vico and spinoza

Upload: yukio-mishima

Post on 03-Jun-2018

221 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    1/21

    Vico and SpinozaAuthor(s): James C. MorrisonSource: Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Jan. - Mar., 1980), pp. 49-68Published by: University of Pennsylvania PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2709102.

    Accessed: 06/02/2014 03:51

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    University of Pennsylvania Pressis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    Journal of the History of Ideas.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=upennhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2709102?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2709102?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=upenn
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    2/21

    VICO

    AND

    SPINOZA

    BY

    JAMES

    C.

    MORRISON

    The

    following

    is

    a

    comparative study

    of Vico's

    New

    Science and

    Spinoza's

    Theological-Political

    Treatise.1

    A

    common

    link

    which

    unifies

    these

    apparentlyquite

    disparate

    works is

    found in

    the

    concept

    of

    history,

    for as

    Vico

    laid the

    basis for

    the

    modern

    historization

    of

    philosophy,

    so

    Spinoza

    laid the

    basis for

    the modern

    historization

    of

    religion.

    Although

    our main

    purpose

    is to

    bring

    to

    light

    the

    major

    philosophical relationships

    holding

    between these

    two

    revolutionary

    and foundational works of

    mod-

    ern

    philosophy,

    we

    believe

    that the

    numerous

    striking

    agreements among

    them

    in

    thought, expression,

    and intention make

    it

    highly

    probable

    that

    Vico had read

    Spinoza

    and

    was

    influenced

    by

    him.2

    We

    also

    hope

    to

    demonstrate that

    a

    comparative

    study

    of the New Science

    and

    the Theo-

    logical-Political

    Treatise

    contributes

    significantly

    to

    a

    clarification of the

    works

    themselves.

    The

    recognition

    of

    the

    Spinozistic

    elements

    in

    Vico's

    thought

    is

    especially

    useful

    for

    disclosing

    his

    real

    (but

    veiled)

    intentions

    and

    the ultimate

    implications

    of the New Science for

    religion

    and

    Scripture.

    1

    All direct

    quotations

    and references to

    Vico are from the

    English

    translation

    by

    T.

    G.

    Bergin

    and

    M.

    H.

    Fisch,

    The New Science

    of

    Giambattista Vico

    (Ithaca,

    N.

    Y.,

    1968),

    hereafter

    designated

    as

    NS;

    numbers refer

    to

    paragraphs,

    which

    are

    the

    same

    as

    those

    in

    the

    edition

    of

    Vico's

    Opere,

    Vol.

    IV,

    ed.

    Fausto

    Nicolini

    (Bari,

    1942). When quoting directly from Spinoza we have used our own translations

    based

    on

    Carl

    Gebhardt's

    edition,

    Spinoza Opera,

    Vol. III

    (Heidelberg,

    1924).

    Numbers refer to

    pages

    of this

    edition,

    hereafter

    designated

    as

    Op.,

    and to

    the

    English

    translation

    by

    Elwes

    in

    Works

    of Spinoza,

    Vol.

    I

    (New

    York,

    1951),

    hereafter

    designated

    as

    TPT.

    2

    In

    regard

    to the

    question

    of

    Spinoza's

    direct influence on

    Vico,

    cf.

    Frederick

    Vaughan,

    La Scienza Nuova:

    Orthodoxy

    and

    the

    Art

    of

    Writing,

    Forum

    Italicum,

    II,

    No.

    4

    (1968),

    350;

    Vaughan

    asserts

    that Vico's

    New

    Science

    was

    written

    under the

    spell

    of the

    Theological-Political

    Treatise and

    Spinoza's

    idea

    of a new kind of critical history.

    He

    even goes

    so far as to

    say

    that

    Spinoza

    was

    the

    most

    important

    influence

    on the formation of Vico's

    philosophy.

    Cf.

    also

    Vaughan's

    The Political

    Philosophy

    of

    Giambattista Vico

    (The

    Hague,

    1972),

    44-51.

    We have

    not been able

    to find an

    unequivocal

    affirmation of

    Spinoza's

    direct

    influence on

    Vico

    in

    the

    writings

    of Fausto Nicolini or in the

    Bibliografia

    Vichi-

    ana,

    2

    vols.,

    ed.

    B. Croce

    & F.

    Nicolini

    (Naples,

    1947-58).

    Croce

    says

    in

    one

    place,

    non

    par

    dubbio,

    il Vico aveva

    letto

    il

    Tractatus

    theologico-politicus

    del

    reprobo

    Spinoza.

    And

    when

    discussing

    Spinoza's

    views

    on

    Moses

    and the

    Pentateuch,

    he

    adds that si

    direbbe

    quasi

    che dalla critica biblica dello

    Spinoza

    il

    Vico

    avesse

    avuto incentive alla

    sua

    della formazione

    e dello

    spirito

    dei

    poemi

    omerici,

    e

    che,

    passato

    per

    tal modo dalla storia sacra alla

    profana,

    da Mose a

    Omero,

    si

    fosse

    poi

    ostinato

    a

    non

    ripassare

    a niun

    patto

    da Omero a

    Mose,

    dalla

    storia

    profana

    alla

    sacra.

    La

    Filosofia

    di

    G.

    B.

    Vico

    (Bari,

    1965),

    182.

    On this

    latter

    point,

    cf.

    Section III

    below.

    49

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    3/21

    50

    JAMES

    C.

    MORRISON

    Our discussion

    is divided

    into

    five sections.

    In Section

    I

    we

    make

    some

    introductory

    remarks

    about the

    general

    thematic

    and

    aims

    of

    both

    works;

    in

    Section

    II we discuss

    the

    critique

    of

    divine

    providence;

    in

    Sec-

    tion

    III

    we

    turn to

    the

    general

    critique

    of revealed

    religion

    and

    Scrip-

    ture;

    in Section

    IV

    we

    deal with

    politics

    and

    natural

    law;

    and in

    Section

    V

    we

    draw

    some

    of

    the

    ultimate

    implications

    of

    Vico's and

    Spinoza's

    methods,

    arguments,

    and

    doctrines.

    1. The

    Theological-Political

    Treatise

    has

    a

    philosophical,

    theological,

    and

    political

    purpose.

    These are

    intimately

    connected.

    Spinoza says

    in

    his

    Preface

    that

    philosophical

    readers

    will find mere

    commonplaces

    (TPT 11; Op. 12). This means that the work is written not for actual

    philosophers

    but for

    potential

    ones.

    The latter

    are

    those

    who could

    or

    would become

    philosophers

    were

    they

    not

    inhibited

    by

    the Christian

    and

    Jewish

    claims to

    possess

    a

    suprarational

    truth which has

    been revealed

    by

    God. The

    belief in

    such a revelation

    inevitably

    leads

    to

    a

    tension be-

    tween

    reason

    and

    faith.3 This

    tension

    expresses

    itself

    either as

    skepticism,

    the subordination

    of

    reason

    to

    faith

    and

    revelation,

    or

    dogmatism,

    the

    subordination

    of faith and

    revelation

    to reason. The

    Theological-Political

    Treatise,

    then,

    is a

    philosophical

    critique

    of revelationaddressed o Chris-

    tian

    or

    Jewish

    skeptics

    or

    dogmatists

    in order

    to convert

    a few

    of

    them

    to

    philosophy

    and the use

    of reason.

    But the

    free use

    of

    reason

    is inhib-

    ited

    not

    only by

    faith in

    revelation

    but

    also

    by

    political

    and

    ecclesiastical

    authority.

    Spinoza

    tries

    to remove this

    other obstacle

    to

    philosophy

    by

    arguing

    that

    everyone

    ought

    to

    have the

    freedom

    to think

    what he

    likes

    and

    say

    what

    he thinks

    (TPT

    6,

    11,265;

    Op.

    7,12,246-7).4

    He

    thus

    addresses

    himself

    to

    present

    and future

    rulers

    in order to

    persuade

    them

    to

    permit

    freedom

    of

    conscience

    and

    expression.

    His

    argument

    is that

    such

    freedom

    is

    necessary

    both

    for

    piety

    and

    public peace

    (TPT

    6;

    Op. 7).

    In

    other

    words,

    the

    Theological-Political

    Treatise

    seeks

    to

    free

    actual

    and

    potential

    philosophers

    from

    persecution

    by promoting

    the

    establishment

    of

    a liberal

    democratic

    state. But the

    political

    and

    legal

    free-

    dom

    to

    think,

    speak,

    and

    write

    is

    ultimately

    worthless unless

    reason

    itself

    is freed

    from

    the

    limitations

    imposed by

    belief

    in

    revelation. The

    freedom

    to think without fear of political and

    ecclesiastical

    persecution

    therefore

    requires

    for its

    full realization

    complete

    confidence

    in the natural

    ight,

    i.e.,

    one's

    capacity

    to

    know

    the

    truth

    by

    one's own reason.5

    For

    when

    the

    philosopher's

    own

    capacity

    to know

    is doubted

    his

    will to

    know

    is

    paralyzed.

    The

    resolute

    commitment

    to

    a task

    presupposes

    complete

    con-

    3

    In

    his

    discussion

    of miracles

    or that

    which cannot

    be

    explained

    through

    natural

    causes,

    Spinoza

    says

    that he

    recognizes

    no

    distinction

    between

    a truth

    supra

    naturam

    and

    contra

    naturam

    (TPT

    85,87;

    Op.

    85,86).

    Since

    the

    spheres

    of nature and reason are coextensive, a truth above reason would also be a truth

    against

    reason.

    .

    ..

    For whatever

    is

    against

    nature

    is

    against

    reason,

    and

    what

    is

    against

    reason

    is

    absurd

    and so

    must be

    rejected

    (TPT

    92;

    Op. 91).

    4

    Cf.

    the

    subtitle

    to the

    Treatise.

    5

    Cf.

    Spinoza's

    critique

    of the

    belief that

    the human

    understanding

    is

    naturally

    corrupt

    (TPT

    7-8;

    Op.

    10).

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    4/21

    VICO AND

    SPINOZA

    51

    fidence

    in one's

    ability

    to

    complete

    the task. The

    philosophical quest

    for

    wisdom

    would be

    annulled

    in

    advance

    it

    one

    did

    not have

    complete

    con-

    fidence

    in

    one's

    ability

    to

    become

    wise.

    The

    possibility

    of revelation or a

    suprarational

    truth leaves

    open

    the

    possibility

    of a contrarationaltruth

    and

    hence casts

    into doubt the

    certainty

    of reason's

    clear

    and distinct

    ideas.

    The

    deceiving

    demon

    of

    revelation must

    therefore be exorcized

    by

    reason and

    philosophy

    themselves,

    which must demonstrate

    their

    autonomy

    and

    power by

    demonstrating

    the

    limitations and deficiencies

    of revealed

    religion.

    In

    short,

    the

    ultimate

    aim

    of

    the

    Theological-Political

    Treatise

    is to refute

    the revealed

    religion

    of

    Christianity

    and

    Judaism

    and

    replace

    it

    by philosophical

    wisdom.

    Whereas

    Spinoza's

    Theological-Political

    Treatise is a

    propaedeutic

    to

    philosophy

    dealing primarily

    with

    theological

    and

    political

    questions,

    Vico's

    New

    Science

    is

    a

    philosophical

    work

    dealing primarily

    with

    philo-

    sophical

    and

    historical

    questions

    and

    only

    secondarily

    with

    theological

    and

    political

    ones.

    Although

    Spinoza's

    work

    is

    primarily

    theoretical,

    it

    has an

    important practical

    purpose.

    Vico's

    New

    Science

    is also

    primarily

    theoretical

    but

    seems to

    have little

    direct

    practical bearing.6

    Its main

    aim

    is not to free potential philosophers from a pre-philosophicalservitude

    to

    faith

    and

    revelation

    but to

    lay

    the

    basis

    of

    a new

    philosophy.

    Vico's

    whole

    problematic

    rests

    on

    a

    fundamental

    distinction

    between the

    world

    of

    nations

    (history)

    and

    the

    world of

    nature.

    This distinction

    is

    linked

    with

    the

    epistemological

    principle

    that the

    knower can know

    only

    what

    he

    has

    made and

    the

    metaphysical-theological

    principle

    that

    nature can-

    not

    be

    the

    subject

    of

    human

    science

    (NS

    331).7

    Vico nowhere tries

    to

    bridge

    the

    dichotomy

    between

    nature and

    history

    or

    to reconcile them

    in a higher unity. For him there is no all-embracingsingle whole but

    two

    mutually

    exclusive

    parts.8

    The

    specific subject-matter

    of Vico's

    new

    science

    is the common nature

    of nations

    or

    the

    origins

    of

    institutions,

    6

    Only

    in

    ##1405-11

    (not

    included

    in

    the

    published

    versions

    of

    the

    Scienza

    nuova)

    does

    Vico

    explicitly

    raise

    the

    question

    of the

    practice

    (prattica)

    of his

    work.

    There

    he

    briefly

    alludes

    to

    possible political

    implications

    and

    applications

    of the

    theory

    of

    the

    New

    Science for the

    wise men

    and

    princes

    of

    the

    com-

    monwealths

    who desire

    to

    recall

    the

    peoples

    to their

    acme

    or

    perfect

    state

    (#1406). These sections have recently been translated and published in Giam-

    battista

    Vico's Science

    of Humanity,

    ed. G.

    Tagliacozzo

    &

    N.

    Verene

    (Baltimore,

    1976),

    451-54.

    7

    It also follows

    that

    man can

    have

    no

    knowledge

    of God.

    Nor can man

    know

    that

    nature has

    been

    created

    by

    God.

    From the

    point

    of view of Vico's

    science,

    the belief

    in God

    and

    His creation

    is a

    mere

    postulate.

    Men

    can

    know the divine

    only

    insofar

    as

    it

    is

    a

    human creation.

    Vico's

    point

    is that

    human

    knowledge

    is limited

    to the

    human.

    It

    ends

    where

    the realm of

    history

    ends and that

    of

    nature

    begins.

    8

    By contrast, Spinoza's thought is essentially a doctrine about an all-embracing

    whole.

    Everything

    that

    is,

    is either nature

    or

    an

    aspect

    or

    part

    of nature

    (the

    substance,

    its

    attributes and

    modes).

    Human

    things

    are

    merely

    finite

    parts

    of

    an

    infinite

    whole.

    Humans

    and

    their creations

    are thus

    wholly

    natural.

    They

    do

    not

    constitute

    an

    independent

    realm

    in

    opposition

    to nature

    but are themselves

    ultimately

    manifestations

    of

    the

    power

    of

    nature.

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    5/21

    52

    JAMES C.

    MORRISON

    religious

    and

    secular,

    among

    the

    gentile

    nations (NS

    31).

    Its

    aim is

    to

    study

    these in

    the

    light

    of

    divine

    providence

    (NS

    31,342).

    On

    one

    level

    this means

    showing

    how

    God

    or

    the

    divine

    will

    operates

    (NS

    182).

    On

    another

    level it

    means

    showing

    the

    way

    providence naturally

    guides

    the

    process

    by

    which

    man becomes

    human

    or the

    families and

    civil

    society

    develop

    from the natural

    state

    of

    bestial

    wandering

    (NS

    146,310,338).

    On

    yet

    another level

    it

    means

    showing

    that

    the

    world

    of

    civil

    society

    has

    certainly

    been made

    by

    men

    (NS

    331).

    Vico's

    argument

    moves

    vertically

    from

    the

    divine

    to

    the natural to

    the human.

    The

    chief

    accomplishment

    of

    the

    New Science

    is therefore

    the

    secular-

    ization of human history. The old Judaeo-Christiantheocentric under-

    standing

    of

    human

    things

    as

    guided

    providentially

    by

    a

    divine

    mind

    is

    replaced by

    a new

    anthropocentric

    doctrine

    according

    to which

    men

    themselves

    have made

    the world

    of nations.

    Tacitly recalling

    the

    Car-

    tesian

    assumption

    that all traditional

    opinions

    might

    be

    false,

    Vico

    speaks

    of

    the

    night

    of

    thick

    darkness

    enveloping

    the

    earliest

    antiquity.

    All

    historical

    knowledge

    is obscure and

    hence doubtful.

    But

    in

    the

    midst

    of

    this

    darkness Vico

    discovers

    the eternal

    and never

    failing

    light

    of

    a

    truth beyond all question: that the world of civil society has certainly

    been

    made

    by

    men

    . . .

    (NS 331).

    The truth

    that the

    human

    world

    has been made

    by

    men recalls

    the Cartesian

    certainty

    of

    the

    cogito.

    But

    Vico

    replaces

    the

    Cartesian

    Archimedian

    point

    of

    self-conscious-

    ness

    by

    human

    self-making:

    the

    identity

    of

    thinker and

    thought

    becomes

    the

    identity

    of

    maker

    and

    made.

    He

    thereby

    completes

    the

    Copernican

    revolution

    in

    astronomy

    and

    the

    Cartesian

    revolution

    in

    metaphysics

    with

    a new revolution

    in

    history.

    Human

    things

    will be understood

    by

    Vico solely in human terms: men have not been made by God or nature

    but

    by

    themselves.

    Human

    self-making

    will

    in

    turn

    provide

    the

    basis for

    the

    accomplishment

    of

    the ultimate

    aim of the

    New

    Science,

    namely,

    to

    unite

    history

    ( philology )

    and

    philosophy.

    II.

    If the

    history

    of

    human

    things

    is

    to

    be

    understood

    anthropologic-

    ally,

    the

    theological

    conception

    of divine

    providence

    must be

    demytholo-

    gized :

    it must

    be shown

    to be

    a

    metaphor

    enclosing

    and

    concealing

    human truths. In Vico's own

    terminology,

    it must be translatedfrom an

    imaginative

    genus

    into an

    intelligible genus.

    This

    is in

    fact

    what

    Vico

    does. He

    presents

    a

    non-theological

    and

    non-traditional

    account of the

    corso of the nations

    under the

    veil

    of

    a

    theological

    and traditional

    account

    of

    divine

    providence.

    But

    at

    the

    same

    time he

    provides

    the

    hermeneutical

    rules

    for

    stripping

    away

    this

    poetic-theological

    surface and

    disclosing

    its

    historical-human

    nucleus.

    For

    the

    New

    Science,

    which

    overtly presents

    the

    method

    of

    interpreting

    the divine

    poems

    of the

    theological

    poets,

    also

    covertly

    presents

    the

    method

    for

    interpreting

    its

    own divine

    poem

    of

    history

    as

    the

    unfolding

    of

    providence.

    Just

    as

    all

    myths

    are

    essentially

    civil

    histories,

    so

    the

    mythical guise

    of

    Vico's

    providence

    masks the

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    6/21

    VICO AND SPINOZA 53

    historical-philosophical

    truths

    which make

    up

    the real

    content of the

    New

    Science.9

    According

    to

    the

    surface

    argument

    of

    the

    New

    Science,

    the

    idea

    of

    providence

    is

    linked

    to

    the

    division between

    gentiles and

    Jews,

    for

    God

    aids

    the

    former

    naturallyby

    divine

    providence

    and

    the latter

    super-

    naturally

    by

    divine

    grace

    (NS 136;

    cf.

    310,

    313).

    This

    division,

    Vico

    says,

    was

    made

    by

    the

    Jews

    themselves

    (NS

    313).

    It

    is

    thus not

    a

    philo-

    sophical

    division

    but a

    traditional

    opinion.

    Consistent with his

    purpose

    of

    replacing

    old

    opinions

    by

    new

    knowledge,

    Vico

    persistently

    ignores

    the

    division between the

    history

    of

    the

    gentiles

    and that of

    the

    Jews,

    eventuallycollapsingthe distinctionbetween them and replacingthe theo-

    logical

    ideas

    of

    providence

    and

    grace

    by

    the

    philosophical

    idea

    of the

    ideal

    eternal

    history

    which

    holds

    universally

    for

    all nations

    (cf.

    NS

    245,

    250,349,393).

    Vico's distinction between

    the

    ordinary

    help

    from

    provi-

    dence

    for

    the

    gentiles

    and

    the

    extraordinary

    help

    from the

    true God

    for

    the

    Jews

    (NS

    313)

    is

    strikingly

    reminiscent of

    Spinoza's

    distinction

    between

    the internal

    aid

    of God

    and

    the external aid

    of God. 10

    The

    former is whatever human nature

    by

    its

    own

    power

    alone

    can

    do

    for

    preservingits existence, while the latter is whateveraccrues to man's

    use

    by

    the

    power

    of

    external

    causes

    (TPT

    45;

    Op. 46).

    Both

    of

    these

    reduce to

    the

    fixed

    and

    unchangeable

    order

    of

    nature or the

    chain of

    natural

    things

    (TPT

    44,

    cf.

    82,89;

    Op.

    45-6;

    82,89).

    So

    for

    Vico,

    the

    help

    of

    divine

    providence

    reduces to

    the

    unchanging

    order

    of the corso

    of

    the

    nations.

    Both

    Spinoza

    and

    Vico therefore secularize the

    divine.

    Spinoza

    does

    so

    by

    naturalizing

    providence

    and

    identifying

    it

    with the

    course

    of

    nature,

    Vico

    by

    historicizing

    providence

    and

    identifying

    it

    with

    the course of history.

    According

    to

    orthodox

    belief,

    a

    primary

    manifestation

    of

    divine

    providence

    in

    the

    Old Testament

    is

    God's

    covenant with

    the

    Hebrews.

    For

    Spinoza,

    however,

    the

    election

    and vocation

    of

    the Hebrews

    has

    only

    a

    political

    meaning.

    It

    has to do

    with the

    temporal happiness

    and

    advantages

    of

    sovereignty

    TPT 47;

    cf.

    48;

    Op.

    48;

    cf.

    49).

    Apart

    from

    that,

    God

    is

    equally

    kind,

    merciful,

    etc.

    to

    all

    (TPT

    49;

    Op.

    50).

    Solomon,

    who

    speaks

    more

    rationally

    of

    God

    than

    anyone

    in the Old

    Testament,

    taught

    that all the

    goods

    of fortune to mortals were vain

    (TPT

    39;

    Op.

    41).11

    The

    difference

    between

    Jews

    and

    gentiles

    is

    not

    based

    on the

    fact that the Jews

    alone had

    the

    gift

    of

    prophecy,

    for

    all

    9

    This

    is

    the

    real

    meaning

    of Vico's

    phrase,

    rational civil

    theology

    of

    divine

    providence

    (NS

    342).

    Vico's

    reasoning

    shows

    that

    the

    theology

    of divine

    provi-

    dence

    is

    really

    a

    civil

    history

    (cf.

    NS

    352).

    10

    Vaughan

    has

    pointed

    this

    out but not

    developed

    it;

    cf.

    op.

    cit.,

    349-50.

    11Cf. Spinoza's account in the Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione of his

    decision

    to

    dedicate himself to

    philosophy

    after

    experience

    taught

    me that all

    things

    which are

    usually

    found

    in common life

    are vain

    and futile.

    Spinoza

    Opera,

    op. cit.,

    II,

    5.

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    7/21

    54

    JAMES

    C.

    MORRISON

    nations

    possessed

    prophets.

    The

    gentile augurs

    were true

    prophets

    and

    the Jews themselves were

    often deceived

    by

    false

    prophets

    (TPT

    49-

    52; Op. 50-3).12 Vico,

    when

    discussing

    the three

    kinds of

    reason,

    calls

    the

    first

    kind divine

    and defines

    it as

    a

    form of

    external

    speech

    to

    the

    gentiles

    through

    he

    auspices,

    the

    oracles,

    and

    other

    corporeal

    signs,

    and

    through

    the

    prophets

    and

    through

    Jesus Christ to

    the

    Apostles

    (NS

    948).13

    Spinoza

    asserts

    that

    the

    prophets always

    had some

    sign by

    which

    they

    became certain

    of

    the

    things they

    were

    imagining prophetic-

    ally,

    that

    the

    prophets'

    revelations

    were

    always accompanied by

    words

    and

    figures,

    and that

    only

    Moses heard a true voice.

    But

    God

    re-

    vealed Himself to Christ's mind immediately, for Christ was not so

    much

    a

    prophet

    as the mouth

    of

    God

    (TPT

    25,28,64;

    Op. 28,30,64).14

    According

    to

    Vico,

    the

    ignorant

    and

    vulgar

    refer

    the

    causes of

    the

    things they

    do

    not know to the

    will of

    God without

    considering

    the means

    by

    which the divine will

    operates

    (NS

    182).

    A

    little earlier

    he

    suggests

    that

    this

    means

    s a

    confused

    idea of

    divinity

    (NS

    178).

    Because

    of

    this

    ignorance

    of

    natural

    causes,

    the

    human

    mind

    makes

    itself the

    rule

    of

    the

    universe,

    so

    that men

    ascribe

    to the

    gods

    what

    they

    them-

    selves do (NS 180; cf. 375). Where Spinoza asserts that misconcep-

    tions

    about

    God arise

    from

    the

    view that all

    things

    in nature act as

    men themselves

    act,

    namely,

    with

    an

    end, 1'

    Vico

    says

    that

    because

    of

    the indefinite nature

    of the

    human

    mind,

    wherever

    it

    is lost

    in

    ignorance

    man makes

    himself the measure

    of

    all

    things

    (NS

    120).

    Spinoza speaks

    of

    men

    imagining

    miracles,

    believing

    themselves to

    be God's

    favorites,

    and the

    final

    cause

    for

    which God

    created and

    continually

    directs all

    things

    (TPT

    82;

    Op. 82).

    The

    law

    and word

    of

    God

    is

    used

    meta-

    phorically for the order and fate of nature (TPT 169; Op. 162). The

    idea

    of

    God

    as

    legislator

    or

    prince

    is

    used

    by

    Paul

    only

    as

    a concession

    to

    the weakness

    of

    the

    understanding

    of

    the

    vulgar

    (TPT 65; Op.

    65).

    Such

    usage

    illustrates

    the

    method which

    depicts

    all

    things poetically

    and

    refers

    them to

    God

    (TPT 92;

    Op.

    91).

    In

    the same

    way,

    Vico

    speaks

    12

    Cf.

    Spinoza's

    reference to

    those

    who

    dream that

    nature had

    formerly

    created

    different

    kinds of men

    (TPT

    45-6;

    Op. 47).

    .

    ..

    All

    men,

    Jews

    as

    well as

    Gentiles,

    have

    always

    been the

    same,

    and in

    every

    age

    virtue has been

    very

    rare

    (TPT

    166:

    Op.

    160).

    13

    As

    far as

    we can

    determine,

    Vico refers

    explicitly

    to

    Christ

    in

    only

    two other

    places

    in

    the

    New Science.

    One

    reference

    is

    to

    a

    Jesuit who claimed to

    have

    read

    (Chinese?)

    books

    written

    before

    the

    coming

    of

    Christ

    (NS

    50).

    In the

    other

    reference,

    Vico

    says

    that

    during

    the returned

    barbarian times

    paintings

    of

    God, Christ,

    and

    Mary depicted

    them as

    exceedingly

    large

    (NS

    816).

    14

    Cf.

    Spinoza's interpretation

    of

    Exodus VII:

    1,

    where he

    says

    that

    Aaron,

    in

    communicating

    Moses'

    words

    to

    Pharoah,

    acted the

    part

    of a

    prophet,

    and

    Moses

    himself was like a God to Pharoah, or one who plays the part of God (TPT

    13;

    Op.

    15).

    15

    In

    the

    Ethics,

    Spinoza

    calls the will of God the

    sanctuary

    of

    ignorance.

    Everyone judges

    of

    things

    according

    to the state of his

    brain,

    or rather mistakes

    for

    things

    the

    forms of

    his

    imagination.

    Ethics,

    Part

    1,

    Appendix.

    Cf.

    TPT

    86;

    Op.

    86.

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    8/21

    VICO

    AND

    SPINOZA

    55

    of that

    religious

    way

    of

    thinking

    according

    to

    which it was the

    gods

    who did whatever men

    themselves

    were

    doing

    (NS 629;

    cf.

    922).

    III. The

    Theological-Political

    Treatise is a

    critique

    of both

    religion

    and

    Scripture,

    for

    Scripture

    is the

    record of God's

    revelations to

    man.

    Revelation is

    the essential

    element

    common to Judaism and

    Christianity.

    The conclusion of

    Spinoza's critique

    of

    Biblical revelation is

    that

    Scrip-

    ture contains no

    speculative

    philosophical

    truths about God

    but

    only

    vulgar

    moral

    precepts

    (TPT

    8,190-5;

    Op.

    9,180-5).

    Scripture

    does

    not

    teach

    or

    claim

    to

    teach

    theoretical

    knowledge

    but

    only practical

    obedi-

    ence:

    it

    has

    nothing

    in

    common with

    philosophy

    (TPT

    9;

    Op. 10).

    Scripture

    demands

    only

    justice

    and

    charity

    in

    practice.

    Whereas

    Spinoza

    launches

    his

    attack

    against

    Biblical

    authority

    di-

    rectly,

    Vico

    proceeds

    under

    the

    mask

    of

    the

    pagan

    poet

    Homer. Homer

    is

    Vico's

    pseudonym

    for Moses. '

    The first

    and

    greatest

    of

    the

    pagan

    poets corresponds

    to

    the first

    and

    greatest

    of

    the

    Hebrew

    prophets.

    The

    question

    of

    the historical

    existence

    of Homer

    is

    the

    question

    of the his-

    torical

    existence of

    Moses.

    The

    question

    of whether Homer wrote the

    Iliad and Odysseyis the question of whetherMoses wrote the Pentateuch.

    The

    questions

    whether Homer was

    wise

    and whether

    his

    poems

    contain

    esoteric

    or

    philosophical

    wisdom are whether

    Moses knew

    God

    better

    than

    all

    other

    prophets

    and

    whether the Pentateuch

    contains

    true

    knowl-

    edge

    of

    the

    nature

    of

    God

    (cf.

    NS

    780).

    And

    just

    as the Homeric

    poems

    are

    two

    great

    treasure

    houses

    of

    the customs

    of

    early

    Greece

    (NS

    904),

    so

    the Old

    Testament

    should be read as a

    treasure house of

    the

    history

    of

    the Jews:

    their

    customs,

    institutions,

    beliefs,

    laws,

    etc.

    In

    short,

    the

    methodwhich Vico uses to discoverthe true Homer is the same method

    to

    be used

    to

    discover the

    true

    Moses.

    The

    aim

    of

    Book

    III of

    the

    New

    Science,

    Discovery

    of the

    True

    Homer, is,

    in

    common

    with the aim

    of

    Spinoza's

    Theological-Political

    Treatise,

    to

    undermine the

    authority

    of

    Scripture.17

    That

    explains why

    16

    Vico

    also sometimes uses Homer as a

    pseudonym

    for all

    the

    authors

    of

    Scripture.

    From this

    point

    of

    view,

    the Iliad

    corresponds

    to the

    Old

    Testament

    and the

    Odyssey

    to the New

    Testament.

    For

    example,

    he

    emphasizes

    that the

    Odyssey

    was

    composed

    later than

    the Iliad

    because

    it

    contains

    references to

    more

    advanced and

    refined

    customs.

    For while in

    the latter

    violent

    passions

    pre-

    dominate,

    in the former there

    is

    evidence

    of

    an

    increased level of reason. The

    hero

    of

    the

    Iliad,

    Achilles,

    is

    the hero

    of

    violence,

    while the hero of

    the

    Odyssey,

    Ulysses,

    is

    the

    hero

    of

    wisdom

    (NS 879).

    Similarly,

    Spinoza

    views

    the

    Old

    Testament

    as more

    primitive

    than

    the

    New

    Testament

    because

    in

    the

    latter

    apostles

    or teachers

    of

    morality

    replace

    prophets

    or

    interpreters

    of

    God.

    Whereas

    the

    apostles

    wrote their

    epistles

    solely by

    the natural

    light,

    the

    prophets

    prophesied

    by

    their vivid

    imaginations

    (TPT

    24-25,161;

    Op.

    27-28,155).

    Paul and

    the other

    apostles philosophized, but the Jews always despised philosophy (TPT 164;

    Op.

    158).

    17

    According

    to

    Nicolini,

    Vico

    adopts

    in Book III

    precisamente

    il metodo

    instaurato

    dal filosofo

    d'Amsterdam

    e dal mentovato

    Simon,

    e

    perfezionato

    dalla

    critica

    moderna,

    nello

    sconvolgere

    analogamente

    la

    tradizionale

    storia esterna

    o

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    9/21

    56

    JAMES

    C.

    MORRISON

    Vico

    made

    it

    the central

    book. What

    initially

    appears

    as

    a

    digression-a

    discussion

    of

    the existence and characteristicsof an historical

    person-is

    in

    reality

    the center:

    a

    critique

    of

    the truth

    of

    Holy Scripture.

    While

    the

    conclusion of

    the

    Theological-Political

    Treatise

    is

    that

    Scripture

    contains

    no

    philosophical

    theoretical

    knowledge

    but

    only vulgar

    practical

    precepts,

    the conclusion

    of

    Vico's

    critique

    of the Homeric

    poems

    is

    that

    they

    con-

    tain

    no

    philosophical

    wisdom

    but

    only

    vulgar

    opinion

    about the

    history

    and

    customs of the Greek

    peoples.

    The real

    content of the

    Homeric

    poems

    is

    not

    philosophical

    but

    historical:

    they

    give

    us not

    philosophical

    truths

    but

    philological

    certainties. .

    .

    .

    The

    meanings

    of esoteric

    wisdom

    were intruded into the Homeric fables by the philosophers who came

    later

    (NS

    834).'8

    The

    Homeric

    poems

    are an

    expression

    of the

    history

    of

    the

    natural law

    of the

    gentes

    (NS

    904).

    Vico

    argues

    that

    the

    (false)

    belief that Homer

    was

    a

    real

    historical

    individual and the actual author

    of

    the

    works

    traditionally

    attributed to

    him

    has

    obscured

    this

    fact

    from

    historians. This

    suggests

    that

    the

    (false)

    belief that Moses was

    a

    real his-

    torical

    individual and the

    actual author

    of

    the

    Pentateuch

    has

    prevented

    historians

    from

    realizing

    that the

    Old

    Testament

    is

    an

    expression

    of the

    natural law of the Hebrews. Vico argues that Homer was not an his-

    torical

    individual but an

    imaginative

    genus:

    Homer

    is

    a class term

    denoting

    an indefinite number of historical

    individuals.l'

    As

    the literal

    meaning

    of

    the

    name Homer

    mplies,

    Homer

    was

    a binder

    or

    compiler

    of fables

    (NS 852), '

    an

    idea

    or

    a

    heroic

    character of

    Grecian

    men

    (NS

    873),

    the

    Greek

    peoples

    were

    themselves

    Homer

    (S 875).

    Moses,

    viewed as

    the

    great law-giver

    of

    the

    Hebrew

    people,

    is

    analogous

    to

    Solon,

    the

    great

    law-giver

    of

    the

    Athenians. Solon too

    was

    not an

    in-

    dividualperson but the Athenian plebeians themselves. Moses is to the

    strutturale del Vecchio Testamento.

    La

    Religiosita

    di

    Giambattista

    Vico

    (Bari,

    1949),

    147.

    Vaughan

    too

    maintains that

    Vico uses Homer as a screen for

    his

    critique

    of the Bible.

    Op.

    cit.,

    353.

    18

    Cf.

    Spinoza's

    criticism

    of Maimonides' method of

    interpreting Scripture,

    according

    to which

    reason is used

    as a standard for

    deciding

    what a

    given

    text

    means and the prophets were considered supreme philosophers and theologians.

    Thus,

    if the literal

    meaning

    of

    a

    text

    is

    unreasonable

    or

    false,

    it must be

    interpreted

    metaphorically.

    For

    Spinoza,

    this

    amounts

    to

    a

    distortion

    of

    Scripture

    (TPT

    115-17;

    Op.

    113-15).

    Cf.

    Section V

    below.

    19

    Nicolini recalls how

    Finetti

    (an

    early

    vociferous

    critic

    of

    Vico's

    heterodoxy)

    noted

    that,

    once Homer

    is

    reduced

    to

    a

    carattere

    poetico,

    non v'e alcuna

    ragione

    valida

    per

    non adotterla

    anche

    nei

    riguardi

    della

    personalita

    storica

    dell'autore dei

    Salmi.

    Op.

    cit.,

    148-49.

    20

    Vico

    derives

    homeros

    from

    homou

    (together)

    and

    erein

    (to link)

    (NS

    852).

    Cf. Martin Buber's

    surprisingly

    Vichian

    analysis

    of the

    name Moses

    as

    meaning

    he who

    draws

    forth,

    which

    signifies

    Moses as

    the

    one

    who drew

    Israel forth

    from

    the flood. Buber

    calls the Mosaic books

    an

    historical

    saga

    or

    mythisa-

    tion of

    history,

    i.e.,

    the

    report by

    ardent enthusiasts

    of that which

    has befallen

    them.

    Moses

    (New

    York,

    1958),

    17,36.

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    10/21

    VICO

    AND SPINOZA

    57

    Hebrews

    as

    Solon

    is

    to the

    Greeks,

    Romulus

    to

    the

    Romans,

    Thrice-great

    Hermes

    to

    the

    Egyptians

    (NS 414-6).21

    Although Spinoza,

    unlike

    Vico,

    accepts

    the

    historical

    reality

    of

    Moses,22

    he

    too

    denies

    that

    Moses

    actually

    wrote the

    Pentateuch.

    Just

    as

    Vico's

    Homer is reduced to a

    compiler

    of

    fables,

    so

    Spinoza

    replaces

    Moses

    by

    the editor

    Aben

    Ezra.

    For

    Spinoza

    the

    Pentateuch,

    like

    Vico's

    Homeric

    poems,

    is

    a

    complex

    collection of written and oral tradi-

    tions

    extending

    over

    many

    years

    and

    issuing

    from

    many

    hands and

    mouths

    (TPT

    128-30;

    Op.

    125-7).

    Just

    as

    Vico's Homer lived

    many

    years

    after

    the

    events

    his

    poems

    describe

    (cf.

    NS

    804,806),

    so

    Spinoza's

    Mosaic books were written and edited long after the Mosaic period. Ac-

    cording

    to

    Vico's

    Chronological

    Table,23

    he revelation to Moses

    at

    Sinai

    occurred

    in

    the

    year

    of the

    world

    2491.

    (Given

    that the traditional

    year

    of

    creation was

    4004

    B.C.,

    this

    means 1513

    B.C.)

    The

    same table

    says

    that in

    the

    year

    3290

    (=

    714

    B.C.)

    vulgar

    letters

    [alphabetical

    writing]

    had

    not

    yet

    been invented.

    This

    implies

    that the

    Pentateuch,

    at least in its

    present

    form,

    could not have been written

    by

    Moses.24

    Since

    alphabetical

    writing

    is,

    according

    to

    Vico,

    always preceded

    by

    heroic

    and

    divine writing (or hieroglyphs ), Moses must have been a number

    of

    theological

    poets

    who

    wrote

    fables about the

    gods

    in a

    divine

    mental

    language

    and

    imagined

    that

    all

    things

    were done

    by

    the

    gods

    (NS

    933-5;

    922,929).

    If

    we

    take this

    conclusion and

    relate

    it

    to Vico's

    description

    of

    the

    synchronous

    structure

    of the course the

    nations

    run outlined

    in

    Book IV

    (cf.

    NS

    915ff.),

    we

    may

    draw the

    following

    inferences

    about

    his

    view

    of

    Hebrew

    history during

    the

    Mosaic

    period.

    The nature

    of

    the Hebrews was

    poetic

    or

    creative

    (NS 916);

    their

    customs

    were

    21Vico remarks that

    Homer

    was called the founder

    of Greek

    polity

    or

    civility (NS

    897).

    22

    In

    many respects, Spinoza's interpretation

    of

    Moses

    is

    strikingly

    similar

    to

    Machiavelli's

    description

    of

    the

    virtuous

    prince.

    Moses

    is

    the

    great

    law-giver,

    the

    founder

    of

    the

    Hebrew

    people,

    nation,

    and

    religion.

    For Moses

    surpassed

    the

    others

    in

    divine

    virtue ;

    by

    his virtue he established

    divine

    rights

    and

    prescribed

    them

    to the

    people ;

    because of

    his

    virtue

    and at the divine command

    he intro-

    duced

    a

    religion

    into

    the

    commonwealth

    (TPT

    75;

    cf.

    74,39;

    Op.

    75; cf. 74,41).

    Cf. for example Machiavelli's discussion in Chapter VI of 11 Principe of the

    virtu

    and

    deeds

    of the four

    great

    princes,

    Romulus,

    Theseus,

    Cyrus,

    and

    Moses.

    23

    Cf.

    the

    insert at the

    beginning

    of Book

    I

    of

    the

    New

    Science.

    24

    Nicolini calculates

    that

    according

    to Vico

    alphabetical writing

    succeeded

    hiero-

    glyphic

    writing

    no later than the

    7th or 6th centuries B.C. He thus draws

    the obvious

    conclusion that Vico

    believed

    that Moses

    had

    not written the

    Pentateuch,

    Joshua

    the

    Book

    of

    Joshua,

    David

    the

    Psalms,

    nor

    Solomon the

    works associated

    with

    his name.

    For

    the events

    recorded

    in

    these

    books

    actually

    occurred,

    and were said

    to

    have oc-

    curred,

    before

    the

    development

    of

    alphabetical

    writing.

    In

    short,

    Nicolini infers

    that

    Vico's chronology of the history of language significava asserire che la materia

    anche

    di ciascuno

    di

    codesti libri

    santi,

    al

    pari

    di

    quella

    dei

    poemi

    omerici,

    si fosse

    formata

    poligeneticamente;

    significava,

    insomma, aderire,

    implicamente

    se non

    esplicamente,

    alle

    conclusioni

    del Tractatus

    theologicus

    politicus

    dello

    Spinoza

    e

    dell'

    Histoire

    critique

    du

    Vieux Testament

    del Simon.

    Op.

    cit.,

    145-47.

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    11/21

    58

    JAMES

    C. MORRISON

    tinged

    with

    religion

    and

    piety

    (NS

    919):

    their

    natural

    law was di-

    vine, i.e.,

    made

    or done

    by

    a

    god

    (NS

    922);

    their

    government

    was

    theocratic

    (NS

    925);

    their

    jurisprudence

    was

    a

    mystic

    theol-

    ogy

    (NS 938);

    the time

    of

    Moses was

    the

    religious

    times

    (NS

    976),

    etc.

    (Cf.

    NS

    944,948,955.)

    The

    reader

    of the

    Theological-Political

    Treatise will

    recognize

    in

    the

    above

    the

    basic

    characteristics of

    Spinoza's

    own

    view of

    the

    early

    He-

    brews.

    Further

    similarities

    between Vico and

    Spinoza

    also

    readily sug-

    gest

    themselves. Where Vico

    notes

    that Homer was called the

    father of

    all other

    poets

    (NS

    900),

    Spinoza

    follows tradition

    in

    calling

    Moses

    the chief of the prophets.

    And

    when

    Vico

    says that

    Homer was the

    source

    of

    all Greek

    philosophies

    (NS

    901),

    Spinoza suggests

    that

    Moses'

    prophecies

    became

    the basis

    of

    all

    subsequent

    theology

    (cf.

    TPT

    7-8;

    Op.

    9).

    Where

    Vico

    says

    that one

    of

    the

    three

    chief

    aims of all

    great poetry,

    including

    Homer's,

    is

    to teach the

    vulgar

    to

    act

    virtuously

    (NS

    376),

    Spinoza

    says

    that

    Moses'

    laws

    aimed at

    controlling

    the stiff-

    necked and obstinate Hebrews

    (TPT

    75;

    Op.

    75).

    Spinoza

    speaks

    of

    the

    Hebrews

    at the

    time

    of

    Moses as

    men

    accustomed

    to

    the

    super-

    stitions of the Egyptians, crude and sunk in the most wretched slavery

    (TPT

    38;

    Op. 40-1).

    For

    Vico,

    the Hebrew exodus

    from

    Egypt

    would

    be

    an

    instance of

    the rebellion of

    the

    plebs

    against

    the

    patricians

    or the

    clients

    against

    the

    fathers.

    Moses,

    like

    Solon,

    would

    have

    been

    a

    leader

    of

    the

    plebs

    and

    their first

    law-giver

    (cf.

    NS

    416).

    The

    Pentateuch,

    as

    the

    history

    of

    the

    beginnings

    of

    the

    Hebrew

    people

    and

    nation,

    would

    be a

    barbarous and

    fabulous

    history

    of barbarous and bestial men

    with

    quite

    wild

    and

    savage

    natures

    (cf.

    NS

    338,

    302,

    840).

    When

    Vico

    speaks of the poverty of the Greeklanguagein early times (cf. NS 830),

    we recall

    Spinoza's complaints

    about the

    obscurities

    and

    inadequacies

    of

    the

    ancient

    Hebrew

    language

    (cf.

    TPT

    108ff.;

    Op.

    106ff.).

    Finally,

    many

    of

    Vico's remarks

    about

    early

    Roman

    history

    would

    be

    applicable,

    mutatis

    mutandis,

    to

    early

    Hebrew

    history.

    The

    most

    ob-

    vious

    example

    is

    his

    lengthy

    discussion of

    the Roman

    Law of the

    Twelve

    Tables. Vico's

    main

    concern

    is

    to

    prove

    that this law was not

    imported

    by

    the Romans

    from

    Greece

    but was an

    indigenous

    expression

    of

    the

    naturallaw (sc. natural customs) of the Romans themselves. Similarly,

    the

    Mosaic

    Decalogue

    was not

    adopted

    by

    the

    Hebrews from

    Egyptian

    law,

    but

    was

    an

    indigenous expression

    of

    the

    natural

    customs

    of

    the

    He-

    brews.25The

    Hebrews,

    like all

    peoples

    in

    the

    divine

    age,

    attributed

    their

    laws

    to the

    gods.

    For

    Vico,

    however,

    this

    poetic

    myth

    should

    be cor-

    rected

    by replacing

    God

    and

    Moses

    by

    the Hebrew

    people.

    The stone

    tablets

    on which

    the

    Decalogue

    was inscribed

    are the

    poetic equivalent

    of

    the bronze

    tablets

    of

    the Roman

    Law

    of

    the

    Twelve Tables.

    They

    were

    25

    In NS

    44,

    Vico

    explicitly

    raises

    the

    question

    of

    whether

    Moses

    brought

    Hebrew

    divine institutions from the

    Egyptians;

    and in NS

    396

    he

    says

    that

    Selden

    had

    failed to

    prove

    that the Jews

    taught

    their natural

    law to the

    gentiles.

    Cf. NS

    794.

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    12/21

    VICO

    AND SPINOZA

    59

    thus

    written,

    not

    by

    the

    hand

    of

    God

    or

    Moses,

    but

    by

    the Hebrew

    peo-

    ple

    (if

    indeed

    they

    ever

    actually

    existed).

    The

    Mosaic

    Decalogue

    was

    formulated

    long

    after

    the Mosaic

    period by

    several unknown

    authors

    in

    order

    to

    codify

    traditional Hebrew

    customs,

    just

    as

    the

    Twelve Tables

    were

    a

    later formulation

    of

    Roman

    legal

    tradition.

    And

    just

    as the

    validity

    of

    the

    Roman law

    is

    delimited

    by

    the

    geographical

    confines of Rome

    and

    her

    territories,

    so

    the

    validity

    of

    the

    Decalogue

    is

    limited

    by

    the

    temporal

    and

    geographical

    confines

    of the Hebrew

    state. It is

    not a uni-

    versal law valid

    for

    all men

    at

    all

    times,

    but a law

    only

    for

    the Hebrews-

    just

    as

    the

    Roman

    law

    was

    binding

    only

    on Roman citizens and

    subjects.

    This conclusion, at least in its main outlines, corresponds to Spinoza's

    interpretation

    of

    the Mosaic law

    as a national law

    (TPT

    17;

    Op. 19)

    and

    Hebrew

    law and

    ceremony

    generally

    as

    valid

    only

    for the Hebrew

    state

    while

    it

    existed and

    for

    the Hebrews when

    they

    lived within

    its

    borders. The Hebrew

    God

    was the

    God

    of

    the

    land and

    the

    laws

    of

    the Old Testament were revealed

    only

    to

    the Hebrews

    (TPT

    37;

    Op.

    39).

    In

    short,

    for Vico

    as

    for

    Spinoza,

    the

    morality

    of

    the Old

    Testament

    is

    not the true

    morality simpliciter

    nor

    by

    implication,

    is

    that

    of

    the

    New

    Testament. The revelation at Sinai and the Sermon on the Mount are

    merely

    historically

    conditioned

    expressions

    of the

    historical

    lives of

    par-

    ticular

    peoples.

    They

    must therefore be

    replaced

    by

    a

    new

    moral teaching

    and a new doctrine of

    the natural

    law.

    Both

    Vico

    and

    Spinoza,

    although

    in different

    ways, attempt

    to effect this

    replacement

    by

    means

    of a

    new

    philosophy.

    IV.

    The New

    Science

    and the

    Theological-Political

    Treatise both

    con-

    tain a doctrine of natural law. Their respective teachings differfrom one

    another

    and,

    even more

    importantly,

    from

    the traditional

    theory

    about

    natural

    law.

    Vico

    and

    Spinoza try

    to refute

    the traditional

    teaching

    by

    subverting

    it,

    that

    is,

    by collapsing

    the

    distinctions

    which

    served as its

    basis

    or

    essence.26

    For

    example,

    the traditional

    view

    contrasts

    nature

    (physis)

    and

    custom

    (nomos).

    The distinction between

    the natural

    and

    the

    customary

    was the distinction

    between

    what

    exists

    independently

    of

    man

    and

    what exists as

    a result of human

    thought

    and

    activity.

    Vico,

    however, derives his doctrine of naturallaw (diritto naturale) not from

    nature

    simply

    or

    from human nature

    (in

    contrast

    to

    human

    customs)

    but from those

    human customs which

    are

    found

    historically

    among

    all

    men: the

    natural law is coeval with the

    customs of

    the

    nations

    (NS

    311;

    cf.

    134-5).27

    Thus,

    the distinction between the

    natural as

    what

    exists

    everywhere

    and

    always

    among

    men,

    and

    the

    customary

    as

    what

    26

    The

    blurring

    and

    collapsing

    of

    basic distinctions

    and the

    tendency

    to reduce

    transhuman

    phenomena

    to the human is

    typical

    of classical

    Sophists.

    On

    Spinoza's

    relation to

    sophistic

    doctrines,

    cf. Hermann

    Cohen,

    Jiidische

    Schriften,

    Vol.

    III

    (Berlin, 1924),

    303-04.

    27

    Cf.

    NS 309

    as an

    example

    of how Vico

    characteristically

    blurs and

    collapses

    the distinctions

    between

    diritto and

    legge,

    costumi and

    natura.

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    13/21

    60

    JAMES

    C. MORRISON

    exists

    only

    in

    some

    places

    and

    times,

    collapses.

    Vico's

    central notion

    of

    the

    natural law

    of

    the

    gentes 28-a

    single

    law

    which

    is

    both a law of

    nature (ius naturae) and a law of the peoples (ius gentium)-thus im-

    plies

    the

    reduction

    of

    political

    and moral

    right

    to historical

    fact:

    what

    ought

    to be

    is

    what

    everywhere

    and

    always

    is,

    has

    been,

    or

    will

    be.

    Polit-

    ical

    philosophy

    thereby

    becomes an

    aspect

    of the

    philosophy

    of

    history

    or

    the

    unity

    of

    philosophy

    and

    philology.29

    Traditional

    political philoso-

    phy

    also rested

    on the

    opposition

    between

    right

    (ius)

    and

    power

    (poten-

    tia).

    Spinoza,

    however,

    identifies

    right

    and

    power.

    Natural

    right

    is

    simply

    the

    power

    (conatus)

    every

    individual

    being

    has

    by

    nature

    to act

    and

    per-

    sist in its existence (TPT 10; cf. 200-01; Op. 11; cf. 189-90). This

    means

    that

    political

    and moral

    right

    are reduced

    to natural

    fact:

    what

    ought

    to be is

    what

    every being

    can

    do. Political

    philosophy thereby

    is

    derived

    from the

    philosophy

    of nature

    or

    the

    doctrine of

    the

    unity

    of

    substance.

    Traditional

    political philosophy

    conceived

    natural law

    as

    a trans-

    human

    standard,

    knowable

    by

    human

    reason,

    prescribing

    limits to hu-

    man

    actions.3

    Vico

    denies,

    contrary

    to

    Spinoza,

    that the

    natural law

    is

    known by reason. Rather, it is known by sense, i.e., the common

    sense

    possessed by

    all

    peoples

    of

    what

    is

    useful

    or

    necessary

    for

    life.

    Human needs and

    utilities

    are

    the two

    sources

    of

    the natural

    law of

    the

    gentes

    (NS

    141,142;

    cf.

    145).

    Spinoza

    denies

    that

    a

    natural

    right

    is

    a

    trans-human

    standard

    possessing

    prescriptive

    force in

    itself;

    for it

    depends

    on

    human

    decree

    that

    men

    yield,

    or be

    compelled

    to

    yield,

    the

    right

    which

    they

    have

    from nature and bind themselves

    to

    a certain

    plan

    of

    living

    (TPT

    57;

    Op.

    58).31

    Spinoza

    does

    not

    say

    that

    natural

    right

    is itself the product of human decree. Natural right in the sense of one's

    natural

    power

    and desire

    is

    given

    by

    nature.

    But

    this natural

    right

    be-

    comes

    a

    political

    and

    moral

    right,

    and hence

    a

    standard

    for

    action,

    only

    when men decide to

    yield

    it to those

    who will rule

    them,

    i.e.,

    when

    in-

    dividual

    men

    by

    a

    contract

    (pactum)

    create

    a

    ruler or

    sovereign

    (TPT

    10,

    cf.

    202-05;

    Op.

    11;

    cf.

    191-94).32

    Since men

    have had

    to

    decree and

    establish

    most

    firmly

    to

    direct all

    things

    .

    .

    .

    only by

    the dictate

    of

    rea-

    son,

    it

    follows

    that

    man

    is

    not

    by

    nature

    a rational

    animal

    but

    by

    com-

    28

    Vico's

    expression

    is

    diritto

    naturale delle

    genti.

    29

    Vico calls the

    sixth

    principal

    aspect

    of

    the

    New Science

    a

    system

    of

    the

    natural

    law

    of the

    gentes,

    which

    is a

    history

    of

    human

    nature

    or a

    history

    of

    the

    ideas,

    the

    customs,

    and

    the deeds

    of mankind

    (NS

    394,368).

    30

    Cf.

    Hugo

    Grotius'

    succinct

    definition

    of the

    jus

    naturale as a dictatum rectae

    rationis.

    De

    Jure Belli

    ac

    Pacis,

    I,I,X,1.

    31

    On

    Spinoza's

    tendency

    to reduce

    reason to

    a

    plan

    or

    project

    cf.

    Leo

    Strauss,

    Spinoza's

    Critique

    of

    Religion

    (New

    York,

    1965),

    16.

    32

    The utilitarian

    aspect

    of

    Spinoza's

    political thought

    and his

    theory

    of the

    compact

    are no doubt the reason

    for Vico's

    contemptuous

    description

    of

    Spinoza's

    commonwealth

    as a

    society

    of hucksters

    (NS

    335).

    For

    according

    to

    such

    a

    view,

    the state

    is formed

    by striking

    a

    bargain

    on

    the

    basis

    of mutual

    self-

    interest

    and

    profit.

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    14/21

    VICO

    AND SPINOZA

    61

    pact

    (TPT

    203;

    Op.

    191;

    my

    emphasis).

    A

    life in

    accordance

    with

    reason

    is

    not

    natural

    but

    conventional. Human

    nature

    is so consti-

    tuted that all indeed seek their own utility, but not from the dictate of

    sound

    reason

    (TPT

    73;

    Op.

    73).33

    Men

    do

    not

    by

    nature

    pursue

    what

    is

    good,

    but

    each man

    pursues

    his

    own

    self-interest or

    what he

    judges

    is the

    greatest good

    or the least evil.

    Spinoza

    adds

    that this law is so

    firmly

    inscribed in human nature that

    it

    ought

    to be

    placed among

    the

    eternal

    truths

    which no one can

    ignore

    (TPT

    203;

    Op.

    192).34

    For

    Vico,

    the state is not

    a

    deliberatecreation

    resulting

    from a

    com-

    pact

    or

    yielding

    of

    natural

    right,

    but

    develops naturally

    from families

    or society. Families are the first societies since they consist of the

    fathers

    and

    their socii

    (or

    dependents).

    These

    form the

    basis of

    the

    later

    political

    classes of civil

    society,

    i.e.,

    the

    patricians

    and

    plebs.

    The

    state

    or

    civil

    society

    emerged

    not when

    isolated

    individuals

    yielded

    their

    right

    or

    power

    but

    when

    the fathers chose

    a leader to defend themselves

    against

    the

    rebellion

    of their

    dependents

    who

    sought

    to

    share the natural

    rights

    already

    possessed

    by

    the

    fathers

    (NS

    583-4;

    cf.

    554-5).

    Civil

    power emerged

    from

    family

    authority

    (NS

    585).

    Since

    those who

    made up the families wereconcerned only with the necessities of life ;

    they

    did

    not

    recognize good

    faith

    (NS 570).

    Thus,

    a

    compact,

    which

    presupposes

    mutual

    trust,

    was

    impossible.

    In

    other

    words,

    for

    Vico

    neither

    the

    state

    nor

    society

    can

    arise from a

    compact

    because

    compacts

    presuppose

    the state and

    society.35

    For

    both Vico and

    Spinoza

    the

    state

    arises from

    human

    actions.

    But for

    Vico,

    these actions

    are not

    a

    con-

    tractual

    agreement

    against

    nature

    but historical

    responses

    to

    natural ne-

    cessities.

    The

    decision to found a

    state is

    not

    a decision

    to live

    rationally

    according

    to a

    plan

    rather than

    naturally according

    to desire and

    pas-

    sion,

    but

    is

    a natural

    response

    to natural

    needs

    and

    utilities. While

    Spin-

    oza

    contrasts

    human reason and

    nature,

    Vico coalesces

    them;

    for

    Spinoza

    the

    state

    is

    an

    artifice,

    for Vico it

    is

    a

    natural institution

    arising

    from

    natural customs.

    Spinoza

    and

    Vico also differ

    concerning

    the

    end

    or

    purpose

    of civil

    society.

    For

    Spinoza,

    the end

    of

    every society

    and

    government

    is

    that

    men

    may

    live

    with

    security

    and

    comfort

    (TPT

    47;

    Op.

    48).36

    To

    achieve

    this

    end it

    is

    necessary

    to free

    everyone

    from fear.

    Living

    se-

    33

    It

    follows from this that the

    philosophical

    life-or

    the

    pursuit

    of

    rational

    truth

    and wisdom-is also not natural for

    most

    humans.

    Philosophy

    is

    not

    the

    fulfillment

    of man's inherent nature.

    Cf.

    Spinoza's

    opening

    statements in the

    Preface

    about men

    being

    naturally

    superstitious

    (TPT

    3-5; Op.

    5-7).

    34

    Cf. Vico's statement

    that

    legislation

    considers

    man

    as he

    is

    in order to

    turn human vices into virtues

    (NS 132).

    35

    Vico

    quotes

    with

    approval Pomponius:

    when the institutions themselves

    dictated

    it,

    kingdoms

    were

    founded''

    (NS 584).

    36

    Cf.

    Spinoza's interpretation

    of God's choice

    (electio)

    of the

    Hebrews

    and

    their

    vocation

    (vocatio)

    in terms of

    temporal happiness

    and

    advantages

    (TPT

    47;

    Op.

    48).

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    15/21

    62

    JAMES C.

    MORRISON

    curely

    involves

    not

    only

    the

    safety

    of

    the

    body

    but the exercise

    of one's

    free reason : therefore the end of a

    republic

    is

    indeed

    liberty

    (TPT

    258-9; Op. 240-1).

    For

    Vico,

    the

    aim of

    civil

    society

    was first

    to

    render

    secure

    the

    lives,

    property,

    and

    rights

    of the

    family

    fathers

    against

    the

    armed threat

    of their

    dependents

    and

    ultimately

    to make

    possible

    the

    full

    deveopment

    of

    reason and

    thus human

    nature

    itself

    (SS

    326,554-5,918,

    924,927,973,1008).

    The

    corso

    of

    the nations is

    therefore

    fulfilled

    in

    a

    monarchy,

    in which the

    natural

    equality

    of all

    men

    is

    actualized and

    protected by

    law

    and institutions

    (NS

    995-8,1008).

    In this

    sense,

    mon-

    archy

    for

    Vico is both the most natural and the

    best

    form of

    government

    because it is consistent

    with both

    the natural

    end

    of the

    historical

    process

    and

    human

    nature.

    By

    contrast,

    Spinoza's

    reduction of

    right

    to

    power,

    and

    hence

    natural

    right

    to natural

    power, implies

    that

    democracy

    is

    the

    most

    natural

    regime,

    for

    there

    is no natural

    hierarchy

    of better and worse

    and no

    natural end of

    either

    history

    or man.

    Since

    all men

    are

    naturally

    equal,

    democracy

    is

    most

    in

    harmony

    with human nature

    (TPT

    263;

    Op. 245).

    And

    because

    sovereignty

    is the

    product

    of

    a

    compact,

    a

    ruling

    class

    does not exist

    because

    of

    its

    natural

    superiority

    but

    by

    a

    common

    convention. Democracy is also the most natural form of government be-

    cause

    it

    is

    most

    consonant with individual

    liberty

    (TPT

    207;

    Op.

    195).

    For

    Vico,

    however,

    there

    is

    a

    natural

    hierarchy

    not

    only

    in

    civil

    society

    but

    also

    in

    the state

    of

    nature.

    This

    hierarchy

    is

    ultimately

    de-

    termined

    by

    superior

    virtue or

    piety,

    for

    the founders of

    the families

    and

    the

    cities were

    the

    pious

    ones whose

    fear of the

    gods

    caused them to set-

    tle

    in

    one

    place.37

    The fathers

    were the virtuous

    few,

    the natural

    aristoi.

    In this

    sense,

    for

    Vico

    aristocracy

    s

    natural,

    since it is rule

    by

    the natur-

    ally virtuous few over the naturally vicious or bestial many.38But this

    natural

    inequality

    is,

    in

    the

    development

    of

    the

    nations,

    replaced

    by

    the

    progressive

    emergence

    of reason

    and

    the

    demand

    of

    the

    plebs

    for

    an

    equal

    share

    in

    the

    rights,

    privileges,

    and

    power

    of the

    patricians.

    This is

    accompanied

    by

    a

    weakening

    of

    the

    plebs'

    belief

    that the

    patricians

    are

    of

    a

    different

    nature from

    themselves,

    i.e.,

    that

    they

    are descended

    from

    the

    gods.

    The old

    belief in natural

    inequality

    is

    replaced by

    a new

    belief based on the

    recognition

    of

    the

    sameness

    of

    nature insofar

    as all

    men are rational. That is, it is replacedby the belief in a common human

    nature

    which,

    in

    its

    state

    of

    perfection,

    is

    reasonable

    and

    intelligent

    (NS 918).

    The

    original

    natural

    inequality

    of

    piety

    is

    replaced

    by

    the

    natural

    equality

    of

    reason:

    pious

    virtue and

    justice

    become

    rational

    virtue

    and

    justice.

    37

    .

    .

    .

    The

    frightful

    thought

    of some

    divinity

    ..

    .

    imposed

    form

    and

    measure

    on the bestial

    passions

    of

    those lost

    men and thus transformed

    them

    into human

    passions

    (NS

    340;

    cf.

    177,338,339,376ff.).

    Spinoza,

    however,

    explicitly

    denies

    that

    religion

    exists in the natural

    state,

    in that no one knows from nature

    whether he

    owes

    any

    obedience

    towards God.

    The state

    of nature is

    without

    religion

    or law

    (TPT

    210;

    Op.

    198).

    38

    The earliest

    kings

    were chosen

    by

    nature,

    that

    is,

    because

    of

    their

    greater piety,

    strength,

    and

    courage

    (NS

    584).

    This content downloaded from 128.226.37.5 on Thu, 6 Feb 2014 03:51:09 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Vico and Spinoza

    16/21

    VICO

    AND

    SPINOZA

    63

    Vico

    presents

    his rational

    civil

    theology

    of

    divine

    providence

    as a

    refutation

    of

    the doctrine

    of chance

    of Hobbes

    (despite

    Hobbes's de-

    terminism), Machiavelli,

    and

    Epicurus,

    and the

    doctrine

    of

    fate

    in

    Spinoza

    and

    Zeno

    (sc.

    the

    Stoics)

    (NS

    179,1109).

    In

    Vico's

    refutation,

    he

    says

    he sides with

    the

    divine

    Plato,

    the

    prince

    of

    the

    political

    philosophers

    (NS

    1109;

    cf.

    130).

    He also

    presents

    his

    philosophy

    as

    a

    refutation

    of

    the

    atheistic

    doctrine of

    Bayle

    and

    Polybius,

    according

    to which

    human

    society

    and

    virtue

    are

    possible

    without

    religion

    and

    piety

    (NS

    179,

    1109).

    Vico

    refutes the

    false

    dictum of

    Polybius

    that

    if

    there

    were

    philosophers

    in

    the world

    there

    would

    be no

    need

    for

    reli-

    gions (NS 179,1112). Human things cannot be understood without

    the

    recognition

    of

    the

    essential

    role

    of

    religion

    and

    religious

    belief.

    Al-

    though

    Vico does

    not

    associate

    Spinoza

    with

    the

    atheistic

    enlightenment

    view

    of

    Bayle

    and

    Polybius

    that

    science or

    philosophy

    could

    replace

    reli-

    gion,

    he

    might easily

    have done

    so.

    For the main

    purpose

    of the

    Theo-

    logical-Political

    Treatise

    is

    precisely

    to show

    that

    a

    republic requires

    the

    freedom

    of

    thought

    and

    expression,

    i.e.,

    the

    freedom

    to

    philosophize

    without

    restriction.

    Thus a

    society

    of

    atheists

    is

    not

    unqualifiedly

    con-

    demned. However, a society of philosophersin the sense of rationalmen

    living

    in accordance

    with

    a

    plan

    cf reason

    rather

    than

    the

    impulsion

    of

    natural

    desire

    is

    not

    possible,

    since it contradicts

    human nature.39

    For

    all

    men are

    by

    nature

    superstitious

    (TPT

    3;

    Op

    5).

    Only

    a

    very

    few

    can

    perform

    the

    extremely

    difficult

    unnatural

    feat

    of

    mastering

    their

    passions

    by

    means

    of reason.4

    Whereas

    for

    Spinoza

    a

    society

    of

    philosophers

    is

    a

    natural

    impossibility,

    for

    Vico it

    is

    an

    historical

    impossibility.

    So

    too

    for

    a

    society

    of

    atheists.

    For

    society

    presupposes

    law and

    law

    presupposes

    religion.

    The first society, that of the families, rests on the three princi-

    ples

    of

    religion,

    marriage,

    and

    burial

    (belief

    in

    immortality).

    The first

    laws

    and

    institutions

    were

    believed to be

    of divine

    origin,

    for law

    or

    juris-

    prudence

    was

    originally

    the

    science

    of

    Jove's

    auspices

    (NS

    398).

    And

    since civil

    society

    presupposes

    families,

    it

    too rests

    on

    piety

    and

    religion

    (NS 179).

    Finally,

    philosophy

    presupposes

    religion

    because

    it

    presup-

    poses

    civil

    soci