-curve - at least in theory, since in practice it is still advisable

to proceed to several measurements of y in order to assess it more accurately.

• The value of any information gathering process can be computed as the difference

between the value of the deal with the help of the additional information and the

value of the deal without.

14

Page 28: Value of Hedging

d) The Decision Analysis Cycle

The decision analysis process [Howard, R.A., 1966a] is iterative. It consists of four

phases, which are depicted below:

Formulation Evaluation Appraisal

0 . . • Deterministic ^ Probabilistic . . . • , ._ . . Structure . • . , • , , • Appraisal —b. n p r i « i n n Analysis Analysis uccisiuu

t Figure 1.3 - The decision analysis cycle

It is another common oversight to believe that the decision analysis process merely boils

down to the construction of a mathematical model and its analysis - in reality, the entire

process can be thought of as a continuous conversation between the decision-maker and

the decision analyst, intended to guide the decision-maker towards clarity of action, and a

mathematical model is no more than one of the recurrent and most visible constituents of

that conversation.

15

Page 29: Value of Hedging

Formulation Phase

The main objective of the formulation phase is to frame the decision situation: decision­

maker and decision analyst seek to distinguish the issues which should be under

consideration in the analysis from those which should not.

Framing is more of an art than a procedure with strictly established steps and guidelines.

However, an important element of virtually every framing exercise is to determine

exactly which decisions need to be made at this epoch in time. In many practical

examples, especially if many stakeholders are involved in the decision process, it is no

simple question to answer. A decision hierarchy is a tool which helps address the issue; it

prompts the decision-maker to separate his decisions into three distinct categories: those

that can be taken as givens; those which are important enough to be the object of the

current analysis; and, finally, those which are thought to have a small enough impact on

the value for them to see their examination safely deferred until later.

TAKE AS GIVEN

V ANALYZE NOW

y EXAMINE LATER

Figure 1.4 - A decision hierarchy

Once all decisions have been sorted into those three separate containers, we can focus our

attention on the middle category. The next important point to ponder is the list of the

uncertainties which should be included in the analysis, given the decisions which are to

16

Page 30: Value of Hedging

be analyzed, and how those decisions and uncertainties all affect one another as well as

the decision-maker's value. Influence diagrams, which are also referred to as decision

diagrams in parts of the literature, are powerful tools which assist analyst and decision­

maker as they communicate about such matters [Howard, R. A., and Matheson, J. E.

1981]. They offer a graphical representation of the structure of the decision situation, and

of the relationships which exist between all the issues involved.

The semantics of influence diagrams are outlined in the following tables; a total of four

kinds of nodes and four kinds of arrows, each with a specific meaning, can be

encountered in influence diagrams:

Table 1.2 - Influence diagram semantics -possible nodes and their meanings

17

Page 31: Value of Hedging

Meaning

D,

D

D

D,

Relevance Arrow

Informational

Arrow

Functional

Arrow

Influence Arrow

A and B are probabilistically

relevant given their parent nodes

Decision Di and the outcome of

uncertainty C are both observed

before making decision D2

Deterministic node F is a function

of decision D and the outcome of E

The probability distribution over the

degrees of C varies depending on

the decision which is made at D

Table 1.3 - Influence diagram semantics -possible arrows and their meanings

An example of an influence diagram for an oil exploration and drilling decision is shown

in the next figure; it is based on one of the models which Ross Shachter presents in his

introduction to the subject [Shachter, R. D., 1997]:

18

Page 32: Value of Hedging

Figure 1.5 — An influence diagram

It should also be noted that the role of influence diagrams can be extended beyond their

use as a representation of the structure of the decision situation: in fact, it is possible to

encode probabilities and value measures into the influence diagram, and to then solve it

in order to identify the best alternative and its associated certain equivalent [Shachter, R.

D., 1986 and 1988].

19

Page 33: Value of Hedging

Evaluation Phase

During the evaluation phase, a mathematical model of the decision situation, as framed

during the formulation stage, is built and analyzed in order to identify the best alternative.

Deterministic Analysis

Naturally, the first step consists in building such a mathematical model of the decision

situation. It should include:

• all of the alternatives under consideration;

• all of the uncertainties listed on the influence diagram; for each of them, the

decision-maker is asked to provide three possible values, either by himself or with

the help of a designated expert: a base value, corresponding to the median of the

probability distribution over the uncertainty; a low value, corresponding to the

10th percentile of the distribution; and a high value, corresponding to the 90th

percentile;

• calculations showing the value which any possible scenario, that is to say any

possible selection of an alternative followed by any possible realization of the

uncertainties, would yield for the decision-maker. In many cases, it is the net

present value of the scenario which is evaluated.

Such models are often built using spreadsheet programs, as they allow for a rapid

recalculation of the value for various scenarios - a feature which will prove valuable on

many occasions throughout the analysis, as we will see later.

The next task for the decision analyst consists in assessing the relative importance of the

uncertainties by comparing their individual effects on the value. Tornado diagrams fill

that need [McNamee, P., and Celona, J., 1987]. For a specific alternative, the analyst first

computes what is called its base value - in other words, the value of the alternative when

all uncertainties are set to their base values. Then, the analyst perturbs each uncertainty,

one by one and one at a time, swinging it from base to low and from base to high. The

results are recorded and the uncertainties are sorted, from the one triggering the greatest

20

Page 34: Value of Hedging

swing in value to the one triggering the smallest. A tornado diagram such as the one

shown below is built in order to display the results in a way which makes it easier to

discuss and interpret them. The whole procedure we just described is sometimes also

called deterministic sensitivity analysis, in recognition of the fact that the probability of

each possible scenario has not yet been taken into account.

-100.0

Market Size I

Revenue per jjnit

Efficacy of the Drug

Number of Compi rtitors

Side Effects of the Drug

Phase III Trial Duration

Phase III Trial Cost

I

Production Cost per Unit

New Plant Construction Cost

-50.0 Profit ($ million)

0.0 50.0 100.0 150.0

Figure 1.6-A tornado diagram

The analyst and the decision-maker can then read off the tornado diagram the names of

the uncertainties which have the greatest potential impact on value, and decide which

variables they want to model probabilistically throughout the remainder of the analysis

[Howard, R. A., 1966; Matheson, J. E., and Howard, R. A., 1968]. Uncertainties which

are not selected will be modeled as deterministic quantities instead. In addition, the

analyst and the decision-maker may choose to exclude an alternative from the analysis, if

they observe during the deterministic sensitivity phase that it is systematically dominated

by at least one of its rivals.

21

Page 35: Value of Hedging

Probabilistic Analysis

A few assessments need to be made before the analyst can proceed with the evaluation of

the probabilistic model: the analyst should first elicit probability distributions for the

uncertainties which were selected at the term of the deterministic phase, with the help of

the decision-maker himself or of a designated expert.

Probability encoding is a time-consuming and complex procedure [Spetzler, C. S., and

Stael von Holstein, A. S., 1975]; like anyone else, decision-makers, experts or other

stakeholders in the decision-making process are often the victims of biases which cloud

their judgment, and it is crucial that the analyst help them discern their true belief from

the distortions that those biases impose. I encourage the reader to refer to the works of

Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman [1974] for an overview of such biases, and to those

of Carl S. Spetzler and Axel S. Stael von Holstein [1975] for an introduction to

techniques which decision analysts can use to combat their influence during probability

encoding.

Armed with those probability distributions, the analyst can then plot for each alternative a

cumulative distribution function over the value measure. Such a curve shows, for each

possible realization of the value measure, the probability assigned to obtaining a result

which would be inferior to that value. An example of two cumulative distribution

functions corresponding to two different alternatives is shown on the next figure.

Next, the analyst can assess the decision-maker's u-curve over the range of prospects

involved in the decision situation; as mentioned earlier, if the decision-maker is

comfortable with following the delta property over that range, the task is considerably

easier, since only one parameter needs to be assessed in that case. Once the u-curve has

been elicited, the analyst can compute the certain equivalents of all the alternatives and

identify the best course of action.

22

Page 36: Value of Hedging

roba

bili

ty

0-4>

"3 g s U

100%

90%

80%

70%

60%

50%

40%

30%

20%

10%

0%

It is at times possible to infer from the cumulative distribution functions of two

alternatives A and B that A will be preferable to B regardless of the degree to which the

decision-maker is risk-averse [Howard, R. A., 1998]; in such cases, it might thus be

unnecessary to assess the decision-maker's risk-aversion coefficient y with great

precision. The situation arises in instances of:

• deterministic dominance: when the worst prospect achievable under alternative A

is better than the best prospect achievable under alternative B;

• first-order probabilistic dominance: when the difference between the cumulative

distribution functions of A and B keeps a negative sign over the entire range;

• or of second-order probabilistic dominance: when the integral of the difference

between the cumulative distribution functions of A and B keeps a negative sign

over the entire range.

In the example shown above, there is no dominance relationship between A and B. It is

not a surprising conclusion when one considers that B offers a better mean profit than A,

23

100 -$50 $150 $0 $50 $100

Net Present Value ($ Million)

Figure 1.7- Cumulative distribution functions for two alternatives

$200

Page 37: Value of Hedging

but at the cost of a substantially larger downside: to a risk-neutral decision-maker, since

the mean is all that matters, B will thus appear as the better alternative, whereas to a

sufficiently risk-averse decision-maker, the magnitude of B's potential downside will

seem so large that A will earn his favors overall.

24

Page 38: Value of Hedging

Appraisal Phase

The decision analyst identified the best alternative during the evaluation phase and

computed its certain equivalent. But that does not mark the end of the analysis; in order

to achieve complete clarity of action, it is helpful to answer two additional questions:

• Under what conditions should we make a different decision?

• Before choosing the alternative which currently appears to be the best available,

can the decision situation be improved by gathering further information, or by

exerting some influence over some of the uncertainties involved? How much

should the decision-maker be willing to pay for each of those activities?

Sensitivity Analysis

Sensitivity analysis [Howard, R. A., 1968] addresses the first of the two issues: by

perturbing the variables involved in the model, one by one and over reasonable ranges of

values, and by tracking the impact that such changes have on the certain equivalent of

each alternative, the analyst can assess the relative importance of different variables;

some may be recognized as being incapable of altering the decision-maker's choice,

while others may trigger spectacular shifts in the decision. At the term of the analysis, the

decision-maker will thus be able discern the elements which are worthy of his attention

from those which are not.

For instance, if there is no dominance between two alternatives up to the second order, it

might prove helpful to perform a sensitivity analysis on the decision-maker's risk-

aversion coefficient, y. An example follows; a decision-maker needs to choose between

four alternatives, A, B, C and D. He follows the delta property over the entire range of

prospects involved and during the assessment process for his risk-aversion coefficient, his

answers all implied values of y comprised between 0.07 and 0.11. At first, that might

seem to be a wide interval of possible values, and the analyst might think that it will be

indispensable to ask more questions in order to assess y more accurately. However,

inspection of the sensitivity analysis chart below reveals that alternative B is the best

alternative within this entire range by a comfortable margin, and its certain equivalent is

25

Page 39: Value of Hedging

contained in a relatively narrow interval: [$112,000; $121,000]. All of a sudden, what

seemed to be an uncomfortably wide range of possible values for y appears as no more

than an inconsequential annoyance.

$160

$140

$120

$100

c a V3 S o

J=

H © $80 =

4>

$60 '3 a-w S $40

$20

Alternative A

Alternate e B

^«. Alternative C

$0 0.000 0.002 0.004 0.006 0.008 0.010 0.012 0.014 0.016 0.018 0.02

Y

Figure 1.8 — Sensitivity to the risk-aversion coefficient

Sensitivity analysis also helps the decision-maker understand how the best course of

action might change given slightly different circumstances. This is especially important

in business settings, since the results of a market study, an important announcement made

by a competitor or a large-scale economic event often leave little time to react, and it

would not be to the decision-maker's advantage if he had to commission a fresh

evaluation of his decision situation every time he receives a new piece of information.

Sensitivity analysis is usually conducted slightly differently in the case of the

uncertainties which were modeled probabilistically during the evaluation phase. As a

reminder, typically, three values are elicited from the decision-maker for each of those

26

Page 40: Value of Hedging

uncertainties: a low, a base and a high, which respectively correspond to the 10 , 50 and

90th percentiles of the distribution. Those three values can then be used to perform what

is called open-loop and closed-loop sensitivity analyses [Howard, R. A., 1968]; more

specifically, if we denote by A the alternative which was shown to be the best at the term

of the evaluation phase, the analyst computes for uncertainty U with fractiles uiow, Ubase

and Uhigh:

• the certain equivalents of A given that U = uiow, given that U = Ubase, and given

that U = Uhigh- This is called an open-loop sensitivity analysis: the alternative is

permanently set at A, and the analyst simply computes the fluctuations in its

certain equivalent as U varies;

• the certain equivalent of the alternative which is preferred when U = uiow, the

certain equivalent of the alternative which is preferred when U = Ubase, and the

certain equivalent of the alternative which is preferred when U = Uhigh. Those

alternatives need not be the same, nor does any of them need to be A. This is

called a closed-loop sensitivity analysis: this time, the alternative is not rigidly

anchored on A; as the analyst varies U, he also allows himself to change his

decision in favor of a better alternative, and it is the certain equivalent of that

alternative which is recorded.

The results of the open-loop and closed-loop sensitivity analyses can be plotted as

illustrated below. It should be noted that the open-loop curve should not surpass the

closed-loop curve at any point.

27

Page 41: Value of Hedging

$300

1? $250 -.2

§ % $200 j -**

s

1 $150 -'3 e $100 '3 V.

o W $50

$0 -U i o w Ubase ^high

Figure 1.9 — Open loop and closed loop sensitivity analyses

Open-loop and closed-loop sensitivity analyses are computationally intensive, since they

require three separate and complete reevaluations of the certain equivalent of each

alternative - one reevaluation for U = uiow, one for U = Ubase and one for U = Uhigh-

However, the results they produce are remarkably compact, since six data points on a

chart are enough to capture them in their entirety, and admirably powerful: in our

illustrative example, the analyst can conclude that A would remain the best alternative

even if the decision-maker were to obtain additional information which led him to believe

that U = uiow with certainty, or that U = Ubase; indeed, at those two values, the results of

the open-loop and closed-loop sensitivity analyses coincide. Conversely, the best

alternative would change if the decision-maker became sure that U = Uhigh- In that event,

A is outperformed by at least one alternative by $56 million.

We will soon see that a few more significant insights can be extracted from the open-loop

and closed-loop curves; but before that, we should mention as a conclusion to our

overview of sensitivity analysis procedures that in many decision situations, it can also be

illuminating to evaluate the sensitivity of the decision to the relevance of various

uncertainties to one another [Lowell, D. G., 1994]. This helps distinguish the relevance

relationships which need to be elicited and explicitly modeled as conditional probability

distributions from those which can be left as marginal distributions without impairing the

28

Page 42: Value of Hedging

quality of the recommendation. Sensitivity analysis to relevance is especially critical in

decision situations with large and intricate probabilistic structures, since it is in those

instances that simplifying the model in order to avoid unessential conditional probability

assessments will tend to prove most valuable.

Value of Information and Value of Control

As announced earlier, a second objective of the appraisal phase is to determine whether

the decision situation can be improved by gathering further information, or by exerting

influence over some of the uncertainties involved.

The value of information [Howard, R. A., 1966b] addresses the first half of the question;

for any information gathering scheme, be it a clinical test in a medical decision setting or

market studies and R&D experiments in a major corporation, the value of information is

defined as the decision-maker's PIBP for the additional information. In other words, it is

the price P at which he is just indifferent between facing his present decision situation as

is, and facing the same decision situation with the help of the additional information but

also with a bank account which was reduced by P.

For decision-makers who follow the delta property over the entire range of prospects

involved, we observed earlier that the value of information on some uncertainty U can be

computed as the difference between the value of the deal with free and perfect

information on U, and the value of the deal without any further information on U. Both of

those quantities can easily be calculated based on the results of the open-loop and closed-

loop sensitivity analyses on U:

• The value of the deal with free and perfect information on U corresponds to what

we might call the certain equivalent of the closed-loop curve; it is equal to the

certain equivalent of an uncertain deal in which there are three monetary

prospects, Qow, Cbase and Chigh, as identified on the previous figure, with

respective probabilities {uiow | &}, { i w I &}, and {uhigh | &}.

• On the other hand, the value of the deal with no additional information on U

corresponds to what we might call the certain equivalent of the open-loop curve;

29

Page 43: Value of Hedging

it is equal to the certain equivalent of an uncertain deal in which there are three

monetary prospects, Oiow, Obase and Ohigh, with respective probabilities {uiow | &},

{ubase I &}, and {uhigh | &}. It should be noted that the analyst already calculated

the quantity in question earlier in the analysis - it is equal to the certain equivalent

of A, as computed during the evaluation phase.

Similarly, the value of control over some uncertainty U is defined as the decision-maker's

PIBP for being able to choose the outcome of U [Matheson, J. E., 1990]. In a business

setting, it is for example possible to try and influence a product's market share by

launching a marketing campaign which will increase the product's visibility. In the high

technology and pharmaceutical sectors, firms might also choose to devote more resources

to a particular project or molecular compound in order to increase the likelihood of

technical success.

Just like in the case of the value of information, there exists an easy procedure to

compute the value of control for decision-makers who follow the delta property over the

entire range of prospects: then, the value of control is equal to the difference between the

value of the deal with free and perfect control over the outcome of U, and the value of the

deal without any control over U. Those two numbers can again be calculated with the

help of the open-loop and closed-loop chart:

• The value of the deal with free and perfect control over U corresponds to the

highest point of the closed-loop curve; in other words, it is equal to the maximum

of the values Ciow, Cbase and Chigh- That can be explained by the fact that this time,

the decision-maker is free to select the outcome of U he prefers, as well as the

best alternative under those conditions.

• The value of the deal with no control over U corresponds once again to the certain

equivalent of the open-loop curve, or more explicitly to the certain equivalent of

A as computed during the evaluation phase.

30

Page 44: Value of Hedging

Conclusion of the Appraisal Phase

By the end of the appraisal phase, the decision-maker has clarity on the following issues:

• He has identified the course of action which is the best given his current

preferences, the alternatives that are available to him and his current beliefs.

• He has identified the variables which may cause him to modify his decision if

they were to change. He also knows for which revised values of those variables

his choice should change, and how large of an impact such an event would have

on his certain equivalent.

• He knows how much he should be willing to pay for information on each one of

the uncertainties involved in the decision situation, and how much he should be

willing to pay for the ability to exert control over them.

If there exists an information gathering scheme whose cost would be inferior to the value

of information it would provide to the decision-maker, then it should be pursued. The

first three steps of the decision analysis process would then be repeated with the help of

the additional information, iteratively, until it eventually becomes sensible to stop the

analysis and act. In Ronald A. Howard's words [Howard, R. A., 1988]:

At some point, the appraisal step will show that the recommended alternative is

so right for the decision-maker that there is no point in continuing the analysis

any further.

31

Page 45: Value of Hedging

5. Hedging in the Financial Literature

In this part of the dissertation, I will provide a succinct account of the views on hedging

which are most commonly expressed in the financial literature. We will first examine

conventional definitions of hedging, before moving on to an exposition of the key points

of the two prevalent normative theories on hedging - the family of mean-variance

approaches, and the family of utility-based approaches.

I will not, however, review the descriptive literature on hedging. This is not for lack of

research on the subject; indeed, a large body of literature studies questions such as the

extent to which hedging is used by corporations [Guay, W. R., and Kothari, S. P., 2003]

or the degree to which corporate hedging is effective [Nance, D. R., 1993, Smith, C. W.,

and Smithson, C. W., 1993]. But this dissertation exclusively focuses on normative

perspectives, and on issues which are almost entirely disconnected from the descriptive

research.

32

Page 46: Value of Hedging

a) Traditional Definitions of Hedging

In much of the financial literature, "hedging" refers to the use of financial derivatives

such as futures and forwards in order to mitigate the risk that exists in another investment.

The following definition by Kandice H. Kahl [Kahl, K. H., 1983] illustrates that view:

The traditional literature on commodity futures markets defined a hedge as a

futures market position which is equal but opposite to the individual's cash

market position.

The fact that trading derivatives and hedging have become synonyms for many in the

financial community has to do with the long common history that those two ideas share.

It is indeed with the inception of commodity futures that the concept of hedging first

emerged: in late 17th century Japan, a futures market in rice was developed at Dojima,

near Osaka, to help suppliers protect themselves against the risks imposed by nature

(poor weather) or by man (war and pillage). It was the first recorded instance in which

such a market was created. In the U.S., derivatives trading also started with commodity

futures, with the Chicago Board of Trade, which had been created in 1848, allowing

investors to trade wheat, pork belly and copper futures as early as in the 1860s.

That history probably explains, at least in part, why there has been so much interest in

hedging in a field such as agricultural economics, and more importantly why in academic

circles the term has often been understood to mean the use of forwards or futures. But

more recently, a more inclusive definition of hedging began to surface: in the financial

literature of the last two decades, more and more frequently, hedging has referred to an

activity which helps reduce or cancel out the risk imposed by another investment.

Shehzad L. Mian, for example, proposes the following definition [Mian, S. L., 1996]:

Corporations are exposed to uncertainties regarding a variety of prices. Hedging

refers to activities undertaken by the firm in order to mitigate the impact of these

uncertainties on the value of the firm.

In that broader definition, the reference to derivatives was progressively relegated to the

role of mere example. For instance, Deana R. Nance and al. observe that there is more to

hedging than the use of financial derivatives, and they make an explicit distinction

between "off-balance-sheet hedging", in other words the use of those derivatives, and

33

Page 47: Value of Hedging

"on-balance-sheet hedging" [Nance, D. R., Smith, C. W., and Smithson, C. W., 1993],

which involves the use of more standard investment mechanisms with the intention of

reducing risk:

Corporate hedging refers to the use of off-balance-sheet instruments - forwards,

futures, swaps, and options - to reduce the volatility of firm value.

Hence, if the value of an American manufacturing firm that faces competition in

its U.S. markets from foreign manufacturers is inversely related to the value of

the dollar, it could employ off-balance-sheet instruments to hedge that exposure.

This exchange rate-induced volatility can be hedged by (1) selling a forward

contract on the foreign currency, (2) selling foreign exchange futures on the

foreign currency, (3) entering into a currency swap in which it receives cash

flows in dollars and pays cash flows in the foreign currency, (4) buying a put

option on the foreign currency, or (5) writing a call option on the foreign

currency. Alternatively, the firm could hedge through an on-balance-sheet

strategy; it might relocate production facilities abroad or fund itself in the

foreign currency.

It should be noted that in spite of the rising popularity of that broader definition of

hedging as an activity which helps reduce the risk of an investment, even beyond

academic circles, many technical papers on the subject still focus exclusively on the

pricing of derivatives. But the definition of hedging we will present and defend in this

dissertation has more in common with the more inclusive of the two definitions.

34

Page 48: Value of Hedging

b) Mean- Variances Approaches

In the 1950s, Harry M. Markowitz developed the first theory on portfolio allocation in

which there was an explicit treatment of risk [Markowitz, H. M., 1952 and 1959]. The

theory taught investors how to identify optimal mean-variance portfolios - portfolios in

which no added diversification could lower the portfolio's risk for a given expected

return, and in which no gain in expected return could be achieved without simultaneously

consenting to an increase in the risk of the portfolio.

Markowitz' work, which earned him the Nobel Prize in Economics in 1990, has had a

profound and lasting influence on financial mathematics. Portfolios which offer the

highest expected return for each level of risk are still called Markowitz efficient

portfolios, and at a philosophical level, much of financial theory remains grounded on the

premise that investors should make trade-offs between a given reward level, as measured

by the mean return of the portfolio, and a given risk level, as captured by the variance of

the portfolio.

It is thus no surprise that mean-variance thinking gave rise to a normative theory of

hedging, and a popular one at that. In what is perhaps its most basic and most radical

form, the method recommends that the investor completely eliminate the variance in his

investment by taking an equal and opposite position in the futures market [Luenberger, D.

G., 1997]; if it is infeasible in practice, for example because there exists no future

contract for the asset whose value needs to be hedged, the investor should identify a

future contract related to a different commodity, but such that the price of the future

contract is probabilistically relevant to that of the asset that requires hedging. The

investor can then compute the number of future contracts he should buy in order to

minimize the variance of the resulting portfolio [Brown, S. L., 1985; Luenberger, D. G.,

1997]. For that reason, the approach is often called "minimum-variance hedge".

I will now illustrate the minimum-variance approach through a simple example, which is

loosely based on one discussed by David G. Luenberger [1997]. A U.S. firm will receive

100,000 euros in a month; they decide to hedge the value of that contract, in U.S. dollars,

by trading future contracts on the Japanese yen: more specifically, the firm will enter an

35

Page 49: Value of Hedging

agreement now to sell h yens in a month at an exchange rate of 0.88 dollar for 100 yen.

The current exchange rate between U.S. dollars and euros is 1.34 dollars for every euro:

$/€ = 1.21

0.3

$/€ = 1.34 O

0.4

$/€ = 1.42

0.3

$/100¥ = 0.82

0.7

$/100¥ = 0.88

0.2

$/100¥ = 0.94

0.1

$/100¥ = 0.82

o

0.3

$/100¥ = 0.88

0.4

$/100¥ = 0.94

0.3

$/100¥ = 0.82

<y

o.i

$/100¥ = 0.88

0.2

$/100¥ = 0.94

0.7

$121,000 /i(0.88-0.82)

$121,000 A(0.88-0.88)

$121,000 /i(0.88-0.94)

$134,000 A(0.88-0.82)

$134,000 /i(0.88-0.88)

$134,000 6(0.88-0.94)

$142,000 /i(0.88-0.82)

$142,000 £(0.88-0.88)

$142,000 /»(0.88-0.94)

Figure 1.10 - Minimum-variance hedging for foreign currency

The above tree shows the possible evolution of exchange rates over the coming month, as

well as the profits the company would be making from the euro contract and the yen

contract under different scenarios as a function of h. Minimizing the variance of the

36

Page 50: Value of Hedging

entire portfolio, we obtain h = -8,750,000 as the optimal value of h. But the answer

raises some fundamental questions: for example, why would the solution not depend on

the decision-maker's risk attitude? If we believe that some investors are more risk-averse

than others, why would they all choose the exact same hedging strategy?

In order to remedy to that weakness of the minimum-variance method, some authors from

the financial literature advocate replacing as the purpose of hedging the minimization of

variance by the optimization of an objective function which encodes the investor's mean-

variance trade-offs [Heifner, R. G., 1972 and 1973; Kahl, K. H., 1983; Frechette, D. L.,

2000]. For example, Kandice H. Kahl elects to optimize the following function, where n

designates profit:

<7T | &> - A. V<7l|&)

In that function, A. is a positive number which captures the risk-aversion of the investor.

As X increases, the influence of the variance of the portfolio on the investor's decision's

will also increase - in other words, larger values of X correspond to more risk-averse

investors.

While the use of such objective functions allows the investor to take into account his

personal risk attitude as he makes hedging decisions, it can be argued that such an

approach is still not entirely satisfactory. In reality, it can sometimes be misleading to

evaluate an investment opportunity based solely on the first two moments of its

probability distribution over profits.

For instance, let us consider the situation of a risk-averse investor who owns a portfolio

with uncertain returns, and who is given the chance to receive for free another financial

instrument which, if added to his present investments, would leave both the mean and

variance unchanged, but would also significantly improve the third central moment of his

profits - by shifting the downside and the upside of the distribution to the right, for

example, and the central region of the distribution to the left. Why would a risk-averse

investor necessarily dismiss such an investment opportunity as uninteresting? Would he

not appreciate this opportunity to reduce the magnitude of the potential downside,

without altering the mean or variance of his investment?

37

Page 51: Value of Hedging

We will come back to that criticism of mean-variance methods much later in the

dissertation: we will show that moments of order three and above can be of considerable

importance, and we will even be able to quantify their weight in the investor's hedging

decisions.

38

Page 52: Value of Hedging

c) Utility-Based Approaches

In the late 1980s, interest in another family of normative theories for the study of hedging

started to surface in the financial literature. Those new approaches, which I will call

utility-based approaches, were originally inspired by a paper written by Stewart D.

Hodges and Anthony Neuberger [1989], in which they adapted the expected utility

framework from decision theory to options pricing: essentially, Stewart D. Hodges and

Anthony Neuberger were computing the price at which the investor would be indifferent

between having a given option in his portfolio and not having it.

The theory, which was soon extended to a larger class of transactional cost structures

than the one it was originally developed for [Davis, M. H. A., Panas, V. G., and

Zariphopoulou, T., 1993], became especially popular for the pricing of derivatives in

what are called "incomplete markets" in the financial literature. In such markets, the cash

flows which an option yields cannot always be replicated by a suitable combination of

other assets in the market; therefore, the traditional financial paradigms of portfolio

replication and risk-neutral valuation are of little help to an investor who is trying to put a

price tag on an option, and that explains the popularity of utility-based approaches to

solve such problems [Cvitanic, J., Schachermayer, W., and Wang, H., 2001; Delbaen, F.,

Grandits, P., Rheinlander, T., Samperi, D., Schweizer, M., and Strieker, C , 2002;

Henderson, V., 2002; Musiela, M , and Zariphopoulou, T., 2004]. For the same reasons,

utility-based approaches have also been used recently to price highly sophisticated assets

such as volatility derivatives [Friz, P., and Gatheral, J., 2005; Carr, P., Geman, H., Madan,

D., and Yor, M., 2005; Grasselli, M. R., and Hurd, T. R., 2007].

In most of those papers, the utility function which is used is the exponential form which

we already discussed in our review of decision analysis concepts; Matheus R. Grasselli

and Thomas R. Hurd for example suggest [Grasselli, M. R., and Hurd, T. R., 2007]:

U(x) = -e - y x

Power utility functions have also drawn some interest from the financial community

[Henderson, V., 2002], but their use has been more sporadic:

39

Page 53: Value of Hedging

x1_R

U(x) = ,whereR>0 1-R

Of all types of power utility functions, the quadratic form is one of the most commonly

encountered in the literature [Luenberger, D. G., 1997]. However, the use of quadratic

utility functions should probably be regarded as a bridge between mean-variance and

utility-based approaches rather than as a utility-based approach stricto sensu, since

maximizing expected utility then becomes equivalent to optimizing a function which only

depends on the mean and variance of the profit distribution. The fact that quadratic-

utility-function maximizers seldom use the vocabulary of indifference pricing is further

proof that their thinking is more characteristic of the mean-variance school of thought

rather than its utility-based counterpart.

The normative theory of hedging which I will present and defend in this dissertation is

much closer in its philosophy to the views developed by the proponents of utility-based

approaches. This is not surprising if we consider the fact that the financial community's

utility-based approaches to hedging are built on a few principles which are similar to

those of decision analysis, such as indifference pricing.

40

Page 54: Value of Hedging

Chapter 2 - Definition & Valuation of Hedging

"We think only through the medium of words; languages are true

analytical methods. Algebra, which is adapted to its purpose in every

species of expression, in the most simple, most exact, and best manner

possible, is at the same time a language and an analytical method. The

art of reasoning is nothing more than a language well-arranged. "

Antoine-Laurent de Lavoisier (1743-1794),

Traite Elementaire de Chimie

Antoine-Laurent de Lavoisier's words should remind us that employing a well-

constructed language is indispensable if we want to think clearly about an issue. Before

we can make any serious attempt at ascribing a monetary value to hedging, it is thus

imperative that we define it in the most precise terms - there is little point in trying to

build a solid edifice on a weak foundation.

Formulating a clear definition of hedging will be our first ambition in this chapter. We

will then see that with that definition in place, it becomes easy and natural to ascribe a

monetary value to hedging.

41

Page 55: Value of Hedging

1. Definition of Hedging

As noted in the previous chapter, hedging is now commonly understood to refer to an

investment "that is taken out specifically to reduce or cancel out the risk in another

investment" [Wikipedia]. Such a definition, unfortunately, is not entirely clear, because it

leaves one important question unanswered - what do we mean by "risk"? Is the word

used as shorthand for "variance", as suggested by supporters of the mean-variance family

of normative theories on hedging?

As we seek to define hedging, we should avoid relying on terms which would only add to

our interlocutor's confusion, such as "risk". In fact, we will abandon the idea of a risk

reduction characterization of hedging altogether, to focus instead on the effect hedging

produces on the decision-maker's preferences with respect to a specific deal: we will

speak of hedging if the decision-maker finds a deal he does not own more attractive when

he values it with his current portfolio in mind than when he values it without considering

his existing portfolio; more formally:

Definition 2.1 - Hedging

Suppose that the decision-maker has wealth w and owns an unresolved portfolio of deals

X; suppose also that he is considering purchasing a deal Y.

We will say that Y provides hedging with respect to X given w if B~(Y | w, X) is greater

than (Y | w + ~(X | w)). In other words, if we compare purchasing deal Y in the

following two states:

• The decision-maker owns portfolio X and wealth w (State 1),

• The decision-maker owns wealth w + S~(X | w), but does not own X (State 2),

then purchasing Y is regarded as more valuable by the decision-maker in the first state

than in the second.

Conversely, we will say that Y provides negative hedging with respect to X given w if B~(Y | w, X) is less than B~(Y | w + S~(X | w».

42

Page 56: Value of Hedging

We are comparing the decision-maker's PIBP for Y under two different sets of

circumstances. Interestingly, those two states of the world, (1) and (2), are so defined that

the decision-maker is just indifferent between them; state (2) is nothing else than state (1),

following the sale of portfolio X for the exact price at which the decision-maker was

indifferent to parting with it, S~(X | w). And yet, nothing guarantees that the decision­

maker would also be indifferent between adding Y to his portfolio in state 1, and adding

Y to his portfolio in state 2.

It is the possible difference in the decision-maker's valuation of Y, in the presence or

absence of X but all else being equal, which determines whether there is hedging or not.

The decision-maker is just indifferent between

State 1 and State 2...

State 2

}S~<X|w>

... but would he prefer to add Y to his portfolio in State 1 or in State 2?

Figure III - Hedging as the comparison of two PIBPs

43

Page 57: Value of Hedging

Example 2.1:

A decision-maker, who states that he is comfortable following the delta property

within the [-$20,000, $20,000] range and who has a risk tolerance of $10,000,

already owns deal X and is thinking of acquiring deal Y as shown below:

•o

0.6

S2

$1,000 -$100

$0 $300

S~<X I 0) = $388.08 B~<Y | 0> = $138.07

Figure II. 2 - Hedging with complete relevance between X and Y

Then: B~<Y | 0) =

But: B~<Y | X)

= $138.07

= $147.61

> B~<Y | 0)

In this example, by our definition, Y does provide hedging with respect to X

given w.

It is reassuring that such a conclusion is not at odds with our intuition - if we had

had nothing to guide us but the vague notion that hedging qualifies an investment

which reduces the risk of another investment, then we would also have declared

that Y provides hedging with respect to X. Indeed, adding Y to X reduces the

magnitude of the possible downside in the decision-maker's prospects, from $0 to

44

Page 58: Value of Hedging

$300, at the cost of a slight reduction in the magnitude of the possible upside,

from $1,000 to $900.

Furthermore, this example shows that in situations of hedging, not only do we

have the inequality B~(Y | w, X) > B~(Y | w + S~(X | w)>, but it sometimes even

turns out that B~(Y | w, X) > (Y | &): a risk-averse decision-maker can thus be

willing to pay more for a deal Y than a risk-neutral decision-maker would pay for

it, even if they both agree on the probabilities and magnitudes of the prospects,

and even if they both own the exact same portfolio X and the same wealth w.

Here:

B~(Y|w,X> =$147.61

><Y|&)(=$140). J

Example 2.2:

Hedging does not only arise in situations in which the monetary prospects of the

deals under consideration are determined by the exact same set of uncertainties, as

in Example 2.1. In order to demonstrate it, let us consider a decision-maker who

has the exact same u-curve as in our first example, and owns the same unresolved

deal X; this time, he is contemplating acquiring a different deal Y, as described by

the next figure.

We now have:

B~(Y | 0> = $82.02

But the PIBP for Y when we take the existing portfolio X into account is larger:

B~(Y | X) = $87.71

> B~(Y | 0 )

45

Page 59: Value of Hedging

Si

0.4

-0

0.6

s2

$1,000

$0

S'l

0.9

•o

•o

0.1

s'2

S'l

0.3

0.7

~sV

-$100

$300

-$100

$300

b~<X | 0 ) = $388.08 B~(Y | 0> = $82.02

Figure II. 3 - Hedging with partial relevance between Xand Y

In spite of the fact that the monetary prospects of X and Y are determined by

different uncertainties, Y provides hedging with respect to X given w. Also, just

as in our first example, that conclusion matches our intuition's predictions, since

Y is structured in such a way that it is more likely than not to compensate for

some of the potential losses imposed by X. 3

46

Page 60: Value of Hedging

To the first time reader of our definition of hedging, it may seem puzzling that we chose

to define it by comparing the decision-maker's PIBPs for Y in states 1 and 2:

• The decision-maker owns portfolio X and wealth w (State 1),

• The decision-maker owns wealth w + S~(X | w), but does not own X (State 2),

instead of comparing the decision-maker's PIBPs for Y in the following states 1 and 2':

• The decision-maker owns portfolio X and wealth w (State 1),

• The decision-maker owns wealth w +J^P^i*w7, but does not own X (State 2').

In more formal terms, why compare B~(Y | w, X) to B~(Y | w + S~(X | w)), instead of

comparing it to B~(Y | w)? Would the latter not be more convenient, and yet yield the

exact same result?

Sadly, problems with that second possible definition of hedging would arise for u-curves

which do not satisfy the delta property. For such u-curves, B~(Y | w + S~(X | w)> is not

necessarily equal to B~(Y | w). The discrepancy has to do with a phenomenon which, in

decision analysis, has often been called the "wealth effect": for a risk-averse individual,

an increase in wealth tends to cause an increase in their PIBP for an uncertain deal.

With that in mind, let us come back to the comparison between states 1 and 2' as a

possible definition of hedging. Consider an existing portfolio X which is deterministic

and offers a sure profit equal to x: one might conclude from applying that erroneous

definition of hedging that since the decision-maker's PIBPs for Y in states 1 and 2' are

different, Y provides hedging or negative hedging with respect to X given w. And yet, it

seems absurd to think that one can hedge a portfolio which involves no uncertainty.

The next example demonstrates the same point numerically.

47

Page 61: Value of Hedging

Example 2.3:

A decision-maker owns $1,000 as his initial wealth, as well as an unresolved deal

X which has an assured outcome, equal to $1,000. Let us suppose that the

decision-maker can choose to purchase deal Y from Example 2.1. Finally, we will

suppose that his u-curve is encoded by u(x) = ln(w + x), where w denotes his

initial wealth - so that the decision-maker does not follow the delta property for

the range of prospects under consideration. Then:

f B~(Y | w,X) = $130.16

L B~(Y | w> = $119.93

The two PIBPs for Y are different, so if we were to define hedging based on a

comparison of B~(Y | w, X) and B~(Y | w) we would then infer that there is

hedging in this example. Yet, it seems preposterous to argue that Y compensates

for any of X's risk.

We can explain that the difference between B~(Y | w, X) and B~(Y | w) with wealth

effects. In our example, the potential negative consequence of acquiring Y,

namely, the possibility of losing $100, is not as much of a concern to a decision­

maker who has an initial wealth of $2,000 (i.e., in our example, owns w = $1,000

as well as deal X) as it is for a decision-maker who simply has an initial wealth of

$1,000.

It should be noted, however, that applying the correct definition of hedging which

we proposed earlier in this chapter would lead to the intuitively acceptable

conclusion that there is no hedging provided by Y with respect to X:

f B~(Y | w,X) = $130.16

I B~(Y|w + s~(X | w» = $130.16.3

48

Page 62: Value of Hedging

2. Definition of the Value of Hedging

Now that we have a better understanding of what constitutes hedging, we are ready to

move on to the question of how to ascribe a monetary value to it. There are three reasons

why we should be keen on defining a value of hedging:

• The value of hedging concept would add to our understanding of the possible

merits of a deal which the decision-maker is considering acquiring -

The value of hedging would help us distinguish between what we might call the

intrinsic value of the deal, as measured by the decision-maker's PIBP for it

without taking his existing portfolio into account, and the merits of the deal in

terms of the hedging it provides, as measured by the value of hedging. We will

come back to that point in greater detail later, but in the meantime, here is an

example to ponder: if the PIBP for Y without taking the existing portfolio into

account is equal to zero, but Y is found out to provide a positive value of hedging

with respect to the existing portfolio, the notion of value of hedging will have

helped the decision-maker understand why Y should be of any interest to him.

• The value of hedging would also allow us to compare several deals based on how

well or how poorly they complement the existing portfolio -

Having a common monetary scale on which we can measure the hedging that

each of those deals provides enables us to sort them, from the best complement of

the portfolio to the worst.

• Using such an ordered list, we can then attempt to identify some common

characteristics that the best hedges might share -

If we succeed in recognizing such patterns, we can start looking for other deals,

outside of the original list, which would also possess the characteristics we

identified. Some of those deals might prove even more valuable as additions to

the portfolio than any of the acquisitions which we had considered prior to that.

49

Page 63: Value of Hedging

a) The Value of Hedging as a Difference of Two PIBPs

How can we quantify the value that a deal provides through hedging, though? The very

form of Definition 2.1 gives us the answer - since Y is said to provide hedging with

respect to X given w if B~(Y | w, X) is greater than B~(Y | w + S~(X | w», we could simply

define the value of hedging as the difference between those two quantities:

Definition 2.2 — Value of Hedging of an Uncertain Deal Y

We will define the value of hedging provided by Y given w and X, which we will denote

by VoH(Y | w, X), as the difference of two PIBPs:

VoH(Y | w, X) = B~(Y | w, X) - B~(Y | w + S~<X | w» [2.1]

Consequently, Y provides hedging with respect to X given w if and only if VoH(Y | w,

X) > 0, and negative hedging if and only if VoH(Y | w, X) < 0.

Example 2.4:

Coming back to Example 2.1:

VoH(Y | X) = B~(Y | X> - B~(Y | 0>

= $147.61-$138.07

= $9.54.

In this example, the value of hedging appears to be relatively small compared to

the intrinsic value of Y, B~(Y | 0 ) . But it is still substantial enough that a decision­

maker who omits the value of hedging in his valuation of Y might end up

declining to buy the deal even though it was in his interest to do so; this would

arise for instance if the price at which the decision-maker can purchase Y was

$140 . •

50

Page 64: Value of Hedging

As a reminder, B~(Y | w, X) and (Y | w + ~(X | w» can both be computed using

equations involving the decision-maker's u-curve.

To show that, let us first introduce more explicit probabilistic notations: suppose the

decision-maker has wealth w and owns an unresolved portfolio of deals X = {(pi, x ^ i ,

n]} whose outcomes are determined by the set of state variables S. He is considering

purchasing a deal Y = {(qi, yOie[i,m]}, whose prospects are a function of another set of

state variables 5". For convenience, we will denote by q^ the conditional probability that

the decision-maker assigns to s'j given Sj.

Then, B~(Y | w, X) and B~(Y | w + S~(X | w)) are the quantities which satisfy the following

two equations:

f x Pi u(w+xs) = x Pi Z % u ( w + x i + y j - B~<Y Iw' x » i2-2] ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

u(w + S~<X | w» = X Qj u ( w + S~<x I w> + Yj" B~<Y I w + S~(X | w») [2.3] je[l,m]

We can already see that the value of hedging is intimately connected with the decision­

maker's u-curve and, thereby, with his risk attitude. We will come back to this point later

on in order to determine the exact nature of that relationship between hedging and risk

attitude.

51

Page 65: Value of Hedging

b) The Value of Hedging as the PIBP of a Translated Deal

Equation [2.1] may give the misleading impression that the value of hedging provided by

Y with respect to w and X can only defined as the difference between two PIBPs, and

that it is not necessarily possible to express it as the PIBP of just one deal. In reality, this

is quite feasible, and I will show how in this part of the dissertation. This will provide

another perspective on the value of hedging concept, which will prove especially useful

in deriving some of the results we will encounter later in this chapter of the dissertation.

So how can we define the value of hedging as the decision-maker's PIBP for one deal?

All we need to do is define a deal Y' by subtracting ~(Y | w + ~(X | w» from all

prospects of Y; Y' = {(qis y'i)ie[i,m]} = {(qit y; - B~<Y | w + S~(X | w»)iG[1,m]}. Then it

turns out that the value of hedging that Y provides with respect to w and X is equal to the

decision-maker's PIBP for Y':

B~/ VoH(Y | w, X) = B~(Y' | w, X) [2.4]

Indifference

Figure II.4 — An equivalent definition of the value of hedging

52

Page 66: Value of Hedging

To use a mathematical metaphor, we could say that the value of hedging provided by Y is

equal to the PIBP for a deal which is the result of translating Y by an amount -B~(Y | w +

S~<X|w».

[2.4] can also be written in terms of u-values as:

£ PiUCw + x,) i*,n] [2A,}

= S Pi Z % u ( w + x i + y > - B ~ < Y i w + s~<x i w » - V o H ( Y i w ' x ) ) ie[l,n] je[l,m]

But why are expressions [2.1] and [2.4] equivalent? Why is B~(Y' | w, X) equal to B~(Y |

w, X) - B~(Y | w + S~(X | w»? The equality follows from a much more general result:

Lemma 2.1 — PIBP for a Deal Translated by an Amount S

Let us consider a decision-maker with wealth w and an existing portfolio of unresolved

deals X. For any deal Z and any amount 8 (positive or negative), his PIBP for a deal Z' in

which all prospects of Z were augmented by the same amount 8 is equal to his PIBP for

Z, augmented by 8:

B~(Z' | w, X) = B~(Z | w, X) + 8

The result holds whether the decision-maker's u-curve satisfies the delta property or not.

Proof:

We start by writing the definition of the decision-maker's PIBP for Z', denoting by

(pOiefi, n] the probability distribution over the prospects of the existing portfolio X,

and by (rk|i)ke[i, S] the conditional probability distribution over the prospects of Z'

given those of X:

X p,u(w + X i )= Z P. Z ^uCw + X i + z ' k - ^ Z ' l w ) ) ie[l,n] ie[l,n] ke[l,s]

= Z P. Z rk|lu(w + xi + (zk+S)-B~<Z' |w» ie[l,n] ke[l,s]

53

Page 67: Value of Hedging

We also have, this time by definition of the PIBP for Z:

2 Piu(w + X i)= X Pi Z rk|iu(w+xi + z k- B ~< z l w » ie[l,n] ie[l,n] ke[l,s]

Comparing the last two equations, we can conclude that B~(Z' | w, X) = B~(Z | w, X) +

8.D

If we then apply this lemma to the particular case of deals Y and Y' as defined earlier,

with 8 = - B~<Y | w + S~<X | w», we can conclude that [2.1] and [2.4] are indeed

equivalent. [2.4] occasionally turns out to be more convenient to use as a definition of

VoH(Y | w, X) than [2.1]. In fact, many of the proofs in this dissertation will be based on

the former rather than the latter.

Example 2.5:

We will reuse Example 2.2 in order to illustrate our alternative definition of the

value of hedging as the PIBP for just one deal through a practical situation.

As a reminder, we previously computed B~(Y | 0) to be equal to $82.02. We first

transform deal Y into Y' by translating it by - B~(Y | 0): we subtract $82.02 from

all of its prospects, and we obtain the deal which is represented in the next figure.

The PIBP for this new deal Y' given X is equal to:

B~(Y' | X) = $5.69

Finally, let us compare that PIBP to the value of hedging for Y. We observe that

the two quantities are equal, as expected:

VoH(Y | X) = B~(Y | X) - B~<Y | 0)

= $87.71-$82.02

= $5.69. D

54

Page 68: Value of Hedging

Si

0.4

-0

0.6

S2

$1,000

$0

-0

•o

S'l

0.9

)

0.1

S'2

S'l

0.3

0.7

-$182.02

$217.98

-$182.02

$217.98

~<X | 0 ) = $388.08

Figure II. 5- Hedging with partial relevance between Xand Y

55

Page 69: Value of Hedging

3. Influence Diagram Representation

I have already mentioned in the first chapter that influence diagrams are among the most

effective communication tools available to a decision analyst, and that it is even possible

to encode probabilities and value measures into them in order to solve them and identify

the best course of action and its associated certain equivalent.

Those features of influence diagrams are the reason I would now like to present an

influence diagram representation of the value of hedging computation. This will help

consolidate our understanding of hedging as defined in this dissertation, and we will see

that the value of hedging can be computed by means of an influence diagram evaluation.

More specifically, the value of hedging can be computed by evaluating and comparing

the two influence diagrams shown below:

Influence Diagram 1 Influence Diagram 2

Figure II. 6 - Using influence diagrams to compute the value of hedging

In both diagrams, the decision-maker would like to decide whether he should buy deal Y

or not, given its cost. The difference between the two situations lies in the fact that in the

first, the decision-maker also owns initial wealth w and an uncertain portfolio X, whereas

in the second, he owns initial wealth w + S~(X | w), but does not own X.

56

Page 70: Value of Hedging

The value of hedging can then be computed using the following algorithm:

Step 1: Adjust the value of the node "Cost of Y" in Influence Diagram 1 until the

decision-maker is indifferent between the two alternatives available at the

decision node, i.e. buying Y and not buying Y. Once that is achieved, we

know that the value of the node "Cost ofY" is exactly ~(Y | w, X).

Step 2: Similarly, adjust the value of the node "Cost ofY" in Influence Diagram 2

until the decision-maker is indifferent between buying Y and not buying Y

in that second diagram as well. Once that is achieved, we know that the

value of the node "Cost ofY" is exactly B~<Y | w + S~<X | w».

Step 3: The value of hedging is equal to the difference between the results

obtained at the end of steps 1 and 2 of the algorithm:

VoH(Y | w, X) = B~<Y | w, X) - B~(Y | w + S~(X | w».

In practice, a binary search would allow for a fast and efficient evaluation of B~(Y | w, X)

and B~(Y | w + S~(X | w)) in steps 1 and 2. For example, here is a detailed view of a

possible evaluation procedure for step 1, for a chosen level of accuracy e:

Step 1-a: Solve Influence Diagram 1 when "Cost of Y" is set to the highest dollar

prospect achievable in deal Y, which we will call ymax. We start from there

because ymax constitutes a natural upper bound on the decision-maker's

PIBPforY.

If the difference between the certain equivalents of the "Buy Y" and the

"Do Not Buy Y" alternatives is less than the desired level of accuracy e,

then return ymax as the approximate value of B~(Y | w, X). Otherwise,

proceed to Step 1-b.

57

Page 71: Value of Hedging

Step 1-b: Solve Influence Diagram 1 when "Cost of Y" is set to the lowest dollar

prospect achievable in deal Y, which we will call ymin. We know that ymin

constitutes a lower bound on the decision-maker's PIBP for Y.

If the difference between the certain equivalents of the "Buy Y" and the

"Do Not Buy Y" alternatives is less than 8, then return ym;n as the

approximate value of B~(Y | w, X). Otherwise, create two variables A and

B and initialize them with values ymjn and ymax respectively, and proceed

to Step 1-c.

Step 1-c: Solve Influence Diagram 1 again when "Cost ofY" is set to C = lA (A+B).

If the difference between the certain equivalents of the "Buy Y" and the

"Do Not Buy Y" alternatives is less than s in that case, then return C as the

approximate value of B~(Y | w, X).

Otherwise, if the best decision is to "Buy Y", it implies that we need to

increase the cost of Y for the decision-maker to be indifferent between

buying it or not: B~(Y | w, X) is thus larger than C. We should then set A to

C, keep B as is, and go back to Step 1-c with those new values of A and B.

In the last possible case, if the best decision is to "Not Buy Y", we can

infer from it that B~(Y | w, X) is less than C; we should then keep A as is,

set B to C, and go on to Step 1-c again with those new values of A and B.

58

Page 72: Value of Hedging

4. Basic Properties of the Value of Hedging

a) Hedging in the Risk-neutral Case

We observed during our review of the minimum-variance approach that one of the most

common criticisms against the theory is the fact that it leaves us with no possibility to

take into account the decision-maker's risk attitude - the solution we would arrive at

would invariably be the same, irrespective of how risk-averse the decision-maker is.

The definition of hedging we have formulated and studied does not suffer from that flaw.

In fact, the value of hedging for a deal depends upon two elements of the decision basis:

• the decision-maker's information, as encoded for instance in the probabilities he

assigns to the prospects of all the deals involved in his decision situation,

• and the decision-maker's preferences, since his risk preference will have a direct

effect on the calculation of PfflPs B~<Y | w, X) and B~<Y | w + S~<X | w», which

are the two quantities we need to compute in order to form the value of hedging.

An interesting risk preference case to examine is that of a decision-maker who is risk-

neutral within the range of prospects involved: if we consider Example 2.1, for instance,

we will realize that the decision-maker would ascribe the same value to deal Y, equal to

the e-value of its prospects ($140), irrespective of whether he has taken his existing

portfolio X into account or not. Hence, the value of hedging will be equal to zero, a

conclusion which appears quite sensible given that a risk-neutral decision-maker will not

see any value in the fact that Y compensates for some of the potential downside imposed

byX.

The result actually turns out to be true in general - to a risk-neutral decision-maker,

hedging considerations are simply irrelevant:

59

Page 73: Value of Hedging

Property 2.1 - Value of Hedging and Risk-neutrality

VoH(Y | w, X) = 0 for a risk-neutral decision-maker, no matter what deals X, Y and

wealth w are.

Proof:

Let us start from equation [2.4], for the particular case of a risk-neutral u-curve:

VoH(Y | w, X) = B~(Y' | w, X)

= <Y'|&>

= <Y-B~(Y|w + s~<X|w»|&>

= <Y-(Y|&) |&)

= <Y | &> - «Y | &> | &>

= <Y|&>-<Y|&>

= 0. D

60

Page 74: Value of Hedging

b) Existence of Negative Hedging

I will continue this overview of some of the elementary properties of hedging with an

important reminder - our definition of hedging allows for the existence of situations in

which the value of hedging is negative. Just as it can be valuable for some deals to

incorporate them into our portfolio in order to mitigate some of its risk, for other deals it

can be detrimental to acquire them because they would only add to the risk.

Property 2.2- Sign of the Value of Hedging

It is important to note that VoH(Y | w, X) can in some cases be negative.

Example 2.6:

Let us suppose that the decision-maker who already owns deal X (as in Example

2.1) needs to decide whether he should buy a second copy of the very same deal.

The PIBP for this new deal, if we were to omit the existence of the first deal,

would be $388.08. If we do take it into account, then the PIBP is equal to $364.62.

It implies that the value of hedging provided by the second copy of X is negative:

it is equal to -$23.46.

This should come as no surprise: when adding a second deal X to the current

portfolio, the monetary prospects involved in both deals reveal a bias in the same

direction; the best outcome occurs for si for both the deal that is already owned,

and the one that the decision-maker is contemplating acquiring. Therefore, by

adding the second copy of deal X to the one he already possesses, our risk-averse

decision-maker would be increasing his exposure to risk, instead of neutralizing

some of it. U

61

Page 75: Value of Hedging

c) Sign and Monotonicity of the Value of Hedging in the Risk-Averse Case

Property 2.1 drew our attention to the fact that hedging considerations can never be of

any use to a risk-neutral decision-maker, because the value of hedging is always equal to

zero for such a choice of u-curve. It is only for other types of risk attitude that the value

of hedging can take on non-zero values.

This insight can lead us to investigate a few related and interesting questions. For

simplicity, we will assume that the decision-maker whose situation we are discussing is

risk-averse and follows the delta property over the entire range of prospects involved,

although the conclusions we will reach can be extended beyond the delta case. A valid u-

curve for such a decision-maker is u(x) = 1 - e"yx. Then:

• For two given investment opportunities X and Y, does the value of hedging

provided by Y with respect to X retain the same sign for all possible values of the

risk-aversion coefficient y? In other words, does the value of hedging have the

same sign for all such decision-makers, irrespective of the degree to which they

are risk-averse?

• Is the value of hedging provided by Y a monotonic function of y?

Even in as simple a situation as the delta case, the answer to both questions is no. Here is

a simple example which will help us convince ourselves of it.

62

Page 76: Value of Hedging

Example 2.7:

A decision-maker wishes to follow the delta property over the [-$1,000,000;

$1,000,000] range. He owns some deal X, and is considering acquiring Y; both

are shown on the next figure:

Sl

•o

0.3

S2

0.4

S3

0.3

$100,000

$40,000

-$20,000

$18,000

-$12,000

-$2,000

Figure II. 7 -An example for which VoH(Y \ w, X) is not monotonic in y

What we will do here is plot VoH(Y | w, X) for different values of y. The results

of that sensitivity analysis are displayed below:

0.00001 0.0001 0.001 0.01 0.1

y (for Deals Expressed in $ Thousand)

Figure II. 8 - Sensitivity of VoH(Y \w,X)toy

63

Page 77: Value of Hedging

The chart shows unequivocally that VoH(Y | w, X) does not keep a constant sign

in the risk-averse range, and that it is not monotonic either.

How can that be explained? We will see in chapter IV that the value of hedging

essentially corresponds to the value which can be derived from reengineering the

moments of the original portfolio X. More explicitly, when choosing to add a deal

Y to a portfolio X, a decision-maker will first and foremost be interested in

augmenting the mean of X, secondly in reducing its variance, and thirdly in

enhancing its third moment.

The reason for the peculiar change of sign in VoH(Y | w, X) we can observe in

the present example is that adding Y to the decision-maker's portfolio has

contradicting effects on its moments; starting with the low-order moments, Y has

the undesirable effect of increasing the variance, but it also has the advantage of

increasing the value of the third central moment. For some values of y the positive

effects will outweigh the negative, so that overall Y will provide positive hedging

with respect to X, while for other values of y the negative effects will outweigh

the positive. H

64

Page 78: Value of Hedging

d) Value of Hedging for Two Deals Which Differ by a Constant

Another important feature of the value of hedging is the fact that if we look at two deals

whose prospects are determined by the same set of uncertainties but differ by a constant,

then we are assured that the two deals provide the exact same value of hedging.

The result is intuitive: after all, two such deals should offer the same benefits or dangers

from a hedging perspective, since the constant by which they differ can neither mitigate

nor add to the risk of the existing portfolio. What is perhaps most surprising about this

insight is the fact that it holds for any possible u-curve, and not just for those which

satisfy the delta property.

Theorem 2.1 — Hedging Provided by Two Deals Which Only Differ by a Constant

Suppose that the decision-maker is considering purchasing a deal Y = {(q;, yi)i<=[i, m]}

whose prospects are fully determined by a set of uncertainties 5', or a deal Z = {(q;, Zi)je[i>

m]} whose prospects are also fully determined by S'.

Furthermore, suppose that the prospects of Y and Z only differ by a constant 8: Zj = yj + 5

for all values of i. Then,

VoH(Z | w, X) = VoH(Y | w, X)

Proof:

By virtue of [2.4], if we define deal Y' by subtracting B~(Y | w + S~(X | w» from all

prospects of Y: Y' = {(qi, y'i)ie[i,m]} = {(qi, y; - B~<Y | w + S~(X | w»)ie[,,m]}, then:

VoH(Y | w, X) = B~<Y' | w, X)

Similarly, if we define deal Z' by subtracting B~(Z | w + S~(X | w)> from all prospects

of Z: Z' = {(qi, z'i)i6[1,m]} = {(qi, Zi - B~(Z | w + S~<X | w»)je[i,m]}, then:

VoH(Z | w, X) = B~(Z' | w, X)

65

Page 79: Value of Hedging

But:

z'i = Zi - B~(Z | w + S~<X | w»

= (y; + 8) - B~(Z | w + S~(X | w»

= y; + 8 - (B~<Y | w + S~(X | w» + 8) (by virtue of Lemma 2.1)

= yi - B~<Y | w + S~(X | w»

= y'i

It follows that B~(Y' | w, X) = B~<Z' | w, X) and therefore that VoH(Y | w, X) =

VoH(Z | w, X). n

Example 2.8:

Let us go back to Example 2.2; this time, however, we will analyze the situation

from the point of view of a decision-maker whose u-curve is ln(w + x), where w =

$2,000 denotes his present wealth.

We will first compute the value of hedging provided by Y. We have:

B~(Y | w + S~(X | w» = B~(Y | w + $259.82)

= $75.30

But the PIBP for Y when we take portfolio X into account is larger:

B~<Y | w, X) = $97.24

> B~<Y | w + S~<X | w»

Therefore, Y provides hedging with respect to X, of a value equal to:

VoH(Y|w,X) =$21.94

Let us now consider Z, which differs from Y only by a positive constant of $100:

66

Page 80: Value of Hedging

Si

0.4

-0

0.6

S2

$1,000

$0

-0

S'l

0.9

)

0.1

S'l

S'l

0.3 ) 0.7

"sV

$0

$400

$0

$400

S~<X | w) = $259.82 B~(Z | w + S~(X | w» = $175.30

Figure II.9- Hedging provided by a deal which differs from Y by a constant

We repeat the same calculations for Z:

B~<Z | w + S~(X | w» =$175.30

B~(Z|w,X) =$197.24

Therefore:

VoH(Z|w,X) =$21.94

The values of hedging provided by Y and Z are indeed equal. •

67

Page 81: Value of Hedging

e) PIBPfor an Uncertain Deal and Value of Hedging

In some situations, it is helpful to reverse the chain of inference implied by our definition

of the value of hedging - instead of computing PIBPs B~(Y | w, X) and B~<Y | w + S~(X |

w» in order to obtain the value of hedging, we might want to infer the value of B~(Y | w,

X) from the value of the other PIBP and from the value of hedging that Y provides.

Such reasoning can be of practical use if we have access to an approximation of the value

of hedging provided by Y, or to an upper bound on it. This might arise, for example, if

we can easily detect that Y is inferior to another deal Z for hedging purposes, and if we

have already computed the value of hedging provided by Z. That property will also be

useful in the next chapter of this dissertation: we will then see that when the decision­

maker's u-curve satisfies the delta property, an upper bound on the value of hedging can

be computed based on the risk premiums of the current portfolio and of the new deal Y.

Property 2.3 - PIBP for an Uncertain Deal and Value of Hedging

As a direct consequence of Definition 2.2, a convenient relationship links the decision­

maker's PIBP for deal Y to the value of hedging provided by deal Y:

B~<Y | w, X> = B~(Y | w + S~<X | w» + VoH(Y | w, X) [2.5]

In its philosophy [2.5] resembles some of the laws of physics, in which the total energy of

a system is the result of a combination of the effects of some variables which are

inherently related to the system itself, as well as of other variables which capture the

interaction of the system with its environment. In the case of [2.5], we decomposed the

PIBP for a deal Y into the sum of two terms; the first, B~(Y | w + S~(X | w)>, measures the

intrinsic worth of Y, while the second, VoH(Y | w, X), is an interaction term which

captures the reciprocal effects of Y and X on each other.

68

Page 82: Value of Hedging

5. Extension of the Value of Hedging Concept to the Sale of Deals

Ever since we introduced our definitions of hedging and of its value, we have been

focusing on situations in which the decision-maker is contemplating acquiring a new deal

which he could incorporate into his existing portfolio. This might give the impression that

we have neglected to address the symmetric issue, in which he is wondering whether he

should sell a deal he currently owns, bearing in mind what the rest of his portfolio is.

Yet, it seems that hedging should play just as large of a role in selling situations as in

purchasing situations. Let us think of an investor who owns a diversified portfolio of

stocks, including stocks of oil companies and stocks of airline companies, which he

believes to mitigate each other's risks; or of a conglomerate with activities that are

thought by the management to compensate for each other's possible downturns. Loss of

hedging should certainly be part of their preoccupations as they contemplate selling one

of their stocks, or ceding one of their business activities.

Can our approach to hedging be extended to selling situations? Fortunately, it can - an

elementary transformation allows us to regard any selling decision situation as an

equivalent buying situation:

Theorem 2.2 -Extension of our Results to Selling Deals

Suppose that the decision-maker owns wealth w, a portfolio X and a deal Y, which the

decision-maker is considering selling. Then,

s~<Y|w,X) = - B ~<-Y |w,X,Y>

This implies that all of our definitions and results on the value of hedging are applicable

to the case in which a decision-maker is contemplating selling an asset, if we only regard

the sale of Y as equivalent to buying -Y.

69

Page 83: Value of Hedging

Proof:

By definition, S~(Y | w, X) satisfies the following equation:

Z piu(w + x i+s~(Y|w,X»= X Pi S qjiiUCw + Xi+Yj)

is[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

As for B~( -Y | w, X, Y), it satisfies:

Z Pi Z q j i i u ( w + x i+y j -y r B ~<- Y l w > x > Y »= Z Pi Z qji iu(w + x i+yj) ie[l,n] Ml,m] is[l,n] je[l,m]

After simplification of the left-hand side, what remains is:

Z P lu(w + x-B~<-Y|w,X,Y» = Z ^ Z qjiiUCw + x .+y^ is[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

This proves that S~<Y | w, X) = B~< -Y | w, X, Y). •

Example 2.9:

We will take yet another look at Example 2.2, this time in the case in which the

decision-maker starts from a situation in which he owns both deal X and deal Y

and is considering selling Y. Both deals are shown on the next page as a reminder.

The decision-maker's u-curve satisfies the delta property within the [-$20,000,

$20,000] range, with a risk tolerance of $10,000.

We have: S~(Y | 0) = $82.02

We should recall, however, that Y provides hedging with respect to X; in other

words, selling Y would leave the decision-maker more exposed to risk. It hence

seems sensible that the decision-maker should actually place a higher value on Y

than (Y | 0) initially seemed to suggest. The actual computation of (Y | X)

confirms this prognosis:

S~(Y | X) = $87.71

70

Page 84: Value of Hedging

This example thus illustrates our observation that hedging can be just as important

a consideration when selling a deal as it is when acquiring a deal. On a side note,

it is also interesting to remark that the numeric values of S~(Y | X) and B~(Y | X)

(which we computed in Example 2.2) match; this is due to the fact that the

decision-maker's u-curve satisfies the delta property. •

Sl

0.4 $1,000

0.6 $0 S2

S'l

0.9

-0 0.1

s'2

S'l

0.3

•O

0.7

S'2

-$100

$300

-$100

$300

~<X I 0> = $388.08 ~(Y | 0) = $82.02

71

Page 85: Value of Hedging

Chapter 3 - Value of Hedging in the Delta Case

"All through history, simplifications have had a much greater long-

range scientific impact than individual feats of ingenuity. The

opportunity for simplification is very encouraging, because in all

examples that come to mind the simple and elegant systems tend to be

easier and faster to design and get right, more efficient in execution,

and much more reliable than the more contrived contraptions that have

to be debugged into some degree of acceptability. "

Edsger Dijkstra (1930-2002)

The delta property often leads to considerable simplifications in a decision analysis. One

of its most notable implications is the fact that the value of any information gathering

process is easier to compute for a decision-maker whose u-curve satisfies the delta

property than for one who does not. In this chapter we will see that the same can be said

of the value of hedging, and we will investigate many of the special properties it exhibits

in the delta case.

Throughout this part of the dissertation, we will work with a u-curve of the form:

u ( x ) = l - e - y x ,

where y > 0 denotes the decision-maker's risk-aversion coefficient. The sign of y

indicates that the decision-maker is risk-averse. We will also write VoH(Y | X) as a

shorthand for VoH(Y | w, X), due to the fact that the decision-maker's initial wealth does

not impact his valuation of uncertain deals in the delta case.

72

Page 86: Value of Hedging

1. A Simpler Formula to Compute the Value of Hedging

In the delta case, the value of hedging provided by Y with respect to X is equal to the

difference between the certain equivalent of the portfolio (X u Y) and the sum of the

certain equivalents of X and Y when considered individually:

Theorem 3.1 -Hedging as the Comparison of Joint and Individual Certain Equivalents in

the Delta Case:

If the decision-maker follows the delta property over the entire range of prospects

involved, then we have:

VoH(Y | X) = S~(X, Y | 0> - S~(X | 0 ) - S~<Y | 0 ) [3.1]

Proof:

Starting from [2.4], VoH(Y | X) is the dollar amount which makes the decision-maker

indifferent between the following two states:

By definition of the certain equivalent for deal X, the above indifference statement

implies that:

73

Page 87: Value of Hedging

s~ (X | 0 )

DealX

+ Deal Y

- S~(Y | 0)

VoH(Y | X)

By definition of the certain equivalent for deals X and Y together, we also have:

s~ < X , Y | 0 )

Due to the fact that the decision-maker follows the delta property, the indifference

statement above remains valid if we add a constant, - S~<Y | 0 ) - VoH(Y | X), to both

sides of this indifference statement:

Finally, we can conclude from the second and fourth indifference statements we have

derived that:

s~ '<X | 0>

This completes the proof of [3.1]. •

74

Page 88: Value of Hedging

Like many of the relationships we discussed in the second chapter, [3.1] illustrates the

fact that the value of hedging measures the direction and magnitude of the interaction that

exists between the portfolio of deals X and the deal which the decision-maker is

considering acquiring, Y. In a sense, we could say that the value of hedging bears the

same relationship to the interaction of two monetary deals X and Y as does the

covariance to the relevance of two random variables; there is indeed a perceptible

similitude between:

VoH(Y | X) = S~(X, Y | 0) - S~(X | 0) - S~(Y | 0)

and:

Cov(X , Y | &) = (X, Y | &) - (X | &> (Y | &)

Also, the fact that the formula for computing the value of hedging can be greatly

simplified in the delta case makes for another striking resemblance, this time between

value of hedging and value of clairvoyance. We will see over the course of this

dissertation that the two concepts actually have many more features in common.

Example 3.1:

We can apply [3.1] to the case of Example 2.2, since the decision-maker follows

the delta property:

VoH(Y | X) = S~(X, Y | 0) - S~(X | 0) - S~(Y | 0)

= $475.79 - $388.08 - $82.02

= $5.69

This matches the result we had obtained in Example 2.2, at a time when all we

could use to compute the value of hedging was its original definition as B~(Y | w,

X)-B~(Y|w + s~<X|w». •

75

Page 89: Value of Hedging

2. Special Properties of the Value of Hedging in the Delta Case

a) Symmetry

The value of hedging provided by Y to a decision-maker who already owns X is the same

as that which is provided by X if he already owns Y, provided by his u-curve satisfies the

delta property. In the delta case it would thus be more adequate to speak of the value of

hedging between two deals, rather than of the value of hedging provided by one deal with

respect to the other.

Theorem 3.2 - Symmetry of the Value of Hedging in the Delta Case:

The value of hedging is symmetric when the decision-maker follows the delta property:

VoH(Y | X) = VoH(X | Y) [3.2]

Proof:

Relationship [3.1] is symmetric in X and Y; consequently, VoH(X | Y) = VoH(Y | X)

when the decision-maker's u-curve satisfies the delta property. •

Many will find such a conclusion intuitively pleasing; after all, we defined the value of

hedging with the intention of quantifying the interaction between two portfolios, and it

only seems fitting that the interaction would be symmetric at least in some situations.

76

Page 90: Value of Hedging

b) Upper Bound on the Value of Hedging

The value of hedging between two deals is dominated by the sum of the risk premiums of

the two deals:

Theorem 3.3 -- Uvper Bound on the Value

If the decision-maker follows the delta

involved and is risk-averse, then we have:

VoH(Y | X) < RP(X |

of Hedging in the Delta Case:

property over

0) + RP(Y 0)

the entire range

[3.3]

of prospects

Proof:

From [3.1]:

VoH(Y | X) = S~(X, Y | 0) - S~(X | 0> - S~<Y | 0>

Since the decision-maker is risk-averse, we also know that:

S~(X, Y | 0> < (X + Y | &)

Combining these two results:

VoH(Y | X) < <X + Y | &> - S~<X | 0> - S~(Y | 0)

< «X | &) - S~(X | 0 » + «Y | &> - S~(Y | 0 »

< RP(X | 0) + RP(Y | 0). 3

77

Page 91: Value of Hedging

Example 3.2:

We will see that the tightness of the upper bound on the value of hedging depends

on the specific probabilities and monetary prospects of the deals involved.

For that purpose, let us consider the deal X which was common to Examples 2.1

and 2.2; with deal Yi which was regarded as a potential addition to X in Example

2.1, upper bound [3.3] yields:

VoH(Yi | X) < RP(X | 0) + RP(Y, | 0)

< ((X | &) - S~<X | 0 » + «Y! | &) - S~<Y, | 0 »

< ($400 - $388.08) + ($140 - $138.07)

< $13.84

As a reminder, we computed earlier the exact value of hedging to be equal to

$9.54. In that instance the difference between the upper bound and the actual

result is thus reasonable.

As for deal Y2 which was combined with X in Example 2.2:

VoH(Y2 I X) < RP(X I 0) + RP(Y2 | 0)

< ((X I &) - S~(X I 0 » + «Y2 I &> - S~<Y2 I 0 »

< ($400 - $388.08) + ($84 - $82.02)

< $13.90

This time the comparison is less impressive, since the actual value of hedging

between Y2 and X is $5.69.

We can find in the probabilistic structures of Yi and Y2 the reason why the upper

bound yields a better answer in the case of the former than in the case of the

latter: Yi and Y2 are similar in some respects (the magnitude of their monetary

prospects is the same), but due to the better relevance between Yi and X

compared to the one between Y2 and X, Yi and X will compensate for more of

each other's risk than Y2 and X will.

That observation leads us to another question - can the upper bound from [3.3] be

achieved? In other words, is there a deal Y* such that the value of hedging

78

Page 92: Value of Hedging

between it and X will be equal to, and not less than, the sum of the risk premiums

of the two deals?

The answer is yes. Intuitively, we might think that what we need to discover is the

best possible complement to deal X, and what better hedge is there than one

which completely eliminates uncertainty from the portfolio? We thus examine the

interaction between X and Y , which we define as follows:

r^ $1,000 $0 0.4

O

0-6 1 $0 $1000 S2

S~<X | 0> = $388.08 B~<Y* | 0) = $587.92

Figure III.l — Best hedge for X

Then:

VoH(Y* | X) < RP(X | 0) + RP(Y* | 0)

< «X | &> - S~<X | 0 » + «Y* | &> - S~(Y* | 0 »

< ($400 - $388.08) + ($600 - $587.92)

< $23.99

Interestingly, but not surprisingly, the actual value of hedging provided by Y* is

equal to that same number:

VoH(Y* | X) = S~<X, Y* | 0) - S~(X | 0) - S~<Y* | 0)

= $1000-$388.08-$587.92

= $23.99.

79

Page 93: Value of Hedging

It should also be noted, by virtue of Theorem 2.1, that the value of hedging would *

have turned out to be identical for any deal which differs from Y by a constant -

for example, if the monetary prospects of Y corresponding to s\ and S2 had

respectively been {-$500; $500}, or {-$2,000; -$1,000}. This means that there

exists an infinity of deals Y such that VoH(Y | X) = RP(X | 0) + RP(Y | 0). J

In chapter II, we introduced the idea that the value of hedging concept can also be used to

infer the value of the decision-maker's PIBP for a deal which he does not own; we had

observed that:

B~(Y | w, X) = B~<Y | w + S~<X | w» + VoH(Y | w, X), [2.5]

and we had announced that the property would prove especially valuable in the delta case,

because we would then have an upper bound on the term which corresponds to the value

of hedging. It is now time to fulfill that promise: we will combine [2.5] with the results of

the theorem we just discussed to obtain a general upper bound on the decision-maker's

PIBP for any deal which he does not already own:

Theorem 3.4- Upper Bound on the PIBP for any Deal Y:

If the decision-maker follows the delta property over the entire range of prospects

involved and is risk-averse, then for any deal Y which he does not own:

B~(Y | X) < RP(X | 0) + (Y | &) [3.4]

80

Page 94: Value of Hedging

Proof:

We first rewrite [2.5] for a decision-maker whose u-curve satisfies the delta property:

B~(Y | X) = B~(Y | 0) + VoH(Y | X)

By virtue of Theorem 3.3, the second term of the sum is dominated by RP(X | 0) +

RP(Y | 0):

B~(Y | X) < B~<Y | 0) + (RP(X | 0) + RP(Y | 0))

< RP(X | 0) + (B~<Y | 0) + RP(Y | 0))

< RP(X | 0) + <Y | &). 3

A decision-maker should thus never pay more for a deal than the sum of the risk premium

of his existing portfolio and the mean of the possible acquisition.

It shows that as decision-makers, we would be well-advised to write down on a piece of

paper the value of the risk premium of our present portfolio and carry it with us:

occasionally, that knowledge will be sufficient to quickly rule out a potential investment

as being unworthy of our attention; all we have to do is add to the risk premium number

the mean of the new investment, which is a simple task compared to the full computation

of a certain equivalent, and compare the sum to the price of the investment. If the price

exceeds RP(X | 0) + (Y | &), no further analysis is required and we should walk away

from the investment opportunity.

Example 3.3:

The decision-maker from Examples 2.1 and 2.2 only holds deal X in his current

portfolio; the associated risk premium is:

RP(X|0) =$11.92

The decision-maker is contemplating acquiring deal Y shown below, for a price

of$260:

81

Page 95: Value of Hedging

S'l

$1,000 0.1

^ ~ $ 6 5 0

&— $200 0.4

^ $100 0.2

f j -$500 o.i

S~(X I 0) = $388.08 <Y | &) = $240.00

Figure III. 2 - Computation of an upper bound on the PIBP ofY

No conditional probability distribution over the prospects of Y given those of X

has been assessed yet; all we have elicited from the decision-maker is a marginal

distribution. Still, based on [3.4], this will be enough to compute an upper bound

on his willingness to pay for Y:

B~(Y | X) < RP(X | 0) + <Y | &>

< $11.92+ $240

< $251.92

Assessing a complete conditional probability distribution over the prospects of Y

given those of X would thus be a waste of time: the decision-maker is already

assured that he should reject the offer to buy Y at a price of $260. •

82

Sl

0.4 $1,000

S '

0.6 $0 S2

Page 96: Value of Hedging

c) Value of Hedging for Multiples of a Deal with Respect to Itself

In this part, for any deal X, we will denote by AX the deal whose monetary prospects

{x'i}ie[i,n] are determined by the same set of uncertainties as the prospects {xi}ie[i>n] of

X, and such that x'j = XXJ for all values of i. We will call such deals multiples of X.

What is the value of hedging between two deals which are multiples of each other? We

have already encountered an instance in which VoH(X | X) was negative (Example 2.6);

but is that true in general?

Theorem 3.5 -- Hedging of a Deal With Respect to Itself:

If the decision-maker follows the delta property over the e

involved and if he is risk-averse, then we have:

For any scalar X

In particular:

Equivalently,

f VoH(X |

\ VoH(-X

in terms of risk

f VoH(X |

L VoH(-X

mtire range of prospects

, VoH(A,X X) is of the opposite sign of X.

X) = S~(2X | 0 ) - 2 S~<X | 0 ) < 0

| X) = - S~(X | 0 ) - S~(-X | 0 ) > 0

premium:

X) = 2 RP(X | 0 ) - RP(2X | 0 ) < 0

[3.6]

[3.7]

[3.8]

| X) = RP(X | 0 ) + RP(-X | 0 ) > 0 [3.9]

[3.5]

Proof

We will prove that VoH(X | X) < 0 for simplicity, but the same reasoning can be

extended to the general case of VoH(A,X | X):

• Proof that VoH(X | X) < 0 for binary deals X where the decision-maker

assigns p chance to receiving x and 1 - p chance to receiving 0:

83

Page 97: Value of Hedging

For now, we are only considering deals of the form detailed above. By

virtue of [3.1], we know that:

VoH(X | X) = S~<2X | 0) - 2 S~<X | 0>

Also, by definition of the certain equivalent, we have:

u(s~<X|0» = pu(x) + (l-p)u(O)

u(s~(2X | 0 » = p u(2x) + (1 - p) u(0)

Let us choose u(z) = 1 - e"yz for all z as a u-curve, to simplify those

equations; then u(0) = 0 and:

u(s~<X|0» = pu(x)

u(s~<2X | 0 » = p u(2x)

This leads to:

s ~(X|0>=-- ln( l -p + pe-yx)

s~ (2X10) = —- ln(l - p + pe"2l,x)

Forming the difference S~(2X | 0) - 2 S~<X | 0):

f s~(2X|0)-2 s~<X|0>=-ln

Y

1, f a - p + pe"^)2^ 1 - p + pe -2yx

We see that the sign of the difference depends on the sign of

(1-p + pa)2 - ( 1 - p + pa2), where a = e"7*. That function of a is always

less than or equal to 0; in fact, the only case in which it is not negative but

equal to zero is the case in which a = 1, or equivalently x = 0.

Consequently, VoH(X | X) = S~(2X | 0) - 2 S~<X | 0> < 0 for such a deal X.

84

Page 98: Value of Hedging

• Proof that VoH(X | X) < 0 for any binary deal X:

Let us now examine VoH(X | X) for deals X where the decision-maker

assigns p chance to receiving x and 1 - p chance to receiving y:

I $x

o

1-p t 1 $y

We define deal X' as follows:

r — $x-y

o

Then, by virtue of the delta property, S~(2X | 0) - 2 S~<X | 0) = (S~<2X' | 0) + 2y) - 2 (S~(X' | 0) + y)

= S~<2X' | 0) - 2 S~<X' | 0)

<0

The last inequality is a mere application of the result we proved earlier for

deals where the decision-maker assigns p chance to receiving some

amount x and 1 - p chance to receiving 0. We have thus shown that

VoH(X | X) < 0 holds for any binary deal X.

85

Page 99: Value of Hedging

Proof that VoH(X | X) < 0 for any deal X:

Any deal can be regarded as a combination of binary deals. It is by

applying the result derived above successively to all of those binary deals

that we will demonstrate that VoH(X | X) < 0 holds for any deal X.

More formally, we will reason by induction. Let Pn be the following

proposition: "For any deal X with exactly n different monetary prospects,

VoH(X\X) <0". Then:

• P2 is true, as shown earlier. As a side note, it may also be

interesting to note that Pi is true, since VoH(X | X) = 0 in that

case. However, the validity of Pi is not significant for the rest

of this proof.

• Let us suppose that for some value n, P2, ..., Pn-i are all true;

we will show that this implies that Pn is true as well. For that,

we will consider a deal X with exactly n different monetary

prospects. We will label them X], ..., xn, and we will call pi, ...,

pn their associated probabilities:

Pi

-0

Pn-l

Pn

$x,

$xn-l

$ X n

Equivalently, the last two branches of deal X can be rearranged

as follows:

86

Page 100: Value of Hedging

Pi $ X j

We will call Xn_i the subdeal which consists of the two

branches of the tree which were highlighted above. Then (2X

| 0 ) is equal to the certain equivalent of the following deal:

Pi

• 0

Pn-2

Pn-l + Pn

$2x,

3> 2 x n .

2X„,

By the substitution rule, that in turn is equal to the certain

equivalent of the deal shown below:

87

Page 101: Value of Hedging

Pi $2x.

•o

Pn-2 q> 2xn.

Pn-l + Pn "<2 Xn., | 0>

By P2, s~<2Xn.i | 0) < 2 s~(X„.i | 0); therefore, S~(2X | 0) is less

than the certain equivalent of:

Pi $2x i

-0

Pn-2

Pn-l + Pn

j> 2xn_

2 s~<Xn., | 0 )

The deal shown above now comprises exactly n-1 branches,

which allows us to make use of Pn_i; its certain equivalent will

be less than twice the certain equivalent of:

Pi $ X i

0

Pn-2 $ xn.

Pn-l + Pn ~<X„-, I 0 )

Finally, to complete the proof, we observe that the certain

equivalent of the deal shown above is equal to the certain

88

Page 102: Value of Hedging

equivalent of X. It demonstrates that s (2X | 0) < 2 S~(X | 0),

and therefore that Pn is valid if P2, ..., Pn-i are valid. :

We have successively proved that P2 is true, and that the

validity of Pn is hereditary: VoH(X | X) < 0 thus holds for any

deal X, no matter how many monetary prospects are involved

in it. 3

Example 3.4:

A decision-maker, who wishes to follow the delta property within the [-$20,000,

$20,000] range and has a risk tolerance of $10,000, holds deal X shown below:

Sl

O

0.3

S2

0.4

S3

0.3

$3,000

$0

-$2,000

We can then plot VoH(A,X | X) for different values of X (see next figure):

89

Page 103: Value of Hedging

DJD

*M $1,000

X

Figure III. 3 - Sensitivity of VoH(XX \X) to X

Two insights can be derived from that sensitivity analysis:

• the value of hedging has the sign predicted by Theorem 3.5;

• it also appears to be a monotonic decreasing function of X over the range

which we studied. D

90

Page 104: Value of Hedging

d) Value of Hedging and Irrelevance

We already observed, in the previous chapter, that the impact of risk attitude on the value

of hedging can be hard to predict and can pose a challenge to our intuition, even in

situations in which the decision-maker's u-curve satisfies the delta property (see Example

2.7). In contrast, we will now see that the absence of probabilistic relevance between two

deals produces an effect which we could have easily foretold: the value of hedging then

becomes equal to zero.

But before we show and discuss this result in greater detail, we should first precisely

define what it means for two monetary deals to be relevant or irrelevant. Stricto sensu,

probabilistic relevance is a concept which qualifies the relationship of two uncertainties,

and not of monetary deals; in order to extend its applicability to the latter, we would be

well inspired to find a way to associate with any given deal an uncertainty which, in a

manner of speaking, would be probabilistically equivalent to it. The solution is evident as

long as the uncertain deal under consideration has prospects which are all distinct:

Definition 3.1 - Minimal Underlying Uncertainty Associated with an Uncertain Deal:

Given an uncertain monetary deal Y = {(p;, yi)ie[i,n]}5 whose prospects are all distinct, we

will call "minimal underlying uncertainty associated with Y" an uncertainty S with n

degrees st such that:

For all i e [ l , n], (Y = y; o S = s.)

Another way to think about this is to notice that minimal underlying uncertainties satisfy

{Y = yj | S = sh &} = 1 as well as {S = s,•• \ Y = ys, &} = 1 for all values of i. But what

about uncertain deals whose prospects are not all distinct? In their case, we cannot apply

the above definition directly, because it would make us create an uncertainty with several

degrees which in fact all correspond to one same monetary prospect of Y. But all we need

to do is collapse Y by successively recombining every pair of equal prospects (y,, yj) into

91

Page 105: Value of Hedging

a single prospect, whose probability will be equal to the sum pi + p,, and we can then

apply Definition 3.1 to the uncertain deal which is produced by that transformation.

From this point on, we will thus say that two uncertain deals are probabilistically relevant

given a specific state of information if their respective minimal underlying uncertainties

are themselves probabilistically relevant given that state of information. With this

foundation in place, it then becomes possible to examine the important result which we

had announced earlier - in the delta case, the value of hedging between two deals which

are irrelevant given & is equal to zero:

Theorem 3.6- Irrelevance and Value of Hedging:

If the decision-maker follows the delta property over

involved, and if X and Y are irrelevant given &, then:

VoH(Y | X) = 0

the entire range of prospects

Proof:

We will start with an alternate form of equation [3.1]:

VoH(Y | X) = S~<Y | X) - S~(Y | 0)

By definition of certain equivalent S~(Y | X):

X P iu(x i + S~<Y|X»= X Pi Z qjiUCxj+yj)

ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

We then make use of the irrelevance between X and Y:

X Piu(x1 + S~<Y|X»= S P, Z qjU(xi+yj)

ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

Since the decision-maker follows the delta property, the right hand side can be

simplified as follows:

X Pi u(x, + S~<Y|X»= X p. u(x, + S~<Y|0» ie[l,n] ie[l,n]

92

Page 106: Value of Hedging

We can then conclude that S~(Y | X) = S~<Y | 0>, and therefore that VoH(Y | X) = 0. •

Why is this result not necessarily true outside of the delta case? In order to understand

that, let us remember that the value of hedging is an entity by which we place a monetary

value on the interaction between X and Y. There are only two ways in which that

interaction can manifest itself:

• if there exists a probabilistic relevance between X and Y,

• and through wealth effects: even if there is no probabilistic relevance between

X and Y, for a decision-maker who does not follow the delta property, the

value which he places on deal Y might be affected by the change in wealth

triggered by receiving some reward or penalty Xj from deal X. At a more

fundamental level, we could say that because X has yet to be resolved, its

presence in the portfolio and its possible outcomes can still influence the

decision-maker's valuation of Y.

Only in the delta case is it guaranteed that such wealth effects need not be considered;

therefore, it is only in the delta case that the absence of probabilistic relevance between X

and Y necessarily implies that the value of hedging between them will be equal to 0.

93

Page 107: Value of Hedging

Example 3.5:

Let us examine the situation of the same decision-maker as in Example 2.2, who

is contemplating buying a deal Y which is irrelevant to the unresolved portfolio X

he already owns:

Sl

0.4

-0

0.6

S2

$1,000

$0

S'l

0.3

-0 0.7

s'2

S'l

-0

0.3

0.7

s'2

-$100

$300

-$100

$300

S~<X | 0) = $388.08 B~(Y | 0) = $178.31

Figure III.4 - Value of hedging for two irrelevant deals

We can then verify that the value of hedging between X and Y is indeed equal to

zero:

VoH(Y | X) = S~<X, Y | 0) - S~(X | 0) - S~(Y | 0>

= $566.40 - $388.08 -$178.31

= $0.3

94

Page 108: Value of Hedging

3. The Chain Rule for the Value of Hedging and its Implications

a) Chain Rule

So far we have examined many important properties of the value of hedging which a

single deal Y provides with respect to the decision-maker's existing portfolio X - but

what can be said of the value of hedging which two deals Y and Z jointly provide with

respect to X? Is the joint value of hedging, VoH(Y, Z | X), related in some way to the

individual values of hedging VoH(Y | X) and VoH(Z | X)?

The idea that there might exist a chain rule connecting those entities is not incongruous.

Indeed, such a chain rule exists in the case of the value of clairvoyance; for a risk-neutral

decision-maker, who is facing a decision situation with two uncertainties, A, with degrees

{ai}ie[i,n], andB:

VoC(A, B) = VoC(A) + ]T {a; | &} VoC(B | a,) i=l

In this equation, VoC(B | a;) stands for what we might call the conditional value of

clairvoyance on B given a\: it is, the decision-maker's personal indifferent buying price

for perfect information on B once he has already acquired the certainty that A = aj.

We will now see that a chain rule which is similar in its spirit can be derived for the value

of hedging. However, we will discuss some tempting but incorrect guesses at what the

chain rule might be before we present the correct answer; indeed, there is much to be

learnt from the reasons why those guesses are incorrect. Here is what might seem the

most evident conjecture:

VoH(Y, Z | X) = VoH(Y | X) + VoH(Z | X).

But we have seen that the relevance relationships between the distinctions involved in the

decision situation can have a great impact on the value of hedging; since the sum VoH(Y

| X) + VoH(Z | X) completely ignores any information pertaining to the relevance or

irrelevance of Y and Z given X, we can dismiss the conjecture as highly unlikely to be

correct. Bearing that objection in mind, this next attempt would certainly seem a more

fitting candidate:

95

Page 109: Value of Hedging

VoH(Y, Z | X) = VoH(Y | X) + VoH(Z | X, Y)

The structure of that equation echoes that of the chain rule for the value of clairvoyance;

in fact, that second conjecture even turns out to be true in a number of cases - but it still

does not hold in the general case.

This time, the intuitive explanation for the invalidity of our conjecture is more subtle. Let

us recall the interaction metaphor we have used many times as a guide for our intuition -

for two deals A and B, VoH(A | B) captures the interaction between those two deals. The

term VoH(Z | X, Y) thus captures the interaction between Z on the one hand, and deals X

and Y on the other. Incidentally, VoH(Z | X, Y) will occasionally be affected by the

nature of the interaction between Y and Z. But the latter should not have any influence on

the value of the number we ultimately seek to evaluate, VoH(Y, Z | X), which should

solely depend upon the interaction between X on the one hand, and the deal formed by

the union of Y and Z on the other.

To put it in another way, in the expression VoH(Y, Z | X), Y and Z are already regarded

as a bundle, and thus their interaction does not need to be accounted for anymore; but in

the term VoH(Z | X, Y), the mere fact that Y and Z are now dissociated and sitting on

opposite sides of the vertical bar makes their interaction germane to the value of the

right-hand side VoH(Y | X) + VoH(Z | X, Y). This is the root of the issue with our second

conjecture. Interestingly, the actual chain rule for the value of hedging is nothing other

than a version of our second conjecture in which that same issue was rectified.

96

Page 110: Value of Hedging

Theorem 3.7' - Chain Rule for the Value of Hedging:

If the decision-maker follows the delta property over the entire range of prospects

involved, then VoH(Y, Z | X) can be decomposed into a sum of other terms involving the

values of hedging provided by Y and Z individually:

VoH(Y, Z | X) = VoH(Y | X) + VoH(Z | X, Y) - VoH(Z | Y) [3.10]

Naturally, it is also possible to start the chain rule decomposition with VoH(Z | X)

instead:

VoH(Y, Z | X) = VoH(Z | X) + VoH(Y | X, Z) - VoH(Y | Z) [3.11]

Proof:

We will evaluate VoH(Y | X) + VoH(Z | X, Y) - VoH(Z | Y) by first applying [3.1] to

each one of the three terms in that expression: r

VoH(Y | X) = S~(X, Y | 0) - S~(X | 0> - S~(Y | 0>

< VoH(Z | X, Y) = S~(X, Y, Z | 0) - S~(X, Y | 0) - S~<Z | 0>

VoH(Z | Y) = S~<Y, Z | 0) - S~(Y | 0) - S~<Z | 0)

When we then form VoH(Y | X) + VoH(Z | X, Y) - VoH(Z | Y), we can observe that

many terms cancel out; all we are left with is:

VoH(Z | X) + VoH(Y | X, Z) - VoH(Y | Z) = S~(X, Y, Z | 0) - S~(X | 0) - S~(Y, Z | 0)

Finally, we can recognize in the right-hand side of the above equation the

decomposition of VoH(Y, Z | X) using [3.1]:

VoH(Y, Z | X) = S~<X, Y, Z | 0> - S~<X | 0) - S~(Y, Z | 0)

Therefore, VoH(Y, Z | X) = VoH(Y | X) + VoH(Z | X, Y) - VoH(Z | Y). U

97

Page 111: Value of Hedging

As announced ahead of Theorem 3.7, our second guess was not far off the mark - all we

needed to do was to subtract the term VoH(Y | Z) from the sum VoH(Z | X) + VoH(Y | X,

Z) in order to compensate for the problem we had detected in that conjecture.

It is also interesting to note that it becomes even easier to remember [3.10] if one draws a

Venn diagram in which X, Y and Z are represented by three intersecting circles, and if,

for any deals A and B, one interprets VoH(A | B) as jl(A fl B), the area of A fl B:

VoH(Y | X) = n * +

+ VoH(Z | X, Y) = 1 + +

_ VoH(Z | Y) = 1 +

VoH(Y, Z | X) + +

Figure III. 5 - Mnemonic for the chain rule for the value of hedging

We will now study a concrete example in which the chain rule can be applied, and see

which kinds of practical insights it allows us to derive.

98

Page 112: Value of Hedging

Example 3.6:

A decision-maker, who wishes to follow the delta property within the monetary

range [-$5,000, $5,000] with a risk tolerance of $2,000, owns deal X and is

contemplating acquiring deals Y and Z as described below:

0.4 $1,000

-0

0.6 $0

0.8

•0

0.2

0.3

-O 0.7

-$200

$500

-$200

$500

-0 o.i 0.9

•0. 0.3 0.7

•O 0.4 0.6

0.3 '0.7

$600

-$100

$600

-$100

$600

-$100

$600

-$100

s~, (X I 0) = $342.50 ~<Y | 0) = $119.53

Figure III.6- A chain rule example

~(Z | 0) = $55.94

We will decompose VoH(Y, Z | X) using [3.10] first and [3.11] afterwards:

VoH(Y|X) =$39.21

+ VoH(Z|X,Y) =$10.52

-VoH(Z|Y) = $5.08

VoH(Y, Z | X) $54.82

99

Page 113: Value of Hedging

Here is the second application of the chain rule to VoH(Y, Z j X):

VoH(Z|X) =$13.64

+ VoH(Y | X, Z) = $36.09

-VoH(Y|Z) = $5.08

VoH(Y, Z | X) = $54.82

There are a few conclusions that we can draw from this analysis:

• The decision-maker should have a positive PIBP for Y and Z taken

individually, and for Y and Z when they are regarded as a bundle: B~(Y |

X) = $158.74; B~<Z | X) = $69.59; B~<Y, Z | X) = $225.21.

• Also, both Y and Z provide hedging with respect to the current portfolio X,

and that again is true whether Y and Z are considered in isolation or

jointly: VoH(Y | X) > 0; VoH(Z | X) > 0; VoH(Y, Z | X) > 0.

• However, it is also important to realize that Z provides less value than Y

in itself, B~(Z | 0) < ~(Y | 0), and it also provides less value than Y

through hedging with respect to X. In fact, a significant portion of VoH(Y,

Z | X) is attributable to deal Y alone.

Those remarks should help the decision-maker realize that, while Y and Z both

constitute valuable additions to his portfolio, Y is the stronger choice of the two.

Perhaps it would be worthwhile for the decision-maker to look for a better

acquisition than Z. •

100

Page 114: Value of Hedging

b) Toward an Irrelevance-Based Value of Hedging A Igebra

We mentioned earlier that VoH(Y, Z | X) = VoH(Y | X) + VoH(Z | X, Y) actually turns

out to be true in some situations; for that, all we need is for VoH(Z | Y) to be equal to

zero. Our earlier discussion of the effect of irrelevance on the value of hedging (see

Theorem 3.6) showed us when such a situation might arise:

Theorem 3.8- Chain rule for the Value c fHedsins when Y' J.Z &:

If the decision-maker follows the delta property over the entire range

involved, and if Y and Z are irrelevant given &, then:

VoH(Y, Z | X) = VoH(Y X) + VoH(Z X,Y) [3.12]

of prospects

Proof:

The general chain rule for the value of hedging was given by equation [3.10]:

VoH(Y, Z | X) = VoH(Y | X) + VoH(Z | X, Y) - VoH(Z | Y)

By Theorem 3.6, the fact that Y and Z are irrelevant given & implies that VoH(Z | Y)

= 0. The chain rule thus simplifies into:

VoH(Y, Z | X) = VoH(Y | X) + VoH(Z | X, Y). •

Theorem 3.8 gives us a first glimpse of the analytical power that we get access to once

we start combining the irrelevance properties of a decision situation with the chain rule.

As the decision-maker contemplates a new acquisition, applying the chain rule in a way

that will let him exploit the irrelevance structure of the resulting portfolio can help him

compute the value of hedging much faster. Such thinking will be of greatest value to

decision-makers who own particularly complex portfolios of unresolved deals.

In a way, we can speak of an irrelevance-based algebra for the value of hedging, an

algebra in which the theorems of probability on irrelevance are transposed into sister

101

Page 115: Value of Hedging

rules on the value of hedging. Another example follows, in which we start from a classic

rule from probability called the contraction property to derive more results on hedging:

Theorem 3.9 - Contraction Property for the Value of Hedging:

If the decision-maker follows the delta property over the entire range of prospects

involved, and if he believes that X L Y | & and that X _L Z | Y, &, then:

f VoH(Y, Z | X) = 0

1 VoH(Z | X, Y) = VoH(Z | Y)

Proof:

Let us first write the contraction property from probability in its most general form -

for any uncertainties or sets of uncertainties A, B, C and D, if A J. C | B, D, & and A

1 B | D, &, then A 1 B, C | D, &.

We will apply this result to the particular case in which A = X, B = Y, C = Z and D =

&; since the decision-maker believes that X 1 Y | & and that X 1 Z | Y, &, he should

also believe that X 1 Y, Z | &.

By Theorem 3.6,

X 1 Y | & implies that VoH(Y | X) = 0

X I Y, Z | & implies that VoH(Y, Z | X) = 0

This already proves the first clause of the conclusion of Theorem 3.9. For the second

part, let us recall the chain rule for the value of hedging given by equation [3.10]:

VoH(Y, Z | X) = VoH(Y | X) + VoH(Z | X, Y) - VoH(Z | Y)

Two terms in the equation are equal to zero; therefore, it simplifies into:

VoH(Z | X, Y) = VoH(Z | Y).

This proves the second clause of Theorem 3.9. D

102

Page 116: Value of Hedging

We will now study a practical illustration of the contraction property for the value of

hedging in order to show how useful it can be:

Example 3.7:

The same decision-maker as in Example 3.6 owns two uncertain deals, X and Y,

which he believes to be probabilistically irrelevant given &. He is contemplating

acquiring a third deal Z, which is irrelevant to X given Y and & but relevant to Y

given X and &. For instance, some investors might well have such beliefs about a

portfolio in which X was the stock of a pharmaceutical company, Y the stock of

an oil company, and Z that of an airline company. All three assets are shown on

the figure below.

Let us help the decision-maker compute his PIBP for deal Z, given that he

presently owns X and Y. There are two ways in which we can do this:

• First, we could compute B~(Z | X, Y) directly. This would require that we

take into account the full probabilistic structure of the problem.

With this approach, we obtain:

B~(Z | X, Y) = $408.96

• Secondly, we could also choose to exploit the irrelevance properties of the

portfolio. We can start by applying Property 2.3:

B~<Z | X, Y) = B~<Z | 0> + VoH(Z | X, Y)

Next we can invoke the contraction property for the value of hedging and

observe that:

VoH(Z | X, Y) = VoH(Z | Y)

Combining the two results:

B~<Z | X, Y) = B~<Z | 0 ) + VoH(Z | Y)

103

Page 117: Value of Hedging

= $378.10+ $30.86

= $408.96

S~(X | 0> = $342.50 S~(Y|0> =-$14.47 S~(Z | 0) = $378.10

Figure III. 7 — Applying the contraction property for the value of hedging

What is particularly interesting about this second approach is that it enables us to

derive the result much more rapidly and efficiently than the first. In general, if X

has nx degrees, Y ny degrees and Z nz degrees, the first approach requires that we

evaluate a tree of size nx x ny x nz. As for the second approach, it requires two

evaluations: one of a tree of size nz (to compute B~(Z | 0)) and one of a tree of

size ny x nz (to compute VoH(Z | Y)).

104

Page 118: Value of Hedging

In other words, the contraction property for the value of hedging eliminates

altogether the need to take the irrelevant component X of our portfolio into

account. The gain in efficiency will be all the larger as X is more complex. •

105

Page 119: Value of Hedging

Chapter 4 - Hedging as Moment Reengineering

"Cause and effect are two sides of one fact. "

Ralph Waldo Emerson (1803-1882),

Circles

The question I will address in this chapter of the dissertation is perhaps more fundamental

and theoretical than any of the other issues we have examined so far - what probabilistic

phenomena lie at the source of hedging? My ambition is to identify some universal

characteristics of the situations in which hedging arises, in order to be able to detect

hedging more easily.

In this entire chapter, we will again assume that the decision-maker is risk-averse and

follows the delta property over the range of prospects involved. We will denote his risk-

aversion coefficient by y. A possible u-curve for him is thus given by:

u(x) = 1 - e-yx

106

Page 120: Value of Hedging

1. General Principle

Ronald A. Howard showed that, for people who follow the delta property over some

range, a convenient decomposition of their certain equivalent for a deal involving

prospects within that range is given by:

"<Z|0) = X ^ ^ Y n - 1 K „ n!

[4.1]

where K„ denotes the nl cumulant of the distribution {Z | &} [Howard, R. A., 1971]. For

the reader who is not familiar with the concept of cumulants, it is sufficient for the

purposes of our discussion to know that the values of those cumulants can be computed

recursively based on the values of the moments of equal or lower order:

K n = U n - E k=l

n-1

k-1 Kk IV:

In particular:

Ki=<Z|&>

K2 = V(Z | &)

K3 = < ( Z - < Z | & » 3 | & >

(first cumulant)

(second cumulant)

(third cumulant)

By truncating the series in [4.1], we can then obtain approximations of the certain

equivalent which will be more or less precise depending on the term at which we stopped.

For example, one of the most commonly used approximations of the certain equivalent in

decision analysis is:

s~<Z|0)«<Z|&)-ly v (Z|&) [4.2]

The approximation turns out to be exact if the probability distribution over Z is normal.

Otherwise, it will be all the more precise as:

V ( Z | & ) « ^

y

If we instead consider the first three terms of [4.1], we obtain:

107

Page 121: Value of Hedging

s~<Z|0>*<Z|&>-^yv<Z|&> + V<(Z-<Z|&>)3 |&>, [4.3] 2 o

which implies that if two deals have the same mean and variance, but one of them is more

skewed toward the right, a risk-averse decision-maker who follows the delta property will

tend to prefer that deal over the other.

Such decompositions of the certain equivalent should remind us that if we are offered an

uncertain deal of which we know nothing, and if we are allowed to ask one question and

only one about the moments of the deal in question, we should inquire about its mean; if

it is negative, we should reject the offer. If we are allowed to ask two questions, then we

should ask about the mean and variance of the deal, so that we can use approximation

[4.2] to assess our certain equivalent for it.

Likewise, if we own a deal and wish to make it more valuable, our best efforts should be

aimed at increasing its mean, then at decreasing its variance, then at increasing the value

of its third central moment, etc. We will now examine some concrete examples in order

to demonstrate that such a process is exactly what hedging is about - in other words,

some deal Y has a positive value of hedging with respect to a deal X which we already

own if and only if Y helps us reengineer the cumulants of X of order 2 and above in a

helpful manner.

108

Page 122: Value of Hedging

2. Variance Reengineering

We saw in the first chapter that the idea that hedging can be used to reduce the variance

of an existing deal is already widespread in the financial literature, to the point that

hedging and variance reduction have often been regarded as complete synonyms. In this

part we will for once also focus entirely on the variance; we will see that in many

situations the certain equivalent approximation

s~(Z|0>*(Z|&>-iyv(Z|&>

can help us compute an approximate PIBP for any deal with a respectable accuracy,

because in those cases a large part of the value that hedging provides comes from a

variance reduction effect.

Example 4.1:

The same decision-maker as in Example 2.1 owns some unresolved deal X and is

considering buying deal Y. The two deals are shown below:

Sl

0.4

O

0.6 1 $0 $200

Figure IV.l - Example of variance reengineering

$1,000 -$300

109

Page 123: Value of Hedging

As with some of our earlier examples, at first sight, it might be tempting to

dismiss Y as a bad investment opportunity; indeed, S~(Y | 0) = -$3.01 < 0, which

is not surprising since the decision-maker is risk-averse and since Y has a mean of

0. However, closer examination reveals that VoH(Y | X) = $11.94, which more

than compensates for the low value of ~(Y | 0) and suffices to make Y worth

buying for a price of up to B~<Y | X) = $8.93.

Where does the positive value of hedging come from? In order to understand it a

little better, let us recall [3.1]:

VoH(Y | X) = S~(X, Y | 0) - S~<X | 0) - S~<Y | 0)

Let us also recall [2.5]:

S~<Y | X) = S~<Y | 0) + VoH(Y | X)

Therefore:

S~<Y | X) = S~<X, Y | 0) - S~(X | 0)

We will decompose that difference along the first two cumulants as in [4.2]:

s~(Y|X) = (<X,Y|&>-iY V(X,Y|&) ]-( <X|&)-^y V(X|&)

V 2 ) \ 2 )

Rearranging the terms, so that the terms corresponding to first moments are

separated from those which correspond to second moments:

s~(Y|X> = (<X,Y|&>-<X|&>)-iY(v<X,Y|&>-v<X|&))

The following table shows the values of the first and second moments of the

original portfolio, X, and of the portfolio in which X and Y are combined, (X u

Y):

110

Page 124: Value of Hedging

Table IV.l - Decomposition of certain equivalents along the first two cumulants

Several interesting observations can be made based on those results:

1) The main reason why S~(X, Y | 0 ) is greater than S~(X | 0 ) is the fact that

Y helps reduce some of the variance of X. The variance of deals X and Y

combined is 60,000, versus 240,000 for the original deal X. In other words,

even though Y does not add to the e-value of the monetary prospects of

our portfolio, it might be worth acquiring because it helps us reduce its

variance.

2) Our approximation of the difference (X, Y | 0 ) - (X | 0) , even when

truncated after only two moments, is accurate enough to help us compute

the decision-maker's PIBP for Y with an error of less than 1%. That can

be explained by the fact that the portfolios we are examining here, be it the

original one, X, or the one resulting from the combination of X and Y, all

have variances small enough for [4.2] to be precise:

V ( X | & > « - ^ and V<X,Y| & > « - ! -Y T

3) The approximation would have been even more accurate if we had

stopped the decomposition after three cumulants instead of two, as shown

below:

111

Page 125: Value of Hedging

Table IV.2 - Decomposition of certain equivalents along the first three cumulants

This time the error is of less than a cent. However, the two-cumulant

decomposition was already so good that it is doubtful that the slight

increase in accuracy obtained as a result of using a three-cumulant

decomposition instead of a two-cumulant decomposition really warrants

the extra computational effort.

The next chart represents the evolution of the certain equivalents of the

original and new portfolio, S~(X | 0 ) and S~(X, Y | 0 ) , as one takes into

account more and more cumulants in summation [4.1]. As shown by that

study, the fourth and fifth cumulants have even less of an impact on the

accuracy of our approximation than the third. D

112

Page 126: Value of Hedging

$410.00

$405.00

$400.00

$395.00

$390.00

$385.00

$380.00

1 Cumulant 3 Cumulants 5 Cumulants 2 Cumulants 4 Cumulants

Figure IV.2 - Accuracy of approximation depending on the number of cumulants

S-KHUMI

S400.0o\

-

i

sw.oo ^ ^ - - - B - • -8

\ * PIBP(Y | X)

$388.00

i i

- • - S~(X | 0) -m- S~(X, Y | 0)

„ „ , , ! § - , . . . „ _ „ . . . «

($8.93)

A A

" ' " " ' ' " :"""

Example 4.2:

As mentioned in the first part of this chapter, there is one situation in which the

certain equivalent approximation based on only two cumulants [4.2] is exact -

that is when the probability distribution over the deal Z whose certain equivalent

we wish to evaluate is normal.

Let us consider the case of a firm, which currently owns a single business division,

X, and is contemplating acquiring a division Y from another company. The profits

generated by X are modeled as a normal distribution, with a mean of $200 million

and a standard deviation of $100 million, whereas those of Y are modeled as

another normal distribution, with mean $50 million and standard deviation $20

million. The company's management also believe that the probabilistic relevance

between X and Y is best captured as a correlation coefficient rXy = -0-5, and they

state that the company is comfortable using an exponential u-curve with a risk-

tolerance of $200 million for this particular decision situation.

113

Page 127: Value of Hedging

What is the most that the firm should be willing to pay for Y? If we neglect the

probabilistic relevance between the two business divisions, and directly apply

[4.2] to Y, we obtain:

s~(Y|0) = ( Y | & ) - - y v(Y|&)

s~<Y 10) - 5 0 - - x 0.005x400 2

s~ <Y 10)= $49 million

The situation looks quite different once we take into account the fact that the

company already owns X and that Y would compensate for some of its risk:

S~<Y | X) = S~<X, Y | 0) - S~<X | 0}

As in the previous example, we will decompose that difference along the first two

cumulants:

S ~ ( Y | X ) = ( ( X , Y | & ) - < X | & > ) - | Y ( V ( X , Y | & > - V ( X | & > )

S~<Y|X) = ( Y | & ) - | Y ( V < X , Y | & > - V ( X | & ) )

s~(Y|X) = (Y|&)-^Y(^Y+2rX YaxaY)

s~<Y|X>=50--0.005 (400-2x0.5x20x100)

Finally:

s~ <Y | X>= $54 million

The company should thus be willing to pay more for the new business division Y

than the mean of the profits it would generate, because Y would mitigate some of

the risk associated with X and reduce the variance of the whole portfolio. It is not

the first time in this dissertation that we encounter a situation in which hedging

114

Page 128: Value of Hedging

effects justify that a risk-averse decision-maker value an uncertain deal at more

than its mean: we had already observed the same phenomenon in Example 2.1. H

115

Page 129: Value of Hedging

3. Reengineering Moments of Higher Order

In spite of the accuracy of the results we obtained on our first example with a two-

cumulant decomposition, it would be a mistake to systematically associate hedging with

variance reduction. [4.1] should remind us that even if we do not have any way to

enhance the e-value of the monetary prospects, nor any way to reduce the variance, there

are still many more cumulants on which we can have a valuable effect.

Here is an example which will demonstrate the potential importance of those higher order

cumulants.

Example 4.3:

The decision-maker's risk tolerance is assessed as being equal to $1,000; his

current portfolio X and the deal he is considering acquiring, Y, follow:

si

-O

0.3

S2

0.4

S3

0.3

$1,000

$400

-$200

s~ (X | 0) = $294.49

$99.52

-$217.71

$190.7

~(Y|0) =-$16.63

Figure IV.3 - Hedging as reengineering of moments of order 3 and above

It turns out that Y, if acquired and used as an adjunct to the portfolio, preserves its

mean as well as its variance. In spite of that, Y does provide hedging with respect

116

Page 130: Value of Hedging

to X; a closer examination of the first five cumulants of deal X, versus those of

deals X and Y when considered together, shows why:

S~(X | 0> S~(X, Y | 0 ) ^(\, Y | 0 ) - S~(X | 0 )

$400.00

-$108.00

$0.00

$2.59

$0.00

$294.59

$400.00

-$108.00

$13.00

$2.45

-$1.02

$306.43

$0.00

$0.00

$13.00

-$0.14

-$1.02

$11.84

Table IV. 3 - Decomposition of certain equivalents along the first Jive cumulants

The next figure presents the exact same information as the table, but in a

graphical manner:

$400.00 "

$380.00 "

$360.00 "

$340.00 "

$320.00 "

$300.00 -

$280.00 H

MOU.IMI

S400.0o\

i

V ' W (10

S292.00 I

s;ov(K i

« \ >

S292.00 1

PIBP(Y | X) ($11.84)

1 Cumulant 3 Cumulants 5 Cumulants 2 Cumulants 4 Cumulants

Figure IV.4 - Accuracy of approximation depending on the number of cumulants

117

Page 131: Value of Hedging

The decision-maker's PIBP for Y, S~(Y | X), turns out to be positive. It is

approximately equal to $11.84, which means that the value of hedging provided

by Y is in the region of $11.84 - (-$16.63) = $28.48.

Therefore, Y would be a valuable addition to the decision-maker's portfolio,

despite the fact that it does not affect its first two moments in any way. Here, most

of the value of hedging seems to be attributable to the fact that adding Y to X has

a beneficial impact on the third moment of the portfolio, with the skewness

shifting into the positive realm. Another, perhaps slightly more graphic way to

look at the effect of Y on the third moment of the portfolio is shown below; we

plot the probability mass function for deal X considered individually (dotted

lines) and then for deals X and Y combined into one portfolio (solid lines):

| 9 r4§-

0.4

0.35

* 0 . 3 i

0.25

'0 .2 I 0.15 I

,0 .1

O.05

L^_

i

i

-$500.00 $0.00 $500.00 $1,000.00 $1,500.00

Figure IV. 5 - Probability mass functions of X and (X uY)

The chart confirms the favorable effect that Y has on the decision-maker's

portfolio - while preserving its mean and variance, it provides a welcome boost to

its skewness. The resulting portfolio has the same center of gravity and the same

spread as the original portfolio, but we have successfully limited its downside

118

Page 132: Value of Hedging

while improving its upside. Both changes will be of great interest to our risk-

averse decision-maker.

The key to analyzing this second example correctly was to include the third

cumulant in our study. If we had assessed S~(Y | X) = S~(X, Y | 0) - S~(X | 0>

based on a three-cumulant decomposition of the two certain equivalents on the

right hand side, we would have obtained S~(Y | X) = $13.00, which is not far from

the result we obtain with five cumulants ($11.84) and not far either from the

actual value of S~<Y | X) ($11.99).

Conversely, we would have made a grave mistake if we had only analyzed the

effects of Y on the mean and variance of the portfolio: we would have rejected a

proposition which in reality was quite attractive given the decision-maker's risk

attitude and current assets.

This example should remind us of the limitations of the two-cumulant

approximation of the certain equivalent; the approximation will only yield

satisfactory results if the variance of the deal is negligible compared to the square

of the decision-maker's risk tolerance. Here the square of the decision-maker's

risk tolerance is equal to 1,000,000, whereas the variances of X and (X u Y) are

equal to 216,000: the risk involved in those portfolios is so close to the decision­

maker's risk tolerance that it is not safe to truncate the decomposition of the

certain equivalent after the mean and variance. •

119

Page 133: Value of Hedging

Chapter 5 - The Value of Perfect Hedging

"To not plan ahead is to whimper already. "

Leonardo Da Vinci (1803-1882)

In earlier parts of this dissertation, we discussed how we can think of hedging in the

context of a specific deal Y with respect to a portfolio of unresolved deals which the

decision-maker owns, X.

We will now examine a different but related situation: suppose that the decision-maker

owns a portfolio of unresolved deals which is fairly complex. He would like to take a

proactive stance and identify deals which might help him hedge his portfolio - however,

he just does not have the time and resources to analyze and evaluate the merits of the

myriad of financial deals which are available to him on the markets. How can he

determine which uncertainties are most worthy of his attention? For which uncertainties

should he seek hedging opportunities, and how much of his resources should he devote to

that research?

120

Page 134: Value of Hedging

1. Definition

The value of perfect hedging is the concept which will help us answer those questions:

Definition 5.1 — Value of Perfect Hedging

Suppose the decision-maker has wealth w and owns an unresolved portfolio of deals X =

{(Pi> Xj)ie[i> n]}, for which S is a minimal underlying uncertainty.

For any uncertainty or set of uncertainties S', we will call perfect hedge on S' given X

and w the deal Y = {(q;, yi)iG[i, m]} which has the highest PIBP of all the deals which

satisfy the following two conditions:

• Its prospects are solely determined by the outcomes of S' (in the sense that S' is a

minimal underlying uncertainty for that deal Y),

• <Y | &> = 0.

We will define the value of perfect hedging on S' given w and X as the decision-maker's

PIBP for that choice of Y. We will denote it by VoPH(S' | w, X).

More formally, VoPH(5" | w, X) is defined as follows:

VoPH(S'|w,X) = max B~<Y | w, X) [5.1] Y s.t. (Y | &> = 0

Y determined by S'

Or, more explicitly:

VoPH(S' | w, X) = max <p [5.2]

s.t. f Y is chosen so that S' is a minimal underlying uncertainty for it and (Y | &) = 0

| Z p iu(w+x i)= X Pi Z q j i i u ( w + x i+y j -^ ) L ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

121

Page 135: Value of Hedging

It is important to understand that our perspective has undergone a radical change

compared to what it was when we were studying the value of hedging concept. In

previous chapters, the inputs to our problem were the decision-maker's current wealth,

his existing portfolio of unresolved deals and a pre-identified potential adjunct to his

portfolio; the goal of our analysis was to quantify the interaction between the existing

portfolio and that possible adjunct, and to place a monetary value on it. In contrast, the

inputs to the value of perfect hedging are current wealth, the existing portfolio of

unresolved deals, X, and a set of uncertainties S' which will serve as a support to build

new deals; the goal of our investigation is to identify the value provided by the best

possible hedging deal of mean zero which one can construct based on that support 5".

In other words, the first situation was one in which our behavior was reactive: the

decision-maker had been given a choice of a deal or several which he could add to his

portfolio, and those were the only alternatives he was considering. From now on, our

approach will be more proactive and open-ended: it is not an external stimulus which has

triggered our decision to look for valuable additions to the decision-maker's portfolio, but

our own resolve to improve it.

Example 5.1:

An oil company is just about to start operating an oil field which it recently

acquired. They believe that their profit will be entirely determined by two

uncertainties - the volume of oil that they will be able to extract, and the price at

which they will be able to sell the oil. They believe the two uncertainties to be

irrelevant given &. Finally, the board also state that they are comfortable

following the delta property for the range of prospects involved, and their risk

tolerance is assessed to be $500 million.

The following figure provides an overview of their current decision situation and

certain equivalent; all monetary prospects are expressed in millions of dollars. We

will denote by X the deal that they own at present:

122

Page 136: Value of Hedging

High Price

0.4

-0

0.6

Low Price

High Volume

0.3 ) 0.7

Low Volume

High Volume

•o 0.3

0.7

Low Volume

$300 M $a

$50 M $b

$120 M $c

-$50 M $d

~<X | 0 ) = $38.99 M

Figure V.l — The value of perfect hedging: an example

We can then compute the value of perfect hedging on the oil price uncertainty and

on the volume uncertainty, in order to help the company ascertain the variable on

which it is most important that they seek hedging.

To compute the value of perfect hedging on oil price, we need to identify the best

hedge such that its prospects are only determined by oil price, which implies that

a = b and c = d on the picture shown above, and such that the mean of its

monetary prospects is equal to 0, which implies that .4 a + .6 c = 0. We thus need

to solve the following optimization problem:

max S~(Y | X)

s.t. f a = b

c = d

.4a + .6c = 0

123

Page 137: Value of Hedging

The solution we obtain is:

a = b =-$70.55 M

c = d = $47.03 M

V6PH(Oil Price | X) = $3.26 M

As was to be expected, the perfect hedge is a deal which provides a benefit if the

situation which is least favorable to the oil company arises (low oil prices), but

leads to a loss if the situation which is most favorable arises (high oil prices).

We then compute the value of perfect hedging on the volume uncertainty by a

similar process; the solution to that second optimization problem is:

a = c =-$137.77 M

b = d = $59.04 M

VoPU(Volume | X) = $7.68 M

The analysis thus shows that perfect hedging on volume is more valuable to the

oil company than perfect hedging on price.

It is also possible to look for a perfect hedge which is determined by none of the

uncertainties which are directly involved in the existing portfolio, but is

probabilistically relevant to at least one of them. Let us suppose for example that

it is not possible for the company to hedge directly on oil price, but instead they

could hedge based on the price of another commodity, gold. They believe gold

price to be irrelevant to the volume of oil they will extract from their field given

&, but relevant to oil price. Given a high oil price, they assign a .8 probability to a

high gold price and .2 to a low gold price, and given a low oil price, they assign

a .9 probability to a low gold price and . 1 to a high gold price.

We then solve:

max S~(Y|X)

s.t. r Y's prospects are solely determined by the gold price uncertainty

L <Y|&) = 0

124

Page 138: Value of Hedging

The best hedge entails a profit of $31.68 million if gold prices are low, and a loss

of $51.69 million if they are high; furthermore, Vo?U(Gold Price | X) = $1.61

million. Interestingly, the value of perfect hedging on gold price is lower than that

on the uncertainty to which it is relevant and which is directly involved in the

determination of the monetary prospects of X, namely the oil price. Also, in spite

of the strong relevance between the two uncertainties Oil Price and Gold Price,

the difference between the values of perfect hedging that they provide is

considerable: one is twice as much as the other. G

125

Page 139: Value of Hedging

2. Basic Properties

a) Risk Attitude and Sign of the Value of Perfect Hedging

We will soon discuss the behavior of VoPH(5" | w, X) as a function of various

characteristics of S'. But before that, it is worth spending a few minutes on some of the

most basic properties of the value of perfect hedging - for example, the relation between

its sign and the decision-maker's risk attitude. The first clause of Property 5.1, which

states that the value of perfect hedging is always equal to zero for a risk-neutral decision­

maker and can therefore never be a useful consideration to him, echoes a similar

observation we made earlier about the value of hedging.

Property 5.1 - Sign of the Value of Perfect Hedging and Risk Attitude

For a risk-neutral decision-maker, VoPH(5" | w, X) is always equal to zero.

For a risk-averse decision-maker, VoPH(5" | w, X) is always greater than or equal to zero.

Proof:

For a risk-neutral decision-maker, B~(Y | w, X) = (Y | &) for any deal Y. Since the

value of perfect hedging is computed as the maximum ofB~<Y|w,X> over the set of

deals Y which have a mean of zero, VoPH(5" | w, X) = 0.

For a risk-averse decision-maker, all we need to do is notice that the deal Y° whose

prospects are all determined by S' and are all equal to 0 belongs to the set of deals

over which we maximize B~(Y | w, X) in [5.1]. Consequently, VoPH(S" | w, X) > B~(Y° | w, X) = 0. 3

126

Page 140: Value of Hedging

b) PIBPfor an Uncertain Deal and Value of Perfect Hedging

Now that we know of situations in which the value of perfect hedging is not an

illuminating concept, let us turn to those in which it is and ask ourselves what makes it

helpful. Why should we ever be interested in computing VoPH(5" | w, X)? What can it

add to our understanding of a decision situation? The following theorem presents one of

the most persuasive reasons:

Theorem 5.1 — PIBPfor an Uncertain Deal and Value of Perfect Hedging

The value of perfect hedging allows us to calculate an upper bound on our PIBP for any

deal Y whose outcomes are solely determined by some set of uncertainties iS":

B~<Y | w, X) < (Y | &) + VoPH(S' | w, X) [5.3]

Proof:

Let us construct a deal Y' which is the exact copy of Y up to a constant: more

specifically, we will define Y' so that y'j = yj - (Y | &) for all values of j .

Let us recall that for any deal Z, any wealth w and any amount 8, the PIBP for a deal

Z' in which all prospects of Z were changed by the same amount 8 is equal to the sum

of the PIBP for Z, augmented by 8 (Lemma 2.1); in particular, that result implies that:

B~<Y | w, X) = (Y | &} + B~(Y' | w, X)

But by virtue of Definition 5.1, we also have:

B~(Y' | w, X) < VoPH(5' | w, X)

Therefore:

B~(Y | w, X> < <Y | &) + VoPH(S' | w, X). •

[5.3] is a remarkable relationship because it provides us with an upper bound on B~(Y | w,

X), a quantity which, in general, is not easy to compute, especially if the probabilistic

127

Page 141: Value of Hedging

structure of the current portfolio of deals X is elaborate. The upper bound consists of the

sum of (Y | &>, which is easy to evaluate and does not depend at all on the decision­

maker's existing portfolio X or even on his exact risk preference, and VoPH(5" | w, X),

which is a more obscure notion at this point of our story but for which we will soon be

able to derive some upper bounds and approximations.

Example 5.2:

Let us go back to Example 5.1, and consider deal Y which is defined as follows

and whose prospects are determined by the Gold Price uncertainty:

High Gold Price

0.38

0.62

Low Gold Price

-$50 M

$100 M

B~(Y | 0) = $37.59 M

Figure V.2- Upper bound on the PIBPfor Y based on the value of perfect

hedging

We directly apply [5.3] in order to compute an upper bound on the decision­

maker's PIBP for Y:

B~<Y | w, X) < <Y | &) + VoPU(Gold Price | w, X)

< $43.00 M +$1.61 M

< $44.61 M

128

Page 142: Value of Hedging

Based on that simple analysis, the oil company already knows that it should not

buy deal Y if its price exceeds $44.61 million.

It should also be noted that in this example, the actual value of the oil company's

PfflP for Y is:

B~(Y | w, X) = $43.56 M

The difference between upper bound and actual value is small, but we should be

aware that the tightness of the bound can vary considerably from example to

example. If we swap the two monetary prospects of the deal Y we have just

studied, and call the resulting deal Y', then the upper bound gives: B~(Y' | w, X) < <Y' | &) + VoPH(GoldPrice | w, X)

< $7.00 M +$1.61 M

<$8.61M

The actual value of the PIBP is:

B~(Y'|w,X> =-$3.65M

The bound gives disappointing results in the case of Y'; the fact that unlike Y, Y'

provides negative hedging with respect to X explains it. •

129

Page 143: Value of Hedging

c) Joint Value of Perfect Hedging

It is a tempting mistake for many new students of decision analysis to believe that there is

a general rule connecting the joint value of clairvoyance on two uncertainties S' and S" to

the sum of the individual values of clairvoyance on S' and S". In reality, it turns out that

in some situations the joint value of clairvoyance is greater than the sum of the individual

values of clairvoyance, and in others it is lower; all that can be said with certainty is that:

VoC(5", S") > max (VoC(S'), VoC(5"))

In other words, having perfect information on both 5" and S" is at least as valuable as

having perfect information on S' alone, and at least as valuable as having perfect

information on S" alone. We will now see that the same can be said of the value of

perfect hedging:

Theorem 5.2 -Joint Value of Perfect Hedging

For two sets of uncertainties S' and S", the joint value of perfect hedging on S' and S" is

greater than or equal to the higher of the two individual values of perfect hedging on S'

and S":

VoPH(S', S" | w, X) > max (VoPH(S' | w, X), VoPH(S" | w, X)) [5.4]

Proof:

We will first prove that VoPH(S', S" | w, X) > VoPH(S' | w, X). For that, let us

denote by Y the deal which helps achieve perfect hedging on 5":

Y* = argmax B~(Y | w, X>

Y s.t. (Y | &> = 0

Y determined by S'

It implies that:

B~(Y* | w, X) = VoPH(S' | w, X)

130

Page 144: Value of Hedging

We can remark that a fortiori, Y* also belongs to the set of deals Y whose monetary

prospects are solely determined by S' and 5"', and whose mean is equal to 0. That is

precisely the set of deals over which we maximize ~(Y | w, X) when we wish to

compute VoPH(S', S" | w, X):

VoPH(S ' ,S" |w,X)= max B~(Y | w, X)

Y s.t. (Y | &> = 0

Y determined by S',S"

Therefore:

VoPH(S', S " | w, X) > B~<Y* | w, X)

>VoPH(S' |w,X)

By the same reasoning, we can prove that VoPH(5", S" | w, X) > VoPH(5"' | w, X).

We thus conclude that VoPH(S', S" | w, X) > max (VoPH(S' | w, X), VoPH(S" | w,

X)).I!

Example 5.3:

We will again refer to Example 5.1; in that situation, the set S of the uncertainties

which completely determine the monetary prospects of X comprises two

elements: Oil Price and Volume.

We will compute the value of perfect hedging on S, and then compare it to the

individual values of perfect hedging on Oil Price and Volume, which we already

computed. Using the same notation {a, b, c, d} as in Example 5.1 to designate the

monetary prospects of the perfect hedge Y we wish to construct, we start by

solving the optimization problem shown below:

131

Page 145: Value of Hedging

max S~<Y | X>

s.t. 0 = <Y|&> = . 1 2 a + . 2 8 b + .18c + .42d

The solution we obtain is:

C a =-$249.40 M

b = $0.60 M

{ c = -$69.40 M

d = $100.60 M

, VoPH(5|X) = $11.61M

For clarity, X and its perfect hedge Y are represented below:

High Volume

High Price

0.4

0.3 ) 0.7

-o Low Volume

High Volume

0.6 •0

Low Price

0.3 l

0.7

Low Volume

$300 M + -$249.4 M

$50 M + $0.60 M

$120 M + -$69.40 M

-$100 M + $100.60 M

$50.60 M

$50.60 M

$50.60 M

$50.60 M

s~ (X | 0 ) = $38.99 M

Figure V.3 — Joint perfect hedging on Oil Price and Volume

132

Page 146: Value of Hedging

We then compare the joint value of perfect hedging to the values of perfect

hedging on Oil Price and Volume:

f VoPH(S|X) = $11.61M

VoPH(CW Price | X) = $3.26 M

Vom(Volume | X) = $7.68 M

It proves that VoPH(S', S" | X) > max (VoPH(S' | X), VoPH(S" | X)), as

announced by Theorem 5.2. Incidentally, let us also make a note of the fact that

the value of perfect hedging on S in this example is less than the sum of the values

of perfect hedging on the individual uncertainties which compose S:

VoPH(0/7 Price | X) + Vo?H(Volume | X) = $3.26 M + $7.68 M

= $10.94 M

< VoPH(S | X)

It illustrates the interesting parallel between the value of perfect hedging and the

value of perfect information which we mentioned previously. The value of

clairvoyance on two uncertainties is not necessarily equal to the sums of the value

of clairvoyance on the individual uncertainties, even when the uncertainties are

irrelevant. Now we know that the same can be said of the value of perfect hedging.

It is also thought-provoking that the perfect hedge which we constructed on Oil

Price and Volume simultaneously would transform the oil company's uncertain

portfolio into a deterministic one, whose monetary prospects are all equal to

$50.60 million (as shown by the previous figure). A point of further interest is that

$50.60 million happens to be precisely equal to the mean of the decision-maker's

original portfolio. We will soon determine that none of this happened by

coincidence. 3

133

Page 147: Value of Hedging

3. Impact of Relevance on the Value of Perfect Hedging

In the course of our investigation of hedging, we have already gathered a few clues here

and there as to the nature of its connection with probabilistic relevance. As we studied the

special properties of the value of hedging in the delta case, for example, we remarked that

it is equal to zero for two deals which are irrelevant given &.

We will examine the connection between relevance and hedging more systematically and

more in depth over the next few pages; we will see that the value of perfect hedging on

any uncertainty S' is determined to a large extent by the relevance relationship between

S' and the set S of the uncertainties which completely determine the monetary prospects

of the existing portfolio. We will examine the following three cases separately:

• Complete relevance: S and S' are identical, or S and S' are deterministic given

each other. In other words, the probability distributions {S | S' = s ) , &} as well as

{S' | S - Sj, &} only consist of ones and zeros.

• Complete irrelevance: S A. 5" | &.

• Incomplete relevance: S and S' are relevant, but not to the extent that S is

deterministic given S'.

134

Page 148: Value of Hedging

a) Complete Relevance

Theorem 5.3 - Value of Perfect Hedging when S' = S

VoPH(,S | w, X) = RPS(X | w). [5.5]

Furthermore, equality of B~(Y | w, X) and VoPH^ | w, X) is achieved if and only if Y is

the deal which transforms every single prospect of X into (X | &).

The result also holds for an uncertainty S' such that S and S' are deterministic given each

other: then again, VoPH(5" | w, X) = RPS(X | w).

Proof:

Proof that VoPH(£ | w, X) > RPS(X | w):

For each prospect Xj of X, define y; = (X | &> - x;. Then (Y | &> = 0 and by

definition of the value of perfect hedging, we have VoPH(5' | w, X) > B~(Y

| w, X). Let us compute B~(Y | w, X) for that particular choice of Y. By

definition of the PIBP, we know that:

£ P iu(w + X i)= X P. Z qj|iU(w + x i +y j -B -<Y|w,X»

ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

X P iu(w + x,)= X Pi Z qjiUCw + x ^ X I & ^ x J - ^ Y I w . X ) ) ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

X PiUCw + x ^ - J ] P iu(w + <X|&)-B~<Y|w,X» ie[l,n] ie[l,n]

Y, p iu(w + x i) = u(w + (X|&)-B~(Y|w,X» i£[l,n]

Let us now remember what the definition of the certain equivalent S~(X |

w) for X is:

X piu(w + xi) = u(w+s~(X|&» ie[l,n]

Combining the last two equations, we obtain:

135

Page 149: Value of Hedging

b~<X I w) = (X ] &) - B~(Y | w, X) B~(Y | w, X> = <X | &> - S~(X | w)

B~(Y | w, X) = RPS(X | w)

This proves that VoPH(5 | w, X) > RPS(X | w).

• Proof that VoPH(S | w, X) < RPS(X | w):

Let us now prove that VoPH(S | w, X) < RPS(X | w). For that let us

consider any hedging deal Y whose outcomes are solely determined by S

and for which (Y | &> = 0. We will show that we necessarily have B~(Y | w,

X) < RPS(X | w).

Consider the situation in which the decision-maker has acquired deal Y for

exactly B~(Y | w, X). He then owns w - B~(Y | w, X), as well as X and Y

which are still unresolved. The mean of those dollar prospects is equal to

w + (X | &) - B~(Y | w, X), since Y itself has a mean of zero.

Since the decision-maker is risk-averse, we have:

£ Pi u(w + x, + y, - B~(Y | w, X)) < u(w + (X | &) - B~(Y | w, X» ie[l,n]

By definition of PIBP B~(Y | w, X), we also have:

£ PiU(w + Xi)= £ PiUCw + Xi+yi -^YIw.X)) ie[1,n] ie[l,n]

Therefore:

£ p iu(w + x i)<u(w + <X|&)- B~<Y|w,X» ie[l,n]

The left-hand side of that inequality can be rewritten as u(w + S~(X | w))

by definition of the PISP for deal X; doing so, we obtain:

u(w + S~<X | w» < u(w + (X | &) - B~(Y | w, X»

u(w + (X | &) - RPS(X | w)) < u(w + (X | &> - B~(Y | w, X»

136

Page 150: Value of Hedging

That in turn shows that B~(Y | w, X) < RPs(X | w), and since it is true for

any deal Y whose prospects are solely determined by S and for which (Y |

&> = 0, VoPH(5 | w, X) < RPS(X | w).

It should also be noted that for a strictly concave u-curve, and for a

hedging deal Y which is not defined by y; = (X | &) - xi, the concavity

inequality we based ourselves upon to prove that VoPH(5' | w, X) < RPs(X

| w) becomes strict:

£ Pi u(w + x; + y, - B~(Y | w, X» < u(w + (X | &> - B~(Y | w, X» ie[l,n]

VoPH(,S | w, X) < RPs(X | w) would then also have become a strict

inequality.

Proof that VoPH(5" | w, X) = RPS(X | w) if S' is an uncertainty such that S is

deterministic given S', and vice versa:

In Theorem 5.5, we will show that for a general uncertainty S', VoPH(5" |

w, X) < RPS(X | w).

As for proving the reverse inequality, i.e. VoPH(5" | w, X) > RPs(X | w) if

5" is an uncertainty such that S is deterministic given 5" and vice versa, we

can simply notice that the deal Y which we defined by taking y; = (X | &)

- Xj in the first part of the proof also belongs to the set of uncertain deals

which have prospects which are solely determined by S' and which have a

mean of 0.

We already computed the PIBP for that deal Y as being equal to the

selling risk premium of X. Therefore, VoPH(S' | w, X) > B~(Y | w, X) =

RPS(X | w). J

Theorem 5.3 shows exactly what becomes of deal X once it is perfectly hedged based on

distinction S: to perfectly hedge X, we use a new deal Y which is defined as the exact

opposite of X, plus a constant equal to (X | &>. Adding Y to the current portfolio thus

137

Page 151: Value of Hedging

transforms every single one of its monetary prospects into (X | &), thus removing any

uncertainty from it.

As a result, the portfolio will gain RPs(X | w) in value because its risk, which was

initially captured by RPs(X | w), is now entirely compensated for by the addition of deal

Y. In light of that explanation, not only does Theorem 5.3 appear as remarkably simple in

its conclusions, but it also seems quite intuitive.

Example 5.4:

Here we will take another look at perfect hedging on the set S = {Oil Price,

Volume}. We have already naively computed the value of perfect hedging on S in

the previous example, by solving an optimization problem as we have always

done it so far; we will now compare that answer to the predictions of our theorem

on perfect hedging when S = S'.

The first clause of Theorem 5.3 announces that the perfect hedge should

transform the oil company's uncertain portfolio into a deterministic one, by

making all of its monetary prospects equal to $50.60 million, which is the mean of

the oil company's original portfolio. If we examine Figure V.4, we will see that it

is indeed the result we had reached when we naively computed the value of

perfect hedging on S.

Next, let us verify the second clause of the theorem; it states that the value of

perfect hedging on S should be equal to the risk premium of the original portfolio:

RPs(X | 0) = (X | &) - S~(X | 0)

= $50.60 M-$38.99 M

= $11.61M

The risk premium matches the value of perfect hedging on S we had computed in

the previous example: RPs(X | 0) = VoPH^ | X) is verified. H

138

Page 152: Value of Hedging

b) Irrelevance

We continue our investigation of the connection between value of perfect hedging and

relevance with the second case in our nomenclature - the case in which S and S' are

irrelevant given &:

Theorem 5.4- Value of Perfect Hedging on S' when S J. S' | &

For any set of state variables 5" which is irrelevant to S given &:

VoPH(S' | w, X) = 0. [5.6]

Furthermore, equality of B~(Y | w, X) and VoPH(5" | w, X) is achieved if and only if Y is

the deal which has all of its prospects set to be equal to 0.

Proof:

Proof that VoPH(S' | w, X) > 0:

We already proved in Property 5.1 that the value of perfect hedging is

non-negative for a risk-averse decision-maker.

Proof that VoPH(S' | w, X) < 0:

Let us now prove that VoPH^ | w, X) < 0. For that let us consider any

hedging deal Y whose outcomes are determined by S'. We will show that

we necessarily have B~(Y | w, X) < 0.

By definition of B~(Y | w, X):

£ P iu(w + X i)= X Pi Z qj i i u(w + x i + yj-B~<Y lw> x» ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

Exploiting the irrelevance between S and S':

^ piu(w + x i)= Z Pi Z qju(w + x i+y j-B^<Y|w,X»

ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

139

Page 153: Value of Hedging

We can now use the fact that the decision-maker is risk-averse to

transform the summation over index j on the right hand side:

X P iu(w + Xl)< X p1u(w + x1+(Y|si,&>-B~<Y|w,X» ie[l,n] is[l,n]

Due to the irrelevance of S and 5", (Y | Sj, &) = (Y | &) = 0 for all values of

i:

£ PiUCw + x,)^ X P iu(w + X i-B~<Y|w,X»

ie[l,n] ie[l,n]

We can finally conclude that B~(Y | w, X) < 0. Also, using the same series

of arguments as in the end of the proof of Theorem 5.3, we can notice that

the inequality VoPH^ | w, X) < 0 would have been strict for any choice of

Y other than the deal whose prospects yj were equal to zero for all values

ofj.D

This theorem shows that it is pointless to hope to hedge a portfolio X based on a set of

uncertainties S' which is probabilistically irrelevant to it: the acquisition of any deal Y

with a mean of zero and at least one non-zero payoff would then have no chance to

compensate for any of X's risk, and could only add to the overall level of risk of the

portfolio.

The theorem should also remind us of an analogous result, which we encountered when

we studied the properties of the value of hedging: we had seen that VoH(X | Y) = 0 if the

decision-maker's u-curve satisfies the delta property and if X and Y are irrelevant given

&. There is an important difference between the two theorems, though: the claims of the

first result were restricted to the delta case, whereas those of the one we just derived are

not.

140

Page 154: Value of Hedging

Example 5.5:

We return to our oil field hedging example, but this time, the oil company wishes

to hedge based on Copper Price. They believe Copper Price to be irrelevant to

both Oil Price and Volume given &. More specifically, they assign a probability

of 0.6 to a high copper price and a probability of 0.4 to a low copper price,

irrespective of the outcomes of Oil Price and Volume.

In order to compute the value of perfect hedging on Copper Price, we need to

solve the following maximization problem:

max S~<Y | X>

s.t. r Y's prospects are solely determined by the copper price uncertainty

1 (Y|&> = 0

The solution we obtain is the one we expected based on Theorem 5.4: it is

impossible to create a hedge Y with a mean of zero but a positive certain

equivalent. The best we can do is to set all of the monetary prospects of Y to zero,

which yields a certain equivalent of zero:

Vo?U(Copper Price | X) = 0. J

141

Page 155: Value of Hedging

c) Incomplete Relevance

When the decision-maker believes S and 5" to be relevant given &, but not completely,

the value of perfect hedging can be proved to be less than or equal to what it would have

been in the case of complete relevance, but higher than or equal to what it would have

been in the case of irrelevance:

Theorem 5.5 - Value of Perfect Hedging on S' in the General Case

For any set of state variables S\ 0 < VoPH^' | w, X) < RPS(X | w). [5.7]

Proof:

• Proof that VoPH(S' | w, X) > 0:

We can again refer to Property 5.1 to find the proof of that result.

• Proof that VoPH(S' | w, X) < RPS(X | w):

We will slightly adapt to the case of a general S' the second part of the

proof we wrote for Theorem 5.3.

Let us prove that VoPH(5" | w, X) < RPS(X | w). For that let us consider

any hedging deal Y whose outcomes are solely determined by S' and for

which (Y | &) = 0. We will show that we necessarily have B~(Y | w, X) <

PvPs(X | w).

Since the decision-maker is risk-averse, we have:

Z P. £ qjpu(w + x i + y j -B ~<Y|w,X»

ie[l,n] je[l,m]

< X piu(w + x i+(Y|s i,&) -B~<Y|w,X» ie[l.n]

Applying one more concavity inequality to the right hand side, we obtain:

142

Page 156: Value of Hedging

I Pi ^qi]iu(VJ + xi+yJ-B~(Y\w,X))

ie[l,n] M ' . m ]

<u(w + <X|&) + « Y | S i , & ) | & ) - B ~ ( Y | w , X »

Since «Y | si? &) | &) = <Y | &) = 0:

Z Pi Z qj|iu(w + x 1 +y J - B ~<Y|w,X»<u(w + <X|&> -B~<Y|w,X» ie[l,n] je[l,m]

Let us now recall the definition of ~(Y | w, X):

Z p iu(w + x i )= Z Pi Z q j i ^ w + X i + y j - ^ Y I w . X ) ) ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

If we combine this equation with the previous inequality, we find that:

Z p,u(w + x i)<u(w + <X|&> - B ~(Y |w,X» ie[l,n]

But the left-hand side of that inequality is also equal to u(w + (X | w)) by

definition of the PISP for deal X. Consequently, we have:

u(w + S~<X | w» < u(w + <X | &> - B~<Y | w, X))

u(w + (X | &) - RPS(X | w)) < u(w + (X | &) - B~(Y | w, X»

This in turn shows that B~(Y | w, X) < RPs(X | &). Since it is true for any

deal Y whose outcomes are solely determined by S' and for which (Y | &)

= 0, VoPH(S' | w, X) < RPS(X | w).

Finally, we should observe that our concavity inequalities and our final

inequality VoPH(5" | w, X) < RPS(X | w) all become strict when S and S'

are not completely relevant. 3

143

Page 157: Value of Hedging

Example 5.6:

In Example 5.1, we computed the value of perfect hedging on Gold Price, an

uncertainty which was believed by the firm to be relevant to the set S = {Oil Price,

Volume} given &, and yet not completely relevant to it.

We had then computed that:

V6PH(Gold Price | X) = $1.61 M

More recently, we established that:

VoPH(S|X) = R P s ( X | 0 )

= $11.61M

We can thus observe that the value of perfect hedging on gold price is indeed

comprised between zero and the risk premium of the original portfolio, as

predicted by Theorem 5.5. However, that value of perfect hedging is much lower

than the total risk premium of X. It is not surprising once we consider the

probabilistic structure of the problem, which is captured by the influence diagram

below:

Figure V.4- Gold Price is only relevant to the value through Oil Price

The probabilistic relevance between the Gold Price uncertainty and the original

portfolio X is entirely channeled through the set S = {Oil Price, Volume}, more

precisely through Oil Price, which is also the one of the two uncertainties in S on

which the value of perfect hedging is the lowest ($3.26 million). Therefore, it

144

Page 158: Value of Hedging

seems intuitive that there should be at most as much to be gained from perfect

hedging on Gold Price as there is to be gained from perfect hedging on Oil Price.

The next theorem expresses the same result in greater generality. D

145

Page 159: Value of Hedging

d) Relevance-Based Dominance of one Hedge over Another

Let us suppose that our decision-maker needs to choose to hedge based on only one of

two uncertainties, S' and S". Both S' and 5"' are incompletely relevant to S given &. Is

there any way to determine that the value of perfect hedging on one uncertainty will be

greater than the value of perfect hedging on the other, without explicitly computing those

two quantities? Or, to put it differently, can we exploit the relevance structure of a

decision situation in such a way as to infer that some value of perfect hedging will

necessarily dominate another?

The following theorem shows that it is possible indeed:

Theorem 5.6-

1fS"±S\S',

of perfect hed

- Value of Perfect Hedging on S" z/S"

&, then the value of perfect hedging

ging provided by S':

J.S\S\ &:

provided by

VoPH(S" | w, X) < VoPH(S' | w, X)

S" is

[5.8]

less than the value

Proof:

We know from Theorem 5.2 that for two sets of uncertainties S' and S", the joint

value of perfect hedging on S' and 5"' is greater than or equal to the higher of the two

individual values of perfect hedging on S' and S":

VoPH(S', S" | w, X) > max (VoPH(S' | w, X), VoPH(5" | w, X))

Here we will aim at proving that S" 1 S | S', & implies that VoPH(5", S" \w,X)<

VoPH(5" | w, X), because that result, combined with the inequality on the joint value

of perfect hedging stated above, would allow us to conclude that VoPH(5"' | w, X) <

VoPH(5'|w,X).

We will thus consider a deal Y whose prospects are solely determined by the

uncertainties S' and S", and such that (Y | &) = 0. If for any such deal Y, B~(Y | w, X)

146

Page 160: Value of Hedging

< VoPH(S' | w, X), then we will have proved that VoPH(S', S" | w, X) < VoPH(S' | w,

X), as desired.

By definition of B~(Y | w, X), it satisfies the following equation involving the

decision-maker's u-curve:

£ P iu(w+X i)= X Pi Z % Z rk|1 ,Ju(w + x i+yJ ,k-B~(Y lw,x», ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m] ke[l,l]

where qj|j denotes the conditional probability distribution over S' given S and &, and

rk|ij the conditional probability distribution over S" given S, S' and &. Since S" J_ S \

S\ &, rk|ij = rky, the equation above then simplifies into:

£ P iu(w + x,)= X Pi Z % Z rk|ju(w + x,+yJ,k-B~<Y|w,X»

ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m] ke[l,l]

Next, we decompose each one of the prospects y^ of deal Y as follows:

yj* = «j + pj,k,

where each a was defined as the conditional mean of Y given S' = s'j and &:

Oj = <Y | S" = s'j, &>

We substitute aj + Pjk for y^ in the definition of B~(Y | w, X) and obtain:

£ piu(w + x i)= Z Pi Z Ijli Z rkij^w + Xi+Oj+p^-^YIw.X) ) ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m] ks[l,l]

Since the decision-maker is risk-averse:

£ P iu(w + Xi)< S P, Z qj|lu(w + x i + a J + < p | y = s'j,&)-B~<Y|w,X» iefl.n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

Because of the way we defined the a's, the conditional mean of p given S' = s'j and &

is equal to 0:

£ PiUCw + x,)^ X P. Z qjpuCw + Xi+oij-^YIw.X))

ie[l,n] ie[l,n] je[l,m]

The inequality above implies that:

B~<Y | w, X) < B~<a | w, X)

147

Page 161: Value of Hedging

We can then remark that a is a deal whose mean is equal to 0, and whose prospects

are solely determined by 5"; therefore, the decision-maker's PIBP for that deal is less

than his value of perfect hedging on 5":

B~(Y | w, X) < B~(a | w, X) < VoPH(S' | w, X)

This proves that B~(Y | w, X> < VoPH(S' | w, X), as desired. 3

Theorem 5.6 is yet another result which highlights the strong resemblance between value

of perfect hedging and value of clairvoyance: for the value of clairvoyance as well, if a

decision-maker has a choice between free and perfect information on 5" and 5"' when S"

± S | S\ &, his preference should go to the perfect information on S'.

In more formal and more mathematical terms, we could say that the partial ordering of

uncertainties based on the conditional irrelevance of one of them with respect to S given

the other and & induces an equivalent partial ordering of the same uncertainties based on

the value of perfect hedging that they provide.

148

Page 162: Value of Hedging

Example 5.7:

Again we will refer to Example 5.1, and more specifically to the Gold Price

uncertainty: by its very definition, it is irrelevant to S= {Oil Price, Volume} given

Oil Price and &. This is also illustrated by Figure V.4.

By Theorem 5.6, the value of perfect hedging on Gold Price should thus be lower

than or equal to the value of perfect hedging on Oil Price. And indeed, we have:

Vo?U(Gold Price | X) = $1.61 M

VoPH(Oz7Price | X) = $3.26 M. •

149

Page 163: Value of Hedging

e) Summary - Impact of Relevance on the Value of Perfect Hedging

The following figure offers a qualitative graphical summary of the results we have just

derived on the impact of the relevance relationship between S and S' on the value of

perfect hedging:

RP, g(X | w)'

= PM o

>

Best hedging deal: y, = <X|&)-X i

S"±S\S',&

SIS' Dependence between S and S' S=S'

Figure V.5- Impact of the relevance between S and S' on VoPH^ \ X, w)

The diffuse area between the two extreme cases S 1 S' and S = S' should remind us that

in order to determine the exact value of perfect hedging when S and S' are relevant given

& but not identical, we first need to assess all the probability distributions and monetary

prospects involved; all we can be assured of prior to computing an exact value is that the

value of perfect hedging is comprised between zero and the selling risk premium of X.

150

Page 164: Value of Hedging

f) Influence of the U-Curve on the Choice of a Perfect Hedge

There is another remarkable observation that we can make based on Theorems 5.3, 5.4

and 5.5:

Property 5.2 - Perfect Hedging Strategies and U-Curves

The deals Y which allow us to achieve perfect hedging in the case of complete relevance

between S and 5" (Theorem 5.3) or complete irrelevance (Theorem 5.4) do not depend on

the decision-maker's u-curve.

In other words, only the value of perfect hedging depends on the decision-maker's u-

curve in those cases; his choice of a preferred hedging strategy does not. Very rarely do

we come across recommendations in a decision analysis which are so universal that they

would be equally valid for any decision-maker, regardless of his u-curve, so the event is

certainly worth remembering.

On the other hand, if there is incomplete relevance between S and S', then the selection of

a perfect hedge might be affected by the decision-maker's u-curve. Here is an example

which will demonstrate it.

Example 5.8:

We will study the behavior of the value of perfect hedging on Gold Price as a

function of the oil company's risk tolerance.

For the risk tolerance figure of $500 million which we have been using so far, we

already know what the perfect hedge and the value of perfect hedging are:

151

Page 165: Value of Hedging

YHigh Gold Price ~ $ 3 1 . 6 8 M

J YLow Gold Price = "$51 69 M

Vo?H(GoldPrice | X) = $1.61 M \-

We then repeat the analysis for two other values of the risk tolerance, one being

higher than the value we have used so far (p = $1 billion), and the other being

lower (p = $200 million). The results are shown in the next table, with the first

two rows indicating what the prospects of the best hedge are for each possible

value of the risk tolerance, and the last row indicating what the corresponding

value of perfect hedging is:

p = $200 M p = $500 M p = $1 B

$29.33 M

-$47.86 M

$3.38 M

$31.68 M

-$51.69 M

$1.61 M

$32.61 M

-$53.21 M

$0.86 M

Table V.l -Impact of the risk tolerance on the selection of a perfect hedge

We can thus remark that the decision-maker's risk attitude has an influence on his

choice of a perfect hedge on Gold Price. This is no surprise since

Also, in this example at least, it seems that the value of perfect hedging increases

with risk-aversion over the range of risk tolerance values we have considered. In

addition, we see here that a more risk-averse decision-maker will tend to select a

perfect hedge with a narrower spread between its monetary prospects. •

152

Page 166: Value of Hedging

4. General Upper Bound on the PIBP of an Uncertain Deal

We mentioned earlier, in Theorem 5.1, that the decision-maker's PIBP for any uncertain

deal whose monetary prospects are solely determined by a set of uncertainties S' will be

less than or equal to the sum of the mean of the deal and the value of perfect hedging on

5". Since we also proved that the value of perfect hedging on 5" is itself less than or equal

to the risk premium of the existing portfolio, we can conclude that:

Theorem 5.7 - Upper Bound on the PIBP for an Uncertain Deal

(Y | &) + RPs(X | w) gives us an easy to compute upper bound on the decision-maker's

PIBP for any deal Y.

Proof:

This is a direct consequence of combining Theorems 5.1 and 5.5. •

The result, which is similar to Theorem 3.4 except for the fact that it is valid beyond the

delta case, further demonstrates the importance to a decision-maker of knowing the value

of the risk premium of his existing portfolio.

As mentioned in our discussion of Theorem 3.4, what is particularly appealing about this

upper bound is that it relies on two quantities of which one, RPs(X | w), can be computed

ahead of time by the decision-maker, and the second, (Y | &), can be assessed without so

much as assessing the relevance relationship between the potential acquisition Y and the

existing portfolio. Indeed, in order to compute (Y | &), assessing a marginal probability

distribution over Y is enough; there is absolutely no need to elicit a conditional

probability distribution over Y given X from the decision-maker, which could be a

daunting task if the existing portfolio was complex.

153

Page 167: Value of Hedging

Example 5.9:

Let us suppose that one of the oilfields bordering the one that the oil company

presently owns is available for sale, at a price of $25 million.

The management of the company believes that since the two oilfields are adjacent,

there is some relevance between the volume of oil that they would be able to

extract from one and what they would be able to extract from the other. More

specifically, they believe that the two fields would connect to the same reservoir;

if the first location allows them to pump out a high volume of oil, it probably

means that the additional amount of oil that can be extracted from the second

location will be low, and vice versa.

However, at present the management are only comfortable assessing a marginal

probability distribution over the volume of oil for the second field, and they are

not ready yet to assess a conditional probability distribution over it given the

volume they will extract from the field they already own: they believe that they

would need to consult experts in the geology of the area before they can think

about such a distribution with clarity.

The next tree shows the distribution over profits for the second oilfield; naturally,

the company's beliefs as to oil prices are the same as in Example 5.1:

154

Page 168: Value of Hedging

High Price

0.4

-6

0.6

Low Price

High Volume

-6 0.2 ) 0.8 Low Volume

High Volume

$140 M

$30 M

$70 M

- -$40M

<Y|&> = $10M

Figure V.6- Distribution over profit for the second oilfield.

-0 0.2

i

0.8

Low Volume

Even though the company has not yet fully assessed the relevance that they

believe exists between this new opportunity Y and their existing portfolio X, we

can compute an upper bound on their PIBP for Y as:

B~(Y | X) < <Y | &> + RPS(X | 0)

< $10.00 M +$11.61 M

< $21.61 M

In this example, we can thus spare the company the cost and the trouble of having

to make any conditional probability assessments: the marginal distribution over

the profits generated by Y was enough to establish that to them, $25 million is too

high a price for that second oilfield. •

155

Page 169: Value of Hedging

5. Approximation of the Value of Perfect Hedging in the Delta Case

The upper bound on the value of perfect hedging which we just discussed has one flaw -

nothing guarantees that it will be tight. In fact, our earlier inspection of the effects of

relevance on hedging has taught us that the value of perfect hedging on 5" can only be

equal to the risk premium of the existing portfolio if S' is completely relevant to S given

&. If instead the relevance between S and S' is weak, we might suspect that the risk

premium of the existing portfolio might make for a poor approximation of the actual

value of perfect hedging.

And yet, we should also bear in mind that in order to compute the exact value of perfect

hedging on S', in the general case in which S' is relevant to S given & but not completely,

we need to solve the optimization problem

VoPH(S' | w, X) = max B~<Y | w, X),

Y s.t. <Y | &> = 0

Y determined by S'

which can be a challenging and computationally intensive task if the probabilistic

structure of the decision situation is complex.

Hence, it would be of considerable practical importance to have access to an

approximation of the value of perfect hedging whose accuracy, unlike that of the risk

premium upper bound we have already derived, would be assured at least as long as some

reasonable conditions are met. Fortunately, such an approximation exists if the decision­

maker's u-curve satisfies the delta property:

156

Page 170: Value of Hedging

Theorem 5.8 - Approximation for the Value of Perfect Hedging

For a risk-averse decision-maker who follows the delta property, B~(Y* | X) where Y is

defined such that y j = (X | &) - (X | S' = s'j, &) is an approximation of VoPH(5" ] X).

The approximation is an underestimate of the actual value of perfect hedging. Also, the

higher the square of the risk tolerance (p2) is compared to the variance of the deals

involved, the better the approximation will be.

Finally, it should be noted that the approximation happens to give an exact answer when

S and iS" are completely relevant or when S and S' are irrelevant given &; unlike the first

part of this theorem, that last result holds no matter what u-curve the decision-maker has.

Proof:

• Proof that y*j = (X | &> - (X | s'j, &) yields an approximation of VoPH(5" | X) in

the general case:

[4.2] reminded us that for small enough values of the risk-aversion

coefficient y, we should devote our best efforts to minimizing the variance

of the combined portfolio made of X and Y together before we focus on

optimizing any of the higher order moments of that portfolio. More

precisely, [4.2] stated that for a decision-maker who follows the delta

property, his certain equivalent for a deal Z can be approximated by:

s ~ ( Z | 0 ) » ( Z | & ) - i y v ( Z | & ) ,

as long as deal Z has a small enough variance compared to the square of

the decision-maker's risk tolerance:

V ( Z | & ) « ^ Y

Consequently, let us consider the problem of the minimization of the

variance of X and Y, where X is a deal whose prospects are determined by

157

Page 171: Value of Hedging

the outcomes of S and Y another deal whose prospects are determined on

the outcomes of S':

( V

Minv~(X,Y|&)=X Z p ^ x . + y j ) 2 - Z E p ^ x . + y j ) ie[l,n] je[l,m] V'6!1 '"] M1.1"]

s.t. <Y|&> = 0,

where we denoted by pij the joint probability {S = Sj, S' = s'j | &}. We can

first notice that the problem is equivalent to the following:

Min £ £ p u (x; +yj)2

y j = o

ie[l,n] je[l,m]

/ \ ^ Z SPM

je[l,m] Vie[l,n] J

In order to find the minimum, we can form the Lagrangian and set its

derivatives to 0 - for all values of k in [1, n], we have:

d

dyk Z IM*.^)2-*! IP,J

ie[l,n] je[l,m] je[l,m] V,ie[l,n] J

= 0

This leads to:

2 Z P u ^ + yJ-X Z Pu=0, ie[l,n] is[l,n]

and to the value of the monetary prospect yk:

Z Pux i _ _ ^ _ ie[l,n]

y k " 2 " S P i ie[l,n]

We can then find the value of X by substituting those values of the

prospects yk into our original constraint, (Y | &) = 0:

f \ ^ = 2 Z Z PiJxi

je[l,m] l^ietl.n] ,

It shows that X = 2 (X | &). Therefore, y k = (X | &) - (X | s'k, &) is indeed

the solution to our variance minimization problem.

158

Page 172: Value of Hedging

• Proof that B~< Y* | w, X) = VoPHCS' | X) when S and S' are completely relevant, or

when S15":

When S = S',(X\S'= s'j, &) = Xj, which yields y*j = (X | &) - XJ. This is

the same hedging deal as the one defined in Theorem 5.3 to achieve

perfect hedging if 5 and 5" are completely relevant.

When S1 S\ (X | S' = s'j, &) = (X | &), which yields y*j = 0. This is the

same hedging deal as the one defined in Theorem 5.4 to achieve perfect

hedging if S IS'.

The approximation is thus exact when S and 5" are completely relevant, or

when S and S' are irrelevant given &.

• Proof that the approximation always gives an underestimate of VoPH(5" | X):

One simply needs to notice that the deal Y we defined belongs to the set

of deals such that <Y | &) = 0. Therefore, by definition of VoPH(S' | X),

we have VoPH(S" | X) > B~(Y* | X). 3

159

Page 173: Value of Hedging

Example 5.10:

We will demonstrate how good the approximation is based on a simple example:

Sl

0.4

-o

0.6

S2

$100,000

$0

S'l

0.8

-0 0.2

S'l

S'l

0.3

-0 0.7

S 2

$yi

$y2

$yi

$y2

Figure V.7 -Accuracy of our value of perfect hedging approximation: an

example

A decision-maker currently owns deal X, which has a mean of $40,000. He is

considering acquiring a deal Y, whose monetary prospects are determined based

on the outcomes of a distinction iS" which is relevant, but not identical, to the S

distinction.

The decision-maker is interested in knowing which choice of deal Y, among all

possible deals that have 0 as their mean, constitutes the best match for his current

portfolio X - more specifically, which deal Y provides the highest PIBP B~(Y | X).

Before we look for the exact answer to that question, let us consider the

approximation we would obtain based on Theorem 5.8. It would require building

160

Page 174: Value of Hedging

a hedging deal Y* such that y*j = (X | &} - (X | S' = s'j, &); we can compute those

two prospects as being y \ = -$24,000 and y 2 = $24,000 respectively.

Let us now numerically solve the problem of selecting the best possible

complement Y to the current portfolio X for different values of y. For that, let us

first notice that Y is fully specified by the choice of yi; indeed, since we want (Y |

&) to be equal to zero, any choice of yi imposes that we choose -yi as y2.

The curves on the following figure show B~(Y | w, X) as a function of yi, for six

different values of the risk-aversion coefficient y. The large dots mark the value of

yi for which the maximum value of B~( Y | w, X) is attained, again for each of the

six values of y. Several insights can be derived from a careful examination of this

figure:

• As noted earlier, Property 5.2 does not stand any longer once we consider

cases in which we have neither complete relevance or irrelevance between S'

and S: the selection of a best hedging deal Y does depend on risk attitude

apart from those extreme cases. For example, B~(Y | X) is maximized for yi ~

-$23,500 when y = 0.001, and for y, = -$20,500 when y = 0.01.

161

Page 175: Value of Hedging

$4,000

$3,000

$2,000

$1,000

$0

-$1,000

-$2,000

-$3,000

-$4,000

-$5,000

-$6,000

k^jm^

^ Value of y given by approximation

$50 -$46 --442 -$38 -254 -$30 -$261 -$22 -$18 -$14 -$>6 -$6 -$2

I 'v=0.01

y=0.02

yi $ Thousand)

Figure V.8- Influence of risk-aversion on the accuracy of the approximation

The approximation suggested in Theorem 5.8, as predicted, seems to yield

more accurate results for low values of y; this is potentially problematic, in

a sense, because on the other hand, hedging will not be as valuable an

alternative to someone whose risk attitude is close to risk-neutral.

That being said, the approximation appears to be quite reliable for values

of y up to 0.02, as shown by the following figure:

162

Page 176: Value of Hedging

0.001 0.005 0.01 0.02

$4,000

$2,000

$0

-$2,000

-$4,000

-$6,000

-$8,000

-$10,000

-$12,000

-$14,000

Figure V.9 - Influence of risk-aversion on the accuracy of the approximation (2)

i VoPH Estimated Using Our Approximation

I Actual VoPH

Why does the accuracy of the approximation break down as risk-aversion

increases? Consider the hedging deal Y suggested by Theorem 5.8;

incorporating it into the decision-maker's portfolio will have two effects:

o It does provide value by reducing the variance of the combined portfolio

of deals X and Y to its minimum.

o It also increases the size of the range of prospects the decision-maker will

be facing, and as a result it has a detrimental impact on some of the higher

order moments of the portfolio (such as decreasing the third central

moment).

The first effect is desirable from the point of view of a risk-averse decision­

maker, whereas the second is a negative side effect from hedging with the

variance-minimizing deal Y ; for higher values of y, risk-averse decision­

makers will grow increasingly concerned about the second effect.

163

Page 177: Value of Hedging

However, a natural solution exists in order to somewhat immunize oneself

against that second effect - it consists in choosing a lower value of yi than the

one suggested by Theorem 5.8. By doing so, a decision-maker renounces to

part of the benefits of the variance reduction effect, while curbing the negative

impact of the second effect more drastically. On the whole, this can turn out to

be a wiser decision than blindly choosing deal Y as defined in Theorem 5.8.

This explains why, on Figure 5.8, the value of yi for which the value of

perfect hedging is achieved increases with y.

• VoPH(5" | X), which we already knew to be equal to 0 for risk-neutral

decision-makers, is also equal to 0 for extremely risk-averse decision-makers.

The value of perfect hedging also seems to reach a maximum for some

specific value of y. In our example, that maximum is reached for y ~ 0.02. For

that value of y, the optimal choice of yi is yi ~ -$16,000, and the value of

perfect hedging is roughly equal to $2,650. •

The PIBP for the deal Y which minimizes the variance of the portfolio gives us, at best,

an accurate approximation of the value of perfect hedging, and at worst, an underestimate

for it. We can thus use that PIBP in conjunction with the risk premium of the original

portfolio, and thereby gain access to both an upper and a lower bound on the value of

perfect hedging. The next example will illustrate that approach.

164

Page 178: Value of Hedging

Example 5.11:

We return to our Gold Price hedging example; to make matters more interesting

we will consider that the oil company's risk tolerance is equal to $150 million

(instead of the $500 million from Example 5.1), so that the approximation from

Theorem 5.8 is not quite as robust as it could be otherwise.

We first need to compute the values of the monetary prospects which will help

minimize the variance of the decision-maker's portfolio; Theorem 5.8 tells us

that:

f y*Low Gold Price = (X | &> - (X | Low Gold Price, &)

L y*High Gold Price = <X | &> - <X | High Gold Price, &)

Therefore:

f y*Low Gold Price = $50.60 M - $17.00 M = $33.6 M

\ y*High Gold Price = $50.60 M - $105.42 M = -$54.82 M

We can then compute the PIBP for deal Y as we defined it:

B~(Y* | X) = $3.99 M

Next, we compute the risk premium of the existing portfolio:

RPs(X | 0 ) = $32.09 M

From that we can infer that the value of perfect hedging on Gold Price is

comprised between $3.99 million and $32.09 million. The exact value of perfect

hedging is equal to $4.15 million, which is much closer to the lower bound than to

the upper bound of our interval, since even with a risk tolerance of $150 million,

the oil company is not risk-averse enough for the approximation from Theorem

5.8 to lead to very inaccurate conclusions. •

165

Page 179: Value of Hedging

6. Similarities between Value of Perfect Hedging and Value of

Clairvoyance

As a summary of our study of the value of perfect hedging and its properties, I will

enumerate the similarities it shares with one of the best known and most useful concepts

of traditional decision analysis: the value of clairvoyance.

The following table presents some of the most striking resemblances; all of them are

supported by various theorems and examples shown throughout this chapter. The last row

of the table, which discusses the impact of risk attitude on the value of clairvoyance and

on the value of perfect hedging, should remind us that in disciplines such as probability

or decision analysis, many of the conjectures which might initially to our intuition as

tempting to believe in are in fact often wrong.

There is an important difference between the properties of the value of information and

those of the value of perfect hedging - in a decision situation, the value of information on

some uncertainty is positive if and only if the decision-maker's preferred alternative

changes for at least one possible report on the value of the uncertainty. Conversely, the

value of perfect hedging on an uncertainty can be positive even if the best alternative

remains the same with or without hedging. The examples we have discussed throughout

this chapter demonstrates this well: the value of perfect hedging was positive even though

the availability of hedging did not modify the decision-maker's choices in any way;

hedging only made his portfolio more valuable in his eyes by limiting its risk.

166

Page 180: Value of Hedging

Definition

Sign

Usefulness

Joint value of

clairvoyance

or of perfect

hedging

Impact of

relevance

Impact of

risk attitude

VALUE OF CLAIRVOYANCE ON S' VALUE OF PERFECT HEDGING ON S'

The most we should be willing to pay

for the clairvoyant's services.

>0

1) Provides an upper bound on the

value of any experiment

2) Helps prioritize uncertainties

based on how valuable it is to

gather additional information on

them

VoCOS", S") > max (VoC(S"),

VoC(S"))

No general rule between joint VoC

and sum of individual VoCs

= 0ifS'±S\&

Increases with relevance otherwise in

the sense that S" 1S | S', & =>

VoC(5") < VoC(S"), until it reaches

VoC on S when S' = 5

Consider two risk-averse decision­

makers who each own a deal X in

which they believe they face the exact

same chances of the same prospects;

then, it is not necessarily true that the

most risk-averse person of the two

will be willing to pay more for

clairvoyance on 5".

The most we should be willing to pay

for a deal whose prospects are

determined solely by 5 ' and whose

mean is equal to 0.

>0

1) Provides an upper bound on our

PIBP for any deal we do not own

2) Helps prioritize uncertainties

based on how valuable it is to

hedge on them

VoPH(5", 5") > max (VoPH(5"),

VoPH(5"))

No general rule between joint VoPH

and sum of individual VoPHs

= 0 i f S " ± S | &

Increases with relevance otherwise in

the sense that S" 1S | S', & =>

VoPH(5" | w, X) < VoPH(5' | w, X),

until it reaches RPs(X w) when S' =

S

Consider two risk-averse decision­

makers who each own a deal X in

which they believe they face the exact

same chances of the same prospects;

then, it is not necessarily true that the

most risk-averse person of the two

will be willing to pay more for perfect

hedging on S'.

Table V.2 - Comparison of value of clairvoyance and value of perfect hedging

167

Page 181: Value of Hedging

7. The Value of Perfect Hedging as a New Appraisal Tool

Of all the steps of the decision analysis cycle, the appraisal phase is probably, with the

formulation phase, the step in which the decision analyst has the most freedom in

choosing how to conduct the process. As a result, it is in the appraisal phase that some of

the analyst's choices will most significantly affect the quality of his final

recommendation to the decision-maker.

What we will advocate in this part of the dissertation is that one more tool be added to

that critical part of the decision analysis cycle - the calculation of the value of perfect

hedging. Just as the value of clairvoyance will help the decision-maker focus his

information gathering activities in the next iteration of the cycle on the uncertainties

which matter the most, the value of perfect hedging will help him decide whether he

should pursue any hedging opportunities, and if so, which uncertainties he should seek to

hedge on.

Formulation Evaluation Appraisal

c . . . Deterministic . Probabilistic . , Structure • , . • , . • Appraisal p. ngpjeJQri

t Analysis Analysis

• Sensitivity analysis • Value of information • Value of control • Value of perfect hedging

Figure V.10 - The value of perfect hedging in the decision analysis cycle

168

Page 182: Value of Hedging

In some cases, the availability of hedging can greatly affect the final recommendation of

an analysis by causing a reversal in the preference order between two alternatives.

Generally speaking, hedging is most likely to have such an effect in situations in which

the decision-maker's risk-aversion prevents him from selecting the alternative with the

highest mean, A, and forces him to settle for an alternative B with a lower mean, but a

narrower risk profile and a higher certain equivalent overall. Perfect hedging might then

enable the decision-maker to redeem more of the risk premium of A than of the risk

premium of B, to the extent that he may eventually prefer A to B.

In that respect, the concept of the value of perfect hedging fills the same need as what is

sometimes called risk-sharing in the decision analysis literature: if an uncertain deal has a

positive mean, but the decision-maker's certain equivalent for it is negative because of

the risk the deal carries, a possible alternative consists in bringing in another individual

and possible investor in this deal, who assigns the same probabilities as the first

individual to the monetary prospects of the deal; we then split the uncertain deal between

the two of them by giving a fraction f of every prospect to the first investor, and a

fraction 1 - f to the other. If the second decision-maker's risk tolerance is sufficiently

high, it will be possible to find a value of f such that both decision-makers have a positive

certain equivalent for the portion of the deal that they are left with.

Example 5.12:

The following example shows the impact that the value of perfect hedging can

have on the final recommendation of a decision analysis.

Several years ago, Zeta, a small biotechnology company, launched a drug for the

treatment of Parkinson's disease called Nemesis. A small study conducted in a

European university was recently published, showing that the compound might

have a neuroprotective quality which no one had suspected up to that point. Zeta's

management would like to convince the Food and Drug Administration (FDA) of

granting them an official neuroprotection claim on the label of Nemesis: if they

succeed, Nemesis will become the first drug with such a claim, and its

profitability will be greatly enhanced. Unfortunately, Zeta's board believes that

169

Page 183: Value of Hedging

the data from the European study would be insufficient to convince the FDA, due

to the small scale of the experiment; Zeta is thus considering funding a phase IV

study, with the hope that it will provide enough evidence to persuade the FDA.

Endpoint 1

Phase IV Study

0.1

Endpoint 2

CE: -$4 M Mean: $286M

0.3

Endpoint 3

•0 0.6

No Phase IV Study

Neuroprotection

0 0.6

0.4

No Neuroprotection

Neuroprotection

0.15

0.85

No Neuroprotection

Neuroprotection

0 0.05

0.95 No Neuroprotection

$3.4 B

-$200 M

$3.4 B

-$200 M

$3.4 B

-$200 M

$0

Figure V.ll — Example for the use of perfect hedging as an appraisal tool

The figure above captures the most important elements of Zeta's decision

situation. The company's board also states that they wish to follow the delta

property for the range of prospects involved, with a risk tolerance of $1.5 billion.

We observe that at present, the best decision for Zeta is to renounce to the phase

IV study: conducting the study yields a negative certain equivalent of -$4 million.

170

Page 184: Value of Hedging

However, we can also notice that the mean of the alternative is $286 million,

which implies that the only reason why it is not the best course of action is that it

currently involves too much risk for the company's taste. That remark should

prompt us to investigate the effect of the value of perfect hedging on the final

recommendation.

When asked about possible hedges, the company's board states that it might be

possible to hedge based on whether or not any drug at all will receive the FDA's

approval for a neuroprotection claim before 2010. Concretely, this could take the

form of an insurance contract. We will denote this uncertainty by NP < 2010.

Naturally, if Nemesis itself were to conduct a phase IV study and receive the

FDA's approval, then NP < 2010 would automatically be true; on the other hand,

if Nemesis were to be denied the claim, the board would assign a 20% chance to

NP < 2010, and an 80% chance to No NP < 2010.

We can then compute VoPH(JVP < 2010 | X): in doing so, we identify as the

perfect hedge on that uncertainty a deal which associates a loss of $528 million to

NP < 2010, and a profit of $235 million to No NP < 2010. The corresponding

value of perfect hedging for the Phase IV Study alternative is:

VoPH(JVP < 2010 | X) = $39 million

Hence, we can conclude that perfect hedging on NP < 2010 is indeed susceptible

of altering the final recommendation in favor of performing a phase IV study.

With perfect hedging, the certain equivalent of the study increases to $35 million.

We can also note that in order to obtain the same certain equivalent of $35 million

for the basic decision situation of Figure V.l 1, in the absence of any hedging, the

company would have needed to have a risk tolerance of about $1.95 billion

instead of $1.5 billion. In a sense, perfect hedging on NP < 2010 can thus be said

to be equivalent to a $450 million increase in the company's risk tolerance for the

purposes of this decision. •

171

Page 185: Value of Hedging

Chapter 6 - Conclusions & Future Work

"It was our use of probability theory as logic that has enabled us to do

so easily what was impossible for those who thought of probability as a

physical phenomenon associated with 'randomness'. Quite the

opposite; we have thought of probability distributions as carriers of

information. At the same time, under the protection of Cox's theorems,

we have avoided the inconsistencies and absurdities which are

generated inevitably by those who try to deal with the problems of

scientific inference by inventing ad hoc devices instead of applying the

rules of probability theory. "

Edwin Thompson Jaynes (1922-1998),

Probability Theory: the Logic of Science

1. Contributions

Over the course of this dissertation, I have argued in favor of adding a study of possible

hedging alternatives to the appraisal phase of the decision analysis cycle. We have

observed on many examples that like additional information, hedging can be of

considerable value to a decision-maker.

I have also shown how a decision analysis of hedging can be conducted in practice. The

concept of the value of perfect hedging helps us identify the uncertainties on which it is

most valuable to seek hedging; it should act as our compass when we do not know where

to start and which uncertainties to hedge on. As for situations in which the decision­

maker needs to choose from an already established shortlist of available hedging

alternatives, we have learnt to compute or approximate the value of hedging which an

uncertain deal provides with respect to the existing portfolio. That value of hedging then

172

Page 186: Value of Hedging

helps us determine the decision-maker's personal indifferent buying price for the

uncertain deal in question.

In this dissertation, we have also proposed a new definition of hedging: we have spoken

of hedging in situations in which the decision-maker's valuation of a deal differs

depending on whether he owns his present wealth w and his current portfolio X, or his

present wealth w augmented by his certain equivalent for X. This new definition has the

merit of being broad enough that it does not restrict our characterization of hedging to the

use of financial derivatives, and yet precise enough for it to pass the clarity test.

In addition, we have covered the topic of the probabilistic origins of hedging and shown

that hedging boils down to moment reengineering. It is probable that our findings on that

front are further removed from the practical concerns of most decision-makers than are

some of the other concepts we discussed, such as the value of perfect hedging; still,

knowledge of the probabilistic origins of hedging might appear as quite useful to a

practicing decision analyst, whose profession requires that he should always be keen on

learning new ways of identifying valuable alternatives for his client.

We have thus addressed all the research questions which I had originally listed in the first

chapter and which I proposed to examine.

173

Page 187: Value of Hedging

2. Limitations

The research presented in this thesis has an important fundamental limitation: in all of our

findings and illustrative examples, we have only considered situations in which the

decision-maker's preferences could be expressed in monetary units. We should bear in

mind that there are decision situations in which it is not natural to do so - most notably in

medical settings, and more infrequently in engineering settings. But those are perhaps

also the decision situations in which it is hardest to think of alternatives which would

provide hedging with respect to the decision-maker's current situation. It thus remains a

relatively modest weakness of this research that its scope is limited to uncertain deals

whose prospects can be evaluated with a monetary measure.

A second limitation of the thesis is that in spite of our efforts to study hedging in its

largest generality, there is one situation which we have not explicitly addressed:

occasionally, hedging can have side effects. By that I mean that it can entail

consequences for the decision-maker which the monetary prospects of the existing

portfolio and of the hedging deal would not suffice to explain.

Some of the best examples can be found in the gold-mining industry, where some

companies are proud to announce that they do not hedge their gold production at all.

There are several reasons for their behavior. The first is that many of those mining

companies appear to be convinced that there is a tremendous upside to gold prices in the

current economic environment, and that hedging might lead them to agree to prices which

would be inferior to the actual future price of gold. The second argument which gold

companies offer to explain why they do not hedge is more atypical: they believe that

many of the shareholders who invest in their company do in fact desire to be exposed to

evolution of the price of gold1, be it because those investors also believe that there is a

great upside to gold prices, or because they regard gold as a safe haven in the event of a

major economic crisis. In either case, gold-mining companies believe that if they began

to hedge their gold positions, their stock would lose some of its appeal to shareholders.

1 See for example a 2006 interview of Peter Marrone, CEO of Yamana Gold, by Bill Mann:

http://www.fool.com,/investing/small-cap/2006/09/13/a-brazilian-gold-mine.aspx

174

Page 188: Value of Hedging

It would be fascinating to see whether the same argument, when applied to other

industries than gold-mining, can work in the opposite direction, that is, in favor of

hedging. Perhaps some companies attach a greater value to hedging practices than our

concept of the value of hedging would detect, because they believe that by hedging, they

also make their stock more attractive to certain kinds of shareholders.

While it is true that I have not explicitly addressed issues of side effects to hedging in the

dissertation, we should also realize that we only need to make a few modifications to the

framework we have proposed before it can lend itself to the successful study of those

situations as well. Those adjustments are best illustrated by an influence diagram such as

the one below; it captures the sort of dilemma which a gold-mining company might face,

if it believes that there would be a negative side effect attached to hedging:

Figure VI. 1 - Hedging with negative side effects

If we compare the influence diagram above with the general influence diagram for

hedging which we presented in Figure II.6, we can see that there is only one important

difference: we added a new uncertainty, Loss of Safe Haven Status, and a new path

leading through it from the decision to buy the hedge to the value node. The result is an

influence diagram with a richer and more complex probabilistic structure, but with the

same overall philosophy as the diagram from Figure II.6. We can then use this

175

Page 189: Value of Hedging

representation of the decision situation to determine the gold-mining company's PIBP for

the hedge as the price at which they would just be indifferent between buying the hedge

and not buying it.

176

Page 190: Value of Hedging

3. Directions for Future Work

The two limitations of the thesis which we mentioned can also be envisaged as promising

research opportunities.

We have already given a few hints as to how our hedging framework can be adapted to

the study of situations in which hedging has side effects, but we have not yet discussed

any possible solutions to the framework's inadequacy to cope with instances in which

preferences are not captured by a monetary value measure.

In that respect, the similarities we have so often detected between value of information

and value of hedging can give us an idea which might be worth investigating. Just like

the value of hedging, the value of information can only be computed if the prospects are

measured in monetary units; however, a related concept, called "probability of knowing"

or "equivalent probability of clairvoyance" [Howard, R. A.], can help us reason on the

merits of an information gathering scheme in the absence of a monetary value measure.

The equivalent probability of clairvoyance is defined as the probability p such that the

decision maker would be just indifferent between using the information gathering scheme

in question, and receiving either full clairvoyance on his decision situation with

probability/' or no additional information at all with probability l—p:

Receive full clairvoyance

Information gathering ^ ^ ^ 6 scheme

1 - P Receive no further information

Figure VI.2 — Equivalent probability of clairvoyance

111

Page 191: Value of Hedging

It is then possible to sort information gathering schemes from most valuable to least

valuable by comparing their respective equivalent probabilities of clairvoyance. Perhaps

it is possible to accomplish the same thing for hedging alternatives, by defining a concept

of equivalent probability of hedging.

I would finally like to suggest the search for additional evaluation methods, for the value

of hedging as well as for the value of perfect hedging, as a third direction for future work

on hedging. We have often remarked throughout this dissertation that the computation of

those quantities can be an intensive task, which is why we have so frequently stressed the

significance of the approximations and bounds we were able to derive. However, it is

probable that we can do much more to complete our arsenal of hedging valuation

techniques. For cases in which the decision-maker's u-curve satisfies the delta property,

we have just laid out the foundations of an irrelevance-based algebra for the value of

hedging, and it might be worthwhile to look for further results in that direction. But it is

the situations in which the decision maker's u-curve does not satisfy the delta property

that we are least equipped to handle: only a small number of the approximations and

bounds we have identified are valid in that case, and it would be of great practical use to

have access to a few more results for at least the most commonly used u-functions, such

as the logarithmic and power u-curves.

178

Page 192: Value of Hedging

List of References

Probability, Bavesian Methods and Decision Analysis:

[1.1] Abbas, A. E., 2003, Entropy Methods in Decision Analysis, dissertation submitted

to the department of Management Science & Engineering of Stanford University.

[1.2] Bayes, T., 1763, "An Essay Towards Solving a Problem in the Doctrine of

Chances", Biometrika, 45, 1958, pp. 293-315. Reprinted from Philosophical

Transactions of the Royal Society, 53, pp. 370-418.

[1.3] Bickel, E. J., 1999, The Corporate Contractual System and Normative Corporate

Risk Attitude, dissertation submitted to the department of Engineering Economic

Systems and Operations Research of Stanford University.

[1.4] Cover, T. M., and Thomas, J. A., 1991, Elements of Information Theory, Wiley,

New York.

[1.5] Cox, R. T., 1946, "Probability, Frequency and Reasonable Expectation",

American Journal of Physics, 14:1-13.

[ 1.6] De Finetti, B., 1970, Theory (/Probability, Wiley, New York.

[1.7] Fishburn, P. C , 1964, Decision and Value Theory, Publications in Operations

Research No. 10, Wiley, New York.

[1.8] Fishburn, P. C , 1981, "Subjective Expected Utility: a Review of Normative

Theories", Theory and Decision, 13:139-199.

[1.9] Howard, R. A., 1964, "The Science of Decision-making", Readings on the

Principles and Applications of Decision Analysis, Vol. 1, R. A. Howard and J. E.

Matheson (eds.), Strategic Decisions Group, Menlo Park, California, 1984, pp.

159-176.

179

Page 193: Value of Hedging

[1.10] Howard, R. A., 1965, "Bayesian Decision Models for Systems Engineering",

IEEE Transactions on Systems Science and Cybernetics, SSC-1:1, pp. 36-40.

[1.11] Howard, R. A., 1966a, "Decision Analysis: Applied Decision Theory",

Proceedings of the Fourth International Conference on Operational Research, D.

B. Hertz and J. Melese (eds.), Wiley-Interscience, New York, pp. 55-71.

[1.12] Howard, R. A., 1966b, "Information Value Theory", IEEE Transactions on

Systems Science and Cybernetics, SSC-2:1, pp. 22-26.

[1.13] Howard, R. A., 1968, "The Foundations of Decision Analysis", IEEE

Transactions on Systems Science and Cybernetics, SSC-4:3, pp. 211-219.

[1.14] Howard, R. A., 1970, "Decision Analysis: Perspectives on Inference, Decision

and Experimentation", Readings on the Principles and Applications of Decision

Analysis, Vol. 2, R. A. Howard and J. E. Matheson (eds.), Strategic Decisions

Group, Menlo Park, California, 1984, pp. 821-834.

[1.15] Howard, R. A., 1971, "Proximal Decision Analysis", Management Science,

Theory, Vol. 17 (May 1971), No. 9, pp. 507-541.

[1.16] Howard, R. A., 1980, "On Making Life and Death Decisions", Readings on the

Principles and Applications of Decision Analysis, Vol. 2, R. A. Howard and J. E.

Matheson (eds.), Strategic Decisions Group, Menlo Park, California, 1984, pp.

483-506.

[1.17] Howard, R. A., 1988, "Decision Analysis: Practice and Promise", Management

Science, 34:6, pp. 679-695.

[1.18] Howard, R. A., 1992, "In Praise of the Old Time Religion", Utility Theories:

Measurements and Applications, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Norwell,

Massachusetts, pp. 27-55.

[1.19] Howard, R. A., 1998, The Fundamentals of Decision Analysis, manuscript in

progress, unpublished.

[1.20] Howard, R. A., 2004, "Speaking of decisions: Precise decision language",

Decision Analysis, 1(2), pp. 71-78.

180

Page 194: Value of Hedging

[1.21] Howard, R. A., and Matheson, J. E., 1981, "Influence Diagrams", Readings on the

Principles and Applications of Decision Analysis, Vol. 2, R. A. Howard and J. E.

Matheson (eds.), Strategic Decisions Group, Menlo Park, California, 1984, pp.

719-762.

[1.22] Jaynes, E. T., 1976, "Confidence Intervals vs. Bayesian Intervals", Foundations

of Probability Theory, Statistical Inference, and Statistical Theories of Science, W.

L. Harper and C. A. Hooker (eds.), D. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 175.

[1.23] Jaynes, E. T., 2003, "Probability Theory: the Logic of Science", Cambridge

University Press, England.

[1.24] Jeffreys, H., 2003, "Theory of Probability", Oxford University Press, England.

[1.25] Keeney, R. L., 1982, "Decision Analysis: an Overview", Operations Research,

Vol. 30, pp. 803-838.

[1.26] Keeney, R. L., and Raiffa, H., 1976, Decisions with Multiple Objectives:

Preferences and Value Trade-Offs, Wiley, New York.

[1.27] Lowell, D. G., 1994, Sensitivity to Relevance in Decision Analysis, dissertation

submitted to the department of Engineering Economic Systems of Stanford

University.

[1.28] Matheson, D., and Matheson, J. E., 1998, The Smart Organization: Creating

Value Through Strategic R&D, Harvard Business School Press, Massachusetts.

[1.29] Matheson, J. E., 1983, "Managing the Corporate Business Portfolio", Readings on

the Principles and Applications of Decision Analysis, Vol. 1, R. A. Howard and J.

E. Matheson (eds.), Strategic Decisions Group, Menlo Park, California, 1984, pp.

719-762.

[1.30] Matheson, J. E., 1990, "Using Influence Diagrams to Value Information and

Control", Influence Diagrams, Belief Nets and Decision Analysis, R. M. Olivier

and J. Q. Smith, eds., proceedings of the conference entitled "Influence Diagrams

181

Page 195: Value of Hedging

for Decision Analysis, Inference, and Prediction", Berkeley, California, May 9-11,

Wiley, Chichester, England, pp. 427-455.

[1.31] Matheson, J.E., and Howard, R. A., 1968, "An Introduction to Decision Analysis",

Readings on the Principles and Applications of Decision Analysis, Vol. 1, R. A.

Howard and J. E. Matheson (eds.), Strategic Decisions Group, Menlo Park,

California, 1984, pp. 17-55.

[1.32] McNamee, P., and Celona, J., 1987, Decision Analysis for the Professional,

Scientific Press, Redwood City, California.

[1.33] McNamee, P., and Celona, J., 1990, Decision Analysis with Supertree, Scientific

Press, Redwood City, California.

[1.34] Owens, D. L., 1978, "The Use of Influence Diagrams in Structuring Complex

Decision Problems", Readings on the Principles and Applications of Decision

Analysis, Vol. 2, R. A. Howard and J. E. Matheson (eds.), Strategic Decisions

Group, Menlo Park, California, 1984, pp. 763-771.

[1.35] Pearl, J., 1988, Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems, Morgan Kaufmann,

San Mateo, California.

[1.36] Pratt, J. W., 1964, "Risk-aversion in the Small and in the Large", Econometrica,

32, pp. 122-136.

[1.37] Pratt, J. W., Raiffa, H., and Schlaifer, R., 1964, "The Foundations of Decision

under Uncertainty: an Elementary Exposition", Journal of the American

Statistical Association, Vol. 59, pp. 353-375.

[1.38] Raiffa, H., 1968, Decision Analysis: Introductory Lectures on Choice under

Uncertainty, Addison-Wesley, Reading, Massachusetts.

[1.39] Savage, L. J., 1951, The Theory of Statistical Decision, Journal of the American

Statistical Association, 46:55-67.

[1.40] Savage, L. J., 1954, The Foundations of Statistics, Wiley, New York.

182

Page 196: Value of Hedging

[1.41] Shachter, R. D., 1986, Evaluating Influence Diagrams, Operations Research, 34

(Nov.-Dec. 1986), pp. 871-882.

[1.42] Shachter, R. D., 1988, Probabilistic Inference and Influence Diagrams,

Operations Research, 36 (July-Aug. 1988), pp. 589-605.

[1.43] Shachter, R. D., 1997, Examples without Numbers, unpublished manuscript.

[1.44] Spetzler, C. S., and Stael von Holstein, A. S., 1975, "Probability Encoding in

Decision Analysis", Management Science, Vol. 22, No. 3 (Nov., 1975), pp. 340-

358.

[1.45] Tribus, M. T., 1969, Rational Descriptions, Decisions and Designs, Pergamon

Press Inc., Maxwell House Fairview Park Elmsford, New York.

[1.46] Tversky, A., and Kahneman, D., 1974, "Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics

and Biases", Science, New Series, Vol. 185, No. 4157 (Sept. 27, 1974), pp. 1124-

1131.

[1.47] Tversky, A., and Kahneman, D., 1983, "Extensional vs. Intuitive Reasoning: the

Conjunction Fallacy in Probability Judgment", Psychological Review, 91, pp.

293-315.

[1.48] Von Neumann, J., and Morgenstern, O., 1947, Theory of Games and Economic

Behavior, Princeton University, Princeton, New Jersey.

183

Page 197: Value of Hedging

Finance and Hedging:

[2.1] American Heritage® Dictionary of the English Language, Fourth Edition.

Houghton Mifflin Company, 2004.

[2.2] Black, F., 1989, "Equilibrium exchange rate hedging", Journal of Finance, 43, pp.

899-908.

[2.3] Black, F. and Scholes, M., 1973, "The Pricing of Options and Corporate

Liabilities", Journal of Political Economy, 81 (1973), pp. 163-175.

[2.4] Boyle, P. P., and Emanuel, D., 1980, "Discretely Adjusted Option Hedges", J.

Financial Economics, 8 (1980), pp. 259-282.

[2.5] Brandt, K., "An Answer to Climate Change - Weather Hedging for Everybody",

available online: http://www.weathereconomy.com/Weather%20Hedging.pdf.

[2.6] Brown, S. L., 1985, "A Reformulation of the Portfolio Model of Hedging",

American Journal of Agricultural Economics, Vol. 67, No. 3 (Aug. 1985), pp.

508-512.

[2.7] Carr, P., Geman, H., Madan, D., and Yor, M., 2005, "Pricing Options on Realized

Variance", Finance andStochastics, pp. 453-475.

[2.8] Castelino, M. G., 1992, "Hedge Effectiveness: Basis Risk and Minimum-Variance

Hedging", Journal of Futures Markets, 12 (April 1992), pp. 187-201.

[2.9] Cvitanic, J., Schachermayer, W., and Wang, H., 2001, "Utility Maximization in

Incomplete Markets with Random Endowment", Finance and Stochastics, 5(2),

pp.259-272.

[2.10] Davis, M. H. A., Panas, V. G., and Zariphopoulou, T., 1993, "European Option

Pricing with Transaction Costs", SI AM Journal of Control and Optimization, 31

(1993) (2), pp. 470-493.

[2.11] Delbaen, F., Grandits, P., Rheinlander, T., Samperi, D., Schweizer, M., and

Strieker, C , 2002, "Exponential Hedging and Entropic Penalties", Mathematical

Finance, 12(2), pp. 99-123.

184

Page 198: Value of Hedging

[2.12] Frechette, D. L., 2000, "The Demand for Hedging and the Value of Hedging

Opportunities", American Journal of Agricultural Economics, Vol. 82, No. 4.

(Nov. 2000), pp. 897-907.

[2.13] Friz, P., and Gatheral, J., 2005, "Pricing Volatility Derivatives as Inverse

Problem", Quantitative Finance, Vol. 5, No. 6, (2005), pp. 531-542.

[2.14] Glen, J., and Jorion, P., 1993, "Currency Hedging for International Portfolios",

Journal of Finance, Vol. 48, No. 5. (Dec. 1993), pp. 1865-1886.

[2.15] Grasselli, M. R., and Hurd, T. R., 2007, "Indifference Pricing and Hedging for

Volatility Derivatives", Applied Mathematical Finance, Vol. 14, No. 4 (Sept.

2007), pp. 303-317.

[2.16] Guay, W. R., and Kothari, S. P., 2003, "How Much Do Firms Hedge with

Derivatives?", Journal of Financial Economics, 70 (2003), pp. 423-461.

[2.17] Heifner, R. G., 1972, "Optimal Hedging Levels and Hedging Effectiveness in

Cattle Feeding", Agricultural Economic Research, 24 (1972), pp. 25-36.

[2.18] Heifner, R. G., 1973, "Hedging Potential in Grain Storage and Livestock

Feeding", Washington DC: U.S. Department of Agriculture Agricultural

Economic Report No. 238.

[2.19] Henderson, V., 2002, "Valuation of Claims on Nontraded Assets Using Utility

Maximization", Mathematical Finance, 12(4), pp. 351-373.

[2.20] Hodges, S. D., and Neuberger, A., 1989, "Optimal Replication of Contingent

Claims under Transaction Costs", Review of Futures Markets, 8, pp. 222-239.

[2.21] Howard, C. T., and D'Antonio, L. J., 1984, "A Risk-Return Measure of Hedging

Effectiveness", Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, 19 (March 1984),

pp. 101-112.

[2.22] Johnson, L. L., 1959, "The Theory of Hedging and Speculation in Commodity

Futures", Review of Economic Studies, 27(1959-60), pp. 139-51.

185

Page 199: Value of Hedging

[2.23] Kahl, K. H., 1983, "Determination of the Recommended Hedging Ratio",

American Journal of Agricultural Economics, Vol. 65, No. 3. (Aug. 1983), pp.

603-605.

[2.24] Lewent, J. C , and Kearney, A. J., 1990, "Identifying, measuring and hedging

currency risk at Merck", Journal of Applied Corporate Finance, 2, pp. 19-28.

[2.25] Luenberger, D. G., 1997, Investment Science, Oxford University Press, New York.

[2.26] Luenberger, D. G., 2004, "Pricing a Nontradeable Asset and Its Derivatives",

Journal of Optimization Theory and Applications, Vol. 121, No. 3, June 2004, pp.

465-487.

[2.27] Markowitz, H. M., 1952, "Portfolio Selection", Journal of Finance, 7(1), pp. 77-

91.

[2.28] Markowitz, H. M., 1959, Portfolio Selection: Efficient Diversification of

Investments, New York.

[2.29] Mello, A. S., and Neuhaus, H. J., 1998, "A Portfolio Approach to Risk Reduction

in Discretely Rebalanced Option Hedges", Management Science, Vol. 44, No. 7.

(Jul. 1998), pp. 921-934.

[2.30] Mian, S. L., 1996, "Evidence on Corporate Hedging Policy", Journal of Financial

and Quantitative Analysis, Vol. 31, No. 3. (Sept. 1996), pp. 419-439.

[2.31] Musiela, M., and Zariphopoulou, T., 2004, "An Example of Indifference Prices

under Exponential Preferences", Finance and Stochastics, 8(2), pp. 229-239.

[2.32] Nance, D. R., Smith, C. W., and Smithson, C. W„ 1993, "On the Determinants of

Corporate Hedging Policy", Journal of Finance, Vol. 48, No. 1. (Mar. 1993), pp.

267-284.

[2.33] Smith, C. W., and Stultz, R. M., 1985, "The Determinants of Firms' Hedging

Policies", Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, Vol. 20, No. 4. (Dec.

1985), pp. 391-405.

[2.34] Stultz, R. M., 1984, "Optimal Hedging Policies", Journal of Financial and

Quantitative Analysis, Vol. 19, No. 2. (June 1984), pp. 127-140.

186

Page 200: Value of Hedging

[2.35] Stulz, R. M., 1996, "Rethinking Risk Management", Journal of Applied

Corporate Finance, 9(3), pp. 8-24.

[2.36] Wikipedia.org on hedging: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hedging

187

Page 201: Value of Hedging

Index of Terms

Certain equivalent xi, 12

Chain rule

Chain rule for the value of hedging 95

Chain rule for the value of information 95

Clarity of action 7

Contraction property from probability 102

Cumulant 107

Cumulative distribution function (CDF) 22

Decision analysis 7

Decision analysis cycle 15

Appraisal phase 25

Evaluation phase 20

Formulation phase 16

Decision diagram See Influence diagram

Decision hierarchy 16

Delta property 13

Deterministic analysis 20

Deterministic dominance 23

Elements of decision quality 8

Equivalent probability of clairvoyance See Probability of knowing

Five rules of actional thought 9

Choice rule 10

Equivalence rule 9

Order rule 9

Probability rule 9

Substitution rule 9

Framing 16

HedgeStreet 3

Hedging 33,42

188

Page 202: Value of Hedging

Minimum-variance hedge 35

Negative hedging 61

Side effects of hedging 174

Incomplete markets 39

Influence diagram 17

Decision node 17

Deterministic node 17

Functional arrow 18

Influence arrow 18

Influence diagram for hedging 56

Informational arrow 18

Relevance arrow 18

Uncertainty node 17

Value node 17

Irrelevance xi

Judgmental bias 22

Mean-variance approaches 35

Minimal underlying uncertainty associated with an uncertain deal 91

Multiple of a deal 83

Normative discipline 7

PIBP xii, 11

PISP xi, 11

Preference probability 9

Probabilistic analysis 22

Probabilistic dominance

First order probabilistic dominance 23

Second order probabilistic dominance 23

Probability encoding 22

Probability of knowing 177

Risk premium

Buying risk premium xii

Selling risk premium xi

Risk-averse 12

189

Page 203: Value of Hedging

Risk-seeking 12

Risk-sharing 169

Sensitivity analysis 25

Open loop / closed loop sensitivity analysis 27

Tornado diagram 20

U-curve 11

Utility-based approaches 39

U-value 11

Value of control 30

Value of hedging

Value of hedging in the delta case 73

Value of perfect hedging 121

Dominance for the value of perfect hedging 146

Joint value of perfect hedging 130

Value of perfect information 29

Venn diagram 98

Wealth effect 47

190