weber bioethical reasoning in islam.pdf

Upload: samir-beglerovic

Post on 02-Jun-2018

225 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/11/2019 Weber Bioethical Reasoning in Islam.pdf

    1/11

    International Journal of Arts and Sciences3(15): 607-617 (2010)

    CD-ROM. ISSN: 1944-6934

    InternationalJournal.org

    Bioethical Reasoning in Islam

    A. S. Weber, WCMC-Q, Doha, Qatar

    AbstractThis contribution surveys the process of bioethical reasoning in the Islamic

    world, comparing it to western medical ethics, in an attempt to answer the broader

    question of whether an international bioethics is feasible or even desirable. Islamic

    medical ethics is primarily based on a morally absolute system of determining

    medical ethical questions. Legal determination in Sunni Islam by Muslim

    jurisconsults (muftis) of the four schools of Shariah law (Hanbali, Malaki, Shafii and

    Hanafi) is a long-standing and well understood process of consulting the authoritative

    texts and practices of Quran, Sunna, and Ahadith, then using consent of scholars

    (ijma), analogies (qiyas), and finally invoking the principle of maslaha (publicbenefit) when authoritative texts are silent on a specific issue. These legal

    determinations are the basis for both Islamic medical codes and individual decision-

    making by Muslim doctors. This process contrasts markedly from western bioethical

    judgments which derive from one of several sources: Hippocratism, Greek and

    Roman philosophy, Judeo-Christian theology, casuistry, Benthamism, or Beauchamp

    and Childresss four principles of medical ethics. To illustrate this difference, in the

    case of a clear moral statement (explicit statement of what isfard, mandubor Sunnah,

    mubah, makruh, and haraam) originating in Quran, a jurist will in general reject a

    pragmatic or utilitarian medical argument if it contradicts the Quranic moral

    principle. Thus Islamic bioethical decision-making tends to be non-consequentialist

    and non-Benthamite in nature the purpose or end (telos) of life in Islam is toworship God, not to maximize human benefits or profits as in the Benthamite cost-

    benefit analysis thinking which dominates managed care health systems and some

    forms of bioethical reasoning in western countries.

    Keywords: Bioethics, Islam, medical ethics reasoning

    1. Introduction

    The medical world would be a much simpler place if a universal bioethics could be

    established through first principles or by consensus. Medical ethics courses could be

    standardized internationally, organs could be routinely distributed across borders, and

    medical personnel could move freely from country to country working under best

    practices with respect to their expected behavior towards patients, colleagues, the

    state, and the general public. This contribution will examine the process of reasoning

    in western medical ethics (for comparative purposes, and to establish fundamental

    definitions for discussion), and then compare these reasoning strategies to bioethical

    determinations in Islam, in order to examine the question of the possibility and

    desirability of a universal medical ethics.

  • 8/11/2019 Weber Bioethical Reasoning in Islam.pdf

    2/11

    International Journal of Arts and Sciences3(15): 607-617 (2010)

    CD-ROM. ISSN: 1944-6934

    InternationalJournal.org

    1.2 A Universal Bioethics?

    For some writers on bioethics, ethical norms are by definition universals. G.B.

    Tangwa, for example, writes: It would be more accurate to say that all ethical norms

    or rules are cultural universals, because a rule or norm cannot properly be described

    as ethical unless it is understood as having cross cultural validity, in the sense of

    being perceived as applying in all similar circumstances, irrespective of place and

    time (Tangwa, 2004: 63). Universalism in medical ethics is equally axiomatic for

    two influential medical ethicists, Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress, who

    call their primary ethical construct the common morality, a self-evident set of moral

    precepts. They define the common morality as: the set of norms that all morally

    serious persons share. The common morality contains moral norms that bind all

    persons in all place (Beauchamp and Childress, 2008: 3). They continue: Sincevirtually everyone grows up with a basic understanding of the institutions of morality,

    its norms are readily understood. All persons who are serious about living a moral life

    already grasp the core dimensions of morality. They know not to lie, not to steal

    property, to keep promises, to respect the rights of others, not to kill or cause harm to

    innocent persons, and the like. All persons serious about morality are comfortable

    with these rules and do not doubt their relevance and importance. They know that to

    violate these norms without having a morally good and sufficient reason is immoral

    and should lead to feelings of remorse. Because we are already convinced about such

    matters, the literature of ethics does not debate them. Such debate would be a waste of

    time (Beauchamp and Childress, 2008: 3).

    Tangwas and Childress and Beauchamps arguments for the a prioriand axiomatic

    philosophical status of ethical universals were probably best answered in antiquity by

    AristotlesNicomachean Ethics: now questions of conduct and expedience.do not

    fall under any art or professional tradition, but the agents are compelled at every step

    to think out for themselves what the circumstances demand, just as happens in the arts

    of medicine and navigation (Aristotle, 2.2.1104a). Aristotle later on in the same

    treatise re-emphasizes this same point: Prudence is not concerned with universals

    only; it must also take cognizance of particulars, because it is concerned with conduct,

    and conduct has its sphere in particular circumstances (Aristotle, 6.7.1141b). For

    Aristotle, specific moral dilemmas arise from very specific circumstances, thus the

    danger of forcing individual cases to fit pre-defined moral universals or schemata. Onthe opposite pole from Tangwas universalism, Tim Cullinan writes, in consonance

    with Aristotle: the great majority of the people of the world receive health care from

    systems that neither share our mind-set, nor see any point in moving towards it.

    international medical ethics, theoretically possible, certainly desirable, will remain

    wildly improbable (Cullinan, 1994: 55).

    As the sciences of human behavior are becoming increasingly grounded in genetics

    and evolutionary biology, another ethical approach called the biological basis of

    morality has gained some prominence. Could a common, shared morality be

    biologically determined? i.e., could remorse and the feelings of sadness after

    committing violence or wrongdoing against a member of ones kin group or tribe,

    simply represent an evolutionary mechanism to strengthen kinship bonds for purposes

  • 8/11/2019 Weber Bioethical Reasoning in Islam.pdf

    3/11

    International Journal of Arts and Sciences3(15): 607-617 (2010)

    CD-ROM. ISSN: 1944-6934

    InternationalJournal.org

    of group survivability, which in turn increases the potential for survival of any one

    individuals genetic inheritance? Edmund Wilson, drawing on earlier work of R.W.

    Gerard and Peter Singer stated boldly in a 1998 Atlantic Monthly article: causal

    explanations of brain activity and evolution, while imperfect, already cover most factsknown about behavior we term moral (Wilson, 1998; Gerard, 1942; Singer, 1981).

    A universal medical ethics based on biology, however, is still highly problematic

    since biological explanations of morality, while alluring, have not been

    experimentally verified. The basis of ethics is especially problematic if we look at the

    original nuances of the Greek word ethos, which can mean variously behavior,

    customs, and morals. Very few would argue that cultures share the same customs

    and behaviors, even in disguised or analogous forms. Different ethical approaches

    may be grounded in fundamentally different ways of perceiving the world.

    2. Modes of Bioethical Reasoning in Western Cultures

    Western medical ethical questions are determined in a wide variety of ways. Below is

    a description of the dominant modes.

    2.1. The Four Principles Approach

    The Four Principles Approach derives from the research and widely used textbooks of

    ethicists Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress (Beauchamp and Childress,2008) and include: 1) Respect for autonomy respecting the decision-making

    capacities of autonomous persons; 2) Nonmaleficence avoiding the causation of

    harm; 3) Beneficence providing benefits and balancing benefits against risks and

    costs; and 4) Justice distributing benefits, risks and costs fairly. These principles

    have been incorporated into a number of medical oaths, codes, and professional

    institutional by-laws, including (possibly due to the influence of the Islamic Medical

    Association of North America and the European training of some Islamic medical

    ethicists) theInternationalIslamic Code for Medical and Health Ethicspublished in

    2005 (El-Gendy, 2005).

    2.2. Hippocratism

    Hippocrates is known as the father of medicine because of his reputation for close

    clinical observation, and his seminal body of texts concerning the ethics and

    profession of medicine, including the Hippocratic Oath (ORKOS). Other important

    Hippocratic medical ethical texts include Decorum (PERI EUSHMOSUNHE), The

    Law (NOMOS), The Physician (PERI IHTROU), and Precepts (PARAGGELIAI)

    (Littr, 183963). Hippocratism established the western medical ethical principles of

    justice, confidentiality, and working for the benefit of the sick. Hippocratic ethics was

    both a deontological ethics (< Greek, = duty, obligation)which prescribed

    certain duties to physician and patient, and a virtue ethics (seeAristotelianismbelow),describing the behavior of the good physician. The persistence of Hippocratism was

  • 8/11/2019 Weber Bioethical Reasoning in Islam.pdf

    4/11

    International Journal of Arts and Sciences3(15): 607-617 (2010)

    CD-ROM. ISSN: 1944-6934

    InternationalJournal.org

    demonstrated by Kao and Parsis 2000 survey of all 122 allopathic and 19 osteopathic

    schools in the U.S., indicating that 49% of U.S. medical schools required a modified

    form of the Hippocratic Oath or the original oath itself (Kao and Parsi, 2000: 883).

    2.3. Kantianism

    Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) produced three primary works on morality: The

    Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals(1785), The Critique of Practical Reason

    (1788), and The Metaphysics of Morals (1797). Kant believed there was a single

    moral obligation called the Categorical Imperative. All moral laws arise from this

    imperative, and should be universal. All rational beings have certain inalienable

    rights; thus Kant is frequently invoked in discussions of autonomy and rights-based

    ethics in health care ethics discussions.

    2.4 Christianity

    Christianity, specifically Roman Catholicism, draws on the early Church fathers and

    medieval theologians such as St. Thomas Aquinas and St. Augustine for guidance.

    Modern Christian apologists attempt to align biomedical innovations with holy

    scripture, and patristic biblical exegesis. Roman Catholics are important contributors

    to modern ethical debates in medicine and science, in particular abortion and

    reproductive technologies.

    2.5 Aristotelianism

    Aristotles two ethical treatises, the Nicomachean Ethics and the Eudemian Ethics

    discuss eudaimonia () or having a happy spirit, and arte (),

    excellence or virtue. His main ethical questions were how do goods such as

    friendship, pleasure, virtue, honor and wealth contribute to a good or virtuous life.

    Aristotle is concerned with social relations and his ethical approach is sometimes

    characterized as a virtue ethics.

    2.6. Libertarianism

    This political philosophy or worldview places extreme emphasis on individual

    autonomy: actions are good if they respect or do not limit the freedom of the

    individual. Libertarianism is a form of radical individualism.

    2.7 Utilitarianism or Benthamism

    Jeremy Bentham (17481832) exercised a profound influence over 19th century

    English thought. Benthams philosophy of Utilitarianism forms the basis of health

    care economics (cost-benefit, cost effectiveness analyses). A utilitarian action is good

    to the extent that it maximizes aggregate utility (benefits) to the community. On an

    individual level, utility can be measured by feelings of pleasure and pain. A good act

    is one that maximizes pleasure, and minimizes pain. Utilitarianism is aconsequentialist ethics, in that it deals with the consequences of actions (end

  • 8/11/2019 Weber Bioethical Reasoning in Islam.pdf

    5/11

    International Journal of Arts and Sciences3(15): 607-617 (2010)

    CD-ROM. ISSN: 1944-6934

    InternationalJournal.org

    products). Utilitarianisms credo is "the greatest good for the greatest number of

    people or Utility. Benthams disciple John Stuart Mill wrote: the greatest

    happiness principle holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote

    happiness; wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness (Mill, 1863).

    2.8 Casuistical Reasoning (Casuistry)

    In Christianity and Judaism during the late Middle Ages and Renaissance, casuistry

    represented a form of case-based moral reasoning grounded in real cases rather than

    abstract principles or theories. Casuistry uses paradigmatic precedent cases, then

    reasons about the new case by analogy. This form of moral reasoning has had a bad

    reputation after Blaise Pascals blistering attack on Jesuit casuistry as deceitful

    sophistry in hisLettres provinciales(16567), although Stephen Toulmin and Albert

    Jonson attempted to rehabilitate the practice in their 1988 history of casuistry

    (Toulmin 1988). Much of the practical day-to-day biomedical reasoning (such as

    disciplinary actions by hospital ethics boards) is broadly casuistical in nature, being a

    case-based endeavor. Casuistry is one of the primary foundations of English common

    law.

    3 Islamic Approaches to Biomedical Reasoning

    The idea of medicine as a distinct, specialized profession requiring regulation and

    prescribed professional conduct predates both Islam and western medicine. During the

    pre-Islamic period known as the age of ignorance (Jahiliyya), the Babylonian Code

    of Hammurabi (Codex Hammurabi) of ca. 1790 B.C. first clearly outlined medicalmalpractice: If a surgeon performs a major operation on an 'awelum' (nobleman),

    with a bronze lancet and caused the death of this man, they shall cut off his hands

    (Halwani and Takrouri, 2007). After the region had been Islamicized, the Caliph Al-

    Mugtadir from the Abbasid dynasty, ordered the Chief Court-Physician Sinan Ibn-

    Thabit in 931 A.D. to screen the 860 physicians of Baghdad, and only those qualified

    were granted license to practice (al-Ghazal, 2004). Thus Islam has a long medical

    ethical tradition derived from native Semitic and Persian sources, as opposed to

    Greek, Indian, or European intellectual movements.

    3.1 Textual and Judicial Sources of Islamic Medical EthicalDecisions

    A significant source of Islamic medical ethics resides in the judicial opinions (sing.

    fatwa, pl.fatawa) issued by muftis responding to specific questions posed to them by

    individuals. Modernfatawaare subsequently gathered into collections, such as in Al

    Fatawa Al-Islamiyah (al-Musnad, n.d.) and Fatawa Islamiyya li Majmua min Al-

    Ulama Al-Afadil. As Rispler-Chaim explains: Contemporary Islamic medical ethics

    is typically conveyed in the form of an individual fatwa (judicial opinion) issued

    by a mufti (juris consult). A fatwa is usually issued in response to a supposedly real

    but sometimes hypothetical question addressed to the mufti by a Muslim man orwoman, or by some governmental agency or officer (Rispler-Chaim, in Baker, 465).

  • 8/11/2019 Weber Bioethical Reasoning in Islam.pdf

    6/11

    International Journal of Arts and Sciences3(15): 607-617 (2010)

    CD-ROM. ISSN: 1944-6934

    InternationalJournal.org

    In Sunni Islam, jurists will pronounce opinions in accordance with one of the

    established schools of law: Hanafi, Malaki, Shafii, or Hanbali. Thus using western

    categories, the process of consulting the Quranic textual authority would classifyShariah-based Islamic medical ethics as a deontological ethics, that is, based on

    foundational moral duties and obligations as expressed in an authoritative textual

    hierarchy. This hierarchy consists of Quran (Allahs revealed truth to Prophet

    Mohammed, Sunna (acts of the Prophet), and Ahadith (collected sayings of the

    prophet attributed to him by other speakers). If these texts cannot provide unequivocal

    answers, jurists turn to the consent of scholars (ijma), analogies (qiyas), and then

    finally invoking the principle of maslaha(public benefit) if necessary.

    Increasingly, Islamic medical codes are being formulated by Muslim medical

    professionals. They normally meet in conferences or congresses, examine the relevant

    medical fatawa by respected muftis, fuqaha (jurisprudence experts), and ulema(scholars), integrate these opinions with current medical opinion, and issue guiding

    statements. Organizations that have carried out this process include the Islamic

    Medical Association of North America (IMANA) in its series of perspective papers

    and the Islamic Organization for Medical Sciences based in Kuwait. In 2005, IOMS

    published the comprehensive International Islamic Code for Medical and Health

    Ethics(El-Gendy, 2005). The code was developed from a meeting of Islamic medical

    and judicial experts on December 1114, 2004 in Cairo, Egypt.

    3.2 Islamic Virtue Ethics

    The focus of this article is the medical ethics in Sunni Islam (the dominant form of

    Islamic practice in the world), although Iranian writers following Shiaa Islam have

    developed a substantial body of bioethical research and debate, and in practice, Iran

    has developed several unique medical ethical innovations such as a controversial

    kidney donor system (Mahdanian, 2008). Also, Turkish writers have been frequent

    contributors to recent debates on Islamic ethics.

    Islam has a tradition of professional medical ethics, Adab or Akhlaq which isboth

    analogous and historically related to Aristotelian virtue ethics. Also, the Hippocratic

    Oath and other works of Hippocrates and Galen (Unani Tibbin Arabic) were known

    to Islamic physicians (Khan, 2007) and a section of Galens commentary on theHippocratic Oath has survived in Arabic (Rosenthal, 1990). A similarity in basic

    principles can be seen in Hippocrates dictum Primum non nocere (first do no

    harm) as compared with the widely applied principle of Shariah law la darar wa la

    dirar or there shall be no harm inflicted or reciprocated, which applies to all areas

    of Islamic life, but is also frequently invoked in medicalfatawa.

    Ali bin Sahl Rabban at-Tabari (d. 855) wrote in his Firdaus al-Hikma fi al-tibb[The

    Paradise of Wisdom in Medicine] In [Physicians], five qualities are united which are

    united in no others. The first of these is the continuous care of that from which they

    hope to provide well-being for everyone, second, their battle with illness and with

    suffering which is hidden from their view; third, respect for kings and the common

    people who have great need of their services; fourth, the agreement of all people with

  • 8/11/2019 Weber Bioethical Reasoning in Islam.pdf

    7/11

    International Journal of Arts and Sciences3(15): 607-617 (2010)

    CD-ROM. ISSN: 1944-6934

    InternationalJournal.org

    respect to their skill; fifth, the name for them, which is borrowed from the name of

    God (Baker et. al, 2009: 276.) Similarly, the Adab al-Tabib by Al-Ruhawi states

    train by employing good morals and actions with sympathy, mercy, gentleness,

    chastity, courage, generosity, justice. Do not aim for an excess of worldly riches(Levey, 1967).

    Thus, many moral dilemmas or moral problems in medical praxis can be solved, or

    will never arise, simply by visiting a virtuous physician as outlined in the Islamic

    virtue ethics tradition. The criteria for the virtuous Islamic physician is similar to

    reliable legal witnesses in Shariah law: Muslim patients should assume their

    physician is a) an adult Muslim, b) sane, c) unbiased, d) and adil, which means

    possessing a good and blameless reputation.

    4 Principle of Maslaha and Consequentialist Ethics in Islam

    Besides referring to textual authority, one other principle of law can be used when

    analogies are not sufficient: the principle of common benefit or maslaha. Maslaha

    appears to have points in common with Benthams principle of utility or aggregate

    good. Do Islamic medical ethics therefore possibly possess a consequentialist aspect?

    Abdulaziz Sachedina provides the following case illustrating the use of

    consequentialist ethical reasoning in Islam: A Muslim before dying has swallowed a

    valuable object belonging to a Muslim orphan. Is it permissable to dissect the cadaver

    to retrieve the object? Many Sunni jurists have said Yes because of the

    consequences. The swallowed object may form part of the orphans inheritance. The

    consequences to the orphan, the loss of his right to his inheritance, outweighs thefoundational Islamic moral principle of not violating the dignity of the dead

    (Sachedina, 2009: 8). The rights of orphans, the subject of several passages in the

    Quran, form a strong concern in Islam, undoubtedly because Prophet Muhammed

    himself was an orphan and knew that they needed special protections. Similarly, for

    new medical technologies, such as cloning and embryonic stem cell research, Islamic

    jurists by necessity will sometimes employ consequentialist arguments, such as

    weighing the benefits to society.

    The writings of Sheikh Yusuf al-Qaradawi, a resident of Qatar and a highly respected

    Muslim scholar, also sometimes reflect consequentialist reasoning when he has

    written about medical ethical issues. During the human cloning debates of the 1990safter Dolly the Sheep became the first mammal to be cloned from an adult somatic

    cell, Qaradawi dismissed the Scientists are playing God arguments about human

    cloning prevalent in the West, declaring: no one can challenge or oppose God's will.

    Hence, if the matter is achieved then it is certainly under the will of God. Nothing can

    be created without God's will creating it. As long as humans continue to do so, it is

    the will of God. Actually, we do not search for the question whether it is in accord

    with the will of God (Qaradawi in Sachedina, 1998).

    Instead, Sheikh Qaradawi looks at the effect (consequences) of cloning on the Muslim

    family. The fundamental ethical question, as Qaradawi states, is whether this

    procedure interferes with growing up in a family that is founded upon fatherhood and

  • 8/11/2019 Weber Bioethical Reasoning in Islam.pdf

    8/11

    International Journal of Arts and Sciences3(15): 607-617 (2010)

    CD-ROM. ISSN: 1944-6934

    InternationalJournal.org

    motherhood. It is in a family that the child is nurtured to become a person

    (Sachedina, 1998).

    Communitarian values tend to override individual rights in Islamic countries.Autonomy, however, an individuals right to medical decision-making about their

    own bodies, is a central feature of Western medical ethics. Numerous examples which

    can be readily drawn from any Arabian Gulf hospital demonstrate that families and

    male guardians demand and expect to be part of the medical decision making process.

    Family concerns can take precedence over individual patient concerns. Thus a

    fundamental principle of Western medical ethics, the respect for autonomy in

    Beauchamp and Childresss four-principle schema, is simply viewed from a different

    cultural standpoint in the West and in Islamic societies.

    5 Precedence of Clearly Defined Quranic Principlesover Consequentialism

    In Islamic medical ethic a pragmatic (utilitarian) argument will never take precedence

    over a clearly articulated principle originating in the Quran. However, Islamic

    jurisprudence does maintain the important principle of maslaha, or public benefit,

    which could be loosely construed as Benthams utility. But even a bioethical

    argument deriving from perceived public or personal benefit cannot override Quranic

    injunction, being unanimously viewed as the word of God by the Muslim ummah.

    For example, The Islamic Medical Association of North America (IMANA) states:

    We believe infertility is a disease and desire for a cure by an infertile couple isnatural (IMANA, 2005). IMANA is therefore in principle supportive of Assisted

    Reproductive Technologies (ART), due to the importance of family, the blessings of

    children, as well as pragmatically the pro-natalist policies in some Muslim countries,

    particularly the Gulf, in which foreign expatriate workers substantially outnumber the

    local populations.

    But the Quran says: It is He who has created man from water: then has He

    established relationships of lineage and marriage: for thy Lord has power (over all

    things) (25: 54). Based partly on this verse, IMANA has forbidden certain assisted

    reproductive procedures such as surrogate motherhood as well as sperm and ova

    donations between non-related donors because this violates the injunction of mixing

    lineages (nasab) and therefore would technically result in adultery or fornication

    (zina) (IMANA, 2005: 7).

    Therefore the Quranic rule is used by IMANA, after reviewing the appropriate

    fatawa, to restrict certain forms of ART and surrogacy despite the obvious benefits to

    the infertile couple and benefits to Islam of increasing the number of faithful (ummah)

    and providing children to faithful parents (a blessing in Islam).

    6 Conclusion

  • 8/11/2019 Weber Bioethical Reasoning in Islam.pdf

    9/11

    International Journal of Arts and Sciences3(15): 607-617 (2010)

    CD-ROM. ISSN: 1944-6934

    InternationalJournal.org

    As we have seen, in Islam the primary source of moral reasoning is in Gods

    commandments and acts and sayings of Prophet Muhammed, which is derived from

    an agreed upon authoritative hierarchy of Quran, Sunna, Hadith, Shariah law based

    on these sources, and fatawa achieved by appeal to the several forms of reasoningoutlined above.

    In the West, in contrast, we find a wider range of sources of moral reasoning in

    medical ethics, including Judeo-Christian theology and Greek and Roman philosophy.

    Specifically, in medicine, Hippocrates has been the primary source of professional

    ethics, and Aristotle and Plato for the virtue ethics of the physician. Due to the

    syncretism of such Islamic medical authors as Ibn sina, who synthesized much of

    previous Greek medical knowledge during the Middle Ages, and the translation

    movements of Baghdad and later Salerno and Andalusia, western and Islamic medical

    ethical traditions have experienced some overlap.

    An in-depth comparison of Islamic and western secular bioethics by Sharmin Islam in

    his 2008 Ph.D. thesis for the Universiti Sains Malaysia on Assisted Reproductive

    Technologies (ART) came to essentially the same general conclusion as this study

    and therefore serves as a good final statement: The findings of the study are that

    Western Secular Bioethics in relation to ART holds a consequential colour while

    Islamic Bioethics has both a deontological and consequential tone. Hence, broadly

    speaking, these two systems of bioethics hold an incommensurable relation to each

    other (Islam, 2008). Due to the difference in modes of bioethical reasoning, and the

    differing historical circumstances and viewpoints of Islamic and non-Islamic cultures

    (although all modern medicine has been strongly impacted at one point by

    Hippocrates), a universal medical ethics will probably not be feasible in the near or

    distant future.

    References

    Al-Ghazal, Sharif Kaf. 2004. The Influence of Islamic Philosophy and Ethics on the

    Development of Medicine During the Islamic Renaissance. Journal of the

    International Society for the History of Islamic Medicine. 3.6: 2004.

    Al-Musnad, Muhammad bin 'Abdul-'Aziz. n.d. Fatawa Islamiyah-English. Vols. 18.

    Riyadh, Saudi Arabia: Darussalam.

    Aristotle. 2004.Nicomachean Ethics. Ed. and trans. Hugh Tredennick, J. A. K.

    Thomson, Jonathan Barnes. London: Penguin Books.

    Baker, R.B., L.B. McCullough, eds. 2009. The Cambridge World History of Medical

    Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.

    Beauchamp, T. and F. Childress. 2008. Principles of Biomedical Ethics. 6thEdition.

    Oxford: Oxford UP.

  • 8/11/2019 Weber Bioethical Reasoning in Islam.pdf

    10/11

    International Journal of Arts and Sciences3(15): 607-617 (2010)

    CD-ROM. ISSN: 1944-6934

    InternationalJournal.org

    Cullinan, Tim. 1994. International Medical Ethics, Is it Possible?Medical Ethics.

    20: 1994.

    El-Gendy, A.R., ed. 2005. The International Islamic Code for Medical and Health

    Ethics.Kuwait: IOMS.

    Gerard, R.W. 1942. A Biological Basis for Ethics. Philosophy of Science. 9.1:

    1942.

    Halwani, T., M. Takrouri. 2007. Medical laws and ethics of Babylon as read in

    Hammurabi's code (History). The Internet Journal of Law, Healthcare and Ethics.

    4.2: 2007.

    IMANA. 2005.Islamic Medical Ethics: The IMANA Perspective.http://www.imana.org/ethics.html.

    Islam, Sharmin. 2008.Ethics of Assisted Reproductive Medicine: A Comparative

    Study of Western Secular and Islamic Bioethics. Ph.D. thesis, Universiti Sains

    Malaysia (USM), January, 2008.

    Jonsen, A., S. Toulmin. 1990. The Abuse of Casuistry: A History of Moral Reasoning.

    Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Kao, A.C., Parsi, K.P. 2000. Content Analyses of Oaths Administered at U.S.

    Medical Schools in 2000.Academic Medicine9: 2000.

    Khan, S. 2007.Islamic Medicine. London: Routledge.

    Levey, M. 1967.Medical Ethics of Medieval Islam with Special Reference to Al-

    Ruhawis Practical Ethics of the Physician. Philadelphia: Transactions of the

    American Philosophical Society. n.s. 57.3: 1967.

    Littr, E. 18391863.Hippocrate: Oeuvres completes d'Hippocrate.10 vols. Paris:

    J.B. Bailliere.

    Mahdanian, A. 2008. Iranian Model of Living, Non-Related Kidney Donation: A

    Style to be Condemned Ethically.Medical Humanities34: 2008.

    Mill, J.S. 1863. Utilitarianism. London: Parker, Son, and Bourn.

    Pascal, B. 16567.Lettres provinciales. Paris.

    Rosenthal, F. 1990. An Ancient Commentary on the Hippocratic Oath. In Science

    and Medicine in Islam.London: Variorum.

    Sachedina, A.A. 1998. "Human Clones: An Islamic View." In The Human CloningDebate. Ed. Glenn McGee. Berkeley, CA: Berkeley Hills Books.

  • 8/11/2019 Weber Bioethical Reasoning in Islam.pdf

    11/11

    International Journal of Arts and Sciences3(15): 607-617 (2010)

    CD-ROM. ISSN: 1944-6934

    InternationalJournal.org

    Sachedina, A.A. 2009.Islamic Biomedical Ethics: Principles and Applications.

    Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Singer, Peter. 1981. The Biological Basis of Ethics. In The Expanding Circle:

    Ethics and Sociobiology. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux 1981.

    Tangwa, G.B. 2004. Between universalism and relativism: a conceptual exploration

    of problems in formulating and applying international biomedical ethical guidelines.

    Journal of Medical Ethics30: 2004.

    Wilson, E.O. 1998. The Biological Basis of Morality.Atlantic Monthly. April:

    1998.