complete copy

80
Page 1 of 80 The Virtuous Egoist: Nietzsche, Virtue, and Social Media. Julian Rickards-Sherrington 2016 Bachelor of Arts (Philosophy) Honours

Upload: julian-sherrington

Post on 14-Feb-2017

33 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Complete Copy

Page 1 of 80

The Virtuous Egoist: Nietzsche, Virtue, and Social

Media.

Julian Rickards-Sherrington

2016

Bachelor of Arts (Philosophy) Honours

Page 2: Complete Copy

Page 2 of 80

Declaration

I declare that this Research Project is my own account of my research

and contains as its main content work which has not previously been

submitted for a degree at any tertiary education institution.

Julian Rickards-Sherrington

Fremantle

October 2016

Page 3: Complete Copy

Page 3 of 80

Abstract

Rapid advancements in technology have seen an increasing shift in how we

socialise and communicate with others. Many of our interactions now take place

online via social media. When interacting with others online, we have a greater

ability to ‘create a self’ and to behave towards others in a way that is not subject to

the same reproofs and constraints that exist when interacting with others. This is due

to the lack of a feedback mechanism within our interactions that communicates the

cost of our social behaviour to others. The freedom and licence that social media

offers us is the closest thing that allows us to experience Sartre’s dictum that

‘existence precedes essence’. Human beings have a greater ability to create a self on

social media, an ability that is a reflection of the existentialist idea of ‘radical

freedom’ and ‘authenticity’. This freedom is neither desirable nor sustainable,

without proper consideration of our embodied context and ethical relationships to

others. It is the argument of this thesis that Friedrich Nietzsche’s philosophy can be

used to interpret and analyse this new social reality. It is argued that a revised

interpretation of Nietzsche as a virtue ethicist, and that a different understanding of

Nietzsche’s social and moral philosophy, can result in different social processes

taking place that are far more likely to result in a more cohesive social framework

online, in which people can enjoy the internet’s freedoms and pursue their own

interests, unhindered.

Page 4: Complete Copy

Page 4 of 80

Contents

Acknowledgements ..................................................................................................... 5

Chapter One: Introduction........................................................................................... 6

Chapter Two .............................................................................................................. 20

Chapter Three ............................................................................................................ 34

Chapter Four ............................................................................................................. 48

Chapter Five: Conclusion .......................................................................................... 65

References ................................................................................................................. 75

Glossary .................................................................................................................... 80

Page 5: Complete Copy

Page 5 of 80

Acknowledgements

I am indebted to Dr Laura D’Olimpio of the University of Notre Dame who

supervised this thesis, and whose interest in me as an undergraduate provided me

with the opportunity to write it. Her suggestions, edits, and criticisms of the ideas

developed in this work allowed me to redefine and reformulate my concepts. Any

insights or innovations that may be present here are partially attributable to her. All

errors are, alas, my own.

I have also benefited from the tireless work and enthusiasm of Dr Angeline

O’Neill, my Honours Co-Ordinator. I would also like to acknowledge my fellow

Honours students Iris Kennedy, Jeremy Sheehan, Jessica Branch, Justine Ralph, Em

Bagg, and Jane Minson.

Finally, my deepest gratitude to Nadene, Bill, and Charlotte Egan, John and

Gail Rickards, James McNaught, Anthony Dermer, and Laura Willoughby for their

unflagging faith, encouragement, and forbearance.

Page 6: Complete Copy

Page 6 of 80

Chapter One: Introduction

Our way of life is changing. Our shopping, our planning, our banking, our

entertainment, and, most importantly, our social interactions, are now taking place

online. A recent Pew Study showed that twenty-four percent of American teenagers

go online “almost constantly”.1 Ninety-two percent of teenagers reported going

online daily.2 More than half (56%) report going online several times a day, twelve

percent report going on once every two days, six percent report going on weekly,

and only two percent report less than that.3 If this demographic change in the United

States is indicative of the West in general (and perhaps globally) then it obviously

offers us many benefits. Never before has there been such easy access to the fruits of

humanity’s endeavours, whether they be artistic, commercial, social, political, and

even sexual. For example, anybody with a Kindle can now purchase the Complete

Works of Plato for less than three US dollars from American book-selling website

Amazon.4 We can now communicate with family, friends, and business associates

on the other side of the world with the click of a few buttons, and expect a reply just

1 Amanda Lenhart, "Teens, Social Media & Technology Overview 2015." Pew

Research Centre. Accessed May 29, 2016.

http://www.pewinternet.org/2015/04/09/teens-social-media-technology-2015/. 2 Ibid. 3 Ibid. 4 Accessed May 29, 2016, from https://www.amazon.com.au/Complete-Works-

Plato-Annotated-ebook/dp/B007MJMUE6/ref=sr_1_4?s=digital-

text&ie=UTF8&qid=1474847976&sr=1-4&keywords=plato

Page 7: Complete Copy

Page 7 of 80

as quickly.5 Our news sources are varied and infinite.6 We can find likeminded

individuals who share our passion for the most obscure hobbies on group message

boards. We can organize parties, protests, conferences, and concerts online,

distributing information and advertising about them to thousands and in some cases

millions of people in the space of a few seconds. For many of us, the internet is a

liberation. So many of the constraints placed on us by our geography, our place in

time, and our access to information are gone.

The freedom and licence that social media offers us is the closest thing that

allows us to experience Sartre’s dictum that ‘existence precedes essence’.7 Human

beings have a greater ability to create a self on social media, an ability that is a

reflection of the existentialist idea of ‘radical freedom’ and ‘authenticity’. This

freedom is neither desirable nor sustainable, without proper consideration of our

embodied context and ethical relationships to others. There are some aspects to the

internet and our use of social media that can be limiting, restrictive, and harmful.

The activity that we repeatedly see online is the product of human beings, and thus

reflects the limitations and moral fallibilities of human activity in the real world.

5 The most obvious example being email in this case. However, it extends to other

social media platforms, like Facebook. 6 Most major media platforms now disseminate a large portion of their output online.

This includes government owned media like the ABC and BBC, to the privately

owned CNN and FOX news. A PEW study released in 2016 revealed that 62% of

American adults get their news from social media, and 18% do so often. The three

most popular websites were Reddit, Facebook, and Twitter. See at

http://www.journalism.org/2016/05/26/news-use-across-social-media-platforms-

2016/ 7 Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism and Humanism (London: Eyre Methuen Ltd.),

1973, 52.

Page 8: Complete Copy

Page 8 of 80

However, it is important to note that the harm that is done online can be

different from the harm that is caused by human beings in real social interactions.

The difference is a quantitative one, not a qualitative one. In this case, the difference

is caused by the lack of a feedback mechanism that deters people from behaving in

the same way at a later date. In the real world, insults and lies, abuse and

harassment, are usually met with social censure and, in extreme cases, punishment.

These deterrents function as a method for communicating to individuals the

unacceptability of their behaviour in a social framework. In the case of the internet,

our capacity to depict ourselves through a distorted image (or anonymously) allows

us to avoid such censorship. We are removed from the harmful consequences of our

actions by a computer screen, and in some cases we are also removed by time zones

and geography from the people whom we are attacking.

The internet is best understood as an information system. Like prices in

economics, or social mores in society, the internet is a process whereby we are able

to access information, more information than has ever hitherto been available to

human beings. However, the information that the internet provides us is not simply

factual information about various subjects, like an encyclopaedia. It also, especially

through social media, provides people with information about private individuals.

This creates a range of different incentives and constraints for people who choose to

use it, than would normally exist when interacting with people face to face.

Subsequently, when discussing social incentives and constraints in relation to the

internet, the most noticeable thing is their absence. Although the usual constraints

Page 9: Complete Copy

Page 9 of 80

created by the law apply to the internet as they would in reality (sexual activity with

minors being one example), the notion of social constraints are far more fluid. This

becomes more and more apparent when the focus of decisions made online are

further away from the agent making those decisions. For example, if I choose to

make a derogatory remark to my best friend’s girlfriend about her weight via an

email, I am more likely to receive negative feedback for this decision by losing my

best friend. However, if I choose to insult a girl who lives in South Dakota,

anonymously via Facebook8, I am unlikely to receive any negative feedback from

that decision here in Western Australia. From this example it can be inferred, that

social constraints apply to online behaviour successfully only to the extent that the

circumstances of the behaviour accurately reflect the individual’s circumstances in

the real world. Some forms of social constraint caused by the effects or reactions to

our online behaviour are less effective than they would be in real life.

One of the most successful facets of the online world is social media. The

social media website Facebook had over 1.5 billion active users as of August 2015.9

YouTube has over one billion,10 and Twitter has up to three hundred million12. In

1995, less than one percent of the world’s population had access to the internet. In

8 A glossary describing the social media platforms referenced is available at the end

of this thesis. 9 Josh Constine. "Facebook Climbs To 1.59 Billion Users And Crushes Q4

Estimates With $5.8B Revenue." TechCrunch. Accessed May 29, 2016.

http://techcrunch.com/2016/01/27/facebook-earnings-q4-2015/. 10 "All YouTube Statistics in One Place." Socialbakers.com. Accessed May 29,

2016, from http://www.socialbakers.com/statistics/youtube/. 12 “About.” Twitter. Accessed May 29, 2016. https://about.twitter.com/company

Page 10: Complete Copy

Page 10 of 80

2016, it is now forty percent, roughly 3.3 billion people and it is growing daily14.

Naturally, such changes are occasion for philosophical reflection and observation.

These reflections raise questions related to character, ethics, and how we form and

maintain relationships in this new setting. In her book Alone Together, technology

specialist Sherry Turkle has argued that social media brings people together while

simultaneously distancing them.15 One of her main contentions is that the detached

medium of a computer screen enables people to more easily treat individuals as

objects rather than as subjects because they are removed from the realities of

interacting with other human beings. Although people have a greater connection to

others through social media, the facile nature of many of these connections leads to

lessening expectations of other people by individuals. Seeing as so many of our

interactions now take place online, this effect can in some cases lead to feelings of

loneliness, envy, anger, and unhappiness16. She writes, “Where we live doesn't just

change how we live; it informs who we become. Most recently, technology promises

us lives on the screen. What values…, follow from this new location? Immersed in

simulation, where do we live, and what do we live for?”17

The internet is an information system that can provide us with information

about diverse subjects and also about private individuals. It also is a system whereby

14 "Internet Users." Internet Live Stats, 2016. Accessed May 29, 2016.

http://www.internetlivestats.com/internet-users/. 15 Sherry Turkle, Alone Together: Why We Expect More from Technology and Less

from Each Other (New York: Basic Books), 2011, 116. 16 Ibid, 95-99. 17 Ibid, 277.

Page 11: Complete Copy

Page 11 of 80

people can present information about themselves to others. However, the absence of

social constraints that is created by the internet allows individuals to present

information that is either inaccurate, or wholly fallacious. Social media creates an

opportunity for individuals to present themselves as they would like to be seen,

rather than as they really are. It also allows individuals to behave in ways online that

they would presumably not in the real world, or in ways that they would not be able

to. Take, for example, the online practice of ‘catfishing’. Popularised in the

documentary Catfish, ‘catfishing’ involves individuals manipulating others by

creating fictional online personas.18 An example of this is the case of Notre Dame

Football star Manti Te’o, who lied about having a deceased girlfriend in order to

boost his coverage in the media. The fake girlfriend, whose name was Lennay

Kekua, had her own Twitter and Instagram account. It subsequently came to light

that Lenny Kekua never existed, her photos were of someone else, and all attempts

to find evidence for her death (which involved a car crash and case of leukaemia)

resulted in nought.19

Although the case of Manti Te’o is one of relatively minor consequence,

there are many instances of ‘catfishing’ and online behaviour that are far more

sinister in intention, and damaging in effect. Many of the studies into the behaviour

18 Schulman, Yaniv, Catfish, DVD, Dir. Henry Joost & Ariel Schulman (New York

City: Supermache, 2010.) 19Timothy Burke and Jack Dickey, "Manti Te'o's Dead Girlfriend, The Most

Heartbreaking and Inspirational Story Of The College Football Season, Is A Hoax."

Deadspin, accessed May 29, 2016, http://deadspin.com/manti-teos-dead-girlfriend-

the-most-heartbreaking-an-5976517.

Page 12: Complete Copy

Page 12 of 80

of young people on social media have found that there are problems that arise with

its usage, with repeated occurrences of cyberbullying.20 A recurring figure on social

media is the troll, a person who sows discord by starting arguments or upsetting

people with extraneous or off-topic messages in an online community (such as a

newsgroup, forum, chat group, or blog) with the deliberate intent of provoking

readers into an emotional response or of otherwise disrupting normal on-topic

discussion, often for their own amusement. There are some incidents where internet

trolling becomes an expression of hateful sentiment, on occasion becoming

synonymous with harassment and abuse. In chapter three, I will be using the online

community known as the ‘alt-right’ as a case study, in order to illustrate such

incidents.

In part, such online behaviour is no different to ordinary behaviour whereby

people wish to present their best self to impress others or perhaps portray a certain

characteristics in order to make a particular kind of impression. Such behaviour may

be done consciously or unconsciously: to fit in, to stand out, and to explore one’s

own sense of identity. The online environment allows for a greater opportunity to

enact all of these desires and whims. The opportunity to break with one’s own

circumstances and what we perceive to be our own inherited weaknesses is a notion

that many people find deeply attractive. One of the opportunities that is offered by

social media is a greater ability to do this. We can create alternative lives on

20 Larry D. Rosen, "Social Networking’s Good and Bad Impacts on Kids," American

Psychological Association, accessed August 1, 2016,

http://www.apa.org/news/press/releases/2011/08/social-kids.aspx.

Page 13: Complete Copy

Page 13 of 80

Facebook that are not accurate depictions of the lives we actually live. We can

manipulate photographs and information on our Tinder accounts in order to make us

appear more attractive than we actually are. Catfishing is an extreme example,

whereby we create a person who does not exist in order to satisfy a psychological

need. Paedophiles, for example, lie about their age on group message boards and

start grooming their victims for a future encounter at the predator’s home. In all of

these ways and more, selves are created using social media, seemingly reflecting the

existentialist ideals of ‘radical freedom’ and ‘authenticity’. Yet we must question

whether such individual freedom is desirable if it lacks an empathetic consideration

of our embodied context that includes our ethical and social commitments to others.

Hence, the thesis that ‘the freedom and licence that social media offers us is the

closest thing that allows us to experience Sartre’s dictum that ‘existence precedes

essence’. Human beings have a greater ability to create a self on social media, an

ability that is a reflection of the existentialist idea of ‘radical freedom’ and

‘authenticity’. This freedom is neither desirable nor sustainable, without proper

consideration of our embodied context and ethical relationships to others.

It would be prudent at first to account for the meaning of the two terms put

forth in this thesis; namely, ‘authenticity’ and ‘radical freedom’. Very often human

beings choose to say things and act in ways that are contrary to one’s own attitudes

and desires.21 From this it follows that, an authentic person is someone who behaves

21 "Authenticity", Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, accessed August 2, 2016,

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/authenticity/.

Page 14: Complete Copy

Page 14 of 80

in a way that is in accordance with desires, motives, ideals and beliefs that express

who that person really is.22 The notion of ‘radical freedom’ is not one concerned

with the metaphysical nature of man’s actions, but with life as it is experienced. It is

important to note that this thesis is not directly concerned with these terms, but

rather how they are a reflection of the constraints and incentives that we face when

we are online. In this case, the notion of ‘radical freedom’ describes the fact that

many of us are shielded from the social consequences of our actions when we

communicate to people online anonymously, especially when we communicate to

harass or abuse others. In a way, this freedom is greater than even Sartre and

Nietzsche could have envisioned, as the freedom to escape these consequences was

something that they regarded as inevitable. ‘Authenticity’, when online, is coupled

with this freedom. Due to the weakness of social constraints on our online

behaviour, the freedom to say and communicate whatever we like is available to us.

We can disregard fashion, good taste, and political correctness in the content of our

communication. Authenticity, in this case, is the satisfaction of the desire to express

ourselves, irrespective and immune to what others may think. The freedom of the

internet allows us to express thoughts and beliefs that are indicative of what we truly

feel and think. Wherein, lies the potential for social selves that reflect ‘authenticity’.

Whether many of the trends prevalent on social media are truly ‘authentic’ will be

examined in this thesis.

22 Ibid.

Page 15: Complete Copy

Page 15 of 80

The moral philosophy of Existentialism is not normative, but rather an

examination of the relationship between ‘values’ and psychology23. Existentialists

regard values as a projection by human beings on to the backdrop of an indifferent

universe, rather than as things that have an actual correspondence to the material

world. If this conclusion is accepted then moral philosophy becomes more akin to

moral psychology: an examination of the ‘mendacity, self-deception, and hypocrisy

in moral consciousness”.24 The manipulation of our image online is similar to the

existentialist desire for freedom and authenticity, to be able to ‘will a self’.

Nietzsche calls upon us to do this when he writes, “Active, successful natures act,

not according to the dictum “know thyself,” but as if there hovered before them a

commandment: will a self and thou shalt become a self”.25 Nietzsche’s idea of

willing a self and creating a self can be used to provide a philosophical insight into

the phenomena of social media, accounting for both its positive and its negative

effects.

It is also important to analyse Nietzsche’s concept of ‘will to power’ and

how it relates to this thesis. Nietzsche’s moral philosophy focused on the potential

for a life lived ‘beyond good and evil’. In doing this, he challenged the moral

assumption that exploiting, dominating, and hurting the weak were always morally

objectionable. Nietzsche justified this by arguing that the purpose of life is to exhibit

23 “Existentialism”, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, accessed August 2,

2016, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/existentialism/. 24 Ibid. 25 Friedrich Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human: A Book for Free Spirits, trans. R.J.

Hollingdale (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1996, 294.

Page 16: Complete Copy

Page 16 of 80

strength and express its ‘will to power’—a process that often entails pain and

deception. Nietzsche says of life, “…it will want to grow, spread, grab, win

dominance, - not out of any morality or immortality, but because it is alive, and

because life is precisely will to power”.26 This ‘will’ is not a lacking in humans, but

a drive. It is the foundation of human energy and desire for satisfaction.27

Nietzsche’s ‘will to power’, is often cited by people as justification for the argument

that Nietzsche is an antisocial egoist. Indeed, the concept of exploiting, dominating,

and hurting the weak (‘the weak’ here being labelled on racial grounds) is a tactic

engaged in by the alt-right when advocating or promoting its political views online.

The relevance of the ‘will to power’ and Nietzsche’s moral philosophy will be

explored in chapter four.

Nietzsche’s encouragement to ‘will a self’ poses problems related to both the

dispositions and activities of individuals. In fact, there are dangers inherent in this

viewpoint. ‘Willing a self’ can have to two meanings, either sincerity in expression

or, fidelity to one’s values. Surely an individual who shows fidelity to their values is

expressing sincerity by doing so. However, the crucial distinction is between

whether emphasis is placed on one’s sincerity, or on one’s fidelity. Sincerity of

expression amounts to an individual believing himself to possess a sufficient amount

of knowledge to act in a way that will shape beneficial outcomes for himself, and for

26 Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the

Future, ed. Rolf-Peter Horstmann and Judith Norman (Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press, 2002), 153. 27 “Friedrich Nietzsche”, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, accessed August 4,

2016, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nietzsche/

Page 17: Complete Copy

Page 17 of 80

others. By contrast, fidelity to one’s own values necessitates fidelity to a specific

role in life. Many of us take on multiple roles in our daily lives: spouse, parent,

professional, citizen. All of them contain their own incentives, obligations, and

constraints that we are obliged to adhere to. These roles provide a sphere within

which people can be trusted to act competently and to serve a larger process that will

determine larger social outcomes. In our behaviour on social media, due to the

weakness of social constraints on behaviour, and in the absence of third parties to

enforce civility, how much of the antisocial behaviour that one sees will be

determined by an individual’s willingness to censure themselves. If the individual

understands his online self to be merely an expression of his sentiment in sincerity,

in all likelihood such behaviour will be more prominent. An understanding of our

activity online to be an extension of our social selves, and our social behaviour been

a reflection of that, will in all likelihood lead to a different outcome. These differing

emphasis on sincerity and fidelity, will be explored in greater detail in later chapters

as differing interpretations of Nietzsche’s notion, “will a self”.

Nietzsche was highly critical of the society which he lived in, and found

much wanting in the culture of his day. He writes, “The surest way of ruining a

youth is to teach him to respect those who think as he does more highly than those

who think differently from him”.28 Although much of his criticisms are of society

and modernity, Nietzsche does not conclude from his criticisms that the solutions are

28 Friedrich Nietzsche, Daybreak: Thoughts on the Prejudices of Morality, ed.

Maudemaire Clark and Brian Leiter (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press),

1997, 153.

Page 18: Complete Copy

Page 18 of 80

social, or reformist, or political. Instead, he emphasises individual striving in one’s

own life and also in affecting the lives of others. Specifically, individuals need to

overcome their own culture and their own limitations29. It is the contention of this

thesis that many of Nietzsche’s ideas, which have had a significant influence on the

culture and history of the world, echo much of the behaviour that is observable on

the internet today, both positive and negative. It is worth noting that I am not

arguing that any antisocial aspects of social media are consciously based on a

philosophical blueprint that is derived from Nietzsche’s writings. Nor am I arguing

that the individuals online who behave in a certain way are self-declared followers

of Nietzsche, it is possible that they have never read or even heard of him. What I

am observing in this analysis are current trends online through the prism of

Nietzsche’s ideas, and arguing that doing so leads to a greater understanding of these

trends.

In the second chapter of this thesis I will be providing an overview of

contemporary Virtue ethics, in light of the apparent contradiction between Nietzsche

as an egoist and Nietzsche as a virtue ethicist. Much of this chapter will be drawing

upon the writings of philosopher Christine Swanton who has written a book that

argues for Nietzsche as the latter.30

29 Ibid. 30 Christine Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche (Hoboken: Wiley &

Sons, 2015) Accessed August 3, 2016,

http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/book/10.1002/9781118939369.

Page 19: Complete Copy

Page 19 of 80

The third chapter will serve as a counterargument to Swanton and focus on

Nietzsche’s reputation as an egoist. Much of the work cited in this chapter will be

from multiple theorists and philosophers who can be used to support and analyse

Nietzsche in this way. The third chapter will also examine the connection between

the misinterpretation and misuse of Nietzsche’s ideas and examples of social media

being used in a way that is harmful to others.

The fourth chapter of this thesis will contain a rebuttal to the

counterargument put forth in the third chapter. As a correction to this view, it will

focus on Nietzsche’s ‘egoism’ as an aspect of his virtuous egoism that is ‘response

dependent’, a phrase coined from Swanton. Much of this chapter will entail a return

to Swanton’s writings. It will also be supplemented by the work of Alasdair

MacIntyre. This chapter will also examine the connection between social media and

virtue, and the assertion of a ‘social self’ that conducts itself online as if it were a

member of a community, and how this ties into Nietzsche’s own role as a virtue

ethicist.

The fifth and final chapter will be a conclusion and summary of the

preceding arguments and how they are essential to understanding the thesis’ central

claim. That, ‘the freedom and licence that social media offers is the closest thing to

that allows us to experience Sartre’s dictum that ‘existence precedes essence’.

Human beings have a greater ability to create a self on social media, an ability that

Page 20: Complete Copy

Page 20 of 80

is a reflection of the existentialist notion of ‘radical freedom’ and ‘authenticity’. This

freedom is neither desirable nor sustainable without proper consideration of our

embodied context and ethical relationships to others.’

Page 21: Complete Copy

Page 21 of 80

Chapter Two

My concern in this thesis is to analyse the current online trends of social

media usage through the prism of Nietzsche’s ideas in order to better understand

how people use social media to construct and create a self, especially when these

‘selves’ are used as avatars to project a particular image of themselves for certain

purposes. Before I critically examine these uses of social media, it is important to

clarify which reading of Nietzsche I am applying. I am supporting Swanton by

arguing that Nietzsche is a virtue egoist and therefore will be providing an overview

of contemporary virtue ethics, as well as critically assessing Swanton’s reading of

Nietzsche31. I will pay particular attention to the apparent contradiction between

Nietzsche as an egoist and Nietzsche as a virtue ethicist.

In the recent literature on virtue ethics, Swanton has attempted to establish a

connection between virtue ethics and Nietzsche32. Swanton states that “Many

writings on Nietzsche think that for Nietzsche …we have a basic instinct for cruelty

and…that this is healthy for this instinct to be manifested. This view is at the heart

of immoralist interpretations of Nietzsche.”33 Swanton contests this interpretation by

arguing that “for Nietzsche we have a basic instinct not for cruelty but for

31 Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche. 32Christine Swanton, Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View (Oxford: Oxford University

Press, 2005), 134-135, 140. 33 Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche, 149.

Page 22: Complete Copy

Page 22 of 80

aggression, which…can be manifested in benign or malignant ways”.34 The work of

Swanton will serve as the lens through which I will examine the connection between

Nietzsche and virtue ethics. In order to understand the possibility of there being a

relationship between Nietzsche and virtue ethics, we must begin with a summary of

the latter and its relevance to moral philosophy over the past sixty years.

Virtue theory regards morality as being constitutive of a person’s character

over a lifetime, and that ‘goodness’ is a necessary precondition for happiness. Virtue

theory is teleological in so far as it regards happiness (or eudemonia) as the final

cause of human behaviour (especially moral behaviour) and it regards virtuous

characteristics as the means by which happiness is cultivated and maintained35. The

father of virtue ethics, Aristotle, writes that, “Every craft and every method of

inquiry and likewise every action and deliberate choice seems to seek some good.

That is why they correctly declare that the good is ‘that which all seek”.36 Happiness

is thus achieved by developing habits of action and thought that are consistent with

or correlate to ‘virtue’ or ‘goodness’. It follows from this that ‘knowledge’ is

incredibly important in making moral decisions, not just the knowledge that

individuals already possess but also the limitations on our knowledge that are a

consequence of our ‘embedded context’.

34 Ibid, 149. 35 Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics, trans. C.D.C. Reeve (Indianapolis: Hackett

Publishing, 2014), 12, 185-186. 36 Ibid, 2.

Page 23: Complete Copy

Page 23 of 80

There are many kinds of knowledge, but the kind that is most important

when making moral judgements is phronesis, or, practical wisdom.37 This

knowledge is one that cannot be acquired through passive learning. It is acquired

through behaviour and through experience which subsequently leads to Aristotle’s

habituation38. ‘Practical wisdom’ is the process through which human beings

cultivate moral knowledge by practicing moral actions that inculcate emotional

dispositions in the individual that are indicators of ‘virtuousness’. As previously

stated, ‘practical wisdom’ is knowledge that is acquired only through experience and

practice, compared to a purely abstract knowledge. The argument that knowledge is

essential to the process of moral decision making will become important later in

understanding the relationship between Nietzsche and virtue theory. It is also

essential in understanding a virtue based alternative to the ‘radical freedom’ that is

constitutive of so much behaviour that is observable online.

Some contemporary moral philosophers have returned to the idea found in

Aristotle’s writings that morality is fundamentally character based.39 This trend

began with a paper written by G.E.M. Anscombe in 1958, titled Modern Moral

Philosophy.40 The main focus of Anscombe’s argument in this paper is what she

37 Ibid, 102. 38 Ibid, 181. 39 “Virtue Ethics,” Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, accessed August 4, 2016,

http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/ethics-virtue/. 40 Anscombe, G.E.M. "Modern Moral Philosophy", Philosophy 33 (January 1958):

1-16, accessed August 5, 2016, http://www.pitt.edu/~mthompso/readings/mmp.pdf

Page 24: Complete Copy

Page 24 of 80

regards as a ‘law conception of ethics’.41 This conception prioritizes itself with

notions of ‘obligation and duty’, examples of this would include Kant’s categorical

imperative.42 In the paper, Anscombe writes “The ordinary (and quite indispensable)

terms ‘should’, ‘needs’, ‘ought’, ‘must’ – acquired this special sense by being

equated in the relevant contexts with ‘is obliged’, or ‘is bound’, or ‘is required to,’ in

the sense in which one can be obliged or bound by law…”43

As an alternative, Anscombe called for a return to character, virtue, and

flourishing as concepts whereby we may discuss moral problems.44 She writes,

“It may be possible…to discard the notion ‘morally ought’ and

simply return to the ordinary ‘ought’…One man – a

philosopher – may say that since justice is a virtue, and

injustice a vice, and virtues and vices are built up by the

performances of the action in which they are instanced, an act

of injustice will tend to make a man bad; and essentially the

flourishing of a man qua man consists in his being good…so a

man needs, or ought to perform, only virtuous actions; and

even if, as it must be admitted may happen, he flourishes less,

or not at all, in inessentials, by avoiding injustice, his life is

spoiled in essentials by not avoiding injustice – so he still

needs to perform only just actions.”45

The revival of virtue ethics over the past sixty years was largely born out of

the disagreements between ‘rule-based’ ethicists and ‘consequence based’ ethicists

41 “Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe”, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy,

accessed August 5, 2016, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/anscombe/ 42 Ibid. 43 Anscombe, “Modern Moral Philosophy”, 15. 44 Ibid, 16. 45Ibid, 16.

Page 25: Complete Copy

Page 25 of 80

that had dominated modern philosophy since the eighteenth century. Karen Stohr

defines ‘traditional’ virtue ethics as “…an ‘agent-centred’ theory…contrast it with

‘act-centred’ theories like utilitarianism or Kantianism… right action is defined in

terms of what a virtuous agent would do, whereas in Kantianism and utilitarianism,

the definition of right action is primary.”46 Kantianism is a ‘rule-based’ theory

concerned with moral actions that conform to a predetermined, abstract ‘law’ about

the nature of morality.47 Consequentialism is a moral theory that focuses on the

consequences of moral decisions.48 They are both ‘act-centred’ theories because they

focus on the decision being made, instead of focusing on the decision maker. The

latter is precisely what virtue ethics does. In Aristotelian virtue ethics, a virtuous

disposition is an ‘emotional mean’ between extremes of excess and deficiency. ‘The

doctrine of the mean’, is central to understanding this view due to the fact that it refers

back to Aristotle’s argument for virtue as a form of ‘practical knowledge’. As a doctor

understands that there are degrees of excess and deficiency in the treatment of a

patient’s wounds, a virtuous person understands that the virtue of courage is a mean

between cowardice and rashness.

This conception of a return to virtue ethics has the potential for diverse

applications. Virtue ethics is particularly relevant to our behaviour on social media

46 Stohr, Karen, "Contemporary Virtue Ethics", Philosophy Compass 1 (January

2006): 22-27, accessed August 5, 2016, doi:10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00004.x. 47 “Deontological Ethics”, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, accessed August

5, 2016, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-deontological/ 48 “Consequentialism”, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, accessed August 5,

2016. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism/

Page 26: Complete Copy

Page 26 of 80

due to the fact that the willingness of individuals to conceptualise their behaviour in a

‘virtue’ framework is more likely to be efficient, compared to rule-based or

consequence-based moral theories. The reason for this is due to the fact that as long

as the internet continues to remains categorically focused around individual freedom,

the absence of third parties to enforce civility means that isolated individuals online

will have to do so. Our behaviour on social media becomes more morally fraught the

more that our self-projected image, our interactions, and our behaviour diverges from

the social reality that social media claims to mirror. Due to the fact that the individual

online is constrained by their ‘embodied context’, the implications of their actions are

not necessarily going to be made relevant to them. If the individual understands their

‘social media presence’ as an extension of their ‘social self’, then virtue ethics

functions as a trade-off between social civility and individual freedom. Of course, it

is entirely possible for ‘rule-based’ and ‘consequence-based’ moral theories to

institute a similar trade-off, through enforcement by third parties. Some websites, like

Twitter, have already begun to do so.49 However, the question then becomes as to

whether third party enforcement will still allow for the internet’s greatest benefit, its

freedom.

MacIntyre, in After Virtue, argues for social customs and social institutions as

the framework through which ‘virtue’ can be understood.50 By contrast, Rosalind

49 Elle Hunt, “Milo Yiannopoulos, right-wing writer, permanently banned from

Twitter”, The Guardian, accessed August 20, 2016,

https://www.theguardian.com/technology/2016/jul/20/milo-yiannopoulos-nero-

permanently-banned-twitter 50 Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (London: Bloomsbury, 2013), 69, 173, 189, 229.

Page 27: Complete Copy

Page 27 of 80

Hursthouse argues that ‘virtue’ is a form of ‘ethical naturalism’, where virtues are

grounded in the natural world, particularly human psychology.51 She writes, “…the

virtues are those character traits that make a human being a good human being – are

those traits that human beings need to live as well as human beings, to live a good,

characteristically human, life. Ethical evaluations of human beings as good or bad are

taken to be analogous to evaluations of other living things as good or bad specimens

of their kind”.52 In this case, virtuous traits that result in human happiness over

multiple time periods, are to be regarded as virtues, akin to a form of natural selection.

Swanton’s application of virtue ethics has allowed her to make insights into

philosophers such as Nietzsche that have not been made by other Nietzsche scholars.

She writes that, “My appropriation of Nietzsche and Nietzsche-inspired psychology

is in the service of shedding some light…Virtue ethics, with its emphasis on the inner,

needs to take seriously the spirit of Nietzsche’s remarks”.53 There are large disparities

in opinion amongst contemporary virtue ethicists regarding the exact nature of ‘the

virtues’. However, what MacIntyre, Hursthouse, and Swanton have argued for is an

understanding of virtue as an individual responding to their moral ‘environment’. Due

to the fact that ‘moral’ environments change over time, it shouldn’t be surprising that

there are disparities in what is considered to be ‘virtuous’, over different time periods

and in different circumstances.

51 Rosalind Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999),

193-197. 52 Ibid, 21. 53 Swanton, Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View, 11.

Page 28: Complete Copy

Page 28 of 80

Knowledge of these disparities is best articulated by Swanton when she

argues that the virtues should be pluralistic, and that they are best understood as

‘response dependent’54. Thus, “…an important aspect of virtue-ethical pluralism,

then, is that the modes of moral responsiveness to items in the fields of the virtues

are plural.” The advantage that this conception of virtue ethics presents for that it,

“…acknowledges the complexity of human responsiveness to the world. The virtues,

with their complex profiles, recognize that we are…not only agents of change in the

attempt to promote good, but also agents of change in the attempt to produce and to

create”.55

What can and cannot be construed as virtuous behaviour is dependent on

“modes of moral responsiveness to items in the fields of the virtues that are

plural”.56 On social media, the question becomes not so much, ‘What is one

responding to?”, as it is ‘Who is the person responding and what is their

understanding of virtuous behaviour’? Nietzsche is a useful philosopher for

analysing the implications of this question, due to the fact much of the diversity of

opinion about his writings are contingent on different assumptions about Nietzsche’s

use of moral and philosophical terms.

54Ibid, 23. 55 Ibid, 23. 56 Ibid, 23.

Page 29: Complete Copy

Page 29 of 80

Nietzsche is an egoist57. The main target of most of Nietzsche’s criticisms is

the idea of altruism. “The greatest obstacle to reading Nietzsche in a virtue ethical

way is his self-ascription as an egoist and his attacks on altruism”58, writes Swanton.

For example, Nietzsche strongly disliked the ethical content of Judaism and

Christianity. Two Nietzsche scholars have written that “What he finds objectionable

in the Jewish moral outlook he usually finds in the Christian perspective as well.”59

Nietzsche describes altruism as a commitment made to denigrate and neglect one’s

own capabilities and potential for greatness, for the benefit of others. As an

alternative, Nietzsche regularly advocates aristocracy as a necessary aspect of any

great society. He writes “Every enhancement so far in the type "man" has been the

work of an aristocratic society—and that is how it will be, again and again, since this

sort of society believes in a long ladder of rank order and value distinctions between

men, and in some sense needs slavery.”60 The full implications of Nietzsche’s

advocacy for aristocracy, and his attack on altruism will be explored at greater detail

in chapter four.

Philosophical egoists, by definition, tend to be amoral in their moral outlook.

Philosophical egoism and virtue ethics appear to be irreconcilable. However,

Swanston has argued that Nietzsche’s egoism can be described as virtuous egoism61.

57 Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche, 109. 58 Ibid, 111. 59 Robert C. Solomon and Kathleen M. Higgins, What Nietzsche Really Said. (New

York City: Knopf Doubleday, 2012), 11. 60 Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future, 151. 61 Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche, 109.

Page 30: Complete Copy

Page 30 of 80

Nietzsche’s criticisms are not simply of altruism, but also of forms of egoism. In

fact, it would be more accurate to say that Nietzsche attacks both non-virtuous

altruism and non-virtuous egoism, or ‘immature egoism’.62 It is easier to understand

and defend the statement that Nietzsche is a virtue ethicist if one chooses to interpret

his advocacy of egoism and his criticisms of altruism as ‘response dependent

virtues’. Nietzsche writes, “Let us for the time being agree that benevolence and

beneficence are constituents of the good man; only let us add: ‘presupposing that he

is first benevolently and beneficently inclined towards himself!”63 Nietzsche is

sceptical of any individual’s ability to act in a way that will create beneficial

outcomes for other people. The reason for this is that doing so would be a

misallocation of a person’s talent and effort. The conscious goal of aiding

individuals, presupposes a greater amount of knowledge that any person is capable

of possessing, and is thus likely lead to unexpected harm.

It is important to emphasise what Nietzsche is arguing for by first stating

what he is not arguing for. “All naturalism in morality that is, all healthy morality, is

dominated by an instinct of life…”64 The phrase “instinct for life” is ambiguous and

can mean different things to different people based on their understanding of the

term. The ‘life denying’ philosophy, the ‘morality of decadence’, that Nietzsche

criticizes could be extrapolated and justified on the basis that it is ‘life affirming’.

62 Ibid, 109 63 Nietzsche, Daybreak: Thoughts on the Prejudices of Morality, 207. 64 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, Twilight of the Idols: And Other

Writings, ed. Aaron Ridley and Judith Norman (Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press, 2005), 171.

Page 31: Complete Copy

Page 31 of 80

Some may say that a ‘life affirming’ philosophy would be one that would affirm all

lives. Nietzsche responds to this that the self-overcoming nature of his philosophy

means that to affirm life is to be preoccupied with one’s own life, rather than an

uncritical adulation of the lives of others.65 It does not mean that one has to exhibit

disgust towards others, particularly those whom we regard as mediocre and weak.66

Nietzsche’s egoism does not in fact make any commentary on the attitude we must

necessarily have towards such people.67 It also does not mean that people have an

obligation to affirm or exalt superior individuals above themselves.68 Again, this

contradicts Nietzsche’s belief that the mature individual affirms their life through

self-overcoming. This is not something that will be achieved through preoccupation

with the lives of others. It also is not necessary to regard one’s own life as being

superior to other lives.69 This comparison implies a standard where one’s worthiness

is deemed in relation to other people, which is again a symptom of the ‘life denying’

philosophy that Nietzsche is trying to refute. The final, most important, and most

fatal misconception regarding Nietzsche’s philosophy is that “each person should

put their own life first in their practical reasoning and actions.”70 As previously

noted, there are large differences in opinion regarding the nature of Nietzsche’s

philosophy. One of the reasons for this is due to the fact that his use of language is

artistic and literary, as opposed to philosophical and argumentative. Above are

65 Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche, 115. 66 Ibid, 116. 67 Ibid, 116. 68 Ibid, 116. 69 Ibid, 116. 70 Ibid, 116.

Page 32: Complete Copy

Page 32 of 80

numerous arguments about Nietzsche’s egoism as antisocial and nihilistic. The

implications of this interpretation will be examined in the next chapter.

The alternative to the depiction of Nietzsche as the ‘antisocial egoist’, is an

understanding of Nietzsche’s egoism as not only a response-dependent virtue but

also a constrained vision of human nature and human potential. One of the illusions

that social media provides individuals with, through communication and self-

representation, is the ability to influence and affect others. It is largely from this

illusion that much of the negative effects of social media originate. Analysing

Nietzsche as a virtuous egoist is beneficial in this context due to his respect for the

integrity of the individual. “All that remains is what it is one understands by one’s

advantage; precisely the immature, undeveloped, crude individual will understand it

most crudely”71. In this sentence, Nietzsche argues that the morality of the ‘mature

individual’ is not the morality of self-gratification or self-importance, nor is it

antisocial in its effects or intent. Swanton argues that, in a social context, this

individual develops a sense of honour and “accords others respect and wants them to

accord respect to him”72. The mature individual is allowed to become a person once

71 Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human: A Book For Free Spirits, 51.; The complete

passage is: “We all of us, to be sure, still suffer from the all-too-little regard paid to

the personal in us, it has been badly cultivated – let us admit to ourselves that our

minds have, rather, been drawn forcibly away from it and offered as a sacrifice to

the state, to science, to those in need, as though what would have to be sacrificed

was in any case what was bad. Even now let us work for our fellow men, but only to

the extent that we discover our own highest advantage in this work: no more, no

less. All that remains is what it is one understands by one’s advantage; precisely the

immature, crude individual will understand it most crudely. 72 Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche, 112.

Page 33: Complete Copy

Page 33 of 80

he is free of a morality that constrains him unjustly through pitying self-sacrifice. As

Nietzsche’s morality evolves, he sees its culmination in “an ever more highly

evolving conception of usefulness and honourableness”73 and acts in accordance

with his “own standard with regard to men and things”74. The idea that the mature

individual possesses a ‘social self’ that behaves as if it were a member of a

community, will be explore in greater detail in chapter four.

The connection between Nietzsche and Virtue ethics at first seems tenuous.

Upon closer examination of both it becomes apparent that these supposed difficulties

are not as large as they first appear. An overview of contemporary virtue ethics

shows that there will be disparities in what is regarded as ‘virtuous’ over differing

time periods and circumstances. Swanton’s application of virtue ethics to Nietzsche

reveals that a philosophy that at first appears to advocate egoism and amorality, can

have virtuous features, depending on what factors these virtues are responding to.

The argument for Nietzsche as an egoist will be used to analyse many of the harmful

and negative trends prevalent on social media in the next chapter. As an alternative

to both this interpretation of Nietzsche, as well as this negative behaviour, chapter

four will outline the full implications of Nietzsche’s virtuous egoism and how it can

successfully be applied to our lives on social media.

73 Ibid, 112. 74 Ibid, 112.

Page 34: Complete Copy

Page 34 of 80

Chapter Three

In this chapter, I will present a counterargument to Swanton’s thesis that

Nietzsche is a virtue ethicist. I will do this by focusing on and analysing Nietzsche’s

reputation as an egoist, a fascist, and a nihilist. The chapter will focus on how

Nietzsche’s ideas are misrepresented and distorted in order to promote goals and

ideas that are the antithesis of Nietzsche’s vision, something that has been done

repeatedly in the twentieth and twenty first centuries. The ‘supposed’ influence of

Nietzsche on National Socialism is the most famous example of this, and thus will

be examined in detail. Returning to the present day, I will then focus on how trends

on social media are indicative of a misapplication of Nietzsche’s ideas in order to

lend credence to self-serving ends. This behaviour on social media is common, I am

using a Nietzschean framework to analyse some of these trends. As a case study, I

will be citing the online phenomenon known as the ‘alt-right’, an informal

movement that cites Nietzsche’s ideas as an influence on its political views. Critical

examination of the alt-right shows that the connection between Nietzsche and their

ideas are largely unfounded. The correction to this interpretation will be laid out

fully in chapter four, arguing for a better way of interpreting Nietzsche’s moral

philosophy as exercise of virtue.

As previously stated, an alternative vision of Nietzsche’s philosophy argues

that it is the seed from which much of the intellectual justification for fascism,

Page 35: Complete Copy

Page 35 of 80

Nazism, and immorality can grow.75 Much of this interpretation has arisen from

historical contingencies, mistranslation (in some cases wilful), and intentional

distortion of Nietzsche’s writings.76 A majority of the contemporary scholarship on

Nietzsche has rejected and refuted this interpretation. Two Nietzsche scholars have

addressed the relationship between Nietzsche and fascism by writing, “The central

ideal of Nietzsche’s philosophy was the individual and his freedom to shape his own

character destiny…What can such a thinker have in common with National

Socialism’s manipulation of the masses for goals that swallowed up the

personalities, concerns, and life of the individual?”77 Here Solomon and Higgins

point out that Nietzsche’s philosophy, properly understood, is focused on individual

freedom. Yet, in spite of this, this interpretation of Nietzsche continues to remain

relevant and influential in the public sphere. This is demonstrable by the prominence

of movements such as the ‘alt-right’, which cites Nietzsche as an influence on its

worldview.

For a long time, ‘Nietzsche as an antisocial egoist’ was the historically

dominant interpretation of Nietzsche and is largely the reason for his association

with anti-Semitism, nationalism, and Nazism78. Subsequent scholarship and new

translations of Nietzsche’s work have showed that this interpretation is not only

ungenerous but inaccurate, and a consequence of historical factors that had nothing

75 Solomon, and Higgins, What Nietzsche Really Said, 3-52. 76 Ibid, 9-11. 77 Jacob Golomb and Robert S. Witrich, Nietzsche, Godfather of Fascism? On the

Uses and Abuses of a Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2009), 1. 78 Ibid.

Page 36: Complete Copy

Page 36 of 80

to do with Nietzsche himself79. Nietzsche’s sister Elisabeth, edited and rewrote his

work to reflect her and her husband’s anti-Semitic and nationalist views80. This

action is from where much of Nietzsche’s negative reputation originates. It was this

decision that allowed the Nazis to deploy a bastardized version of Nietzsche’s

philosophy to serve their own nefarious ends. Anyone who questions the potential of

philosophers to influence historical and political affairs should note that in 1932

Nietzsche’s sister received a bouquet of flowers from Adolf Hitler, and two years

later the same man gave her a wreath for Nietzsche’s grave inscribed with the words

“To a Great Fighter”.81

Comparisons between Nietzsche and fascism began to be made not long after

the end of the Second World War. Albert Camus wrote that, “If Nietzsche and Hegel

serve as alibis to the masters of Dachau and Karaganda then that does not condemn

their entire philosophy. But it does lead to the suspicion that one aspect of their

thought, or of their logic, can lead to these appalling conclusions”.82 Thomas Mann

put it more forcefully when he wrote that, “In Kant and Nietzsche we have the

moralists of German militarism”.83

79 Walter Kauffmann, Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist (Princeton:

Princeton University Press, 1974). 80 Ibid, 4-5. 81 John Rodden, Repainting the Little Red Schoolhouse: A History of Eastern

German Education, 1945-1995 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 289. 82 Albert Camus, The Rebel: An Essay on Man in Revolt, trans. Anthony Bower

(New York City: Knopf Doubleday, 2012), 137. 83 T.J. Reed, Thomas Mann: The Uses of Tradition (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996),

189.

Page 37: Complete Copy

Page 37 of 80

One of the ways to understand the relationship between Nietzsche and

fascism is through the framework of Wittgenstein’s ‘family relationships’. In his

Philosophical Investigations, Ludwig Wittgenstein writes, “consider for example the

proceedings that we call ‘games’…look and see whether there is anything common

to all”.84 After elaborating on differing kinds of games, he writes “…we can go

through the many, many other groups of games in the same way; we can see how

similarities crop up and disappear.”85 Wittgenstein concludes from this that, “I can

think of no better expression to characterize these similarities than "family

resemblances"; for the various resemblances between members of a family: build,

features, colour of eyes, gait, temperament, etc. etc. overlap and criss-cross in the

same way…"games" form a family.”86 It is possible to understand the similarities

between Nietzsche and Hitler as ‘family resemblances’, of the kind excogitated by

Wittgenstein. Indeed, one historian of philosophy writes that Nietzsche was, “…the

child of Darwin and the brother of Bismarck”.87 Hitler’s ideas have been described

as a form of ‘social Darwinism’, and the man himself as a spiritual successor to

Bismarck.

Other theorists have also argued for a ‘family resemblance’ between

84 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (Hoboken: John Wiley &

Sons, 2010), 95. 85 Ibid, 95. 86 Ibid, 95. 87 Will Durant, The Story of Philosophy (New York City: Simon & Schuster, 1965),

522.

Page 38: Complete Copy

Page 38 of 80

Nietzsche’s ideas and those of National Socialism. One of them, Richard Wolin,

acknowledges that in his personal life Nietzsche was more concerned with “cultural

grandeur”, than with politics88. However, he also states that Nietzsche “was a

dogged defender of power, cruelty, and the warrior ethos…personified by several of

history’s more sanguinary tyrants: Alexander the Great, Julius Caesar, and

Napoleon”.89 A family resemblance between power, cruelty, and egotistical and

abusive behaviour should surprise no one, as we will see when we analyse some of

the tactics of the alt-right.

Nietzsche shared many traits with Adolf Hitler. They were both opponents of

democracy, egalitarianism, socialism, and parliamentary government. Nietzsche

wrote that “Where there have been powerful governments, societies, religions,

public opinions, in short wherever there has been tyranny, there the solitary

philosopher has been hated”.90 Hitler’s mistrust and contempt for democracy is also

evident from his writings. “...democracy will in practice lead to the destruction of a

people's true values…for the outstanding achievements of individuals...are now

rendered practically ineffective through the oppression of mere numbers.”91 Both

men despised Christianity. Nietzsche wrote, “I abhor Christianity with a deadly

88 Richard Wolin, The Seduction of Unreason: The Intellectual Romance with

Fascism: From Nietzsche to Postmodernism (Princeton: Princeton University Press,

2004), 31. 89 Ibid, 31. 90 Friedrich Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, ed. Daniel Breazeale (Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press, 1983), 139. 91 Roderick Stackelberg and Sally A. Winkle, ed., The Nazi Germany Sourcebook:

An Anthology of Texts (Abingdon-on-Thames: Routledge, 2013), 105.

Page 39: Complete Copy

Page 39 of 80

hatred”92. Hitler objected to Christianity as “a rebellion against the natural law of

selection by struggle and survival of the fittest”.93 Nietzsche also promoted “…the

development of the possibility of international species-unions which will set

themselves the task of rearing a new master race, the future ‘lords of the earth’”.94

Hitler writes that, “The Jew uses every possible means to undermine the racial

foundations of a subjugated people…” Hitler goes on to describe the Jewish people

as, “…responsible for…the ultimate idea of bastardizing the white race which they

hate… Never in this world can the Jew become master of any people except a

bastardized people.”95

Nietzsche had ambivalent feelings towards the Jewish people.96 In

Beyond Good and Evil, he wrote, “…the Jews achieved that miracle of

inversion of values thanks to which life on earth has for a couple of

millennia acquired a new and dangerous fascination…” Nietzsche

concludes that, “It is in this inversion of values ... that the significance of

the Jewish people resides: with them there begins the slave revolt in

morals.”97

92 Friedrich Nietzsche, Writings from the Late Notebooks, ed. Rudiger Bittner

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 259. 93 Alan Bullock, Hitler: A Study in Tyranny (New York City: HarperCollins, 1991),

219. 94 Tracy B. Strong, Friedrich Nietzsche and the Politics of Transfiguration

(Oakland: University of California Press, 1988), 290. 95 Adolf Hitler, Mein Kampf, trans. James Murphy (London: Hurst & Blackett,

1939). Accessed August 15, 2016. http://gutenberg.net.au/ebooks02/0200601.txt. 96 Solomon and Higgins, What Nietzsche Really Said, 12. 97 Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future, 84.

Page 40: Complete Copy

Page 40 of 80

In many cases the evidence for a relationship between Nietzsche and Hitler

seems considerable. However, to observe these resemblances is not to equate them.

Numerous scholars of Nietzsche have stressed the two men’s significant differences,

differences that result in a greatly reduced parity between the two. Solomon notes on

Nietzsche and anti-Semitism that, “Germany had a long history of anti-Semitism,

dating back (at least) to the Middle Ages…It is much to Nietzsche’s credit, then,

living where he did and surrounded by anti-Semites, that he refused to share their

intolerance and openly came to denounce anti-Semitism”.98 Walter Kauffmann

closely analyses Nietzsche’s advocacy for a ‘master race’ and finds Nietzsche’s

thought process to be greatly different from Hitler’s. He writes that, “…it was

perfectly clear that Nietzsche looked to art, religion, and philosophy – and not to

race – to elevate man above the beasts, and some men above the mass of

mankind”.99 Kauffmann elaborates that, “…no man could presume to know with any

certainty who among his fellow men might be chosen and who damned; and all men

might have to be treated with respect as “potentially human beings”.100 Kauffmann’s

proviso in this last quote provides a hint to what is the most significant difference

between Hitler and Nietzsche. Nietzsche does not presume to know the exact details

of what superior person would emerge in his ideal society, or where they would

emerge from. He does not base his advocacy for a ‘master race’ on any form of

determinism, particularly not genetic or ethnic determinism as will be evidenced in

98 Solomon and Higgins, What Nietzsche Really Said, 11. 99 Kauffmann, Nietzsche, Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist, 285. 100 Ibid, 285-286.

Page 41: Complete Copy

Page 41 of 80

the next chapter.

Returning to the present day, I would argue that there exists a ‘family

resemblance’ between this misinterpretation of Nietzsche, and the unrestrained and

antisocial behaviour that is observable on the internet today. Ideas, even irrational

and inaccurate ones, contain their own internal logic and have an influence that

exists independently of their lowly origins. A good example of this would be the

continued prevalence of racism and anti-Semitism across the world today, in spite of

the disastrous consequences these ideas have had when put into practice. Solomon

writes that, “The literature about and against Nietzsche is voluminous, but despite a

great deal of scholarship in the past half century, old myths and prejudices remain

prominent in the public consciousness”.101 As previously stated, these resemblances

between Nietzsche and fascism can be used to understand the angry, antisocial, and

egotistical behaviour that is observable on the internet today.

One case study that strongly highlights the ‘family resemblance’ between the

antisocial interpretation of Nietzsche and the antisocial internet of today is the

online phenomenon known as the Alternative Right, or the ‘alt-right’. The ‘alt-right’

is a political group that advocates an alternative to political conservatism,

particularly in the United States.102 It rose to prominence in 2016 for its support of

101 Solomon and Higgins, What Nietzsche Really Said, 3. 102 Benjamin Welton, "What, Exactly, Is the 'Alternative Right?", The Weekly

Standard, accessed August 18, 2016, http://www.weeklystandard.com/what-exactly-

is-the-alternative-right/article/2000310.

Page 42: Complete Copy

Page 42 of 80

Republican presidential candidate Donald Trump103, and for its opposition to

multiculturalism and immigration104. Numerous commentators have linked it to

white supremacism, white nationalism, anti-Semitism, and reactionary politics. The

alt-right derives much of its notoriety from its presence on social media, especially

its use of internet memes to advance its views105. As stated in chapter one, the harm

that is done by the alt-right through social media is quantitative, not qualitative.

Using internet memes to function as a wall of anonymity in order to express hateful

views is what creates the lack of a feedback mechanism that would normally deter

such behaviour in the real world.

In spite of what many people may think about the politics of the alt-right

movement, the popularisation of unpopular ideas does not necessarily translate into

what one would typically call ‘antisocial’ behaviour. This is where the alt-right

movement’s presence on social media becomes important. Members of the alt-right

movement have repeatedly targeted individuals and groups online, especially Jewish

organisations, with abusive and derogatory content.106 The repeated use of internet

memes to advance racist views online has provoked a response from the Anti-

103 Abby Ohlheiser, "Anti-Semitic Trump Supporters Made a Giant List of People to

Target with a Racist Meme," The Washington Post, accessed August 18, 2016,

https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/the-intersect/wp/2016/06/03/anti-semitic-

trump-supporters-made-a-giant-list-of-people-to-target-with-a-racist-meme/ 104 Cathy Young, "Donald Trump’s Hate for Political Correctness Is Comfort Food

to Racists," Newsday, accessed August 18, 2016,

http://www.newsday.com/opinion/columnists/cathy-young/donald-trump-s-rant-

against-political-correctness-is-comfort-food-to-racists-1.11391400. 105 Abby Ohlheiser,"Anti-Semitic Trump Supporters Made a Giant List of People to

Target with a Racist Meme". 106 Ibid.

Page 43: Complete Copy

Page 43 of 80

Defamation League in the United States. ‘Pepe the Frog’ (also known as the ‘sad

frog’) has been a popular internet meme since 2005, when it appeared in an online

cartoon Boy’s Club.107 On September 28, the Anti-Defamation League declared that

Pepe’s image was a hate symbol, particularly when used with racially charged

symbolism.108

109

The Anti-Defamation League justified its decision by stating that,

“…it was inevitable that, as the meme proliferated in

on-line venues such as 4chan, 8chan, and Reddit, which have

many users who delight in creating racist memes and

imagery, a subset of Pepe memes would come into existence

that centred on racist, anti-Semitic or other bigoted themes.

In recent years, with the growth of the "alt right" segment of

the white supremacist movement, a segment that draws some

107 “Pepe the Frog”, The Anti-Defamation League, accessed September 28, 2016,

http://www.adl.org/combating-hate/hate-on-display/c/pepe-the-

frog.html?referrer=https://en.wikipedia.org/#.WAWiJPl96Ul 108 Mary Bowerman, “Pepe the Frog declared a hate symbol by Anti-Defamation

League,” USA Today, accessed September 28, 2016,

http://www.usatoday.com/story/news/nation-now/2016/09/28/pepe-the-frog-internet-

meme-declared-hate-symbol-anti-defamation-league/91210140/ 109 “Pepe the Frog.”

Page 44: Complete Copy

Page 44 of 80

of its support from some of the above-mentioned Internet

sites, the number of "alt right" Pepe memes has grown, a

tendency exacerbated by the controversial and contentious

2016 presidential election. Though Pepe memes have many

defenders, the use of racist and bigoted versions of Pepe

memes seems to be increasing, not decreasing.”110

111 112

Above are Pepe memes that the Anti-Defamation League used as an example

of the content that the alt-right proliferates online in order to promote its views, or to

abuse the people it targets. The influence of Nietzsche on the politics of the alt-right

is often implied, and on the ‘Alternative Right’ blog, Nietzsche is directly cited as an

influence on the ‘movement’. As noted in chapter one, the alt-right seems to be

enacting Nietzsche’s will to power, by denigrating others in order to advance its own

aims. The similarities between Nietzsche and the alt-right are useful in order to

understand what this movement is indicative of, even though there are large

divergences between Nietzsche and the politics of the alt-right. One of the alt-right’s

110 Ibid. 111 Ibid. 112 Ibid.

Page 45: Complete Copy

Page 45 of 80

greatest attractions to individuals is its rejection of political correctness.113 Many

members of the alt-right movement regard ‘political correctness’ as a form of

censorship imposed by society’s mediocrities. This opinion congeals well with

Nietzsche’s criticisms of democracy quoted earlier. It isn’t hard to think of many

members of the alt-right community envisioning themselves as philosopher kings,

deposed and oppressed by a tyrannical majority in the form of ‘society’. Nietzsche’s

criticisms of democracy, socialism, collectivism and other forms of group

association all lend credence to the similarity between Nietzsche and far right

philosophies like National Socialism, and, the alt-right.

It is important to refer back to the notion of ‘willing a self’ that was quoted

from Nietzsche in the first chapter and how this relates to the activities of the alt-

right. Much of the content that is proliferated by the alt-right is done anonymously,

through websites like 4chan and 8chan. Such abuse and harassment is obviously a

reproof from any form of social censure or punishment by one’s peers, due to the

fact that the identity of the person is wholly unknown. It is also different from the

behaviour referenced in chapter one of ‘catfishing’, where one creates a fake

persona. To what extent this kind of behaviour constitutes philosophically traditional

conceptions of ‘self’ is beyond the scope of this thesis. However, it is important to

stress the complete divergence in outcome between this behaviour taking place

online, and it taking place in the real world. What the lack of social constraints

113 “What You Need To Know About The Alt-Right Movement”, NPR, accessed

September 15, 2016, http://www.npr.org/2016/08/26/491452721/the-history-of-the-

alt-right

Page 46: Complete Copy

Page 46 of 80

within the online sphere has created for internet users is the freedom to act in a way

that is divorced of social realities. In this way, how we choose to communicate to

individuals is subject only to our own desire. We are ‘radically free’ in this way, in

fact it provides greater freedom than Sartre or Nietzsche would have thought

possible, due to the fact that we are free of the social consequences of this

behaviour. This freedom, coupled with the individual’s desires, is what amount to

sincerity in expression referenced in the first chapter. It is in this way that the

members of the alt-right can be said to be ‘willing a self’. Without a conscious

acknowledgement of our online presence as a facet of our ‘social self’, this kind of

behaviour will be more likely to occur.

Although much of Nietzsche’s reputation as a fascist is a result of

mistranslation, distortion, and historical contingencies, there still remain similarities

between Nietzsche’s philosophy and visions of the world that are prejudiced,

antisocial, and reactionary. Notable philosophers and intellectuals like Camus and

Mann made this observation not long after the downfall of National Socialism, a

political movement that Nietzsche’s name is likely to be forever tarnished with.

Much of the similarities between Nietzsche’s philosophy and these visions are due to

Nietzsche’s dislike of all forms of collectivism, especially the idea that society

should dictate to individuals what they can say, and what they can think. Although

similarities exist between Nietzsche and the far right, the differences between the

two are considerably more important when properly examined. These differences

will form part of the focus of the penultimate chapter of this thesis, displaying how

Page 47: Complete Copy

Page 47 of 80

Nietzsche’s ideas are radically different from these groups that he has been

associated with. The rest of chapter four will focus on a corrective to this

interpretation of Nietzsche, which is of Nietzsche as a virtue ethicist. This corrective

will not only function as a different interpretation of Nietzsche, but also offer a

corrective ethic to the behaviour online that the alt-right embodies.

Page 48: Complete Copy

Page 48 of 80

Chapter Four

In the previous chapter, I examined interpretations of Nietzsche as an

antisocial egoist, and that his moral philosophy confers upon others only a

responsibility to disparage others in favour of one’s self. In this chapter, I will

defend a more accurate interpretation of Nietzsche’s work that can be understood

and extrapolated by using a virtue ethics framework. The two key philosophers I will

be using to support this claim are MacIntyre and Swanton, both contemporary virtue

ethicists who have written about Nietzsche. This will be done by analysing

Nietzsche’s moral and social philosophy as a process of excellence that is applied to

individuals. Once this process has been fully analysed it will then be applied to

current trends on social media, and how it can offer an alternative to its negative

effects and outcomes.

In After Virtue, Alasdair MacIntyre frames moral philosophy in the present

day as a conflict between ‘individualism’ and what he refers to as the ‘Aristotelian

tradition’.114 In his argument, MacIntyre regards Nietzsche’s writings as an

extension and conclusion of Enlightenment morals; namely, the idea of grounding

morality solely on rationality and secularism. MacIntyre goes on to claim that

Nietzsche’s importance lies in his, “proposal to raze to the ground the structures of

inherited moral belief”.115 His analysis of Nietzsche supports the theory that

114 MacIntytre, After Virtue, 300. 115 Ibid, 256.

Page 49: Complete Copy

Page 49 of 80

Nietzsche is a denier and destroyer of shared morality, seeking to replace it with a

society of isolated, amoral egoists. MacIntyre cites passages from Nietzsche’s work

to support this interpretation, such as the following:

“A great man – a man whom nature has constructed and

invented in the grand style – what is he? …If he cannot lead,

he goes alone; then it can happen that he may snarl at some

things he meets on the way… he wants no “sympathetic” heart,

but servants, tools; in his intercourse with men he is always

intent on making something out of them. He knows he is

incommunicable: he finds it tasteless to be familiar; and when

one thinks he is, he usually is not. When not speaking to

himself; he wears a mask. He rather lies than tells the truth: it

requires more spirit and will. There is a solitude within him

that is inaccessible to praise or blame, his own justice that is

beyond appeal”.116

MacIntyre interprets this passage by arguing that Nietzsche’s conception of

‘the great man’ represents, “individualism’s final attempt to escape from its own

consequences”.117 Basing an ethical framework on individualism is a mistake

because the ‘individual’ is not what necessitates morality, what necessitates it are

human relationships. For morality to be based on any form of isolation from human

relationships, would be to undermine the foundations on which morality is built.

MacIntyre argues,

“…relationships which constitute communities whose

central bond is a shared vision and understanding of goods.

To cut oneself off from shared activity in which one has

initially to learn obediently as an apprentice learns, to isolate

oneself from the communities which find their point and

116 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, ed. Walter Kauffmann, trans. Walter

Kauffmann and R.J. Hollingdale (Vintage: New York City, 1968) , 499. 117 MacIntyre, After Virtue, 300.

Page 50: Complete Copy

Page 50 of 80

purpose in such activities, will be to debar oneself from

finding any good outside oneself. It will be to condemn

oneself to that moral solipsism which constitutes Nietzschean

greatness.”118

MacIntyre’s critique of Nietzschean individualism is fundamentally a

critique of his egoism, which is the greatest obstacle to any interpretation of

Nietzsche as a virtue ethicist. 119 There are similarities in the criticisms that

MacIntyre makes of Nietzsche and the assumptions made by those people who

condone the latter’s egoism. The only difference of course is that the former is a

detractor, while the latter is an endorser. For example, both assume that Nietzsche’s

egoism in conjunction with his advocacy for the ‘mature individual’, necessitates an

asocial, isolated individual, free from all social and moral concerns. This is evident

in MacIntyre’s argument about Nietzsche’s moral philosophy as a natural extension

of individualism and Enlightenment morality. He writes of Nietzsche, “…the

Nietzschean stance turns out not to be a mode of escape from or an alternative to the

conceptual scheme of liberal individualist modernity, but rather one more

representative moment in its internal unfolding”.120

An alternative to this interpretation is Swanton’s argument that virtue ethics

must be understood as ‘response dependent’. This is due to the fact that different

moral situations will warrant different responses and actions from people, and this

becomes significant when examining the character of the individual who is making a

118 Ibid, 300. 119 Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche, 111. 120 MacIntyre, After Virtue, 259.

Page 51: Complete Copy

Page 51 of 80

moral decision. Swanton writes that, “Different types of responses are warranted by

the different types of morally significant features in the items constituting the field

of the virtues”.121 She goes on to write, “…What counts as bias, self‐indulgence,

selfishness, self‐centredness, or narrowness of concern is not in my view something

that can be determined without looking deeply into the agent.” Instead, “we need to

know in a deep sense, what the agent's behaviour expresses…”122

The above passage is relevant to examining Nietzsche as a virtue ethicist. It

is easy to assume that many of Nietzsche’s views are an expression of his “self-

indulgence, selfishness, self-centredness, or narrowness…”123 This is done by

equivocating Nietzsche’s thought with the immoral behaviour of people who claim

to be influenced by him. However, as examined in chapter three, the similarities

between Nietzsche and these actions do not stand up to scrutiny.

This is evidenced in Nietzsche’s own personal correspondence with his

sister, Elisabeth. In spite of the accusations of anti-Semitism, Nietzsche is notable

for the fact that he refused to condone or support such beliefs. His brother-in-law

Bernhard Forster, was a prominent German nationalist who regularly wrote anti-

Semitic tracts about the ‘Jewish question’.124 Nietzsche’s letter to his sister in

121 Swanton, Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View, p. 24. 122 Ibid, 177. 123 Ibid, 177. 124 Carol Diethe, Nietzsche’s Sister and the Will to Power: A Biography of Elisabeth

Forster-Nietzsche (Champaign: University of Illinois Press, 2003), 36.

Page 52: Complete Copy

Page 52 of 80

response to her husband’s literary activities reveals that Nietzsche held no

ambivalence about such views:

“…I’ve seen proof, black on white that Herr Dr Forster

has not yet severed his connection with the anti-Semitic

movement…Since then I’ve had difficulty coming up with

any of the tenderness and protectiveness I’ve so long felt

toward you. The separation between us is thereby

decided…Now it has gone so far that I have to defend myself

hand and foot against people who confuse me with these anti-

Semitic canaille. After I read the name Zarathustra in the

anti-Semitic Correspondence my forbearance came to an end.

I am now in a position of emergency defence against your

spouse’s party. These accursed anti-Semitic deformities shall

not sully my ideal”.125

As previously stated, Nietzsche’s advocacy for the ‘great man’ and a ‘master

race’ was not based on any form of ethnic or genetic determinism, indeed he was

hostile to such ideas. The following paragraphs will analyse Nietzsche’s moral and

social philosophy as a process of excellence that is applied to individuals. Once this

process has been fully analysed it will then be applied to current trends on social

media, and how it can offer an alternative to its negative effects and outcomes.

However, what of Nietzsche’s ‘will to power’. It would seem that this idea of

Nietzsche’s would derail any attempt to account for his status as a virtue ethicist.

Many scholars of Nietzsche, such as Solomon, regard the ‘will to power’ as a minor

factor in Nietzsche’s philosophy, and that all it indicates is Nietzsche’s dislike of

125 David Farrell Krell, Nietzsche: A Novel (Albany: SUNY Press, 1996), 324.

Page 53: Complete Copy

Page 53 of 80

hedonism.126 However, presume this is not the case. Just as Nietzsche did not regard

‘pleasure’ as a good, he also did not regard ‘power’ as intrinsically good either, what

was ‘good’, was whether or not this power was exercised excellently.127 Nietzsche

notes that there are different kinds of ‘will’, than the ‘will to power’. There is the

“will to memory”, and the “will to truth”.128 Even if one were to argue that these

different wills were simply different parts of the ‘will to power’, it would still follow

from this conclusion that there is no single thing called ‘power’. Following from

this, it becomes important to remember that Nietzsche did not regard ‘power’ as the

final end or telos of his moral philosophy, but rather the application of the will of

individuals. Focusing on these individuals allows for a more congruent reading of

Nietzsche as a virtue ethicist, and his philosophy as being as process of excellence.

After ‘altruism’, as discussed in chapter two, the main focus of Nietzsche’s

criticism is ‘immature egoism’.129 If altruistic actions are to be rejected, then surely

it follows that all of our actions should be done for the sake of the self and solely for

the sake of the self. In fact, Nietzsche’s writing does not support this interpretation.

What Nietzsche advocates is an entirely different moral response that did not

conform to the intellectual climate of his day. This is what Swanton refers to as the

‘collective-individual.’130

126 Robert C. Solomon, Living with Nietzsche: What the Great ‘Immoralist’ Has To

Teach Us (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 85-88. 127 Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche, 119. 128Ibid, 122. 129 Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human: A Book for Free Spirits, 51. 130 Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche, 116; Christine Swanton,

“Nietzsche and the Collective-Individual,” in Individual and Community in

Page 54: Complete Copy

Page 54 of 80

Nietzsche does not assert that individuals are divorced from their society, or

that they should strive to be. If this were true, it would reveal a contradiction in

Nietzsche’s admiration for art and culture, and the harsh criticism that he made of

those who failed to admit the latter’s importance. This is evidenced in the preface to

Nietzsche’s first book, The Birth of Tragedy, where he writes that, “Art is the

supreme task and the truly metaphysical activity in this life…”131

The contradiction here is the fact that any kind of culture, especially high

culture, is rarely produced in isolation. Although we regularly romanticize the lone

artist struggling in solitude, the reality is that many people are required in order to

guarantee that Beethoven’s symphonies, Shakespeare’s plays, and Rembrandt’s

paintings are preserved and disseminated to others, especially in the transferral of

cultural knowledge from one generation to the next. Great art is dependent on the

many. Nietzsche’s personal values suggest that he implicitly understood this and so

his ‘collective-individuals’ are not without culture. They have a stake in the society

that they live in. Yet, these people are not responsible for, or accountable to, the

whole society. Nietzsche’s denunciations of altruism were consistent. So, where do

the “collective-individuals” locate themselves?

Nietzsche’s Philosophy, ed. Julian Young (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

2014), 174-195. 131 Friedrich Nietzsche. The Birth of Tragedy and Other Writings, ed. Raymond

Geuss and Ronald Speirs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 14.

Page 55: Complete Copy

Page 55 of 80

Is it possible to be a member of a society without the ‘interests’ of said

society becoming preeminent over the lives of the individuals who compose it? This

is the relevant question when analysing Nietzsche’s moral philosophy. As stated in

chapter three, Nietzsche’s antagonism to collectivism is due to its propensity to

frustrate and restrict the capabilities of the individuals within that collective.

Nietzsche writes that, “In his heart every man knows quite well that, being unique,

he will be in the world only once and that no imaginable chance will for a second

time gather together into a unity so strangely variegated an assortment as he is.” But,

instead of embracing this uniqueness, he “…knows it but he hides it like a bad

conscience—why? From fear of his neighbour, who demands conventionality and

cloaks himself with it.”132

Examples of the frustrating and restrictive effects of collectivism would be

the ‘slave-morality’ that Nietzsche describes in his book, On the Genealogy of

Morality. Nietzsche saw kindness, humility, and sympathy as the essence of the

‘slave-morality’ framework. This is not because Nietzsche disparages these

qualities, in and of themselves. It is due to the fact that they are grounded in what

Nietzsche regarded as resentment, an envious desire to have what others do not.

Unfortunately for his later reputation, Nietzsche originated this quality in the Jewish

people of the ancient world. He writes:“...the Jews achieved that miracle of inversion

of values thanks to which life on earth has for a couple millennia acquired a new and

dangerous fascination--their prophets fused 'rich', 'godless', 'evil', 'violent', 'sensual'

132 Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, 127.

Page 56: Complete Copy

Page 56 of 80

into one and were the first to coin the word 'world' as a term of infamy.” According

to Nietzsche, a consequence of this was “…an inversion of values (with which is

involved the employment of the word for 'poor' as a synonym for 'holy' and 'friend')

that the significance of the Jewish people resides: with them there begins the slave

revolt in morals.”133

Nietzsche goes on to argue that Christianity universalised these qualities in

people, by making them synonymous with the deity, and it is from here that much of

the weakness and decay of Western culture originates.134 However, an important

caveat in Nietzsche’s opinion of Christianity is his admiration for the figure of Jesus

Christ. Nietzsche writes that, “…there was really only one Christian, and he died on

the cross.” Nietzsche stresses a distinction between the man Christ and the people

who claimed to be his followers, “It is false to the point of absurdity to think that

Christians are characterized by their ‘beliefs’…only the practice of Christianity is

really Christian, living like the man who died on the cross.”135 Jesus Christ could be

used as an appropriate example of the ‘collective-individual’ that Nietzsche

describes. One whose social concerns were tied to his personal ones. The collective-

individual and virtuous egoist is one who “cultivates what is personal”.136

133 Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality ed. Keith Ansell-Pearson,

trans. Carol Diethe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 145. 134 Ibid, 167. 135 Nietzsche, The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, Twilight of the Idols, and Other

Writings, 35. 136 Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche, 116.

Page 57: Complete Copy

Page 57 of 80

Nietzsche argues that each individual’s contribution to society, within a

moral framework, is to cultivate one’s own preferences and desires. This does not

mean that Nietzsche presumes that there will be a beneficial or equal outcome for

each individual, even for those with the same interests. However, it is the best

framework within which to allow for individuals to ‘flourish’, to use the Aristotelian

term. If we refer back to Nietzsche’s statement that, “Every enhancement of the type

"man" has so far been the work of an aristocratic society—and it will be so again

and again”, this trend results in “…a society that believes in the long ladder of an

order of rank and differences in value between man and man, and that needs slavery

in some sense or other.”137

A different understanding of Nietzsche’s assumptions when he uses such

phrases leads to a radically different conclusion about Nietzsche’s intentions in

writing it. Nietzsche’s vision is not a society of predestined individuals who are

ranked at the expense or benefit of others. Instead, it is a philosophy of moral

behaviour where different people with different values, ‘cultivate what is personal’,

and in doing so inadvertently contribute to the greatness of the society at large. The

slavery that Nietzsche mentions here is perhaps not be taken literally as economic

slavery, his hostile response to racism and anti-Semitism suggests that he did not see

people as innately slavish or successful. The slavery that Nietzsche is referring to

here are the inevitable failures that occur in life. What is important, for Nietzsche, is

how we deal with such inevitable disappointments.

137 Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil¸ 151.

Page 58: Complete Copy

Page 58 of 80

This different interpretation of Nietzsche’s writings allows us to re-examine

social media in a different light. On first observation, social media is simply a

method of communication, performed through the medium of the internet. However,

it is also a social process that transfers information. The sources of this information

are diverse, ranging from formal organizations that influence whole societies (i.e.

political, economic, the media, and the entertainment industry), to informal

associations and relationships that individuals voluntarily enter into (i.e. Facebook,

Tinder). However, the information that we receive through the internet is only half

of the story. The information we receive also facilitates decision making in response.

In chapters one and three I claimed that the harm performed on social media

is quantitative, not qualitative. It is not ‘qualitative’ due to the fact that much of the

abuse administered online is no different from any other comment that one might

hear on the street in a face to face confrontation. It is ‘quantitative’ due to the fact

that the absence of usual deterrents and constraints on such behaviour allows it to

increase and flourish, unchecked. This situation includes our ability to communicate

to others anonymously, to create fake personas or ‘selves’ online, and to direct

abusive or hateful rhetoric to others without the usual consequences of social

censure. The point to this thesis has been to identify the underlying logic or rationale

behind this activity, and how it responds to the different kinds of incentives and

constraints that social media creates.

Page 59: Complete Copy

Page 59 of 80

It would at first be prudent to address the issue of ‘free speech’ before

examining social media in greater detail. One possible defence of the alt-right’s

tactics online is that to cause offense, even intentionally, is not in and of itself an

immoral act due to the fact that offence, in itself, is not wrong. The issue becomes a

question of a trade-off between individual liberty and the unintentional harm that is

done to others by exercising this freedom.

The three normative moral theories of western philosophy provide different

interpretations of this trade-off. The utilitarian ethic usually cites John Stuart Mill’s

“harm principle” when analysing this topic, “That the only purpose for which power

can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his

will, is to prevent harm to others.”138 This philosophy is enshrined in Australia’s

legal system, where the potential for harm in the exercising of free speech is taken

into account. One example of this would be Section 18C of the Racial

Discrimination Act.139 Compare this to the United States constitution’s first

amendment, “Congress shall make no law…prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or

abridging the freedom of speech…”140 This position reflects deontological ethics,

where the government’s allowance for free speech is morally and legally required,

138 John Stuart Mill, On Liberty and Other Writings, ed. Stefan Collini (Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press, 1989), 13; “John Stuart Mill”, Stanford Encyclopaedia

of Philosophy, accessed September 2, 2016, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill/ 139 “Racial Discrimination Act 1975 – Sect 18C”, Commonwealth Consolidated

Acts, accessed September 2, 2016,

http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/legis/cth/consol_act/rda1975202/s18c.html 140 “First Amendment”, Legal Information Institute, accessed September 2, 2016,

https://www.law.cornell.edu/constitution/first_amendment

Page 60: Complete Copy

Page 60 of 80

without forbiddance.141 This position was best described by Kant, when he wrote

that, “…act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same

time will that it become a universal law”.142

A virtue ethics analysis of this trade-off yields a different interpretation. Note

that it is not the intention of this thesis to go into great depth about the complications

and particularities related to freedom of speech, as such a task is beyond the scope of

this thesis. However, it would be useful to examine how the notion of free speech

applies to a virtue ethics framework. In virtue ethics, there are greater variances

allowed when judging an action. These include the effects of the act, the intention of

the moral agent, and the moral agent’s overall character. This style of moral

examination is referred to by MacIntyre as a “socially embedded argument”143

where the,

“…individual’s search for his or her good is generally

and characteristically conducted within a context defined by

those traditions of which the individual’s life is a part and this

is true both of those goods which are internal to practices and

of the goods of a single life”.144

141 “Deontological Ethics.” 142 Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, ed. Mary Gregor

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 31. 143 Alasdair MacIntyre, “The Virtues, the Unity of a Human Life and the Concept of

a Tradition” in The Good Life, ed. Charles Guignon (Indianapolis: Hackett

Publishing, 1999), 313. 144 Ibid, 313.

Page 61: Complete Copy

Page 61 of 80

For MacIntyre, the application of ‘internal goods’ over a period of time is

what constitutes a ‘living tradition’. Analysis of this tradition entails a discussion

between the practitioners of that tradition and the people who are exterior to it, about

what these goods are, and what they are not. In the case of free speech, it is

necessary for its defendants and its critics to discuss whether the alt-right’s

exercitation of free speech is a vice, or a virtue.

To take the alt-right’s behaviour into the real world would be to subject it to

constraints and deterrents that would make the group unlikely to flourish in the same

way that it has online. The alt-right regards the internet as the forum where the

desired outcome of an aristocratic society will take root. The nature of this outcome

is intended to be aristocratic in form, where one group or individuals is ranked

higher than another. The fallacy at work here is the presumption of a result

occurring through individual intention, rather than as a systemic outcome from each

individual behaving in a constrained manner. It is in fact this understanding of

aristocracy as a systemic outcome that lies at the heart of understanding Nietzsche as

a virtuous egoist.

The virtuous egoism that I have argued Nietzsche’s writings embody,

envisions aristocracy as the outcome of a process of excellence that is applied to

individuals. It is important to emphasize that Nietzsche does not make the same

mistake as the alt-right in assuming that this ‘aristocratic society’ can be designed. In

order to clarify this, we need to return to the dichotomy introduced in chapter one,

Page 62: Complete Copy

Page 62 of 80

between sincerity in expression, and fidelity to one’s values. The alt-right exercises

sincerity in expression when it prioritizes the sincerity of its beliefs, and where this

sincerity can only be validated by creating or instigating outcomes that are reflective

of this. By contrast, fidelity to one’s own values is more concerned with an

individual’s loyalty to their own objectives, which are pursued for their own sake

and to one’s best ability. When this pursuit is subjected to a process of excellence,

the outcome becomes secondary to the activity itself, due to the fact that the

outcome is likely to be produced by larger systemic factors than simply by individual

intention.

This process of excellence is one where individuals ‘cultivate what is

personal’ within them and behave accordingly. Due to the diverse nature of human

capabilities and desires, and due to the sheer number of people living in the world,

what kind of outcome that would result if such a process was applied universally is

impossible to say. However, it would create different incentives and constraints that

would undermine and remove the harmful and toxic effects of altruism and

immature egoism. The incentives in this case would be of people striving to achieve

their own desired goals and ends within their own capabilities and means. This is far

more likely to produce a healthy and robust high culture than any other. The

alternative is a social process whereby the beneficial desires of individuals are

judged by third parties, and where certain individuals pay the costs in order to

benefit others. This different process becomes the decider in how individuals will

subsequently behave as well as direct their attention and labours. These third parties

Page 63: Complete Copy

Page 63 of 80

could be the Church, the state, numerous institutions, and advocacy groups like the

alt-right that wish to reduce the options available to other people.

In order to support this argument for virtuous conduct online, it is important

to examine what this virtuous conduct would look like. One examples of ‘collective

individuals’ behaving in a manner that was an extension of their social selves, is the

‘I’ll ride with you hashtag’ that emerged on social media in the wake of the 2014

Sydney hostage crisis. Amassing 120,000 tweets on Twitter, the hashtag was a

message of solidarity to Australian Muslims who feared that they might be subject to

retributive violence from people on public transport, due to the religiously motivated

nature of the attack.145 Another example would be the ‘Ice Bucket Challenge’ where

participants filmed themselves having a bucket of ice water poured on their heads, in

order to promote awareness of motor neurone disease. The challenge became an

online phenomenon, raising one hundred million dollars for the ALS Association.146

What these two examples illustrate are individuals pursuing solitary activities that

nevertheless have a systemic effect on society. One of the benefits of the internet is a

more efficient allocation of information, access to this information is something that

allows individuals to behave as ‘collective individuals’ when online, and to

communicate with people whom they never would have previously been able to.

145 Brittany Rupert, “Martin Place siege: #illridewithyou hashtag goes viral”, Sydney

Morning Herald, accessed September 4, 2016, http://www.smh.com.au/nsw/martin-

place-siege-illridewithyou-hashtag-goes-viral-20141215-127rm1.html 146 “The ALS Association Expresses Sincere Gratitude to Over Three Million

Donors”, ALS Association, accessed September 4, 2016,

http://www.alsa.org/news/media/press-releases/ice-bucket-challenge-

082914.html?referrer=https://en.wikipedia.org/

Page 64: Complete Copy

Page 64 of 80

In this chapter, the argument of Nietzsche as an antisocial egoist has been

shown to be a fallacious distortion and misuse of his work. One alternative to this

popular interpretation has been of Nietzsche as a virtuous egoist, who argued for a

different social process to be applied to people, in order for them to realise their

fullest potential. MacIntyre’s argument for virtue ethics as an ‘embedded social

argument’ means that the moral capabilities of the individual are constrained by

different systemic factors that often exist independently of any individual’s intention

or behaviour. It is the argument of this thesis that a process of excellence needs to

become customary in our usage of the internet, where its users understand

themselves as ‘collective-individuals’ whose activities on social media are an

extension of their social selves. If this process were to become recognized as part of

our ‘lived tradition’, then the chance of such antisocial behaviour increasing would

most likely decline.

Page 65: Complete Copy

Page 65 of 80

Chapter Five: Conclusion

In this thesis I have argued that the freedom and licence that social media offers

us is the closest thing that allows us to experience Sartre’s dictum that ‘existence

precedes essence’. This is due to the fact that we have a greater ability to create a self

on social media, using online avatars and tools available to us through social media’s

inbuilt mechanisms that require users to establish and build personal profiles. Social

media encourages us to add further details and information that is shared in public,

inviting us to project an image of ourselves for others to see and judge, perhaps

explaining why social media often relies on images rather than words. Social media

promises us liberty – the liberty to connect with others all over the world

instantaneously and to portray ourselves as we would like to be seen; seemingly

reflecting the existentialist ideas of ‘radical freedom’ and ‘authenticity’. Yet this

freedom is neither desirable nor sustainable, without proper consideration of our

embodied context and the ways in which we ought to conduct our relationships to

others. Furthermore, the untrammelled freedom of social media websites and

platforms paradoxically limit this freedom through the costs that such freedom

imposes on its users.

The internet, particularly social media, allows human beings to create an

online self. I have connected this freedom to the existentialist notion of ‘radical

freedom’ espoused by Sartre, but more specifically to Friedrich Nietzsche’s

commandment ‘will a self’. Nietzsche wrote that, “Active, successful natures act, not

according to the dictum “know thyself,” but as if there hovered before them a

Page 66: Complete Copy

Page 66 of 80

commandment: will a self and thou shalt become a self”163. This thesis has explored

in great detail the ramifications of how creating an online self reflects Nietzsche’s idea

of the will to power and how we should critically analyse this endeavour, as applied

to social media today.

Chapter two contained the main argument that Nietzsche was a virtue ethicist,

citing virtue ethicists and philosophers to support this claim. The most important and

influential moral philosopher for this argument was Christine Swanton, who has

argued that the virtues are response dependent, meaning that what is or is not

understood as virtuous behaviour is contingent on what the moral agent is responding

to in a particular time and place. This new interpretation of virtue ethics allowed for

Nietzsche to be interpreted as a virtue ethicist, with his criticisms of altruism and

immature egoism as manifestations of virtue in Nietzsche’s moral philosophy.

One of the important tenets of virtue theory that was expounded in chapter two

was the idea of ‘practical wisdom’ in moral decision making. Compared to abstract or

theoretical knowledge, practical wisdom (or phronesis) was described as a form of

knowledge that is acquired over an individual’s lifetime and their experiences. It was

argued that this conception of moral knowledge would be important when examining

our behaviour on social media, due to the fact that the most important aspect of our

moral knowledge was its limitations, and the dangers of presuming that the internet

grants us greater access to knowledge than it actually does.

163 Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human: A Book for Free Spirits, 294.

Page 67: Complete Copy

Page 67 of 80

The chapter then summarised virtue ethics in the twentieth century, beginning

with G.E.M Anscombe’s essay Modern Moral Philosophy¸ where she criticized the

‘law conception of ethics’ that had dominated moral philosophy since the eighteenth

century, particularly the work of Kant. As an alternative to this, Anscombe advocated

a return to such notions as ‘character’, ‘goodness’, and ‘flourishing’ when examining

morality. It was noted that there are many diverse applications of virtue ethics in

contemporary literature. One argument being the work of Alasdair MacIntyre and his

argument that social institutions were the best way to understand the virtues, another

interpretation was Rosalind Hursthouse’s ‘ethical naturalism’. The most important

theorist cited, however, was Swanton and her argument that virtues are ‘response

dependent’. Swanton herself had applied her conception of virtue ethics to Nietzsche’s

moral philosophy, arguing that Nietzsche is a virtue ethicist.

As previously noted, the greatest obstacle to interpreting Nietzsche as a virtue

ethicist is his egoism. This egoism is usually justified on two grounds, Nietzsche’s

attacks on altruism, or his advocacy for aristocracy. Nietzsche regarded altruism as

the injunction to denigrate one’s own capabilities and talents for the benefit of others.

Alternatively, he saw aristocracy as necessary aspect of any great society. In Beyond

Good and Evil, he wrote, “Every enhancement so far in the type "man" has been the

work of an aristocratic society”.

Page 68: Complete Copy

Page 68 of 80

Swanton responds to these difficulties by arguing that Nietzsche’s egoism can

be understood as a form of virtuous egoism. Swanton argues that this position is more

easily defended when one takes into account the fact that Nietzsche was not only a

critic of altruism, but was also a critic of ‘immature egoism’. Nietzsche writes that,

“Let us for the time being agree that benevolence and beneficence are constituents of

the good man; only let us add: ‘presupposing that he is first benevolently and

beneficently inclined towards himself!”164. Nietzsche goes on to specify that, “All that

remains is what it is one understands by one’s advantage; precisely the immature,

undeveloped, crude individual will understand it most crudely.”165 Nietzsche’s egoism

was clarified further by elaborating on what he did not mean to say. Nietzsche’s

egoism does not make any commentary on the attitude people must necessarily have

towards people. It also does not mean that people have an obligation to affirm or exalt

superior individuals above themselves. This would contradict Nietzsche’s belief that

the mature individual affirms their life through self-overcoming. This is not something

that is achieved through preoccupation with the lives of others. It also is not necessary

to regard one’s own life as being superior to other lives. This comparison implies a

standard where one’s worthiness is deemed in relation to other people. The final, most

important, and most fatal misconception regarding Nietzsche’s philosophy is that

“each person should put their own life first in their practical reasoning and actions.”166

164 Nietzsche, Daybreak: Thoughts on the Prejudices of Morality, 207. 165 Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human: A Book For Free Spirits, 51. 166 Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche, 151.

Page 69: Complete Copy

Page 69 of 80

The third chapter functioned as a counterargument to the thesis laid out in the

second chapter that Nietzsche’s egoism was a form of ‘virtuous egoism’. Instead, it

posited that Nietzsche’s moral philosophy entailed an antisocial egoism that rejected

the concerns of other people. The chapter began by noting the observations of many

philosophers and scholars that there was an uncomfortable relationship between

Nietzsche’s writings and the totalitarian regimes of the early twentieth century,

particularly National Socialism. This relationship was framed as a ‘family

resemblance’ between two systems of thought, the question then being examined

whether this relationship did in fact exist, and whether the similarities between the

two were greater or of more importance than the differences.

This began by focusing on the similarities between Nietzsche and Adolf Hitler.

Both of them were opponents of democracy, socialism, collectivism, and

parliamentary government. They also despised Christianity, while Nietzsche had

ambiguous feelings about Judaism and Jewish culture. However, further examination

revealed that the differences between Nietzsche and Hitler were greater than the

supposed similarities. Despite Nietzsche’s feelings, he became a fierce opponent and

critic of anti-Semitism, this was in a country with a long history of this prejudice. As

some scholars noted, Nietzsche’s opposition to anti-Semitism was abnormal in his

time. The conclusion of this examination was that although certain resemblances

between Nietzsche and totalitarianism existed, the differences were considerably

greater. However, this did not mean that this ‘family resemblance’ did not exist and

that its influence did not continue to promulgate itself into the present day.

Page 70: Complete Copy

Page 70 of 80

This conclusion brought the focus back to present day, to social media in

particular. It was argued that there existed similarities between Nietzsche’s thought

and much of the antisocial and egotistical behaviour that was observable on social

media today. As a case study of this behaviour, the online political movement known

as the ‘alt-right’ was cited. This group gained much of its notoriety by using internet

memes to function as a wall of anonymity, expressing hateful views without a

feedback mechanism that would normally deter such behaviour in the real world.

In chapters one and three I claimed that the harm performed on social media

is quantitative, not qualitative. It is not ‘qualitative’ due to the fact that much of the

abuse administered online is no different from any other comment that one might hear

on the street in a face to face confrontation. It is ‘quantitative’ due to the fact that the

absence of usual deterrents and constraints on such behaviour allows it to increase and

flourish, unchecked. This situation includes our ability to communicate to others

anonymously, to create fake personas or ‘selves’ online, and to direct abusive or

hateful rhetoric to others without the usual consequences of social censure. The point

to this thesis has been to identify the underlying vision behind this activity, and how

this vision responds to the different kinds of incentives and constraints that social

media creates. The similarity between the alt-right’s tactics and Nietzsche’s notion of

‘willing a self’ were then analysed. Noting that the anonymity provided by internet

memes and aliases allowed internet users, and the alt-right, to act out in ways that they

Page 71: Complete Copy

Page 71 of 80

would not normally be able to do in the real world. The ‘freedom’ that this platform

allowed for individuals culminated in their ability to create a self.

The fourth and penultimate chapter of the thesis provided a response to the

counterargument that focused on Nietzsche as an antisocial egoist. It then went on to

examine in greater detail how Nietzsche’s philosophy can be interpreted as an exercise

in virtue, and how this virtue theory could be applied to our behaviour on social media.

It began by focusing on Nietzsche’s reputation as anti-moral and as a precursor to

Nazism, however Nietzsche’s own writings were cited in order to demonstrate that

such interpretations do not withstand empirical analysis.

The chapter began by examining different interpretations of Nietzsche’s

notion of the ‘great man’. MacIntyre’s criticisms of Nietzsche were examined at first,

particularly the thesis that Nietzsche’s moral philosophy was the logical conclusion

of attempting to ground morality on the ‘individual’. MacIntyre argues that the fallacy

behind this exercise is due to the fact that morality is born out of the fact of human

relationships, not solely the individual. However, upon closer examination, it became

apparent that MacIntyre’s critique did not withstand scrutiny. Firstly, an examination

of Nietzsche’s relationship with his sister showed that Nietzsche did not ground his

advocacy for the ‘great man’, or ‘aristocracy’ on any form of genetic or ethnic

determinism. Instead, it was argued that Nietzsche urged for a process of excellence

to be applied to all individuals, and that the ideal individual that would emerge from

this process would be the ‘collective-individual’. After examining Nietzsche’s views

Page 72: Complete Copy

Page 72 of 80

on art, Christianity, and individualism, the conclusion was reached that Nietzsche’s

collective-individual was the person who “cultivated what is personal”.167

Nietzsche argued that each individual’s contribution to society, within a moral

framework, is to cultivate one’s own preferences and desires. This does not mean that

Nietzsche presumes that there will be a beneficial or equal outcome for each

individual, even for those with the same interests. However, it is the best framework

within which to allow for individuals to ‘flourish’, to use the Aristotelian term.

Nietzsche’s vision is not of a society of predestined individuals who are ranked at the

expense or benefit of others. Instead, it is a philosophy of moral behaviour where

different people with different values, ‘cultivate what is personal’, and in doing so

inadvertently contribute to the greatness of the society at large. The slavery that

Nietzsche speaks of is perhaps not be taken literally as economic slavery, his hostile

response to racism and anti-Semitism suggests that he did not see people as innately

slavish or successful. The slavery that Nietzsche is referring to here are the inevitable

failures that occur in life and lead to unequal outcomes among people.

The constraints and incentives created by social media were also examined in

this chapter, as well as the problems created by the fact that the internet was a format

structured categorically around individual freedom, at the expense of other factors

(social cohesion, being an example). It was argued that in order to reduce much of the

antisocial trends that were observable on social media, while still retaining the

167 Swanton, The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche, 116.

Page 73: Complete Copy

Page 73 of 80

individual’s freedom, it would be important for the internet’s users to restrain

themselves and to engage in self censure. It was argued that virtue ethics was the most

efficient means for facilitating this kind of behaviour, due to the fact that the individual

would understand their online presence as an extension of their ‘social selves’ and

thus would behave accordingly, without having to resort to third-party enforcement of

civility.

This different interpretation of Nietzsche’s writings allows us to re-examine

social media in a different light. On first observation, social media is simply a method

of communication, performed through the medium of the internet. However, it is also

a social process that transfers information. The sources of this information are diverse,

ranging from formal organizations that influence whole societies (i.e. political,

economic, the media, and the entertainment industry), to informal associations and

relationships that individuals voluntarily enter into (i.e. Facebook, Tinder). However,

the information that we receive through the internet is only half of the story. The

information we receive also facilitates decision making in response.

Although it is beyond the scope of this thesis to analyse fully, areas for future

research could focus on ways to facilitate the process of people realising their ‘social

selves’ in an online community. This process could take place in schools, in the

workplace, and on community message boards. Examples could be cited of how

particular website administrators are attempting to create certain constraints in which

the costs of antisocial behaviour online are paid for by its practitioners. There are also

Page 74: Complete Copy

Page 74 of 80

many other philosophers whose ideas could be used to analyse the ever changing

landscape of social media and the internet.

In conclusion, the freedom that the internet provides us is unlikely to produce

a net social benefit without consideration of our relationships to others, and

understanding our online presence as an extension of our ‘social selves’. Nietzsche’s

philosophy is useful in examining the moral dilemmas created by our lives moving

more and more online. This is due to the fact that his philosophy appears to attract

justifications for behaviour that is inexplicably antisocial and hostile, which could in

part be the reason for his continued fame amongst people who are not philosophers.

Revising our interpretations of Nietzsche and our understanding of his assumptions is

not simply an exercise in theoretics, it is also an attempt to alter the climate of opinion

that will lend credence to an alternative way of understanding our social selves and

our ethical obligations to others, even if they only exist to us on a screen.

Page 75: Complete Copy

Page 75 of 80

References

Anscombe, G.E.M. "Modern Moral Philosophy", Philosophy 33 (1958): 1-16.

Accessed August 5, 2016. http://www.pitt.edu/~mthompso/readings/mmp.pdf

ALS Association. ““The ALS Association Expresses Sincere Gratitude to Over

Three Million Donors”. Accessed September 4, 2016.

http://www.alsa.org/news/media/press-releases/ice-bucket-challenge-

082914.html?referrer=https://en.wikipedia.org/

Anti-Defamation League. “Pepe the Frog”. Accessed September 28, 2016.

http://www.adl.org/combating-hate/hate-on-display/c/pepe-the-

frog.html?referrer=https://en.wikipedia.org/#.WAWiJPl96Ul

Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by C.D.C. Reeve. Indianapolis:

Hackett Publishing, 2014.

Bowerman, Mary. “Pepe the Frog declared a hate symbol by Anti-Defamation

League”. USA Today. Accessed September 28, 2016.

http://www.usatoday.com/story/news/nation-now/2016/09/28/pepe-the-frog-

internet-meme-declared-hate-symbol-anti-defamation-league/91210140/

Bullock, Allan. Hitler: A Study in Tyranny. New York City: HarperCollins,

1991.

Burke, Timothy and Jack Dickey. "Manti Te'o's Dead Girlfriend, The Most

Heartbreaking And Inspirational Story Of The College Football Season, Is A

Hoax." Deadspin. Accessed May 29, 2016. http://deadspin.com/manti-teos-dead-

girlfriend-the-most-heartbreaking-an-5976517.

Camus, Albert. The Rebel: An Essay on Man in Revolt. Translated by Anthony

Bower. New York City: Knopf Doubleday, 2012.

Commonwealth Consolidated Acts. “Racial Discrimination Act 1975 – Section

18C”. Accessed September 2, 2016.

http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/legis/cth/consol_act/rda1975202/s18c.html

Constine, Josh. "Facebook Climbs to 1.59 Billion Users And Crushes Q4

Estimates With $5.8B Revenue." TechCrunch. Accessed May 29, 2016.

http://techcrunch.com/2016/01/27/facebook-earnings-q4-2015/.

Diethe, Carol. Nietzsche’s Sister and the Will to Power: A Biography of

Elisabeth Forster-Nietzsche. Champaign: University of Illinois Press, 2003.

Durant, Will. The Story of Philosophy. New York City: Simon & Schuster, 1965.

Page 76: Complete Copy

Page 76 of 80

Golomb, Jacob, and Robert S. Witrich. Nietzsche, Godfather of Fascism?: On

the Uses and Abuses of a Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press,

2009.

Hitler, Adolf. Mein Kampf. Translated by James Murphy. London: Hurst &

Blackett, 1939. Accessed August 15, 2016.

http://gutenberg.net.au/ebooks02/0200601.txt.

Hunt, Elle. “Milo Yiannopoulos, right-wing writer, permanently banned from

Twitter”. The Guardian. Accessed August 20, 2016.

https://www.theguardian.com/technology/2016/jul/20/milo-yiannopoulos-nero-

permanently-banned-twitter

Hursthouse, Rosalind. On Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.

Internet Live Stats. "Internet Users." Accessed May 29, 2016.

http://www.internetlivestats.com/internet-users/.

Kant, Immanuel. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Edited by Mary

Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

Kauffmann, Walter. Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist. Princeton:

Princeton University Press, 1974.

Krell, David Farrell. Nietzsche: A Novel. Albany: SUNY Press, 1996.

Legal Information Institute. “First Amendment”. Accessed September 2, 2016.

https://www.law.cornell.edu/constitution/first_amendment

Lenhart, Amanda. "Teens, Social Media & Technology Overview 2015." Pew

Research Centre. Accessed May 29, 2016,

http://www.pewinternet.org/2015/04/09/teens-social-media-technology-2015/.

MacIntyre, Alasdair. After Virtue. London: Bloomsbury, 2013.

MacIntyre, Alasdair. “The Virtues, the Unity of a Human Life and the Concept

of a Tradition.” In The Good Life. Edited by Charles Guignon. Indianapolis:

Hackett Publishing, 1999.

Mill, John Stuart. On Liberty and Other Writings. Edited by Stefan Collini.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989.

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the

Future. Edited by Rolf-Peter Horstmann and Judith Norman. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press, 2002.

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Human, All Too Human: A Book For Free Spirits.

Translated by R.J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996

Page 77: Complete Copy

Page 77 of 80

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Daybreak: Thoughts on the prejudices of morality. Edited

by Maudemaire Clark and Brian Leiter. Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press, 1997

Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, Twilight of the Idols: And

Other Writings. Edited by Aaron Ridley and Judith Norman. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press, 2005.

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Untimely Meditations Edited by Daniel Breazeale.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983.

Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Will to Power. Edited by Walter Kauffmann.

Translated by Walter Kauffmann and R.J. Hollingdale. Vintage: New York City,

1968.

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Writings from the Late Notebooks. Edited by Rudiger

Bittner. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003.

Nietzsche, F. On the Genealogy of Morality. Edited by Keith Ansell-Pearson.

Translated by Carol Diethe. Camrbridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006.

NPR. “What You Need To Know About The Alt-Right Movement.” Accessed

September 15, 2016. http://www.npr.org/2016/08/26/491452721/the-history-of-

the-alt-right

Ohlheiser, Abby. "Anti-Semitic Trump Supporters Made a Giant List of People

to Target with a Racist Meme". The Washington Post. Accessed August 18,

2016. https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/the-intersect/wp/2016/06/03/anti-

semitic-trump-supporters-made-a-giant-list-of-people-to-target-with-a-racist-

meme/

Reed, T.J. Thomas Mann: The Uses of Tradition. Oxford: Clarendon Press,

1996.

Rodden, John. Repainting the Little Red Schoolhouse: A History of Eastern

German Education, 1945-1995. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.

Rosen, Larry D. "Social Networking’s Good and Bad Impacts On Kids."

American Psychological Association. Accessed August 1, 2016.

http://www.apa.org/news/press/releases/2011/08/social-kids.aspx.

Rupert, Brittany. “Martin Place siege: #illridewithyou hashtag goes viral”.

Sydney Morning Herald. Accessed September 4, 2016.

http://www.smh.com.au/nsw/martin-place-siege-illridewithyou-hashtag-goes-

viral-20141215-127rm1.html

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Existentialism and Humanism. London: Eyre Methuen, 1973.

Page 78: Complete Copy

Page 78 of 80

Schulman, Yaniv. Catfish. DVD. Directed by Henry Joost & Ariel Schulman.

N New York City: Supermache, 2010.

Socialbakers.com. "All YouTube Statistics in One Place." Accessed May 29,

2016. http://www.socialbakers.com/statistics/youtube/.

Solomon, Robert C., and Kathleen M. Higgins. What Nietzsche Really Said. New

York City: Knopf Doubleday, 2012.

Solomon, Robert C. Living with Nietzsche: What the Great ‘Immoralist’ Has To

Teach Us. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003

Stackelberg, Roderick, and Sally A. Winkle, ed. The Nazi Germany Sourcebook:

An Anthology of Texts. Abingdon-on-Thames: Routledge, 2013.

Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. "Authenticity." Accessed August 2,

2012016. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/authenticity/.

Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. “Existentialism.” Accessed August 2,

2016. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/existentialism/.

Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. “Friedrich Nietzsche”. Accessed August

4, 2016. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nietzsche/

Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. “Virtue Ethics,” Accessed August 4,

2016. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/ethics-virtue/.

Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. “Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret

Anscombe”. Accessed August 5, 2016.

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/anscombe/

Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. “Deontological Ethics”. Accessed

August 5, 2016. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-deontological/

Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. “Consequentialism”. Accessed August 5,

2016. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism/

Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. “John Stuart Mill”. Accessed September

2, 2016. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill/

Stohr, Karen. "Contemporary Virtue Ethics", Philosophy Compass 1 (2006): 22-

27. Accessed August 5, 2016. doi:10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00004.x.

Strong Tracy B. Friedrich Nietzsche and the Politics of Transfiguration.

Oakland: University of California Press, 1988.

Swanton, Christine. The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche. Hoboken: Wiley

& Sons, 2015. Accessed August 3, 2016.

http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/book/10.1002/9781118939369.

Page 79: Complete Copy

Page 79 of 80

Swanton, Christine. Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View. Oxford: Oxford

University Press, 2005.

Swanton, Christine. “Nietzsche and the ‘Collective-Individual’”. In Individual

and Community in Nietzsche’s Philosophy, edited by Julian Young, 174-195.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014.

Turkle, Sherry. Alone Together: Why We Expect More from Technology and

Less from Each Other. New York: Basic Books, 2011.

Twitter. “About.” Accessed May 29, 2016, from

https://about.twitter.com/company

Welton, Benjamin. "What, Exactly, Is the 'Alternative Right?" The Weekly

Standard. Accessed August 18, 2016. http://www.weeklystandard.com/what-

exactly-is-the-alternative-right/article/2000310

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations. Hoboken: John Wiley & on

Sons, 2010.

Wolin, Richard. The Seduction of Unreason: The Intellectual Romance with

Fascism: From Nietzsche to Postmodernism. Princeton: Princeton University

Press, 2004.

Young, Cathy. "Donald Trump’s Hate for Political Correctness Is Comfort Food

to Racists". Newsday. Accessed August 18, 2016.

http://www.newsday.com/opinion/columnists/cathy-young/donald-trump-s-rant-

against-political-correctness-is-comfort-food-to-racists-1.11391400.

Page 80: Complete Copy

Page 80 of 80

Glossary

Facebook: An online social networking service.

YouTube: A video sharing website.

Twitter: An online social networking service that enables users to send and

read short 140-character messages called ‘tweets’.

Tinder: A location-based social search service application (using Facebook)

that facilitates communication between mutually interested users, allowing

matched users to chat. The app is commonly used as a dating service.

4chan: An English-language image board website. Users generally post

anonymously, with the most recent posts appearing above the rest. 4chan is

split into various boards with their own specific content and guidelines.

8chan: Also called Infinitechan, is an English-language image board website

composed of user-created boards. Each board is moderated by its respective

creator, with minimal interaction from other site administration.

Reddit: A social news aggregation, web content rating, and discussion

website. Reddit's registered community members can submit content, such as

text posts or direct links.

Instagram: An online mobile photo-sharing, video-sharing, and social

networking service that enables its users to take pictures and videos, and

share them either publicly or privately.