a hipotese do cerebro social kevin dunbar

Upload: cesar-pessoa

Post on 07-Aug-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    1/13

    ARTICLES 

    The Social Brain HypothesisRobin I.M. Dunbar

     The concensus view has tradition-ally been that brains evolved to pro-cess i nformation of ecological rel-evance. This view, however, ignores animportant consideration: Brains are

    exceedingly expensive both to evolveand to maintain. The adult humanbrain weighs about 2% of body weightbut consumes about 20% of total en-ergy intake.2 In the light of this, it isdifficult to justify the claim that pri-mates, and especially humans, needlarger brainsthan other species merelyto do the same ecological job. Claimsthat primate ecological strategies i n-

    volve more complex problem-solv-ing3,4 are plausible when applied to

    the behaviors of particular species,such astermite-extraction bychimpan-zees and nut-cracking by Cebu s  mon-keys, but fail to explain why allprimates, including those that are con-ventional folivores, require larger brainsthan thoseof all other mammals.

    An alternative hypothesis offeredduring the late 1980s was that pri-mates’ large brains reflect the compu-

    tational demands of the complex so-cial systems that characterize theorder.5,6 Pri ma facie, this suggestionseems plausible: There is ample evi-dence that primate social systems aremore complex than those of otherspecies. These systems can be shownto involve processes such as tacticaldeception5 and coalition-formation,7,8

    which are rare or occur only in sim-pler forms in other taxonomic groups.Because of this, the suggestion wasrapidly dubbed theM achiavellianintel-ligencehypothesis, although there is agrowing preference to call it thesocialbrain hypothesis.9,10

    Plausible asit seems, thesocial brainhypothesis faced a problem that wasrecognized at an early date. Specifi-cally, what quantitative empirical evi-dencethere was tended to favor oneorthe other of the ecological hypoth-eses,1 whereas the evidence adducedin favor of the social brain hypothesiswas, at best, anecdotal.6 In this article,I shall first show how we can testbetween the competing hypothesesmore conclusively and then considersome of the implications of the social

    brain hypothesis for humans. Finally,I shall briefly consider some of theunderlying cognitivemechanismsthatmight beinvolved.

    TESTING BETWEEN ALTERNATIVE

    HYPOTHESES

     To test between the competing hy-potheses, we need to force thehypoth-eses into conflict in such a way thattheir predictions are mutually contra-dictory. This allows the data to dis-

    criminate unequivocally betweenthem. In the present case, we can dothis by asking which hypothesis bestpredicts the differences in brain sizeacross the primate order. To do so, weneed to identify the specific quantita-tivepredictions made by each hypoth-esis and to determine an appropriatemeasure of brain size.

     The four classes of hypotheses thathave been put forward to explain pri-mate brain evolution are epiphenom-enal, developmental, ecological, andsocial in orientation (Table 1). Theepiphenomenal and developmental hy-potheses share the assumption thatevolution of thebrain (or brain part) isnot a consequence of external selec-tion pressures but rather simply aconsequence of something to do withthe way biological growth processesareorganized.The epiphenomenal hy-potheses thus argue that brain evolu-tion is a mere byproduct of body sizeevolution, and that brain part size is,in turn, a byproduct of total brainevolution.11

     The developmental versions differonly in that they provide a more spe-cific mechanism by presuming thatmaternal metabolic input is the criti-cal factor influencing brain develop-ment. This claim is given credibility bythe fact that the bulk of brain growthin mammals occurs prenatally. In-deed, it appears to be the completionof brain development that precipitatesbirth in mammals, with what littlepostnatal brain growth occurs beingcompleted by the time an infant isweaned. From this, the conclusion isdrawn that brain evolution must beconstrained by the spare energy, overandaboveher basal metabolic require-ments, that the mother has to channelinto fetal development.12–14 Some evi-dence in support of this claim comesfrom the fact that frugivorous pri-mates have larger adult brains relative

    Robin Dunbar is Professor of EvolutionaryPsychology and Behavioural Ecology atthe University of Liverpool, England. Hisresearch primarily focuses on the behav-ioral ecology of ungulates and human andnonhuman primates, and on the cognitivemechanisms and brain components thatunderpin the decisions that animals make.He runsa large research group, withgradu-ate students working on many differentspecies on four continents.

    Key Words: brain size, neocortex, social brainhypothesis, social skills, mind reading, primates

    Conventional wisdom over the past 160 years in the cognitive and neurosciences

    has assumed that brains evolved to process factual information about the world.

    Most attention has therefore been focused on such features as pattern recognition,

    color vision, and speech perception. By extension, it was assumed that brains

    evolved to deal with essentially ecological problem-solving tasks. 1

    178 Evolutionary Anthropology

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    2/13

    to body size than do folivorous pri-mates.1  This has been interpreted asimplying that frugivores have a richerdiet than folivores do and thus havemore spare energy to divert into fetalgrowth. L arge brains are thus seen asa kind of emergent epigenetic effect of sparecapacity in thesystem.

    Both kinds of explanations sufferfrom the problem that they ignore afundamental principle of evolutionarytheory, which is that evolution is theoutcome of the balancebetween costsandbenefits. Becausethecost of main-taining a large brain is so great, it isintrinsically unlikely that large brainswil l evolve merely because they can.Largebrains will evolve only when theselection factor in their favor is suffi-cient to overcome thesteep cost gradi-ent. Developmental constraints areun-doubtedly important, but rather thanbeing causal their role is that of aconstraint that must be overcome if larger brains areto evolve. In addition,Pagel and H arvey15 have shown that

    the energetic arguments do not addup: P recocial mammals do not havehigher metabolic rates than do altri-cial mammals despite the fact thatthey have neonatal brain sizes thatare, on average, twice as large. Wetherefore do not need to consider ei-

    ther epiphenomenal or developmentalhypotheses any further in the contextof this article.

     This does not necessarily mean thatthese explanations are wrong. Bothkinds of explanation may be true inthe sense that they correctly identifydevelopmental constraints on braingrowth, but they do not tell us whybrains actually evolved as they did. They may tell us that if you want toevolve a large brain, then you mustevolve a large body in order to carrytheenergetic costs of doing so or a diet

    that ensures sufficient energy to pro-vide for fetal brain development. Nosuch allometric argument can everimply that you have to evolve a largebrain or a large body. The large brainor brain part is a cost that animalsmust factor into their calculationswhen considering whether or not alargebody or a largebrain is a sensiblesolution to a particular ecologicalproblem. Shiftsto more energy-rich ormore easily processed diets may beessential precursors of significant in-creases in brain or brain part size.2

     This would explain why frugivoreshave larger brains than folivores doand why hominids have larger brainsthan great apes do.

     This leaves us with just two classesof hypotheses, the ecological and thesocial. At least three versions of theformer can be identified, which I willterm the dietary, mental maps, andextractive foraging hypotheses. I n es-sence, these argue, respectively, that

    primatespecies will need larger brainsif (i) they arefrugivorousbecausefruitsare more ephemeral and patchy intheir distribution than leaves are, andhence require more memory to find;(ii) they have larger ranges becauseof the greater memory requirements of large-scale mental maps; or (iii) theirdiet requires them to extract resourcesfrom a matrix in which they are em-bedded (e.g., they must remove fruitpulp from a case, stimulate gum flowfrom a tree, extract termites from atermitarium, or hunt species that are

    cryptic or behave evasively).For obvious reasons, I used theper-

    centageof fruit in thediet as an appro-priateindex for thedietary hypothesis.I used the size of the range area andthelength of theday journey asalterna-tive indices for the mental mappinghypothesis, though I present the dataonly for thefirstof thesehere. Thefirstindex correspondsto thecasein whichanimals have to be able to manipulateinformation about the locations of re-sources relative to themselves in aEuclidean space (an example would

    be the nut-cracking activities of the Taı̈ chimpanzees16); the second corre-sponds to the possibility that the con-straint lies in theneeds of some aspectof inertial navigation. The extractiveforaging hypothesisis less easy to char-acterize in quantitative terms becausethere is no objective measure of thedegree to which diets vary i n theirextractiveness. However, Gibson4 pro-vided a classification of primate spe-cies i nto four categories of diet thatdiffer in their degree of extractiveness.We can test this hypothesis by askingwhether there is a consistent variationin brain size among these four catego-ries, with the species having the moreextractive diets having larger brainsthan those with the less extractivediets.

    Finally, we need an index of socialcomplexity. In my original analyses, Iused social group size as a simplemeasure of social complexity. Althoughat best rather crude, this measurenonetheless captures oneaspect of the

    TABLE 1. Hypotheses Used to Explain the

    Evolution of Large Brains in Primates

    Hypothesis Sources

    A. Epiphenomenal 

    hypotheses 

    1. Large brains (or brain parts)

    are an unavoidable conse-

    quence of having a largebody (or brain) 11, 70

    B. Ecological hypotheses 

    2. Frugivory imposes higher

    cognitive demands than

    folivory does 1, 65

    3. Brain size constrains the size

    of the mental map: 1

    (a) constraint on size of

    home range

    (b) constraint on inertial

    navigation (day journey

    length)

    4. Extractive foraging

    hypothesis 3, 4

    C. Social hypotheses 5. Brain size constrains size of

    social network (group size):

    6, 71,

    72

    (a) constraint on memory

    for relationships

    (b) constraint on social skills

    to manage relationships

    D. Developmental 

    hypotheses 

    6. Maternal energy con-

    straints determine energy

    capacity for fetal brain

    growth

    12, 13

    46, 55,

    73

    Because the cost of

    maintaining a large brainis so great, it is

    intrinsically unlikely that

    large brains will evolvemerely because they

    can. Large brains will

    evolve only when the

    selection factor in theirfavor is sufficient to

    overcome the steep costgradient.

    ARTICLES    Evolutionary Anthropology 179

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    3/13

    complexity of social groups, the factthat information-processing demandscan be expected to increase as thenumber of relationships involved in-creases. M ore importantly, perhaps,this measure has the distinct merit of being easily quantified and widelyavailable. Although it is possible toconceive of a number of better mea-sures of social complexity, the appro-priate data are rarely available formore than oneor two species.

     The second problem concerns themost appropriate measure of brainevolution. Hitherto, most studieshaveconsidered the brain as a single func-tional unit. This view has been rein-forced byF inlayandDarlington,11 whoargued that theevolution in brain partsize closely correlates with the evolu-tion of total brain size and can beexplained simply in terms of allome-tric consequences of increases in totalbrain size. However, Finlay and Dar-lington failed to consider thepossibil-ity that changes in brain size mightactually be driven by changes in itsparts rather than in the whole brain. This is especially true of the neocor-tex, for its volumeaccounts for 50% to80% of total brain volumein primates. Thus, changes in the volume of theneocortex inevitably have a large di-rect effect on apparentchangein brainvolume that may bequiteunrelated tochanges in other brain components. This point is given weight by the factthat Fi nlay and Darlington themselves

    showed that neocortex size is an expo-nential function of brain size, whereasother brain componentsare not.

    Finlay and Darlington11 notwith-standing, there is evidence that brainevolution has not been a history of simple expansion in total volume.Rather, brain evolution has been mo-saic in character, with both the rateand the extent of evolution havingvaried between components of thesys-tem. M acL ean17 pointed out manyyearsago that primatebrain evolutioncan be viewed in terms of three majorsystems (his concept of the triunebrain). These systems correspond tothe basic r eptili an brain (hind- andmidbrain systems), the mammalianbrain (palaeocortex, subcortical sys-tems), and theprimatebrain (broadly,the neocortex). A more importantpoint, perhaps, is that variations canbe found within these broad catego-ries in the rates at which differentcomponents expanded, which, in atleast some cases, have been shown tocorrelatewith ecological factors.10Par-tialling out the effects of body size onthe size of brain components suggeststhat the story may be more complexthan Finlay and Darlington11 sup-posed, with some remodeling of braingrowth patterns occurring in thetran-sitions between insectivores, prosim-ians, and anthropoids.18

     The important point in the presentcontext is that, asPassingham19 noted,relative to the more primitive parts of 

    the brain such as the medulla, theneocortexshowsdramatic andincreas-ing expansion across the range of pri-mates (Fig. 1). The neocortex is ap-proximately the same size as themedulla in insectivores; however, it isabout 10 times larger than the me-

    dulla in prosimians and 20–50 timeslarger in the anthropoids, with thehuman neocortex being as much as105 times thesizeof themedulla.

     This suggests that rather than look-ing at total brain size, as previousstudieshavedone, weshould in fact beconsidering the brain system, namelythe neocortex, that has been mainlyresponsible for the expansion of theprimate brain. From the point of viewof all the hypotheses of primate brainevolution, this makes sense: The neo-

    cortex is generally regarded as beingthe seat of those cognitive processesthat we associate with reasoning andconsciousness, and therefore may beexpected to be under the most intenseselection from the need to increase orimprovethe effectivenessof thesepro-cesses.

    One additional problem needs to beresolved. In his seminal study of brainevolution, J erison20 argued that brainsize can beexpected to vary with bodysize for no other reason than funda-mental allometric relationshipsassoci-ated with the need to manage thephysiological machinery of the body.What is of interest, he suggested, isnot absolute brain size, but the sparebrain capacity over and above thatneeded to manage body mechanisms.

    Figure 1. Neocortex volume as a ratio of medulla volume in different groups of primates (after

    Passingham19). Source: Stephan et al29

    . . . brain evolution has

    not been a history ofsimple expansion in total

    volume. Rather, brain

    evolution has beenmosaic in character,

    with both the rate and

    the extent of evolution

    having varied betweencomponents of the

    system.

    180 Evolutionary Anthropology   ARTICLES 

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    4/13

    For this reason, J erison derived hisencephalization quotient. All subse-quent studies have used body size astheappropriatebaselineagainst whichto measure relativedeviations in brainsize. However, a problem has sinceemerged: Brain size is determined

    early in development and, comparedto many other body systems, appearsto be highly conservative in evolution-ary terms. As a result, body size canoften changedramatically bothontoge-netically across populations in re-sponse to local environmental condi-tions21 and phylogenetically22,23

    without corresponding changes inbrain size. This is particularly con-spicuous in thecase of phyletic dwarfs(e.g., calli trichids and perhaps mod-ern humans andhylobatids22) and spe-cies in which body size may have

    increased in response to predationpressure following the occupation of more open terrestrial habitats (e.g.,papionids24).

     The labili ty of body size thereforemakes it a poor baseline, though onethat probably is adequate for analyseson the mouse-elephant scale. Conse-quently, it is necessary to find an inter-nally moreconsistent baseline for taxo-nomically fine-grained analyses.Willner22 suggested that either molartooth size or brain size may be suit-able because both are developmen-

    tally conservative. Becausewe arecon-cerned with brain part size, someaspect of brain size seems the mostappropriate.

    At this point, threeoptionsareavail-able. Onei s to compare theneocortex,the brain part of interest, with thewhole brain; the second is to use therest of thebrain other than the part of interest; the third is to use some lessvariable primitive component of thebrain, such as the medulla, as a base-line. Two options are in turn availableas mechanisms for controlling forbrain size in each of these cases. Oneis to use residuals from a commonregression line against the baseline(e.g., theresidual of neocortex volumeon total brain volume or medula vol-ume). Theother choiceis to useratios.

    We have considered and tested allthese options10,24 (see Box 1). The re-sults are virtually identical irrespec-tive of which measure i s used. Oneexplanation for this may be that allthesemeasuresactually indexthesame

    thing, absolute neocortex size, mainlybecause the neocortex i s such a largecomponent of the primate brain. In-deed, the use of absolute neocortexsize produces results that are similarto thoseobtained from relativized indi-ces of neocortex volume.24,25  This

    makes some sense in computationalterms: As Byrne26 has pointed out, a10% increasein the processing capac-ity of a small computer is worth agreat deal less in information-process-ing terms than is a 10% increase in alarge computer. Although residualsfrom a common regression line wouldconventionally be considered the saf-est measure, and have been used inmany recent analyses,27,28 I shall con-

    tinue to use my original ratio indexbecause it provides the best predictor(see Box 1).

    Finally, it is now widely appreciated

    thatcomparativeanalyses need to con-

    trol for the effects of phylogeneticinertia. Closely related species can be

    expected to have similar values for

    many anatomical and behavioral di-

    mensions merely by virtue of having

    inherited them from a recent common

    ancestor. In such cases, plotting raw

    data would result in pseudoreplica-

    tion, artificially inflating the sample

    size by assuming that closely related

    speciesare actually independent evolu-

    tionary events. The ways of dealing

    with this problem include plotting

    means for higher taxonomic units,per-

    forming nested analyses of variance

    using phylogenetic levels as factors,

    comparing matched pairs of species,

    andmaking independent contrasts that

    control directly for phylogeny. Each

    method has its own advantages and

    disadvantages, but the first and third

    procedures are particularly associated

    with loss of information and small

    sample sizes. I shall use the first and

    last method, the last because it allows

    individual species to becompared, but

    the first because it allows grade shifts

    within data sets to be identified (a

    problem that independent-contrasts

    methods have difficulty dealing with).

    I shall take the genus as a suitable

    basis for analysis becausegenera typi-cally represent different reproductive

    or ecological radiations and thus are

    more likely to constitute independent

    evolutionary events.

     The resulting analyses arerelatively

    straightforward: Figure 2 presents the

    datafor neocortex ratio for theanthro-

    poid primate species in the data base

    of Stephan, Frahm, and Baron.29 Neo-

    cortex size, however measured, does

    not correlate with any index of the

    ecological hypotheses, but does corre-

    late with social group size. Similarfindings were reported by Sawaguchi

    and K udo,30 who found that neocortex

    size correlated with mating system in

    primates. Barton and Purvis31 have

    confirmed that using both residuals of 

    neocortex volume on total brain vol-

    ume and the method of independent

    contrasts yields the same result. Both

    Barton10 and T. J offe (unpublished)

    have repeated the analyses using the

    medulla as the baseline for compari-

    son. M ore importantly, Barton and

    Purvis31 have shown that while rela-tive neocortex volume correlates with

    group size but not the size of the

    ranging area, the reverse i s true of 

    relative hippocampus size. A correla-

    tion between range area and hippo-

    campus sizeis to be expected because

    of hippocampal involvement in spatial

    memory.32,33  This correlation demon-

    strates that it is not simply total brain

    sizethati simportant (apotential prob-lem, given the overwhelming size of 

    The neocortex isgenerally regarded as

    being the seat of thosecognitive processes that

    we associate with

    reasoning andconsciousness, and

    therefore may be

    expected to be underthe most intense

    selection from the needto increase or improvethe effectiveness of

    these processes.

    ARTICLES    Evolutionary Anthropology 181

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    5/13

    the primate neocortex). M oreover, itpoints to the specific involvement of the neocortex.

     The validity of this relationshipcould be tested directly by using it topredict group sizes in a sample of 

    species for which brain volumetricdata were not available in the originalsample of Stephan, Frahm, and

    TABLE 2. Stepwise Regression Analysis

    of Indices of Brain Component Volume

    as Predictors of Group Size in

    Anthropoid Primates, Based on

    Independent Contrasts Analysis*

    Independent Variable   t P 

    Absolute brain volume   1.69 0.107

    Residual of brain volume

    on body mass   0.91 0.371Absolute telencephalon

    volume   1.72 0.101

    Residual of telen-

    cephalon volume on

    body mass 0.61 0.546

    Residual of telen-

    cephalon volume on

    brain volume 1.69 0.107

    Absolute neocortex

    volume   1.70 0.104

    Residual of neocortex

    volume on body mass 0.56 0.583

    Residual of neocortex

    volume on brain

    volume 1.60 0.136Neocortex ratio (against

    rest of brain) 3.79 0.001

    *Sample: 24 species of anthropoid pri-

    mates from Stephan, Frahm, and

    Baron.29

    Box 1. How to Measure Brains

    R. Dunbar and Tracey H. Joffe

    The different ways of measuring

    relative brain size have raised doubts

    as to the most appropriate technique

    to use.65 Many researchers have pre-

    ferred to use residuals from the com-

    mon regression line of best fit for the

    data set concerned. This provides a

    measure of the extent to which brain

    (or brain part) volume deviates from

    what would be expected for an aver-

    age member of the relevant taxon of

    the appropriate size. Although ratios

    have been used to compare the rela-

    tive size of brain components,29,66 this

    has been criticized on the grounds

    that trade-offs within the brain may

    mean that a given index simply mea-

    sures total brain size (or the size of a

    brain part) and thus does not remove

    the effects of absolute size. Ratios

    may also be prone to autocorrelation

    effects, especially when the baseline

    is taken to be the whole brain and, as

    in the case of the neocortex, the part in

    question is a major volumetric compo-

    nent of the brain.

    Although there are likely to be

    some trade-offs of this kind within the

    brain, the fact that neocortex volume

    increases progressively across the pri-

    mate order suggests that such con-straints are less likely to have a signifi-

    cant effect on a ratio measure. Of

    course the residuals procedure is itself

    a ratio: Encephalization-type indices

    are calculated as actual volume di-

    vided by predicted volume (which,

    when data are logged, becomes the

    conventional actual minus predicted

    values). Thus, ratio measures per se

    may not be the problem. Rather, the

    substantive objection is whether or not

    a ratio partials out the allometric ef-

    fects of body size. In fact, it seems that

    neocortex ratios are not correlatedwith the basal brain (i.e., brain volume

    excluding the neocortex) within major

    taxonomic groups (unpublished analy-

    ses). Consequently, this criticism has

    less force than it might appear to have

    on first sight. Moreover, any index that

    uses the whole brain as its base is

    likely to suffer from autocorrelation

    effects. Because the neocortex is such

    a large proportion of the brain in pri-

    mates, residuals of neocortex from

    total brain size may simply be a mea-

    sure of neocortex plotted against it-

    self.

    To consider the problem in more

    detail, we ran a stepwise regression

    analysis on the 24 species of anthro-

    poid primates, including humans, on

    the data base of Stephan, Frahm, and

    Baron,29 with group size as the depen-

    dent variable and nine indices of rela-

    tive brain or brain-part volume as inde-

    pendent variables. In addition toneocortex ratio, these included total

    brain volume as well as telencephalon

    and neocortex volume, each taken as

    absolute volume and as a residual

    from both body mass and brain vol-

    ume. All variables were log10-trans-

    formed for analysis. In both cases,

    neocortex ratio was selected as the

    variable of first choice. We carried out

    both regressions on generic plots and

    independent contrast analyses. For

    the contrasts analysis, the best fit

    least-squares regression equation

    through the origin was:

    Contrast in log10 (group size) 3.834

    * Contrast in log10 (neocortex ratio)

    (r 2 0.395, F 1,22   15.39,

    P  0.001).

    With all other variables held constant,

    none of the other eight indices made a

    significant contribution to the variabil-

    ity in group size in either analysis.

    Table 2 gives the results for the inde-

    pendent contrasts analysis.

    Neocortex ratio is thus the singlemost powerful predictor of group size

    in these species. While the biological

    significance of this variable remains

    open to interpretation, the fact that it

    provides the best predictor, indepen-

    dently of all other confounding mea-

    sures, suggests that more detailed

    consideration needs to be given to its

    significance and meaning. It may be,

    for example, that body size, rather

    than being a determinant20 is simply a

    constraint on neocortex size: A spe-

    cies can evolve a large neocortex only

    if its body is large enough to provide

    the spare energy capacity through

    Kleiber’s relationship for basal meta-

    bolic rate to allow for a larger than

    average brain. This interpretation is

    implied by the Aiello and Wheeler2

    ‘‘expensive tissue hypothesis.’’It would

    also be in line with Finlay and Darling-

    ton’s11 claim that in mammals the evo-

    lution of brain-part size is driven, devel-

    opmentally at least, by the evolution of

    the whole brain, thus generating very

    tight correlations between brain-part

    size and total brain size.

    182 Evolutionary Anthropology   ARTICLES 

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    6/13

    Baron.29 I did this by exploiting thefact that neocortex ratios can be pre-dicted from total brain volume,34 aresult that, in fact, follows directlyfrom the Finlay and Darlington11 find-ings. The result was a significant fitbetween predicted neocortex ratio andobserved mean group size for a sam-ple of 15 New and Old World monkeyspecies.35

    Barton27 noted that the originalanalyses of Dunbar24 seemed to implythat variation in neocortex size wasmuch greater than variation in groupsize in the prosimians. Using Dun-bar’s24 data on group size, Barton sug-gested that the relationship betweenneocortex and group size did not ap-ply in the case of prosimians. How-ever, the data on prosimian groupsizes in this sample suffered from apaucity of data, particularly for thenocturnal species. Because many of theseare described as semi-solitary, itwas conservatively assumed in theDunbar24 database that their groupsize was one. M ore recent field studieshave produced markedly improved es-

    timates of the sizes of social groupsand, in the case of the semi-solitaryspecies, daytime nest groups.36 Re-analysis of the data for prosimiansusing these improved estimates of so-cial group size suggests that thesespecies do in fact adhere to the samerelationship between neocortex andgroup size as that which pertains forother primates.25 M ore importantly,the regression line for this taxon isparallel to, but shifted to the left of,that for other anthropoid primates(Fig. 3).

     This relationship has now beenshown to hold for at least four othermammalian orders: bats,10 carnivoresand insectivores,37,38 and odontocetecetaceans.39,40 In the case of the insec-tivores, the data points are shifted farto theleft of those for the primates, asmight be expected of a taxonomicgroup that is considered to bebroadlyrepresentative of the ancestral mam-mals.37 However, the relationship isweak in this case, probably becauseestimates of group size are particu-larly uncertain for insectivores.

    Surprisingly, the data for the carni-

    vores map directly onto those for the

    simian primates, that is, the regres-

    sion lines for the two data sets do not

    differ significantly. However,thecarni-

    vores do not exhibit as widea range of 

    neocortex ratios or group sizes as do

    anthropoid primates. The fact that theprosimians lie to the left of both these

    taxonomic groupsimplies that thecar-

    nivores represent an independent evo-

    lutionary development alongthesameprinciples astheanthropoid primates,

    thedifferencebeing that they just have

    not taken it as far as primates have.

    One reason for this may be that thecarnivore social world is olfaction-dominated rather than vision-domi-

    nated, as in the case of the primates.

    Barton10,27,41 has pointed out that the

    shift to a diurnal lifestyle based on

    color vision, perhaps initially diet-

    driven, but leading to a shift into vi-

    sion-based communication, may bethekey featurethat has spurred on the

    dramatic development of the primate

    neocortex.

    Figure 2. Relative neocortex size in anthropoid primates plotted against (a) percentage of fruit in the diet, (b) mean home-range size scaled as

    the residual of range size regressed on body weight (after Dunbar24), (c) types of extractive foraging (after Gibson4), and (d) mean group size.

    ((a), (b), and (d) are redrawn from Dunbar 24, Figures 6, 2 and 1, respectively; (c) is from Dunbar,35 Figure 2.)

    ARTICLES    Evolutionary Anthropology 183

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    7/13

    REFINING THE RELATIONSHIP

     The social brain hypothesis impliesthat constraints on group size arisefrom the information-processing ca-pacity of the primate brain, and thatthe neocortex plays a major role inthis. However, even this proposal isopen to several interpretations as tohow the relationship is mediated. Atleast five possibilities can be usefullyconsidered. The constraint on groupsize could be a result of the ability torecognize and interpret visual signalsfor identifying either individuals ortheir behavior; limitations on memoryfor faces; the ability to remember whohas a relationship with whom (e.g., alldyadic relationships within the groupas a whole); the ability to manipulateinformation about a set of relation-ships;andthecapacity to processemo-tional information, particularly withrespect to recognizing and acting oncuesto other animals’emotional states. Theseare not all necessarily mutuallyexclusive, but they do identify differ-ent points in thecognitivemechanismthat might be thecrucial information-processing bottleneck.

    Although visual mechanisms arelikely to be important for social inter-action, and may well have been the

    initial kick for the evolution of largebrains in primates,10 it seems intrinsi-cally unlikely that the ultimate con-straint lies in the mechanisms of thevisual system itself.28 Although thereis a correlation between the relative

    sizeof the visual cortex and group sizein anthropoid primates, thefit is muchpoorer, and theslopesignificantly shal-lower than that between thenonvisualneocortex and group size(r 2 0.31 vsr 2 0.61, respectively) (Fig. 4). Partialcorrelation analysis indicates that onlythe correlation for the nonvisual rela-tionship remains significant when theother component is held constant28

    (though this is not true for prosim-ians25). A more important point is thatthe volume of the lateral geniculatenucleus, a major subcortical way sta-tion in visual processing, does notcorrelatewith groupsizeat all, indicat-ing that pattern recognition per se isunlikely to be the issue.28 It may be of some significance that the absolutesize of thevisual cortex seemsto reachan asymptotic value i n the great apeclade, whereas the nonvisual neocor-tex continues to increase in size. Oneinterpretation of this is that visualprocessing does not necessarily con-tinue to improve indefinitely as the

    size of thecortical processingmachin-ery increases, at least relative to theopportunitycost of taking cortical neu-rons away from other cognitive pro-cesses.

    It seems equally unlikely that theproblem lies with a pure memory con-

    straint, though memory capacity obvi-ously mustimposesomekind of upperlimit on the number of relationshipsthat an animal can have. There arethree reasons for this claim. First, inhumans at least, memory for faces isan order of magnitude larger than thepredicted cognitive group size: Hu-mans are said to be able to attachnames to around 2,000 faces but havea cognitive group size of only about

    150. Second, there is no intrinsic rea-

    son to suppose that memory per se is

    the issue. The social brain hypothesis

    is about theability to manipulateinfor-

    mation, not simply to remember it.

     Third, and perhaps most significantly,memories appear to be stored mainly

    in the temporal lobes,42 whereas re-

    cent PE T scan studies implicate the

    prefrontal neocortex, notably Brod-

    man area 8, as the area for social skills

    and, specifically, theory of mind.43

    Frith44 has suggested that memories

    and representations for objects or

    events may involve interactions be-

    tween several levels of the neocortex

    depending on the kinds of operations

    Figure 3. Mean group size plotted against neocortex ratio for individual genera, shown

    separately for prosimian, simian, and hominoid primates. Prosimian group size data, from

    Dunbar and Joffe,25 include species for which neocortex ratio is estimated from total brain

    volume. Anthropoid data are from Dunbar.24 Simians: 1,  Miopithecus;  2,  Papio;  3,  Macaca;  4,

    Procolobus;  5,  Saimiri;  6,  Erythrocebus;  7,  Cercopithecus;  8,  Lagothrix;  9,  Cebus;  10,  Ateles;  11,

    Cercocebus; 12, Nasalis; 13, Callicebus; 14, Alouatta; 15, Callimico; 16, Cebuella; 17, Saguinus; 

    18, Aotus;  19,  Pithecia;  20,  Callicebus. Prosimians: a, Lemur;  b,  Varecia;  c,  Eulemur;  d,  Propithe- 

    cus; e, Indri; f, Microcebus; g, Galago; h, Hapalemur; i, Avahi;  j, Perodictus.

    The social brainhypothesis implies thatconstraints on group size

    arise from the

    information-processingcapacity of the primate

    brain, and that the

    neocortex plays a majorrole in this. However,

    even this proposal is

    open to severalinterpretations as to how

    the relationship is

    mediated.

    184 Evolutionary Anthropology   ARTICLES 

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    8/13

    involved. These interactions could oc-cur between the sensory and associa-tion cortices (perceiving an object),between the association and frontal

    cortices (remembering an object), andamong all three (being aware of per-ceiving an object). It is worth notinginthis context that although social skillsarecommonly disrupted by damage tothe prefrontal cortex, memory forevents and peopleis not.42

    It seems unlikely that emotional re-sponses per se are the substantiveconstraint. Although the correct emis-sion and i nterpretation of emotionalcues is of singular importance in themanagement of social relationships,45

    there is little evidence that thesubcor-tical areas principally associated withemotional cuing (for example, theamygdala in the limbic system) corre-late in any way with social groupsize.28 Indeed, K everne, Martel, andNevison46 point out that there hasbeen progressivereduction in therela-tive sizes of the ‘‘emotional’’ centers inthe brain (the hypothalamus and sep-tum) in favor of the ‘‘executive’’ cen-ters (the neocortex and striate cortex)during pri mate evolution. They inter-

    pret this in terms of a shift away fromemotional control of behavior to moreconscious, deliberatecontrol.

     The only remaining alternative is

    that the mechanisms involved lie i nthe ability to manipulate informationabout social relationships themselves. This claim is supported by six addi-tional lines of evidence that point tothe fundamental importance of socialskills in the detailed management of social relationships.

    Onei s the fact that close analysis of the data on group size and neocortexvolumesuggests that there are, in fact,distinct grades even within theanthro-poid primates (Fig. 3). Apes seem to lieon a separategradefrom themonkeys,which in turn lie on a separate gradefrom theprosimians. The slopecoeffi-cients on these separate regressionlinesdo not differ significantly, but theintercepts do. It is as if apes requiremore computingpower to manage thesame number of relationships thatmonkeys do, and monkeys i n turnrequiremorethan prosimiansdo. Thisgradation corresponds closely to theperceived scaling of social complexity.

     The second line of evidence is that

    therates with which tactical deceptionare used correlate with neocortexsize.26 Species with large neocortexratios make significantly more use of tactical deception, even when the dif-ferential frequencies with which theselarge-brained species have been stud-

    ied are taken into account. Third, Pawlowski, Dunbar, andLowen47 have shown that among po-lygamous primates the male rank cor-relation with mating success is nega-tively related to neocortex size(Fig. 5). This is just what we would predict if the lower ranking males of specieswith larger neocortices were able tousetheir greater computational capaci-ties to deploy more sophisticated so-cial skills, such as theuseof coalitionsand capitalizing on female matechoice, to undermine or circumvent

    thepower-based strategies of thedomi-nant animals.

     The fourth line of evidence is J of-fe’s48 demonstration that adult neocor-tex sizein primates correlates with thelength of the juvenile period, but notwith the length of gestation, lactation,or the reproductive life span, eventhough total brain size in mammalscorrelates with thelength of thegesta-tion period.49,50 This suggeststhat whatis most i mportant in the developmentof a large neocortex in primates is notthe embryological development of brain tissueper se, which is associatedmainly with gestation length, butrather the ‘‘software programming’’that occurs during the period of sociallearning between weaning and adult-hood.

    Fifth, Kudo, Lowen, and Dunbar51

    have shown that grooming cliquesize,a surrogate variable that indexes alli-

    Figure 4. Independent contrasts in mean group size plotted against contrasts in the visual

    cortex and the volume of the rest of the neocortex (nonvisual neocortex) for individual

    anthropoid species. Note that the visual cortex is here defined as visual area V1; the nonvisual

    cortex is the non-V1 volume of the neocortex and thus includes some higher order visual

    processing components (e.g.,visual area V2). Unfortunately, thedata base of Stephan, Frahm,

    and Baron29 doesnot allow usto define our measure ofthe nonvisual areaany more finely than

    this. (Reprinted from Joffe and Dunbar,28 Fig. 1.)

    . . . there is no intrinsicreason to suppose that

    memory per se is the

    issue. The social brainhypothesis is about the

    ability to manipulate

    information, not simply toremember it.

    ARTICLES    Evolutionary Anthropology 185

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    9/13

    ancesize, correlates rather tightly withrelative neocortex and social groupsize in primates, including humans(Fig. 6). The human data derive fromtwo samples: hair-care networksamong female bushmen52 and supportcliques among adults in the UnitedK ingdom.53 What is remarkableis howclosely the human data fit with thedata from other primate species.Grooming cliques of this kind invari-ably function as coalitions in primategroups. Coalitionsarefunctionally cru-cial to individuals within these groupsbecause they enable the animals tominimize thelevels of harassment andcompetition that they inevitably sufferwhen living in close proximity to oth-ers.54 Coalitions essentially allow pri-mates to manage a fine balancing actbetween keeping other individuals off their backs while at the same timeavoiding driving them away altogetherand thereby losing the benefits forwhich the groups formed in the firstplace. Theseresults can thus probablybe interpreted as a direct cognitivelimitation on the number of individu-als with which an animal can simulta-neously maintain a relationship of suf-

    ficient depth that they can berelied onto provide unstinting mutual supportwhen one of them is under attack.Because this is the core process that

    gives primatesocial groups their inter-nal structure and coherence, this canbe seen as a crucial basis for primatesociality.

    Fi nally, K everne, Martel, and Nevi-son46 have suggested that the neocor-tex and striate cortex, those areas of 

    theprimate brain that are responsiblefor executive function, are under ma-ternally rather than paternally im-printed genes (i.e., genes that ‘‘know’’which parent they came from),whereas the converse is true for thelimbic system, those parts of thebrainmost closely associated with emo-tional behavior. They interpret this inrelation to the cognitive demands of the more intense social life of femalesin matrilineal female-bonded societ-ies.

    IMPLICATIONS FOR HUMAN

    GROUPS

     The fact that the relationship be-tween neocortex size and what I willterm thecognitivegroup size holdsupso well in so many different taxonomicgroups raises the obvious question of whether or not it also applies to hu-mans. Wecan easily predict a valueforgroup sizein humans. Doingso,whichis simply a matter of using thehumanneocortex volume to extrapolate avalue for group size from the primate

    Figure 5. Independent contrasts in the Spearman rank correlation (r s ) between male rank and

    mating success plotted against contrasts in neocortex size for two different male cohort sizes (4

    to 8, and 9 to 30 males) for individual species. The regression equations for the two cohort sizes

    are significantly differentfrom b 0. Thespecies sampled are C. apella, P. entellus,C. aethiops,

    M. fuscata, M. mulatta, M. radiata, M. arctoides, P. cynocephalus, P. anubis, P. ursinus,  and  P.

    troglodytes. (Redrawn from Pawlowski, Dunbar, and Lowen,47 Fig. 1.)

    Figure 6. Mean grooming clique size plotted against mean neocortex ratio for individual

    primate genera. The square is Homo sapiens. Species sampled are L. catta, L. fulvus, Propithe- 

    cus, Indri, S. sciureus, C. apella, C. torquatus, A. geoffroyi, A. fusciceps, P. badius, P. entellus, P.

    pileata, P. johnii, C. campbelli, C. diana, C. aethiops, C. mitis, E. patas, M. mulatta, M. fuscata,

    M. arctoides, M. sylvana, M. radiata, P. anubis, P. ursinus, P. cynocephalus, P. hamadryas, T.

    gelada, P. troglodytes, P. paniscus. (Redrawn from Kudo, Lowen, and Dunbar,51 Fig. 4a.)

    186 Evolutionary Anthropology   ARTICLES 

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    10/13

    equation, produces a value in the or-der of 150. The real issue is whetherhumans really do go around in groupsof this size.

    I dentifying the relevant level of grouping to measure in humans isdifficult because most humans live ina series of hierarchically inclusivegroups. This, in itself, is not especiallyunusual: Hi erarchically structuredgroups of this kind are characteristicof primates54 and may be typical of many mammals and birds.55 At leastin the case of the diurnal primates, itseems that, with a few notable excep-tions, the various species’ groupingpatterns exhibit an overt level of stabil-ity at roughly the sameposition in thehierarchy across a wide range of taxa.M oreover, because the various layersof this hierarchy appear to be inti-mately related to each other, probablythrough being part of a seriesof cause-and-consequence chains,51 it wouldnot matter which particular groupinglevel (for example, stable social group,

    network, or grooming clique) wastaken to bethe grouping criterion.

     The problem with respect to hu-mans is that it is difficult to identifywhich of the many potential groupinglevels is functionally or cognitivelyequivalent to the particular level of grouping that I happened to use forprimates. This difficulty is particularlyintrusive in this case because humanslivein a dispersed social system some-times referred to as a fission-fusionsystem. In order to get around thisproblem, I adopted the conversestrat-egy in my original analysis,56 askingwhether there was any group sizecon-sistently characteristic of humans thatwas of about the requisite size and, if so, whether its intrinsic psychologicalcharacteristics were similar to thosefound in primategroups.

    Because of the structural complex-ity of postagricultural societies, I con-sidered only traditional hunter-gath-erer and small-scale horticulturalsocieties. Although census data on

    such societies are limited, those thatare available suggest that there is in-deed a consistent group size in theregion of 150 individuals (Fig. 7). E x-cept among settled horticulturalists,where the village seems to be therelevant unit, this typically involves

    theset of individuals from whom over-night camps are easily and regularlyformed. Such groups are not oftenconspicuous as physical entities (theydo not often appear together in oneplace at one time), but they do invari-ably have important ri tual functionsfor the individuals concerned. AmongAustralian aboriginals, for example,the relevant group is the clan, whichmeets from time to time in jamboreeswhere the rituals of life (marriagesand rites of passage) are enacted andtales of the old times are rehearsed to

    remind everyone who they are andwhy they hold a particular relation-ship to each other. Indeed, this genu-inely seems to be the largest group of people who know everyone in thegroup as individuals at the level of personal relationships. Thi s is essen-tially the definition that holds in thecaseof primates.

    A more extensive exploration of hu-man groups in other contextssuggeststhat groupings of this size are wide-spread and form an important compo-nent of all human social systems, be-

    ing present in structures that rangefrom business organizations to thearrangement of farming communi-ties.56 Estimates of community sizefor two traditional farming communi-ties in the United States, H utteritesandan East Tennesseemountain com-munity, and of actual social networksizes (from small-worlds experiments)(shown astriangles on theright sideof Fig. 7) fit very closely within the rel-evant range of group sizes.

    It is easy, of course, to play thenumerologist in this context by find-ing groups that fit whatever group sizeonewishes to promote. The importantfeature to note here, however, is thatthe various human groups that can beidentified in any society seem to clus-ter rather tightly around a series of values (5, 12, 35, 150, 500, and 2,000)with virtually no overlap in the vari-ance around these characteristic val-ues. They seem to represent points of stability or clustering in thedegrees of familiarity within the broad range of 

    Figure 7. Mean sizes for different types of groups in traditional human societies. Individual

    societies are ordered along the bottom, with data for three main types of social groups

    (overnight camps, clans or villages, and tribes). Societies include hunter-gatherer and settled

    horticulturalists from Australia, Africa, Asia, and North and South America. The triangles give

    mean group sizes for three contemporary United States samples: mean network size from

    small-worlds experiments (N 2),67 mean Hutterite community size,68 and the size of an East

    Tennessee mountain community.69 The value of 150 predicted by the primate neocortex size

    relationship (from Fig. 1d) is indicated by the horizontal line, with 95% confidence intervals

    shown as dashed lines.

    ARTICLES    Evolutionary Anthropology 187

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    11/13

    human relationships, from the mostintimateto themost tenuous.

    COGNITIVE MECHANISMS

     The suggestion that the mecha-nismsinvolved in theseprocesses maybe concerned with social skills raisesthe issue alluded to by the originalM achiavellian intelligencehypothesis,namely to what extent cognitively so-phisticated mechanismsconferring theability to ‘‘mind-read’’ might be in-volved. Tactical deception, in its strongsense, i mplies the ability to hold falsebeliefs and, thus, the presence of theability known as ‘‘theory of mind’’(ToM). Of course, tactical deception aspracticed by primates on a daily basismay not, as Byrne26 himself haspointed out, be quite as sophisticatedas first impressions suggest. A moreconventional behaviorist accountbased on simple associative learningcan i nvariably be given for almost allexamples reported in theliterature.

    Nonetheless, convincing evidencesuggests that humans at least do use ToM in executing some of their moremanipulative social activities. Andwhilewe may not wish to attribute full ToM to all primates, at least circum-stantial evidence suggests that basic ToM is present i n great apes and thatmonkeys may aspire to a level thatByrne26 has described as level 1.5 in-tentionality (full ToM being level 2intentionality) (see Box 2). The differ-ence has been summed up rather

    graphically by Cheney and Seyfarth’s57

    observation that apes seem to be goodpsychologists in that they are good atreading minds, whereas monkeys aregood ethologists in that they are goodat reading behavior—or at least atmaking inferences about intentions inthe everyday sense, even i f not in the

    philosophical senseof belief states.

    Evidence that chimpanzees aspireto at least a basic form of ToM is

    provided by their performance on ex-

    perimental false-belief tasks.58–61 These

    studies haveattempted to develop ana-

    logues of the classic false-belief tasks

    used with children.62 Though it is clear

    that chimpanzees do not perform to

    the level at which fully competent

    children perform, O’Connell’s61 experi-

    ments at least suggest that they can

    perform at the level of children who

    stand on the threshold of acquiring ToM. M ore importantly, chimpanzeesdo better than autistic adults, one of whose defining features is the lack of  ToM, on thesametests.

     That mind-reading, thebasis of ToM,is difficult to do has been shown byexperiments on normal adults testedon ‘‘advanced’’ ToM tasks, up to fifth-order intentionality.62 These data sug-gest that normal humans find tasks of greater than fourth-order intentional-

    ity exceedingly hard to do. The higherror rates at theselevels do not reflecta memory retention problem: All sub- jects passthe tests that assess memoryfor the story line. M oreover, the samesubjects show considerable compe-tence on reasoning tasks that involvecausal chains of up to the sixth order. The difficulty seems genuinely to besomething to do with operating withdeeply embedded mental states.

    One possibly significant observationin this context is that the visual andnonvisual components of the primate

    neocortex do not increase isometri-cally. Although initially there is a moreor less linear increase in the visualarea V1 with increasingsizeof therestof the neocortex, this drops off withinthe great ape clade. From gorillasthrough humans, increases in the sizeof thevisual area progress moreslowlythan do increases in thesizeof therestof theneocortex.28 Weinterpret this asimplying that beyond a certain pointthe acuity of the visual system does

    Box 2. A Beginner’s Guide to Intensionality

    Computers can be said to know

    things because their memories con-

    tain information; however, it seems

    unlikely that they know that they know

    these things, in that we have no evi-

    dence that they can reflect on their

    states of ‘‘mind.’’ In the jargon of the

    philosophy of mind, computers are

    zero-order intensional machines. In-

    tensionality (with an   s) is the term

    that philosophers of mind use to refer

    to the state of having a state of mind

    (knowing, believing, thinking, wanting,

    understanding, intending, etc).

    Most vertebrates are probably ca-

    pable of reflecting on their states of

    mind, at least in some crude sense:

    they know that they know. Organisms

    of this kind are first-order intensional.

    By extension, second-order inten-

    sional organisms know that someone

    else knows something, and third-order

    intensional organisms know that some-

    one else knows that someone else

    knows something. In principle, the se-

    quence can be extended reflexively

    indefinitely, although, in practice, hu-

    mans rarely engage in more than

    fourth-order intensionality in everyday

    life and probably face an upper limit at

    sixth-order (‘‘Peter knows that Jane

    believes that Mark thinks that Paula

    wants Jake to suppose that Amelia

    intends to do something’’).

    A minimum of fourth-order inten-

    sionality is required for literature thatgoes beyond the merely narrative (‘‘the

    writer wants the reader to believe that

    character A thinks that character B

    intends to do something’’). Similar abili-

    ties may be required for science, since

    doing science requires us to ask

    whether the world can be other than it

    is (a second-order problem at the very

    least) and then ask someone else to

    do the same (an additional order of

    intensionality).

    . . . apes seem to be

    good psychologists inthat they are good atreading minds, whereas

    monkeys are good

    ethologists in that theyare good at reading

    behavior . . .

    188 Evolutionary Anthropology   ARTICLES 

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    12/13

    not increase linearly with size. Be-cause thetotal size of theneocortex islimited by embryological and ener-getic factors, this means that dispro-portionately more capacity can bededicated to nonvisual areas of theneocortex once the volume is above

    the crucial threshold. This might ex-plain why apes appear to becapableof theadditional cognitive processing as-sociated with mind reading, whereasmonkeysarenot. It might also explainwhy humans are better at it than apes.

    For humans, one important aspectof ToM concerns its relevance to lan-guage, a communication medium thatcrucially depends on understandinginterlocutors’ mental states or inten-tions. The kinds of metaphorical usesof language that characterize not onlyour rather telegraphic everyday ex-

    changes (in which ‘‘you know what Imean?’’ is a common terminal clause)but also lies at the very heart of themetaphorical features of language. Asstudiesof pragmatics haveamply dem-onstrated,63 a great deal of linguisticcommunication is based on metaphor:Understanding the intentions behinda metaphor is crucial to successfulcommunication. Failureto understandthese intentions commonly results inconfusion or inappropriate responses.Indeed, without these abilities i t isdoubtful whether literature, notably

    poetry, would be possible. Our conver-sations would be confined to the ba-nally factual; those fine nuances of meaning that create both theambigu-itiesof politenessand thesubtleties of public relations would not be pos-sible.64

    REFERENCES

    1Clutton-Brock TH , Harvey PH (1980) Primates,brains and ecology. J Zool Lond 190: 309–323.

    2Aiello LC, Wheeler P (1995) The expensivetissuehypothesis. Curr Anthropol 36 : 184–193.

    3Parker ST, Gibson K R (1977) Object manipula-

    tion, tool use and sensorimotor i ntelli gence asfeeding adaptations in great apes and cebusmonkeys. J H um Evol 6: 623–641.

    4Gibson K R (1986) Cognition, brain sizeand theextraction of embedded foodresources. In Else J ,Lee PC (eds), Primate Ontogeny, Cognition andSocial Behaviour, pp 93–104. Cambridge: Cam-bridgeU niversity Press.

    5Whiten A, ByrneR (1988) Tactical deception inprimates. BehavBr ain Sci 12 : 233–273.

    6Byrne R, W hiten A (eds) (1988) Machiavelli anIntelli gence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    7Harcourt AH (1988) Alli ances in contests andsocial intelligence. In Byrne R, Whiten A (eds),Machiavellian Intelligence, pp 142–152. Oxford:Oxford University Press.

    8Harcourt AH (1989) Sociality and competitionin primates and non-primates. In Standen V,Foley R (eds),ComparativeSocioecology, pp 223–242. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific.

    9Brothers L (1990) The social brain: A projectfor integratingprimatebehaviour andneurophysi-ology in a new domain. Concepts Neurosci  1 : 27–251.

    10Barton RA, Dunbar RL M (1997) E volution of 

    the social brain. In Whiten A, Byrne R (eds),M achiavellian In telligence,   Vol. I I. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

    11FinlayBL , Darlington RB (1995) Linked regu-laritiesin thedevelopment andevolution of mam-malian brains. Science268: 1678– 1684.

    12Martin RD (1981) Relative brain size andmetabolic rate in terrestrial vertebrates. NatureLond 293: 57–60.

    13Martin RD (1983) Human brain evolution inan ecological context. 52nd J ames Ar thur L ec-ture, American M useum of N atural H istory, New York.

    14Hofman MA (1983) E volution of the brain inneonatal and adult placental mammals: A theo-retical approach. J Theoret Biol  105: 317–322.

    15Pagel M , Harvey P H (1988) How mammalsproduce large-brained offspring. Evolution   42: 948–957.

    16Boesch C, Boesch H (1984) Mental map inchimpanzees. Primates 25: 110–170.

    17MacLean PD (1982) On theorigin and progres-sive evolution of the triune brain. I n ArmstrongE, Falk D (eds),   Pr i ma t e B r a i n E v o l u t i o n ,   pp291–310. New York: Plenum Press.

    18 J offe T, Dunbar RI M (n.d.). Primate brainsystem evolution. Brain Behav E vol, submittedfor publication.

    19Passingham RE (1982)   T h e H u m a n P r i ma t e.San Francisco: Freeman.

    20 J ersion H J (1973) E v o l u t i o n o f t h e B r ai n a n d  I ntelli gence. N ew York: Academic Press.

    21Dunbar RI M (1989) E nvironmental determi-nants of i ntraspecific variation in body weight inbaboons. J Zool London 220: 167–169.

    22Willner LA (1989) Sexual Dimorphism in Pri-mates. Ph.D. thesis, Universityof London.

    23Deacon T W (1990) Fallacies of progressionindices in theories of brain-size evolution. Int JPrimatol 12: 193–236.

    24Dunbar RI M (1992) N eocortex size as a con-straint on group size in primates. J Hum Evol20: 469–493.

    25Dunbar RI M, J offe TH (n.d.) Neocortex sizeand social group size in prosimians. P rimates,submitted for publication.

    26Byrne RB (1995)   The Thinking Primate.   Ox-ford:Oxford UniversityP ress.

    27Barton RA (1995) Neocortex size and behav-ioural ecology in primates.Proc R SocL ondon B,263: 173–177.

    28 J offe TH , Dunbar RI M (1997) Visual andsocio-cognitive information processing in pri-mate brain evolution. Proc R Soc L ondon B,264: 1303–1307.

    29Stephan H, Frahm H , Baron G (1981) Newand revised data on volumes of brain structuresin insectivores and primates. F olia Primatol35: 1–29.

    30Sawaguchi T,K udoH (1990) Neocortical devel-opment and social structure in primates. Pri-mates 31: 283–290.

    31Barton RA, Purvis A (1994) Primate brainsand ecology: L ooking beneath the surface. InAnderson J R, Thierry B, Herrenschmidt N (eds),Current Primatology, pp 1–12.Strasbourg:U niver-sityof Strasbourg Press.

    32.O’K eefe J , N adel L (1978)   The Hippocampus a s a C ogn i t i v e M a p.   Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress.

    33. Krebs J H, Sherry DF, H ealy SD, Perry VH ,Vaccarino AL (1989) Hi ppocampal specialisationof food-storing birds. Proc N atl Acad Sci USA86: 1488–1492.

    34.Aiello LC, Dunbar RI M (1993) Neocortexsize, group size and the evolution of language.

    Curr Anthropol34: 

    184–193.35Dunbar RI M (1995) Neocortex sizeand groupsize in pri mates: A test of the hypothesis. J HumEvol 28: 287–296.

    36.Bearder S K (1987) Lorises, bushbabies andtarsiers: Di verse societies in solitary foragers. I nSmuts B, Cheney D, Seyfarth R, Wrangham R,Struhsaker T (eds), Prim ate Societies,  pp 12–24.Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    37Dunbar R IM , B ever J (n.d.) N eocortex sizedetermines group size in carnivores and i nsecti-vores. Ethology, in press.

    38Gittleman J H (1986) Carnivore brain size,behavioural ecology and phylogeny. J Mammal67: 23–36.

    39M arino L (1996) What can dolphins tell usabout primateevolution? Evol Anthropol 5: 81–86.

    40 Tschudin A (1996) The Use of Neuroimaging

    in the Assessment of Brain Sizeand Structure inOdontocetes. MSc thesis, University of Natal(Durban).

    41Barton RA, Purvis A, Harvey PH (1995) Evolu-tionary radiation of visual and olfactory brainsystems in primates, batsand insectivores. Phil os Trans R Soc B 348: 381–392.

    42Kolb B, Wishaw LO (1996)  Fundam entals of    Hu man Neuropsychology.   San F rancisco: F ree-man.

    43Fletcher P, HappéF, Fri th U, Baker SC, DolanRJ , Frakowiak RSJ , Frith CD (1996) Other mindsin thebrain: A functional imagingstudy of ‘‘theoryof mind’’ in story comprehension. Cognition  0 0: 000–000.

    44Frith C (1996) B rain mechanisms for ‘‘havinga theory of mind.’’ J Psychopharmacol 10 : 9–16.

    45Armstrong E, Clarke MR, Hill EM (1987)Relativesizeof theanterior thalamic nuclei differ-entiates anthropoids by social system. Brain B e-hav Evol 30 : 263–271.

    46K everne EB , Martel FL , Nevison CM (1996)Pri mate brain evolution: Genetic and functionalconsiderations. Proc R Soc Lond B  262: 689–696.

    47Pawlowski B, Dunbar R, Lowen C (n.d.) Neo-cortex size, social skills and mating success inprimates. Behaviour, in press.

    48 J offeTH (1997) Social pressures have selectedfor an extended juvenile period in primates. JHum Evol, in press.

    49Bennett P M , Harvey P H (1985) Brain size,development and metabolism in birds and mam-mals.J Zool London 207: 491–509.

    50M arino L (1997) The relationship betweengestation length,encephalisation and bodyweight

    in odontocetes. Marine M ammal Sci 14 : 143–148.51Kudo H, Lowen S, Dunbar RI M (n.d.) Neocor-tex size and social network size in primates.Behaviour, submitted for publication.

    52Sugawara K (1984) Spatial proximity andbodily contact among the central K alahari San.Afr Studies Monogr 3.

    53Dunbar RIM , Spoor M (1995) Social net-works, support cliques and kinship. Hum Nature6: 273–290.

    54Dunbar R IM (1988)  Primate Social Systems.London: Chapman & Hall.

    55Dunbar RI M (1989) Social systems asoptimalstrategy sets. I n Standen V, Foley R (eds),   Com- parative Socioecology, pp 141–149. Oxford: Black-well Scientific.

    ARTICLES    Evolutionary Anthropology 189

  • 8/20/2019 A Hipotese Do Cerebro Social Kevin Dunbar

    13/13

    56Dunbar RI M (1993) Coevolution of neocorti-cal size, group size and language in humans.BehavBr ain Sci 11 : 681–735.

    57CheneyDL , Seyfarth RM (1990) How Monkeys See the World. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    58Povinelli DJ , Nelson K E (1990) Inferencesabout guessing and knowing in chimpanzees. JComp Psychol 104: 203–210.

    59Povinelli DJ (1994) Whatchimpanzees (might)

    know about the mind. In Wrangham R, McGrewW, de Waal F, H eltne P (eds),   Chimpanzee Cul- tures,   pp 285–300. Cambridge: Harvard Uni ver-sity Press.

    60O’Connell SM (1996) Theoryof Mind in Chim-panzees. Ph.D. thesis, Universityof Li verpool.

    61Perner J , Wimmer D (1985) ‘‘J ohn thinks thatMary thinks that. . . .’’ Attribution of second-order beliefs by 5 and 10year-old children. J ExpChild Psychol 39: 437–471.

    62Kinderman P, Dunbar RIM, Bentall RP (n.d.) Theory of mind deficits and causal attributions.Br J Psychol, in press.

    63Desalles J -L (n.d.) Altruism, status and theorigin of relevance. In Hurford J R, Studdert-Kennedy M, Knight C (eds),   E v o l u t i o n o f L a n -  gua ge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    64Dunbar RIM (1997) Groomin g, Gossip and the Evolution of Language. Cambridge: Harvard Uni-versity Press.

    65HarveyP H, K rebsJ R (1990)Comparingbrains.Science 249: 150–156.

    66StephanH (1972) Evolution of primatebrains:A comparativeanatomical investigation. In TuttleR (ed),   F u n c t i o n al a n d E v o l u t i o n a r y B i o l o gy o f    Primates,  pp 165–174. Chicago: Aldine-Atherton.

    67Ki llworth PD, Bernard HR, McCarty C (1984)M easuring patterns of acquaintanceship. CurrAnthropol 25: 391–397.

    68M ange A, M ange E (1980)  Genetics: H um an Aspects. W.B. Saunders.

    69Bryant FC (1981)   W e’ r e A l l K i n : A C u l t u r al  Study of a Mountain Neighbourhood.   K noxvill e:University of TennesseePress.

    70Gould SJ (1975) All ometry in primates, withemphasis on scaling and the evolution of thebrain. Contrib Primatol 5: 244–292.

    71 J olly A (1969) Lemur social behaviour and

    primatei ntelli gence. Science163: 501–506.

    72Humphrey NK (1976) T he social function of intellect. I n B ateson P PG, Hi ndeR A (eds) G r o w -  ing Points in Ethology,  pp 303–317. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

    73Armstrong E (1985) Relative brain size inmonkeys and prosimians. Am J Phys Anthropol66: 263–273.

    1998 Wiley-Liss, Inc.

    190 Evolutionary Anthropology   ARTICLES