vivarium, vol. 18, nos. 1-2, 1980

Upload: manticora-venerabilis

Post on 01-Jun-2018

228 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    1/165

    Vivarium

    Volume 18

    1980

    Reprinted ith hepermission ftheoriginal ublisher

    by

    Periodicals Service

    Company

    Germantown,

    NY

    2013

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    2/165

    Printedn

    cid-free

    aper.

    This

    eprint

    as

    reproduced

    romhe

    best

    riginal

    dition

    opy

    vailable.

    NOTE

    OTHEREPRINTDITION:

    In

    ome asesfull

    age

    dvertisementshicho not dd

    o

    the

    cholarly

    alue

    f his olume ave een mitted.

    As

    result,

    ome

    eprinted

    olumes

    ay

    ave

    rregularagination.

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    3/165

    VIVARIUM

    AN

    INTERNATIONAL

    JOURNAL

    FOR THE

    PHILOSOPHY

    AND

    INTELLECTUAL

    LIFE

    OF THE

    MIDDLE

    AGES

    AND

    RENAISSANCE

    VOLUME

    XVIII

    1980

    E.

    J.

    BRILL

    -

    LEIDEN

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    4/165

    VIVARIUM

    AN

    INTERNATIONAL

    JOURNAL

    FOR

    THE

    PHILOS-

    OPHY

    AND

    INTELLECTUAL LIFE

    OF THE

    MIDDLE

    AGES

    AND RENAISSANCE

    vivarium

    s

    devoted

    n

    particular

    o the

    profane

    side

    of

    mediaeval

    hilosophy

    nd the

    ntellectualife fthe

    Middle

    Ages

    and

    Renaissance.

    editors

    C.

    J.

    de

    Vogel,

    Utrecht)

    L. M.

    de

    Rijk,

    Leyden)

    H.

    A.

    G.

    Braakhuis,

    Nijmegen)

    F. F.

    Blok,

    Amsterdam) J.

    IJsewijn,

    Louvain).

    SecretaryftheEditorial oard Prof. . M. deRijk.

    All

    communications,

    xcept

    hose f business

    ature,

    hould

    be

    addressed

    o

    C.

    H.

    Kneepkens,

    atholieke

    Universiteit,

    Erasmusplein

    , 8.20,

    P.O.

    Box

    9103,

    6500

    HD

    Nijmegen,

    The Netherlands.

    advisory

    Marie-Therse

    Alverny,

    Paris-Poitiers)

    Tullio

    Gregory,

    committee

    (Rome)

    Paul

    Oskar

    Kristeller,

    New

    York)

    -

    Jan

    Pinborg,

    (Copenhagen)

    Albert

    immermann,

    Cologne).

    publishers

    E.

    J.

    Brill,

    eiden,

    The Netherlands.

    published

    Twice

    yearly,

    ay

    nd

    November;

    a

    160

    pages

    yearly.

    Contributionsubmitted o vivarium should preferably

    be

    writtenn

    English,

    rench r German.

    he

    manuscripts

    should

    be

    typewritten

    nd double

    paced,

    except

    for

    ong

    quotations

    nd footnotes.

    dequatemargins

    1

    inch)

    hould

    be

    left at

    each

    edge

    of

    the

    sheet. Footnotes

    hould

    be

    numbered

    ontinuously

    hroughout

    ach article.

    hey

    may

    be

    placed

    either

    t the foot f

    the

    page

    or at the

    end of

    the

    text.

    Contributors

    eceive

    5

    off-prints

    ree

    f

    charge.

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    5/165

    CONTENTS

    OF VOLUME XVIII

    (1980)

    L. M. de

    rij

    On Ancient

    and

    Mediaeval

    Semantics

    Leiden

    and

    Metaphysics

    3)

    1

    c. h. KNEEPKENS

    M

    ore

    Evidence

    on

    the

    Manuscript

    Tra

    -

    Nijmegen

    dition

    of

    Aimeric s Ars

    lectora: Paris

    ,

    B.N .lat.

    y

    i

    and

    Rolduc

    Abbey

    ...

    63

    paul

    a. STREVELER

    Gregory f

    Rimini

    and theBlack Monk

    WestChester on Sense and Reference 67

    Daniel

    o.

    Dahlstrom

    Signification

    nd

    Logic:

    Scotus

    on

    Uni

    -

    Santa

    Clara

    versais

    from

    a

    Logical

    Point

    of

    View 81

    paul

    M.

    j.

    E. tummers

    Geometry

    nd

    Theology

    n

    the Xlllth

    Nijmegen

    century.

    An

    example of

    their

    nterrela-

    tion

    as

    found

    n

    the

    Ms

    Admont

    42.

    The

    influence f

    William

    of

    Auxerre? . . .

    112

    Leonard a. Kennedy

    Cesare

    Cremonini and

    the

    Immortality

    Saskatoon

    of

    the

    Human

    Soul

    143

    review

    Vincent

    Ferrer,

    Tractatus de

    Supposi

    -

    tionibus

    ed.

    John

    A.

    Trentman

    (E.

    P.

    Bos)

    79

    books

    received

    159

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    6/165

    Vivarium

    VIII,

    i

    (1980)

    On

    Ancient

    and

    Mediaeval

    Semantics

    and

    Metaphysics (3)*

    L.

    M.

    DE

    RIJ

    4

    The

    Categories

    as

    Classes

    of

    Names

    4.1

    Status

    quaestionis

    The

    relation

    previous

    between

    sections

    three

    contain

    maior

    issues

    several

    in

    hints

    Plato's

    to

    doctrine,

    the

    close

    viz.

    inter-

    the

    elation

    between

    three maior

    issues

    in

    Plato's

    doctrine,

    viz. the

    question about the true nature of the Forms and those about

    participation

    and

    predication.1

    ndeed,

    for

    the

    founder

    of

    the

    theory

    of the

    Forms,

    predication

    was

    bound to

    become a

    problem.

    Forms

    are immutable and

    indivisible;

    yet

    other

    Ideas

    have to

    participate

    in

    them;

    they

    are

    unique,

    by

    themselves

    and

    subsistent;

    yet,

    when

    saying

    '

    John

    is man

    (or

    white),

    *

    Peter is

    man

    (or

    white),

    should

    there be

    one

    perfect,

    eternal,

    immutable

    etc. Form of MAN

    (or

    WHITE)

    in the one

    and

    another in

    the

    other?

    Or,

    as

    I

    have

    put

    it

    above

    [1977: 85]:

    if

    John,

    Peter,

    and

    William

    are

    wise,

    does

    this

    mere fact mean that there must be

    something

    which

    they

    are all

    related

    to in

    exactly

    he same

    manner

    namely

    WISDOM

    itself?

    And

    if

    'John

    is

    wise

    ,

    '

    Peter

    is wise' and

    '

    William is

    wise are all

    true

    statements,

    what

    exactly

    is the

    meaning

    of

    the

    predicate

    name

    '

    wise ?

    The former

    question

    is

    concerned

    with

    participation,

    the

    latter

    with

    predication.

    Well,

    that

    the

    crux

    of the latter

    problem

    is

    not the

    separate

    existence of the

    Forms

    (chrismos) learly appears

    from

    he

    fact that also

    the

    author

    of

    the

    Categories

    who had

    entirely

    abandoned

    all

    kind

    of

    chrismos

    could apparently not get rid of a

    similar

    problem:

    if the

    categories

    really

    are

    classes

    of

    'things

    there

    are'

    (1

    a

    20)

    (i.e.

    'real1

    ubstances,

    real'

    natures,

    and 'real'

    properties),

    rather

    than

    concepts

    (i.e. logical

    attributes),

    what kind

    of

    'thing'

    is

    meant

    by

    a

    term

    qua

    'category'

    ?

    So

    for

    Aristotlethe

    semantic

    problem

    still

    remained. His

    distinction

    between

    en

    hypokeimeni

    nd kath

    hypokeimenou

    ould

    only

    hide the

    original

    problem.

    It is

    often said

    that

    these

    phrases

    refer o

    different

    omains,

    the

    metaphysical

    and

    *

    Parts

    1)

    and

    (2)

    are found n

    this

    Journal

    5

    (1977),

    81-110

    nd

    16

    (1978),

    81-107.1 See also R. E. Allen,

    Participation

    nd

    predication

    n Plato's Middle Dia-

    logues

    n:

    Gregory

    lastos

    ed.)

    Plato

    :

    Metaphysics

    nd

    Epistemology.

    Col-

    lection f

    Critical

    ssays,

    New

    York

    1974,

    i7-i83),

    167.

    I

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    7/165

    the

    logical

    one,

    respectively.

    We

    have

    already

    found ome

    good

    reasons

    to

    qualify

    this

    opposition

    (see [1978],

    84;

    88).

    It

    seems

    to be useful

    now to collect all kind of information romAristotle'sown writings,

    not

    only

    the

    Categories,

    bout

    the

    proper meaning

    of the

    categories.

    This

    will be the

    aim

    of our

    sections

    4.2-4.7.

    One

    preliminary

    emark, however,

    about

    Kapp's approach

    to the

    question.

    He much insisted

    ([1952]:

    36-42;

    see

    also

    25-27,

    discussed

    above,

    [1978], 82-84) upon

    what he consideredan

    utmost unfortunate

    development

    n the

    history

    of

    ogic concerning

    he Aristotelian

    ateg-

    ories.

    They

    were

    not

    usually interpreted,

    s

    they

    should,

    he

    says,

    as

    a due

    attempt

    to

    differentiate,

    orcertain dialectical and

    philosophical

    purposes, the sometimesmisleading uniformityfgrammaticalpred-

    ication,

    but in a

    nearly

    opposite

    sense,

    namely,

    as an

    arbitrary

    nd

    superficial

    urvey

    of

    classes

    or

    general

    heads to

    which Aristotlewanted

    to reduce all

    the

    objects

    of our

    thought.

    And,

    still on

    Kapp's

    view,

    it

    is

    Aristotle himself

    who was

    responsible

    for

    the

    abandonment

    of

    his

    original point

    of

    view,

    since

    in

    various

    writings

    of

    his

    a more

    or

    less

    complete

    enumerationof the

    categories

    s used as a

    conveniently

    compendious

    inventory

    of the

    main

    aspects

    of

    reality

    Kapp, p.

    39;

    italics

    mine).

    Even as

    early

    as

    in the

    Categories

    he llusion was created

    that the ten classes of the

    categories

    were intended, from the be-

    ginning,

    o

    cover the

    whole field of the

    possible

    signification

    f

    single

    words' and

    might

    be used

    as such. And this is

    something,Kapp

    adds

    (p.

    41),

    that in

    Antiquity

    nobody

    could in the

    long

    run know

    apart

    from he field of

    things

    n

    general'.

    Therefore

    Kapp,

    on

    purpose,

    eft

    out of

    consideration

    those

    passages

    in

    undoubtedly

    Aristotelian

    writings

    where use is

    made of

    the doctrineof the

    categories

    n

    a

    sense

    wider than

    what

    he takes for

    their

    original

    one.

    To his

    mind,

    Aristotle

    himselfwas the firstvictim of this

    illusion.

    Much could

    be

    objected

    to

    Kapp's

    view

    (see

    also

    [1978], 84).

    I

    think,

    the

    most

    fundamental

    point against

    Kapp

    should be

    that, if,

    really,

    in

    Antiquity

    nobody

    could,

    in the

    long

    run,

    know

    apart

    the

    classification

    of

    predicates

    from

    that of

    'things',

    what,

    for heaven's

    sake,

    can

    guarantee

    us that

    not

    from

    he

    very

    beginning

    f the

    doctrine,

    any

    sharp

    distinction

    between

    'things

    said' and

    'things

    said'

    was

    missing

    at

    all

    ?

    Nothing

    ndeed,

    I

    am sure.

    What

    Kapp

    did,

    is

    nothing

    but to

    find

    n the

    Categories

    sharp ( )

    distinction,which,

    on closer

    inspection, urnsout to be misleadingly ague notonly n thepresenta-

    tion of

    the doctrine

    as

    found

    in the

    Categories

    ut also

    in

    Aristotle's

    own

    mind,

    to

    the effect

    hat he

    himselfwas the firstvictim of the

    2

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    8/165

    supposed

    illusion.

    Had

    we

    not better

    dismiss

    Kapp's

    strict

    opposition

    of

    things

    sai

    and

    'things'

    entirely

    4.2

    On

    some

    modern

    nterpretations

    f

    kata

    symplokri

    Aristotle

    himself

    professes

    to

    deal

    in his

    Categories

    with

    'things

    that are said

    without

    combination'

    (1

    a

    16-17).

    What

    does

    the author

    mean

    here

    by

    '

    combination

    {symplok,

    itterally

    'inter-

    eaving'

    ?

    As

    for

    the

    word

    symplok

    one

    commonly

    refers

    to

    Plato,

    Sophist

    262

    A-B,

    where

    he maintains that a

    sentence

    is

    not

    just

    a

    series of

    names

    or of verbs but

    results

    from

    he combination

    of

    a

    name

    (noun)

    witha verb

    a

    line of

    thought

    which

    s

    admittedly

    aken

    up by

    Aristotle

    in hisDe interpretatione16 a 9-18; 17 a 17-20). Our author's examples

    (at

    i a

    19)

    'mari

    'ox',

    'runs' 'wins'

    are

    clearly

    set

    against

    those

    clarifying

    he

    'things

    said

    that

    involve

    combination'

    ('man

    runs'

    'man

    wins'),

    to

    the

    effect hat the

    former

    eem

    to stand

    for

    possible

    ingredients

    parts)

    of

    a

    sentence.

    This

    interpretation

    eems to

    find

    some additional

    support

    in

    that

    Aristotle treats

    such

    phrases

    as 'in

    the

    Lyceum'

    and

    'in the

    market-place

    as

    lacking

    combination

    (2

    a

    1).

    By

    '

    combination

    he

    apparently

    means the

    composition and division)

    accomplished

    n a

    sentence,

    one

    would

    presume.

    There is, however,some difficultynvolved in what Aristotlesays

    in

    Ch.

    4

    of

    Categories

    every expression

    without combination

    ignifies,

    he

    says,

    an item

    in

    some

    one

    category.

    Professor

    Ackrill has

    rightly

    argued

    that

    this

    implies

    that

    an

    expression

    like

    '

    white

    man'

    which

    introduces

    two items

    from two

    different

    ategories

    is an

    expression

    'involving

    combination'.

    Therefore ne

    may

    conclude

    that

    the

    phrase

    kata

    symplokn

    oes not refer

    o

    sentence-making

    xclusively.

    When

    discussing

    the

    problem

    in

    the

    notes added to his

    translation

    of

    the

    Categories

    Ackrill

    suggests (73-74)

    two

    possible

    solutions:

    (a)

    the

    necessary

    and sufficient ondition for an

    expression's

    being

    'without

    combination' is

    that it

    should

    signify ust

    one item

    in

    some

    category.

    On

    this

    surmise,

    Ackrill

    adds,

    the

    author's

    statement

    at

    the

    beginning

    of Ch.

    4

    is

    analytic,

    and

    the

    examples

    in Ch. 2

    are

    mis-

    leadingly

    selective,

    since,

    on this

    criterion,

    single

    word could be

    an

    expression

    involving

    combination,

    whereas

    a

    group

    of words could

    be an

    expression

    without

    combination.

    Well,

    it will

    be

    clear

    that,

    on

    this

    assumption,

    Aristotle's

    examples

    are misleading,and that 'without ombinationwould stand forboth

    2

    The first

    nterpreter

    o do so

    was

    F. A.

    Trendelenburg,

    eschichte

    erKate-

    gorienlehre,

    erlin

    1846;

    repr.

    Olms

    1963,

    11.

    3

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    9/165

    'not

    surpassing

    one

    category'

    and

    'not

    making

    up together

    sentence'

    'involving

    combination'would

    be

    the

    case

    if,

    and

    only

    if,

    either

    or

    both conditions would not be fulfilled. To combine', accordingly,

    would stand for either

    bringing

    ogether

    ome

    elements,

    ay

    x

    and

    y,

    as

    subject

    and

    predicate

    in a sentence or

    combining

    x and

    y,

    which

    belong

    to different

    ategories.

    I will come

    back to the sense

    of com-

    bining'

    implied

    here later

    on

    (below, p.

    7-11).

    Ackrill's second

    suggestion (b)

    seems rather

    unsatisfying.

    t runs

    as follows: the distinction

    n Ch.

    2

    is,

    as it

    looks,

    a

    purely linguistic

    one between

    single

    words and

    groups

    of words

    (or

    perhaps sentences),

    whereas in Ch.

    5

    the author

    neglects

    the

    possibility

    of

    single

    words

    withcompoundmeaningand is indifferento thelinguistic omplexity

    of

    expressions

    like 'in the

    Lyceum'.

    The

    inconsistency

    on Aristotle's

    part

    is

    aggravated,

    then,

    by

    the fact that he does

    pay

    attention to

    them in De

    interpretation,

    Chs.

    5,

    8 and

    11,

    as is

    pointed

    out

    by

    Ackrill himself

    74).

    But it

    is

    precisely

    the

    supposedly 'purely linguistic'

    character of

    Aristotle's ssertions

    n

    Ch.

    2 that could make one reluctant o Ackrill's

    second

    suggestion.

    Moreover,

    t seems to be of no

    help

    either,

    ince it

    explains

    our

    confusion

    as a

    result

    of Aristotle's carelessness but

    does

    not remove its cause properly. Finally, Ackrill's suggestionimplies

    that

    Aristotle's

    distinction

    between different

    arts

    of

    language

    rests

    on rather

    superficial

    features,

    whereas

    the

    opposite

    view is

    de-

    fended

    elsewhere

    (Ackrill

    refers

    to

    Topics

    I

    4,

    101 b

    26-28,

    Poetics

    1457

    a

    25I).3

    Moravcsik

    4

    makes the usual

    start in

    pointing

    to Plato

    employing

    the term

    symplok'

    n

    Sophist,

    262 A-B

    in order to refer

    not

    to

    mere

    conjunction

    or

    juxtaposition,

    but

    ratherto the

    interweaving

    f words

    and

    phrases

    into sentences.

    This would

    suggest,

    he

    adds,

    that the

    uncombined elements are

    parts

    of

    language

    from which sentences

    can

    be

    formed.

    In his

    opinion

    this is confirmed

    by Categ.,

    2 a

    4ft.,

    where "Aristotle

    says

    that the combination of

    these items

    produces

    a

    true or

    false

    sentence"

    (127).

    For that

    matter,

    this seems to

    be an

    over-statement:

    what Aristotle

    is

    saying

    here is

    that

    none

    of the

    'things

    said

    without

    any

    combination'

    (1

    b

    25)

    is said

    just by

    itself

    in

    any

    affirmation,

    ut

    that

    by

    the combination

    of

    these

    with one

    s

    See

    also

    J.

    M.

    E.

    Moravcsik,

    Aristotle's

    heory f Categories,34-135

    n:

    J.M. E. Moravcsiked.),Aristotle, Collectionf Critical ssays,New York

    1967,125-145.

    *

    Op.

    cit.,

    27

    ff.

    4

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    10/165

    another

    an

    affirmation s

    produced;

    none of

    them,

    taken

    by

    itself,

    is eithertrue

    or

    false

    (2

    a

    4-10).

    So

    the

    only thing

    Aristotle s

    asserting

    is that a combination of those elements is needed to make up an

    affirmation;

    his is

    no

    statement

    about their

    nature

    proper

    as

    long

    as

    they

    are

    by

    themselves.So

    it

    is

    only

    implied

    that

    they

    are

    potential

    elements

    of sentences.

    t

    can

    still be asked whether

    they

    are taken as

    nothing

    ut

    potential

    parts

    of a

    sentence.

    I am afraid

    that

    Moravcsik

    goes

    even

    further

    n the

    wrong

    direction

    by having

    an

    eye

    solely

    for the

    categories

    taken s

    possible

    sentence

    elements. As

    a

    matter of fact he

    suggests

    some

    (plausible,

    I

    have

    to

    concede)

    qualification

    of the 'sentence'

    under discussion.

    But his

    exclusive concern for 'things uncombine taken as just potential

    ingredients

    f a sentence

    recludes

    him

    from

    onsidering

    hem n their

    own

    right.

    Moravcsik's

    further

    iscussion

    (i27ff.)

    is

    entirely

    focused

    on

    'sentence'.

    To

    give

    an

    example.

    As for

    phrases designating

    com-

    plex

    that crosses

    two

    categories,

    uch as

    '

    whiteman'

    '

    incontinent an

    (that

    are to be

    ruled

    out),

    Moravcsik

    thinks

    (130)

    that

    we

    have

    to

    introduce

    ome

    qualification

    which,

    however,

    s not backed

    by

    direct

    textual

    evidence,

    he

    admits,

    yet

    supported by

    what he

    (sc )

    takes

    to

    be

    the

    sense

    of

    aneu

    sympioks.

    his

    qualification,

    now,

    serves

    to

    rule out "as not completelyuncombined" all those phraseswhich the

    mere addition

    of connectors

    i.e.

    auxiliary

    expressions)

    can transform

    into a

    sentence.

    For

    though

    white

    man is

    not

    a

    sentence it can be

    expanded

    into the

    sentence

    '

    some

    man

    is

    white

    by

    the mere addition

    of

    a

    connector.

    t is for

    that

    reason,

    Moravcsik

    assumes,

    that

    phrases

    such

    as

    '

    white

    man' are

    (to

    be)

    ruled

    out.

    Summing

    up

    what,

    on

    his

    interpretation,

    s

    Aristotle's

    basic

    view,

    Moracvsik

    says

    (133)

    that

    Aristotle's

    principle' says

    that

    by

    what

    we

    would

    call

    semantic

    and

    syntactic analysis (Aristotle,

    like

    Plato,

    did not

    distinguishbetween

    them,

    as Moravcsik

    rightly

    remarks),

    we can discover cer-

    tain

    basic

    units

    among

    the

    elements

    of

    sentences

    f

    subject

    -predicate

    form

    These

    turn out to

    designate

    those

    simple

    elements of

    reality

    that

    fall under

    just

    one

    category.

    Thus

    the

    designative

    link

    between

    these

    simple parts

    of

    language

    and the

    simple

    parts

    of

    reality

    which

    fall

    under

    only

    one

    category

    s,

    according

    to

    Aristotle

    on

    M.'s

    inter-

    pretation),

    the

    key-link

    between

    the

    structure

    of

    language

    and that

    of

    reality.

    It is true, Moravcsik (p. 133) is well aware of the difficultiesm-

    plied by

    his account. The

    main

    problem

    is

    the

    unexplained

    doctrine

    of

    the

    genuine

    unity

    of a

    categorial

    expression

    (of

    course M.

    has

    5

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    11/165

    "predicate

    expression").

    Another

    problem

    is that the

    supposed

    ex-"

    elusion

    of

    phrases

    as 'white

    man' which

    rests on the

    possibility

    of

    expanding them into sentences with the help of connectors s not

    supported

    by any

    evidence

    (see

    above,

    p. 5).

    However,

    Moravcsik

    thinks

    that

    the two solutions

    suggested by

    Ackrill

    (notes,

    73-74;

    see

    above

    pp.

    3-4)

    are inferior

    to his

    own

    account

    of the

    doctrine. He

    rightlypoints

    to the

    deceptive

    character of

    Aristotle's statement

    at

    the

    opening

    of Ch.

    4)

    that

    "the elements hat

    re

    in

    no

    way

    combined"

    -^M.'s ranslation

    132);

    it is worth

    noting

    that Aristotlehas:

    "what

    is said

    without

    any

    combination",

    1

    b

    25

    designate

    items

    falling

    under

    only

    one

    of the ten

    categories,

    f the statement s to be

    taken

    as analytic, as is implied by Ackrill's first olution. For this would

    mean that

    there is

    no

    way

    of

    sorting

    out the uncombined

    elements

    except by

    observing

    whether their

    designata

    fall under

    only

    one

    category.

    If

    so,

    however,

    the

    opening

    lines of Ch.

    4

    (on

    Moravcsik's

    view)

    could

    just

    as well

    have run: "some elements

    st'c ) ignify

    ither

    substance or

    quantity

    or

    quality

    etc.,

    and we take these

    as

    being

    without

    combination".

    I

    think,

    so far

    Moravcsik's

    criticism eems

    to

    the

    point,

    with which

    may

    be

    compared

    Ackrill's

    own critical

    re-

    marks on account

    of

    his first

    uggestion.

    However,

    when he

    goes

    on

    and

    says

    that,

    moreover

    (according

    to the

    interpretation

    mplied

    by

    Ackrill's

    suggestion)

    what Aristotle

    says

    about the combined

    and

    uncombined

    'things'

    (of

    course Moravcsik has

    "parts

    of

    language",

    134)

    rests

    entirely

    on

    metaphysical

    grounds

    and thus

    may

    not

    be

    connected

    with

    what he

    says

    elsewhere bout

    the structure f

    anguage,

    Moravcsik seems

    to miss

    the

    point

    in a twofold

    way.

    First,

    what he

    labels

    'resting

    on

    metaphysical

    grounds'

    is

    nothing

    but

    the semantic

    aspect

    at

    issue.

    When

    a

    single

    word

    signifying smainn)

    something

    that crosses two categories (e.g. 'leukon'

    =

    'white thing') is used,

    what

    matters is

    its

    complex

    mode of

    signification,

    ather than

    any

    (supposed)

    complex

    metaphysical

    structure

    f

    the

    'thing' signified.

    t

    should

    be

    noted

    in this connection

    that whenever

    a

    word

    signifies

    'thing'

    falling

    under

    only

    one

    category,

    the

    metaphysical

    structure

    f

    the

    thing

    signified

    s not

    concerned either.

    Secondly,

    the

    supposed

    inconsistency

    between

    Aristotle's

    statements

    in the

    Categories

    nd

    what

    he

    says

    elsewhere seems

    to be a result

    of an

    optical

    error

    on

    Moravcsik's

    part

    (see

    below,

    our

    section

    4.6).

    -

    As

    for

    M.'s

    rejection

    ofAckrill's second suggestion, ee below, p. 17.

    It is

    worthnow

    returning

    o Moravcsik's

    basic

    view that the

    categ-

    ories

    (being

    the

    'things

    uncombined')

    are

    nothing

    but the

    genuine

    6

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    12/165

    units

    among

    the elements of

    sentences

    of the

    subject-predicate

    form.

    It

    entirely

    rests

    on

    the

    assumption

    that

    the

    phrase

    '

    aneu

    symploks'

    does still take the 'thingsthereare' as related to a potential sentence

    they

    are

    apt

    to

    make

    up,

    to

    the effect hat

    they

    must

    be

    predicates

    rather than

    things

    aid

    Well,

    this

    assumption

    will

    prove

    to

    be

    rather

    weak.

    I am

    to show

    this later

    on

    (our

    sections

    4.5

    4.7).

    But first

    discussion

    of

    some related

    questions

    as to the use

    (4.3)

    and the

    origin

    (4.4)

    of

    the list of

    categories.

    4.3

    Aristotle*

    use

    of

    the

    categories

    Apelt

    has

    tabled

    {op.

    cit.,

    140-141)

    63

    passages

    in Aristotle's

    works

    wheretwo or more categories are mentioned.They can be classified

    into three

    groups,

    according

    to their

    being

    used as either a classifica-

    tion

    of

    reality

    or

    a classification of

    sentence

    terms,

    or a

    classification

    of

    the different

    meanings

    of

    what

    may

    be

    termed

    copulative being'.

    4.31

    The

    categories

    s

    a

    classification

    f

    reality

    I

    shall

    give

    some

    examples

    which

    may

    clarify

    his use of the

    categ-

    ories.

    Topics

    I

    9

    presents

    a

    well-known

    passage

    in

    this connection.

    At

    103

    b

    7 19

    the

    propositions

    (p

    rotaseis

    logot)

    are

    distinguished

    accordingto the predicables. In the next lines (103 b 20 104 a 1) the

    division

    s based on the

    categories.

    The

    former

    ivision of the

    protaseis

    concerns

    the

    (logical)

    relations

    between

    their

    predicates

    and

    subjects,

    the

    latter divides

    them

    according

    to

    their

    contents,

    .e.

    the

    things

    they

    are about.

    The final

    part

    of the

    passage (103

    b

    35ff.)

    requires

    some

    comment.

    The

    problem

    is

    how

    to

    explain

    that

    ti

    esti

    at

    b

    35ff.

    designates

    the

    category

    of

    substance

    in

    opposition

    to the

    non-sub-

    stance

    categories

    while

    the

    same

    phrase

    was

    used at

    b

    27-35

    to

    desig-

    nate all

    categories indiscriminately.

    Well,

    it

    clearly appears

    from

    Aristotle'swords that at b

    27-35

    he is

    dividing

    subjects

    by

    means

    of the

    phrase

    4i esti and at

    b

    35ff.

    predicates

    Thus

    it

    can be

    easily

    explained

    why

    Aristotle

    concludes our

    passage

    in

    remarking

    b

    3gff.)

    "such, then,

    and so

    many

    are

    the

    subjects

    on which

    arguments

    take

    place

    [peri

    hn

    hoi

    logoi)

    and

    the

    materials

    with

    which

    they

    start

    (ex

    hn)"

    i.e. the

    predicates.

    At

    103

    b

    27-35

    it

    is the ekkeimena

    =

    subjects

    on which

    arguments

    take

    place)

    that

    are

    divided

    by

    Hi

    esti';

    5

    For this

    ection,

    ee

    also

    my

    Utrecht

    issertation,

    he

    Place

    of

    he

    ategoriesofBeing n Aristotle*Philosophy, ssen1952 henceforthuoted s De Rijk:

    1952),76-88.

    have had

    to

    correct r

    to

    adjust

    my

    former

    iews

    on

    several

    points.

    7

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    13/165

    at b

    35ff.,

    on

    the

    other

    hand,

    the

    division

    starts

    from

    the

    different

    types

    of

    predicate

    terms

    and

    is

    concerned,

    accordingly,

    with their

    relationto the subject terms.

    Topics

    9,

    103

    b 20

    104

    i :

    Next,

    hen,

    we

    have to

    distinguish

    etween

    the classes

    of

    categories

    n

    which he four

    rders n

    question

    i.e.

    the

    our

    predicables]

    re found.

    They

    are

    ten in

    number:

    ubstance,

    Quantity,

    Quality,

    Relation,

    lace,

    Time,Position,

    tate,

    Activity,

    assivity.

    or

    the accident nd

    genus

    nd

    property

    nd

    definition

    f

    anything

    ill

    al-

    ways

    be in

    one of

    these

    ategories:

    or

    ll

    the

    propositions

    ound

    hrough

    these

    viz.

    predicables]

    ignify

    ither

    substance

    ti

    esti)

    or a

    quality

    r

    quantity

    r some

    one

    of

    the

    other

    ategories.

    t

    is

    clear, oo,

    on the

    face

    of t

    that the

    man

    who

    ntends

    o

    say

    of

    something

    hat

    t is

    signifies

    sometimessubstance

    ousian

    ,

    sometimes

    quantity,

    ometimes

    quality,

    sometimesomeofthe other ategories.or when man s set before im

    [as

    a

    subject

    or

    dialectical

    iscussion]

    nd he

    says

    thatwhat

    s set

    there

    (to ekkeimenon)

    s 'a

    man' or 'an

    animal',

    he

    states

    what t

    is

    and

    sig-

    nifies substance

    ousian);

    but whena

    white olour s set

    before

    im

    and he

    says

    hat

    what

    s

    setthere

    s white'

    or

    colour',

    e

    stateswhat

    t s

    and

    signifies

    quality

    Likewise, lso,

    in

    the other

    ases.6

    For

    7

    each of such

    categories

    nvolved,

    f

    either

    t

    be

    said of itself

    i.e.

    if

    the

    eidos

    s

    said

    of the

    individual

    hing

    et

    before

    he

    respondent],8

    r

    the

    genus

    of

    the

    eidos,

    ignifies

    hat

    t is

    (ti

    esti);

    whenever,

    n

    the other

    hand,

    one

    category

    s

    asserted

    f

    another,9

    t

    is not

    what t is

    that s

    sig-

    nified,

    ut

    a

    quantity

    r

    a

    quality

    r

    one of the

    other

    ategories.

    uch,

    then,

    nd so

    many

    re

    subjects

    n

    which

    rguments

    ake

    place

    and

    the

    materials ithwhich hey tart i.e. their redicates].

    Thus Aristotle

    tries

    to

    show

    (103

    b

    25

    104

    a

    1)

    that

    when

    dividing

    the

    dialectical

    propositions

    according

    to the

    'things'

    they

    are

    about,

    one

    always

    arrives

    at one

    of

    the

    categories,

    no matter

    whether

    one

    starts

    from he

    subjects

    or the

    predicates.

    epi

    tn lln

    at b

    35

    seems

    o

    refer

    oosely

    o the other

    ypes

    f

    ekkeimena

    together

    ith he

    propositions

    f

    which

    hey

    re the

    subject

    erms, nd,

    ac-

    cordingly,

    o

    the

    other

    ategories

    hich

    upply

    he

    predicate

    erms

    or hem.

    Thereforehe translation

    n

    the

    other

    ases'

    (Oxford

    ranslation)

    s

    quite

    to

    thepoint.The phrasehekastonntoioutnb 35-36) eemsto be somewhat

    more

    pecific

    n

    referring

    o the

    categories

    nvolved.

    7

    The

    conjunction

    gar ('for')

    refers

    o

    all what s

    said

    in

    the

    preceding

    ines

    (103

    b

    21-33).

    Therefore

    e

    have

    to

    put

    a full

    top

    after

    pi

    tn

    lln t b

    55.

    De

    Riik:

    1952,p. 77

    should

    be corrected

    o this ffect.

    8

    See

    above,

    he

    end

    of note

    6.

    9

    The

    phrase

    ean

    te

    auto

    peri

    hautou*

    "

    f

    tself

    . . about

    tself)

    at b

    36

    must

    be

    opposed

    ob

    :

    hotn

    de

    peri

    heterou'

    "whenever

    on

    heother

    and,

    t .

    . .

    about

    another",

    where another

    (heteron)

    s

    to

    be

    equated

    to

    'belonging

    o

    another

    enus'

    heterogens)

    t

    Categ.

    ,

    1

    b

    16

    (if

    this s

    the

    correct

    eading

    there)

    of

    things elonging

    o

    another

    enus

    nd,

    accordingly,

    ot ubordinate

    one o theother". p.Metaph. 28,1024b 9ff. Seealsobelow, . 35.However,at b

    J5

    wheret is followed

    y

    the

    phrase

    or fthegenus s said oftheeidos',

    the

    formula

    uto

    peri

    hautou

    mustrefer

    o the

    ndividual

    hing

    nd

    its

    eidos,

    respectively.

    8

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    14/165

    Another

    example

    of

    this use of the

    list

    of

    the

    categories

    s

    found

    n

    Physics

    E

    i,

    225

    b

    5

    ff.,

    where

    Aristotle

    is

    engaged

    in

    finding

    the

    various kinds of 'movement' (kinesis by means of the list. As is

    known,

    when

    analysing

    the

    concept

    of kinsis

    movement

    nd

    change)

    he

    concludes

    that

    instances of

    t

    can

    be found n

    threeof the

    categories

    (viz.

    Quality,

    Quantity

    and

    Where).

    In De

    generai

    et

    corrupt

    (I.3,

    317

    b

    19,

    318

    a

    15,

    and

    319

    a

    12)

    our

    list serves

    for

    examining

    the

    concept

    of

    '

    genesis (coming

    into exist-

    ence).

    In De

    anima I

    1,

    402

    a

    24

    ff. nd

    I

    5,

    410

    a

    14

    ff.)

    t s

    employed

    in

    Aristotle's

    nquiry

    nto the true

    nature of the

    soul.

    It

    is

    especially

    in

    the

    Metaphysics

    that

    the ontic character

    of the

    categoriesappears as signifyingthings*to the effect, ndeed,that the

    table

    here

    seems

    to

    be

    about the

    main

    types

    of

    'things'

    signified.

    pick

    out

    some

    examples.10

    In

    Metaph.

    E

    4,

    1027

    b

    33

    1028 a

    4

    Aristotle

    distinguishes

    es-

    sential

    being'

    ('on

    kath

    hauto*)

    from

    'accidental

    being'

    (on

    kata

    symbebkos)

    nd from

    being

    as truth

    (on

    hs

    althes)

    on account of

    the

    formersontic character.11

    This

    is in

    full accordance with

    what

    we

    find

    in

    Metaph.

    7,

    1017

    a

    22-30,

    where

    Aristotle

    says

    that

    the

    kinds of

    'essential

    being'

    12

    are

    precisely

    those

    that

    are

    signifiedby the schemata of '

    katgoria

    '

    (for

    the

    ambiguity

    of the latter term,

    see

    below,

    our

    section

    4.5),

    since the

    meanings

    of

    'being*

    re

    just

    as

    many

    as

    these schemata

    indicate.

    Since,

    then,

    (he goes on)

    some

    of

    the

    'things'

    said

    (ton

    kategoroumenon)

    ignify

    substance

    (ti

    esti)t

    others

    quality,

    others

    quantity,

    ,

    'being*

    has

    a

    meaning

    answer-

    ing

    to each of

    these

    (categories).

    There

    is a

    well-known

    distinction

    between

    the

    mode

    of

    being

    of

    things

    existing

    by

    themselves and

    that

    of

    things

    which

    do not exist

    by

    themselves but

    only

    inhere in

    those of the formerkind; see also

    below,

    pp.

    22

    ff.

    Well,

    the

    opening

    chapter

    of

    Metaph

    Z

    shows

    that

    10

    For a

    more

    omplete

    iscussionf

    these

    passages,

    ee

    De

    Rijk:

    1952,

    5-43;

    56-66

    nd

    82-88,

    nd

    below

    p. 22-31.

    11

    For

    the

    correct

    meaning

    f

    accidental

    eing',

    ee

    Ross

    ad loc.

    nd De

    Rijk:

    x952>

    1-35;

    o*

    essential

    eing',

    De

    Rijk: 1952,

    35-43

    against

    Ross)

    and for

    'being

    s

    truth',

    bid.,

    -35

    against

    Ross).

    t

    should

    e

    noted, owever,

    hat

    n

    either f

    hese

    ooks

    here s an

    unfortunate

    ack of

    ttention

    o the emantical

    aspects

    f

    the

    texts

    nvolved,

    n

    that a

    term's

    redication

    s more

    n

    the

    focus

    of

    the

    nterpreters'

    nterest

    han

    ts

    naming omething.

    12

    Essential

    eing

    s what

    s

    signified

    y

    the

    essential

    nity

    f

    the

    copula

    est'

    and thepredicate erm e.g. convalescens'viz. convalescentemsse = con-

    valescentia.

    For

    a

    detailed

    discussion,

    ee

    De

    Rijk: 1952,

    35-43,

    and our

    Section

    .

    9

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    15/165

    this distinction

    runs

    parallel

    with

    that

    between

    the

    category

    of

    substance

    and

    the non-substance

    categories.

    The former s

    primarily,

    the latter are only in a secondary way:

    Metaph.

    Z

    x,

    1028

    25-30:

    Now

    these

    i.e.

    the non-substance

    ategories]

    are seen

    to be more eal

    because

    here s

    something

    efinite

    hich nder-

    lies

    them,

    .e. individual

    ubstance

    h

    ousia

    kai to kath'

    hekaston),

    hich

    is

    implied

    n such

    a

    designation Clearly,

    hen,

    t is

    in virtue f

    this

    ategory

    i.e. substance)

    hat ach of

    the others lso s.1*

    Aristotle

    s

    quite

    consistent

    n

    confining

    is

    inquiry

    nto true

    being

    (in Metaph.

    Z-H)

    to the domain

    of

    the

    categories.

    What came

    up

    for

    discussion

    n

    7,

    1017

    a 22

    30,

    viz.

    the

    categories

    s

    signifying

    hat

    is called 'essential being', returns n Z 6 after a thoroughmetaphys-

    ical discussion.

    There

    the

    categories

    turn

    out to

    signify

    he

    highest

    essences,

    which are to

    be found

    nowhere else but in

    every-day

    reality.

    As for the

    several

    categories,

    Aristotle

    more than once

    mentions

    their

    ontic

    character,

    .g.

    Metaph.

    2,

    1003

    b

    5

    ff.; Zi,

    1028 a

    25

    30

    (see

    above,

    p.

    10)

    Z

    4,

    1030

    a

    21

    ff.

    and

    b

    4

    ff.

    x,

    1045

    b

    27

    ff.

    n

    all these

    passages

    the author

    stressesthat

    all

    categories

    have an

    ontic

    character;

    the

    category

    of substance

    has this character

    primarily

    (firts),

    he non-substance

    categories

    n a

    secondary

    way

    (

    hepomens

    ,

    viz. as a result,orin virtue,of their ntimateconnectionwithprimary

    being.

    We

    may compare

    this

    with what is said

    in

    Categ.

    5,

    2 b

    7ff.

    about the

    ontic character

    of

    secondary

    substances as

    borrowedfrom

    primary

    ubstance,

    with the

    proviso,

    of

    course, that,

    in the

    Categories,

    the

    non-substance

    genera

    and

    species

    are not involved,

    (see

    below,

    p. 24;

    39-41).

    Before

    concluding

    this

    section

    it

    should

    be remarked

    that Aristotle

    in

    nearly

    all

    the

    passages

    discussed

    above,

    though using

    the

    categorial

    division for a classificationof reality, yet introducesthe categories

    themselves as

    'things

    said'

    {ta legoumena,

    a

    katgoroumena,

    nd

    the

    like).

    This

    may

    be

    an

    additional

    motive

    to discuss the two other

    ways

    in which

    the

    categories

    are used

    by

    Aristotle,

    viz.

    as

    a

    classifica-

    tion

    of

    predicates

    4.32)

    and of

    copulative

    being' (4.33).

    4.32

    The

    categories

    s

    a

    classification

    f

    sentence

    redicates

    It

    is

    on this

    use of the

    categories

    that the attention of

    all modern

    interpreters

    eems

    to be

    focused,

    to

    the effect

    hat most

    of

    them are

    in

    a

    constant

    habit of

    associating

    'category'

    exclusively

    with

    pre-

    ls

    For

    furtheriscussion

    f

    this

    mportant

    assage,

    ee

    below,

    . 23

    ff.

    10

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    16/165

    dicate.14

    Some

    of

    them

    do,

    indeed,

    see some minor

    problems

    (such

    as

    the

    non-predicable

    character of

    primary

    ubstance)

    or are cautious

    enoughto speak of"a verywide sense of predicate'

    "

    (thusMoravcsik,

    143).

    Nevertheless

    they

    do not

    make

    any

    attempt

    to clear

    up

    the

    situation.

    I

    will

    make

    an

    attempt

    at a

    reconsideration

    n

    sections

    4-5-

    4-7-

    My

    rejection

    of the

    common

    view,

    however,

    does

    definitely

    not

    imply

    a

    denial

    of the fact

    that

    the

    categories

    frequently

    eem

    to

    be

    used

    as

    (possible)

    sentence

    elements. In fact the first book

    of the

    Organon

    does

    classify

    what

    is called

    (

    Categ

    1,

    1 a

    16-17)

    'things

    that

    are

    said

    without

    combination'. Above all I

    object

    to the common

    view nthat it takes thephrase things hat re said without ombination

    to

    refer

    o the

    'things'

    concerned as

    nothing

    but

    potential parts

    of

    a

    sentence.

    On

    my

    view

    they

    are rather

    things'

    taken

    by

    themselves,

    i.e. not related

    to

    any

    possible

    sentence

    whatsoever. In other words:

    the

    expression

    without

    ombination

    (aneu

    symploks)

    hould

    be

    taken

    as

    not

    only ruling

    out

    any

    actual

    combination

    into a sentence but

    also,

    in

    fact,

    as

    setting

    side the

    very

    question

    of

    any

    possible

    sentential

    use

    of the

    terms involved.

    (See

    above,

    our

    section

    4.2

    and

    below,

    sections

    4.5

    4.7).

    In

    Categories

    ch.

    3,

    where the

    author

    discusses the

    transivity

    of

    the

    'being-said-of'

    relation,

    the

    classification of

    the

    categories

    really

    may

    also be

    taken as

    a

    table

    for

    reading

    off

    the mutual

    relations

    of

    the

    terms

    involved

    according

    to

    their

    capacity

    to

    be

    subject

    and

    predicate

    of one

    another

    (see

    however,

    below,

    p.

    35).

    Another

    important

    passage

    is

    found in

    the

    Posterior

    Analytics

    There

    (chs.

    19-22)

    15

    Aristotle

    argues

    that

    it

    is

    impossible

    that a

    demonstration should

    consist

    of an

    infinite

    chain

    of

    premisses.

    In

    14

    So

    in

    recent

    imes

    Ross,

    Kapp,

    Ackrill

    nd

    earlier

    Otto

    Apelt

    Die

    Kate-

    gorienlehre

    es Aristoteles

    in:

    Beitrge

    ur

    Geschichte

    er

    griechischen

    hilo-

    sophie,

    eipzig

    1891),

    101-216),

    H.

    Maier

    Die

    Syllogistik

    es

    Aristoteles

    II,

    277ff.);

    C.

    M.

    Gillespie,

    he

    Aristotelian

    ategories

    n:

    The Classical

    Quarterly,

    19

    (1925),75-84

    also

    in

    J.

    Barnes,

    M.

    Schofield,

    .

    Sorabji

    eds),

    Articles

    n

    Aristotle,

    Metaphysics,

    uckworth

    979,

    1-12),

    sp.

    p.

    75:

    "the scheme

    f

    the

    Categories

    ..

    is

    primarily

    onnected

    ith

    he

    use

    of

    inguistic

    hought

    o

    make

    ssertions

    italicsmine)

    bout

    reality

    nd

    hence

    with

    he

    proposition

    the

    judgement

    s

    expressed

    n

    language".

    All

    the

    same

    Gillespie

    ppears

    ften

    o

    have

    had

    an

    eye

    for

    he

    semantic

    ide

    p. 76:

    "the

    Categories

    lassify

    he

    many

    nameswhich

    we

    apply

    to

    the

    ndividual; p.

    ibid.

    pp. 78; 70; 81).15 followheexcellentnalysis iven ySirDavidRoss,Aristotle*Prior nd

    Posterior

    nalytics

    A

    Revised

    Text

    with

    Introduction

    nd

    Commentary,

    Oxford

    949,

    566

    ff.

    II

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    17/165

    Ch.

    19

    the main

    question

    is

    split up

    into

    three

    sub-questions:

    (1)

    can

    therebe

    an infinite hain of attributes

    scending

    rom

    given

    subject

    ?

    (2) can there be such a chain of subjects descending roma given

    attribute?;

    and

    (3)

    can there

    be an

    infinite

    eries

    of middle

    terms

    between

    a

    given subject

    and

    a

    given

    attribute

    The

    following

    hapters

    (20 22) argue

    that the answer

    to

    all

    these

    questions

    must be

    in the

    negative.

    One of

    the three

    proofs

    put

    forward n

    Ch.

    22 as

    to the

    third

    question

    is

    of interest

    o our

    purpose.

    It

    is a dialectical one

    and

    extends,

    with its

    preliminaries,

    from 82 b

    37

    to

    83

    b

    31.

    The

    argu-

    mentation

    runs

    as follows:

    -

    82 b

    37

    83

    a i : essential

    predicates

    of a

    subject

    must be finite

    n

    number; if the attributesin a series of predication such as we are

    discussing

    are

    substantial,

    they

    must be finite n

    number,

    because

    they

    are

    then the elements

    constituting

    he definition

    f a

    substance

    (

    Oxford

    ranslation,

    ote ad

    83

    a).

    -

    83

    a

    19-35

    on

    the

    preliminary

    ssumption

    that

    any

    predicate

    is

    invariably predicated

    strictly

    (

    hapls

    and not

    accidentally

    of the

    subject (since

    demonstrations

    depend

    on such

    predication

    for their

    force),

    it is stated

    than when

    a

    single

    attribute

    is

    predicated

    of a

    single

    subject,

    the

    predicate

    must

    affirm

    f

    the

    subject

    either some

    elementconstituting ts substance (

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    18/165

    The

    purport

    of

    the discussion

    in

    Ch.

    22 is

    clearly

    summed

    up

    by

    Ross

    as

    follows

    (579):

    "Thus

    Aristotle

    contemplates

    several finite

    chainsofpredicationreachingupwardsfrom n individualsubject like

    Callias.

    There is a

    main chain of

    which the successive

    terms re

    Callias,

    infima

    species

    to which

    Callias

    belongs,

    differentia

    f that

    species,

    proximate

    genus,

    differentia f that

    genus,

    next

    highergenus

    .

    .

    .

    -

    *

    category (i.e.

    substance).

    But

    also

    each

    of

    these elements

    in

    the

    essence

    of

    the

    individual

    subject

    entails one or more

    properties

    and

    is

    capable

    of

    having

    one or more

    accidental

    attributes,

    and each

    of

    these

    generates

    a

    similar train of

    differentiae nd

    genera, terminating

    in the

    category

    of which the

    property

    or

    accident

    in

    question

    is

    a

    specification quality, quantity,relation,etc.".

    It

    may

    be

    easily

    concluded

    from he

    discussions

    n

    Anal. Post.

    I,

    22

    that

    the

    doctrine

    f the

    categories

    an

    serve for

    ogical purposes,

    viz.

    in

    order to

    classify

    the terms of

    scientific

    premisses

    according

    to their

    capability

    of

    being

    subject

    or

    predicate

    of one

    another.

    4.33

    The

    categories

    s a

    classification

    f

    copulative

    being

    As

    we have seen above

    (4.31 p. 9-10)

    Aristotle

    eems

    to

    distinguish

    in

    Metaph.

    7,

    1017

    a

    22-30

    the

    various

    senses

    of essential

    being'

    bymeans of the doctrineof the

    categories.

    As a matter of fact the ratio

    distinguendi

    s

    a

    more substantial

    one than

    is

    suggested by

    our

    phrase

    'by

    means

    of.

    Really,

    the

    various

    senses

    are

    distinguished

    n virtue

    of the distinction etween what

    is conceived

    of as the

    categorial

    modes

    of

    being.

    We

    should notice the

    use

    of

    'epei'

    ('since')

    at

    a

    24:

    "since,

    then,

    some

    of the

    things

    said

    (ton

    katgoroumenn)ignify

    ubstance,

    others

    quality,

    other

    quantity

    . . .

    etc.,

    being'

    has a

    meaning

    nswering

    to

    each

    of these"

    (a 24-26).

    It will

    be

    remembered hat in

    our section

    4.31 (p. 7-10)

    this

    passage

    was

    adduced

    in

    support of the view that

    the

    categories may

    be taken

    as

    providing

    a

    division of

    reality.

    It

    should be

    noticed,

    however,

    that

    this

    ontological

    function of the

    categories

    is

    explained

    here

    by

    clarifying

    heir

    relationship

    to what

    may

    be

    called

    'copulative

    being'.

    The

    categories

    turn out to be

    of

    major importance

    to the

    correct

    view of

    this kind of

    being

    (einai)

    11.

    In

    Soph

    El.

    ,

    167

    a

    i

    ff.

    Aristotle

    sserts

    that

    some

    sophists

    did not

    distinguish

    between

    esse

    simpliciter einai

    hapls)

    and

    esse

    quid

    (einai

    ti).

    Our author

    himself

    does make

    the

    proper

    distinction at

    167

    a

    2,

    as well as in De interpr. 1, 21 a 24 ff. implicitly),Anal. Pr. I 38, 49

    18

    For

    a

    further

    iscussion

    f

    copulative

    eing',

    ee

    our

    ection which

    will

    deal with he

    anatomy

    f

    the

    proposition

    n

    Plato and

    Aristotle.

    13

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    19/165

    a

    31

    and Anal. Post. 1

    10,

    76

    b 6.

    That,

    on

    Aristotle's

    view,

    copulative

    being

    has as

    many

    senses as there are

    categories,

    ppears

    fromAnal.

    Pr. I 36, 48 b 2-4when taken togetherwithI 37, 49 a 6-8: "We must

    suppose

    the verb to

    belong'

    (tohyparchein)

    o have as

    many

    meanings

    as those

    in

    which B is A'

    and

    'it

    is true to

    say

    that is A' are used"

    (48

    b

    2-4)

    . . . "The

    expressions

    this

    belongs

    o that'

    nd 'that s

    true

    of

    thai'

    must be taken

    in as

    many

    ways

    as

    there

    Eire ifferent

    ategories"

    (49

    a

    6-8).

    For

    that

    matter,

    the einai ti

    (

    esse

    quid)

    is a

    genericheading

    over the

    categorial

    distinctions

    f

    being.

    For from

    he lines next fol-

    lowing

    the latter

    passage

    (49

    a

    8-9)

    it

    appears

    that the

    predicates

    within this

    or that

    category may

    be said of the

    subject

    either

    n a

    particular respect or absolutely (hapls), and either as simple or

    compound (

    haplas

    sympeplegmenas).

    Finally,

    the

    categorial

    distinction urns out to be

    indispensable

    for

    solving

    various difficulties

    oncerning

    predication.

    Antisthenes ad-

    mittedly

    denied the

    possibility

    of

    any non-identifying redication

    (see

    Plato,

    Sophist,

    251

    A; Theaet.,

    201 E ff. nd

    Aristotle,

    Metaph.

    A

    29, 1024

    b

    32-33).

    He admitted

    only

    of

    tautological predications

    uch

    as

    'man is man'

    or

    'the

    good

    is

    good'

    In his

    Metaphysics

    A 29,

    1024

    b

    29-36)

    Aristotle

    points

    out,

    011 he

    contrary,

    hat also

    non-tautological

    predication s possible, since "it is possible to describe each thingnot

    only by

    the account of tself

    i.e.

    in a

    definitory

    ay]

    but also

    by

    that

    of

    something

    else"

    (b 34-36).

    As

    a matter of

    fact,

    n Anal. Post.

    I,

    22

    (discussed

    above,

    11-13)

    is

    it

    clearly mplied

    that accidental

    (=

    non-

    definitory)predication

    is

    possible

    no

    less

    than essential

    predication,

    of which the

    tautological

    ones make

    up

    a

    special

    group (which

    is

    rejected by

    Aristotle s

    being

    useless,

    indeed;

    see

    loc.

    cit.).

    From

    I

    22,

    83

    a

    24-32

    it

    appears

    that,

    from the

    ontological point

    of

    view,

    acci-

    dental

    predicates

    are

    just

    accidents

    ( ymbebkota

    of their

    subjects,

    falling

    under one

    of the nine non-substance

    categories.

    All this seems

    to be based

    on his

    view that it is

    possible,

    and

    quite

    natural, ndeed,

    to assert

    one of

    the

    non-substance

    categories

    of substance

    (

    ousia

    .

    It

    should be

    noted

    in this connection

    that individual substance

    is

    char-

    acterized

    by

    its

    not

    being

    asserted

    of

    any subject,

    whereas

    every

    thing

    else

    (viz.

    all non-substance

    categoriesplus secondary

    substance

    and

    differentia)

    an

    be

    said

    of t. See

    e.g.

    Metaph.

    A

    8,

    1017

    b

    13

    Z

    3,

    1029

    a

    8;

    Physics

    I

    2,

    185

    a

    32

    and

    7, 190

    a x.

    Finally, it should be borne in mind that all the passages discussed

    in

    this

    section

    can

    be

    interpreted

    s

    dealing

    with

    copulative being.

    So

    they

    all admit

    of

    translatingkategorein

    Categoria

    by

    'to

    predicate'

    14

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    20/165

    ('predicate').

    Of

    course,

    the same

    applies

    a

    fortiori

    to the

    passages

    dealt with

    n our section

    4.32.

    Well,

    taking

    nto account that even the

    passages where the categoriesseem to serve as a means of classifying

    reality

    (our

    section

    4.31),

    are

    presented by

    Aristotle as

    dealing

    with

    'things'

    said rathei

    than

    things'

    see

    above,

    p. 10),

    one

    might suppose

    that

    Kapp

    and others are

    right

    n

    taking

    the Aristotelian

    categories

    as classes of

    predicates.

    So

    we have to

    deal,

    again,

    with the

    question

    are

    the

    categories

    the

    'highest

    predicates'

    ? This discussion

    will take

    place

    in

    our

    section

    4.5

    after a

    discussion

    of

    the

    possible

    origin

    of the

    list

    of

    categories.

    4.4 How did Aristotle rriveat his listofcategories?

    Sir David Ross was

    right

    n

    maintaining Aristotle,

    ondon,

    si949,

    p. 22)

    that

    the

    controversy

    bout

    the

    meaning

    of the doctrine of the

    categories

    was

    largely owing

    to the fact

    that nowhere n Aristotlewe

    see it in the

    making.

    Against Trendelenburg's

    view that the

    distinc-

    tions between

    the

    categories

    were

    derived from

    grammatical

    distinc-

    tions,

    Ross

    pointed

    out that the

    only parts

    of

    speech

    which Aristotle

    recognizes

    as such are the noun

    and the verb

    {De

    interpr.,

    hs.

    2-3),

    and that the

    doctrine

    bringstogetherthingsthat grammar separates

    (c.q.

    'Quantity'

    and

    'Quality'

    include certain nouns

    as well as

    adjec-

    tives)

    and

    separates

    things

    that

    grammar

    does not

    distinguish,

    viz.

    primary

    nd

    secondary

    substance.

    Ross himself

    hought

    t

    was

    highlyprobable

    that

    the doctrine

    began

    as

    an

    attempt

    to

    solve

    certain

    difficulties

    oncerning predication

    which had

    troubled the

    Megaric

    school and other

    earlier thinkers.The

    same view was defended

    by

    Otto

    Apelt

    as

    early

    as

    1891

    and C.

    M.

    Gillespie

    n

    1925

    ie. On

    this

    view

    Aristotle's

    purpose

    has

    been

    to clear

    up the question of predication by distinguishing he main types of

    meaning

    of those words and

    phrases

    that can

    be combined

    to make

    up

    a

    sentence.

    And in

    doing

    this he arrived at

    his classification of

    the

    main

    types

    of

    entity

    nvolved in the

    structure f

    reality {op.

    cit.

    23).

    Professor

    Ackrill,

    too,

    has

    discussed the

    question

    of how

    Aristotle

    did arrive

    at

    his list of

    categories {notes,

    8-81).

    He discerns one

    way

    of

    classifying hings

    n

    distinguishing

    ifferent

    uestions

    which

    may

    be

    asked about

    something

    nd in

    noticing

    hat

    only

    a

    limited

    range

    of

    answers

    can be

    appropriately given

    to

    any particular

    question.

    He

    thinks that such a proceduremay explain some of Aristotle's abels

    "

    Apelt,

    p.

    cit.,101-216;

    Gillespie, p.

    cit.

    15

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    21/165

    for

    categories, e.g.

    poson, poion, pou, pote,

    which, indeed,

    all are

    indefinite

    pronouns, corresponding

    as

    linguistic

    items

    with the

    respective nterrogatives so izoavwith toctov, oiv with tcoov tc.;

    see, however,below,

    p. 37).

    Some

    additional

    support

    for

    this view

    can

    be found

    n

    the

    actual

    examples

    Aristotle

    uses which

    strongly

    uggest

    that he is

    thinking

    f answers

    to

    questions

    about a man

    20

    nd

    certainly

    will have

    thought

    of the

    questions

    as

    being

    asked

    of

    a

    substance.

    An

    alternative

    way

    to

    arrive at the

    list of

    categories

    may

    be

    found,

    on

    Ackrill's

    view,

    in

    addressing

    oneself not to

    the various answers

    ap-

    propriate

    to various

    questions

    about a

    substance but to

    the various

    answers

    to one

    particular question

    which can be

    asked

    about

    any

    thingwhatsoever the question 'what s it?'. So we may ask 'what s

    Callias',

    'what

    is

    generosity?'.

    Ackrill

    interprets

    uch

    questions

    as

    asking

    in what

    species,

    genus,

    or

    highergenus

    an

    individual,

    species

    or

    genus

    is.

    Repeating

    the same

    question

    with

    reference

    o the

    species,

    genus,

    or

    higher

    genus

    mentioned

    n

    answer to

    the

    previous question,

    and

    continuing

    thus,

    in the end one shall arrive at some

    extremely

    high genera.

    As

    a matterof

    fact,

    Aristotledoes

    thinkthat

    Substance',

    'Quantity',

    'Quality'

    etc.

    are

    supreme

    and

    irreducibly

    ifferent

    enera

    under one of

    which falls each

    thing

    there s.

    Ackrill is of the

    opinion

    that these two

    ways

    of

    grouping

    things

    have led

    to the same results:

    a

    thing aptly

    introduced n answer to

    the

    question

    'of

    what

    quality?'

    (in

    Greek

    {poion),

    as in some modern

    languages,

    e.g.

    French

    quel,

    Dutch

    hoedanig,

    single-wordnterrogative,

    as should

    be

    noticed)

    will

    naturally

    be

    found,

    when classified

    in

    a

    generic

    tree,

    to fall

    under the

    genus

    of

    Quality'.

    These two

    approaches

    involve

    equivalent

    assumptions.

    The

    assumption

    that a

    given

    question

    determines

    range

    of

    answers that does not

    overlap

    with

    any range

    determinedby any otherquestion corresponds

    o the

    assumption

    that

    no item

    when defined

    per genus

    et

    differentiam

    ill be found such

    that

    it wl fall

    under

    more than

    one

    highestgenus.

    The

    assumption

    that a

    certain list

    of

    questions

    contains

    all

    the

    radically

    different

    uestions

    that

    may

    be asked

    corresponds

    to the

    assumption

    that a

    certain

    list

    of

    supreme

    genera

    contains

    all the

    supreme

    genera.

    As a matter

    of

    fact,

    Aristotle's

    use

    of

    the

    doctrine n

    Topics

    I,

    9

    may

    be adduced

    in

    support

    of Ackrill's

    view,

    (see

    above,

    p.

    7-8).

    0

    See Gillespie, p.cit.,8iff.Kapp (op.cit.,38, n. 14) remarkedhat of the21

    examples

    fdifferentategories hich heCategoriesffers,nly5 (horse,

    double,

    alf,yesterday,

    ast

    year)

    would

    be ont of

    place

    in

    a

    sentence

    with

    man

    or

    child)

    s its

    subject.

    16

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    22/165

    The

    criticism

    put

    forward

    by

    Moravcsik

    (140-142)

    does

    not

    seem

    to

    the

    point,

    (cp.

    above,

    p.

    6-7). Especially

    his remark

    that it

    would be

    surprisingf the two approaches describedbyAckrillwereto yieldthe

    same

    list

    of

    categories

    deserves

    our

    attention. For that matter

    Moravcsik

    thinks

    t

    is

    unlikely

    that

    the

    classification of the

    aspects

    of

    one

    kind

    of

    entity, e.g.

    Substance,

    should coincide with

    an ex-

    haustive

    classification

    of

    the

    essences

    of all

    entities

    that make

    up

    reality.

    To

    his

    mind such a

    correlationwill

    not hold

    unless one views

    everything

    s a modification or

    relational accident

    of

    the

    type

    of

    entitypreferred.

    Well,

    this

    way

    of

    viewing

    reality

    s,

    in

    fact,

    the one

    Aristotle

    displays

    throughout

    his

    works,

    in

    spite

    of

    Moravcsik's

    verdict that it is a trivial one. Substance, really, is the logical and

    ontological

    focus

    of

    Aristotle's

    nterest s a

    philosopher.

    In

    making

    an

    objection

    as

    to

    AckrilTs econd

    way,

    Moravcsik

    s

    no

    more

    fortunate.

    He

    objects

    (141)

    to

    AckrilTs

    view

    that

    one

    could

    never

    decide whether

    the

    highest genera

    had been

    reached. To

    take

    one of

    Aristotle's

    examples,

    why

    should one not

    arrive

    at

    change

    (kinsis)

    as

    one of

    the

    categories

    Moravcsik

    seems

    to

    be

    quite right

    n

    observing

    this,

    for the

    'what

    is

    it'

    question

    can

    certainly

    be

    answered

    n

    some

    specific

    cases

    by 'change'.

    Yet,

    as we

    know,

    Aristotle

    does

    definitely

    not take kinsis as a categorybut tries to show that is cuts across

    three

    categories (

    Physics

    E

    1,

    see

    above,

    p.

    9).

    However,

    how can

    this

    be adduced as

    a

    decisive

    argument

    gainst

    AckrilTs

    view

    ? It

    only

    proves

    that

    kinesis

    is not

    a

    simple entity

    (on

    Aristotle's

    view).

    For

    that

    matter,

    Moravcsik

    himself

    dmits

    (141)

    that

    Topics

    I

    9,

    103

    b

    22ff.

    states,

    amony

    other

    things,

    that

    the

    categories

    make

    up

    such

    an

    exhaustive

    classification

    f

    reality

    that no

    real

    essence

    will

    cut across

    categories.

    Therefore,

    whenever

    the

    'what

    is

    it'

    question

    does not

    produce

    a

    simple

    answer

    (i.e.

    a

    one-category nswer),

    either one

    has

    to

    keep

    asking (e.g.

    if one has arrivedat answers such

    as

    '

    white

    man')

    or to correct one's

    way

    of

    asking

    (e.g.

    if

    one

    has arrived at

    answers

    such

    as

    'being'

    matter'

    change

    y

    ll

    spanning

    more

    than

    one

    category).

    However,

    when

    it

    comes

    to

    explaining

    the

    proper

    meaning

    of the

    Aristotelian

    categories

    Ackrill's view

    of how

    Aristotle

    arrived

    at,

    and

    used,

    his

    list of

    categories

    seems

    to

    fail. For

    Ackrill, too,

    takes

    them

    exclusively

    as

    possible

    sentence

    predicates.

    It

    may

    be

    remarked

    n

    the

    first

    place

    that when

    taking

    the

    question-procedure

    s

    a

    way

    of

    grouping things,one is inclined to conceive of the categoriesas (pos-

    sible)

    parts

    of a

    sentence

    in

    which

    the

    answers are

    given.

    It

    is

    true,

    when Ackrill

    asserts that

    Aristotle

    reaches the

    first

    way

    of

    categorial

    17

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    23/165

    classification

    by observing

    that

    different

    ypes

    of

    answer are

    ap-

    propriate

    to

    different

    questions,

    he can find

    (79)

    some

    support

    for

    this view in the predicativeformofsome of Aristotle's xamples. For

    that

    matter,

    he

    question-answer rocedure

    s such s bound to involve

    expressions

    n a

    subject-predicate

    form.

    In

    focusing exclusively

    on

    the

    relationship

    of the

    categories

    to

    sentences

    (of

    which

    they

    are

    the

    potential parts

    indeed)

    Ackrill

    appeals

    to

    share

    the

    common view.

    I

    have

    already pointed

    (above

    p.

    15,

    n.

    19)

    to

    Apelt

    and otherswho

    saw

    the

    doctrine

    of

    the

    categories

    primarily

    s an

    attempt

    to solve certaindifficulties

    oncerning redica-

    tion

    occurring

    with the

    Megarians. Among

    them

    Ernst

    Kapp

    was most

    explicit in maintaining op. cit. 23 . 37-42) that our earliest docu-

    ment,

    the

    Topics,

    shows

    that the doctrinewas

    originally

    doctrine

    of

    sentence-predicates

    nd was

    only

    later

    transformed,

    s

    early

    as

    in

    Aristotle

    himself,

    nto a scheme for

    pigeonholing

    whatever carries a

    single

    word as its

    name. I intend to show in

    the

    next

    sections

    4.5-4.6)

    that

    Kapp

    has

    caused much confusionboth in

    opposing

    the

    syntactic

    to the

    semantic

    function

    nd in

    separating

    them

    chronologically.

    4.5

    Are the

    categories

    he

    highest redicates'?

    As has been said before

    above,

    p. 2-7;

    10-13;

    I5"I8)

    modern nter-

    preters

    associate

    the Aristotelian

    categories

    with one or other kind of

    predication.

    t need

    not

    surprise

    us that the Greek word

    katgoria'

    s

    commonly

    accepted

    as

    predicate.

    Ross

    (

    Aristotle

    23)

    takes

    'predicate'

    as the

    ordinary

    meaning

    of

    katgoria'

    and so

    does

    Kapp

    (op.

    cit.,

    21)

    who maintains

    that

    "the

    singular 'katgoria'

    means

    originally imply

    predicate,

    but the

    plural 'katgoriai'

    could

    naturally

    be

    used

    in

    the

    sense of 'different

    inds or formsof

    predicates'

    the

    full

    Aristotelian

    expressionforwhat we call a 'category',he adds, s kind ofcategory'or

    'form of

    category'

    "

    ;

    elsewhere

    37)

    he

    speaks

    of Aristotle'sdistinction

    of

    ten

    different

    lasses or forms of

    predication'.

    Ackrill

    (Notes, 80),

    too,

    holds that

    the Greek word transliterated

    category' ctually

    means

    'predication'

    or

    'predicate'

    and

    he calls the

    categories

    the ultimate

    predicates'.

    I should

    like, first,

    o make a

    preliminary

    emark on the

    original

    meaning

    of

    katgoria' .

    De

    Rijk: 1952, 89-91).

    Before

    Aristotle he

    word

    always

    had the sense

    of 'accusation'.

    However,

    the connected

    verb 'katgore' nd the primitiveword of the substantivenoun and

    the

    verb,

    that

    is,

    'katgoros',

    ad

    originally

    the neutral

    (non-hostile)

    meaning

    of

    'revealing',

    'betraying'

    (so

    Aeschylus,

    Septem,

    439;

    18

  • 8/9/2019 VIVARIUM, VOL. 18, NOS. 1-2, 1980

    24/165

    Xenophon,

    Oeconomica

    20,

    15;

    Hippocrates,

    De

    arte

    13,

    19

    Jones).

    Similarly,

    n the earliest

    passage

    extant the verb

    'katgore'

    has

    a

    non-hostilemeaning: Aeschylus, Agamemnon, 71: "ay, for t is of a

    loyal

    heart

    that thine

    eye argues

    thee"

    (

    omma sou

    katgorei

    ; .

    Herodotus

    III,

    1x5;

    Xenophon,

    Cyrop.

    I

    4,

    3;

    Plato, Phaedo,

    73

    and

    passim (see

    Friedrich

    Ast,

    Lexicon

    Platonicum,

    .v.).

    It should be

    noticed

    that

    a

    scholion ecentissimumn

    Sophocles,

    Aiax,

    907 says

    that

    both

    good

    and bad

    things

    can be the

    object

    of our verb

    (see

    Boisson,

    Anedota

    II,

    351),

    and the

    Etymologicum

    Magnum

    apparently

    holds

    'to

    speak

    about' to be

    its

    primary

    ense.

    In

    moulding

    the term

    'katgoria'

    for his

    philosophic purposes

    Aristotle seems to have returned to the original sense of the verb

    katgore.

    or the

    rest,

    the

    basic

    question

    still

    remains:

    what

    is,

    in

    this

    connection,

    he

    proper meaning

    of

    the verb

    'kaigore?'

    I will to

    come back to

    the

    question

    below

    (p. 21).

    Of

    course,

    most

    interpreters

    were

    fully

    aware that there

    are some

    embarrassing ieces

    of evidence

    against

    the

    acceptance

    of

    katgoria'

    =

    'predicate'.

    The first

    category,

    which

    should be considered the

    key-

    stone of the

    doctrine,

    as for ts

    primary

    members ndividual

    ubstances

    (primary ubstances)

    which

    are the

    proper

    nhabitants of the

    group

    of

    things

    hat are neither

    present

    n a

    subject

    nor are said

    of

    any

    subject

    (Categ.

    2,

    i

    b

    3-4;

    cp.

    5,

    2 a

    34

    ff.).

    Thus

    the

    primary

    members of the

    most

    basic

    category

    are

    anything

    but

    predicates.

    Ross

    (23)

    is

    right

    n

    rejecting

    the conclusion

    sometimes drawn from

    this

    that

    primary

    substances

    do not fit

    properly

    nto

    the doctrine of

    the

    categories.

    He

    tries to solve

    the

    problem

    in that he

    recognizes

    that

    'Socrates'

    is,

    on

    Aristotelian

    principles,

    no

    proper

    predicate;

    but if we

    ask

    what

    Socrates

    s,

    the

    ultimate,

    .e.

    the most

    general,

    answer s 'a

    substance',

    just as, if we ask what red is, the ultimateanswer s 'a quality'. Thus,

    Ross

    concludes,

    the

    categories

    are

    a

    list of the

    widest

    predicates

    which

    can

    be

    predicated

    essentially

    of the

    various nameable

    entities,

    i.e.

    which

    tell

    us what kinds of

    entity

    at

    bottom

    they

    are.

    The

    question

    at issue should

    be related to

    another

    one,

    viz.

    whether,

    generally peaking,

    the

    categories

    nclude

    only

    universais,

    or

    particu-

    lars as well. Moravcsik

    deals with

    this

    question

    in a

    remarkable

    way

    {op.

    cit.,

    142-143).

    He

    thinks

    that

    it is

    difficult o

    conceive of each

    categor