craig marketing

Upload: juancarlosgarcia

Post on 08-Jul-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    1/33

    ETHICAL GUIDELINES FOR MARKETING PRACTICE:

    A REPLY TO GASKI & SOME OBSERVATIONS ON THE ROLE OF

    NORMATIVE MARKETING ETHICS

    N. Craig Smith

    Centre for Marketing Working Paper

    No. 00-701

    March 2000

     Acknowledgement: The author thanks George G. Brenkert for helpful comments on anearlier version of this article.

    London Business School, Regent's Park, London NW1 4SA, U.K.Tel: +44 (0)20 7262-5050 Fax: +44 (0)20 7724-1145

    http://www.london.edu/Marketing

      Copyright    London Business School 2000

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    2/33

    2

    ETHICAL GUIDELINES FOR MARKETING PRACTICE:

    A REPLY TO GASKI & SOME OBSERVATIONS ON THE ROLE OF

    NORMATIVE MARKETING ETHICS

    Abstract

    Gaski (1999) is critical of marketing ethics and suggests that its ethical guidelines amount to

    no more than ‘obey the law’ and ‘act in your self-interest’. This reply questions Gaski’s critique

    and clarifies possible misconceptions about the field that might otherwise result. It identifies the

    limitations and assumptions of Gaski’s argument and shows that there are exceptions to his central

    proposition even when narrowly circumscribed. It is not disputed that there is merit to reminding

    managers of their obligations to obey the law and to act in their enlightened self-interest. However,

    although fulfilling these obligations is generally a necessary requirement for good conduct, it is not

    sufficient. There are situations where ethics demands more of marketing managers than ‘obey the

    law’ and ‘act in your self-interest’. In addition, managers may face situations where ethics, the law

    and self-interest are inconsistent. The article incorporates observations on the role of normative

    marketing ethics, including the requirement to develop ethical theory for marketing as well as

    ethical guidelines.

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    3/33

    1

    John Gaski has doubts about the contribution of the field of marketing ethics. In “Does

    Marketing Ethics Really Have Anything to Say?” Gaski (1999, p. 330) refers to the “total

    redundancy and superfluity of marketing ethics,” asserting: “What are almost universally

    positioned as ethical issues in marketing are, in reality, nothing more than legal or economic

    issues” (p. 330). He suggests that marketing ethics should “concede that it has nothing to say

    beyond ‘obey the law’ and ‘act in your own commercial interest’” (p. 328). Gaski goes so far as

    to suggest that “the subject of marketing ethics appears to be completely undistinguished,

    feckless, jejune, and vacant operationally, offering not an iota of content distinct from other

    established normative concepts” (pp. 328-330).

    It is tempting to simply dismiss Gaski’s claims as bizarre or in jest. How could

    marketing ethics possibly be ‘totally redundant’? But this would be too hasty. Gaski appears to

    be serious in his critique (and reviewers and editors at the Journal of Business Ethics have

    treated his essay as such). While Gaski’s argument is readily exposed as seriously flawed, it still

    warrants a reply if only because of the credence given by its publication. Accordingly, a

    primary purpose of this article is to provide a reply to Gaski that examines his argument and

    addresses possible misconceptions that his essay might create. Gaski’s argument is somewhat

    more narrowly circumscribed than his provocative title and the foregoing quotations might

    suggest.i  Nonetheless, after careful dissection, it is rejected and his criticisms of marketing

    ethics refuted.

    However, this article has a broader purpose beyond offering a reply to Gaski. It is not

    unusual to come across students and managers who, naively perhaps, claim that ethical issues in

    marketing may be resolved easily by reference to the law or self-interest. Gaski’s article

    prompts an examination of such claims. Furthermore, it provides an opportunity to offer some

    observations on the role and challenges of normative marketing ethics. This discussion

    acknowledges the importance of basic ethical prescriptions—including obey the law and

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    4/33

    2

    consider your enlightened self-interest—but also shows that marketing ethics has a more

    extensive domain. Finally, Gaski’s article is a useful basis for reflections on the contribution of 

    marketing ethics to marketing practice.

    In the next section, Gaski’s claims and their foundation are examined in more detail.

    The circularity of his reasoning with regard to the asserted redundancy of marketing ethics

    prescriptions is exposed. More important, however, is clarification of the explicit and implicit

    limitations of his critique of marketing ethics and the argument regarding obey the law and

    follow your self-interest as maxims for ethical marketing practice. Next, this article examines

    the law and self-interest as guides to good conduct and concludes that they are not sufficient.

    This is evident from ethical prescriptions within the extant literature and from identifying

    situations where marketing managers are expected to do more or do something different than the

    law or self-interest would appear to dictate. Finally, the article concludes with observations on

    the contributions of marketing ethics to date and opportunities for further work to advance this

    important area of research and practice.

    GASKI’S CRITIQUE & THE SCOPE OF MARKETING ETHICS

    Gaski (1999, abstract) asserts that “in terms of pragmatic behavioral guidance as well as

    conceptual content, marketing ethics has nothing new or distinctive to offer.” His apparent

    starting point was a suspicion that “all or most so-called ethical guidelines for marketers are

    mere restatements of other established normative principles such as law and economic self-

    interest” (p. 316). Hence his central proposition is as follows:

    all the standard ethical prescriptions in the field of marketing can be reducedconceptually to either (a) obey the law or (b) act in your own self-interest, i.e., do what isright because if you do not, it will be damaging to your interests in the long run (p. 316).

    To test this proposition, Gaski identifies an inventory of ethical prescriptions from the

    marketing ethics literature and then attempts to show that they are redundant with his law and/or

    self-interest prescription. There are a number of limitations that Gaski explicitly or implicitly

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    5/33

    3

    imposes on this proposition. Nonetheless, by implication, were it to be supported, a marketing

    manager faced with a decision that has ethical content need not give any thought to ethical

    prescriptions in the literature, but rather can rely on obeying the law and acting in his or her

    long-run commercial self-interest.

    Gaski’s review identified seventeen ethical prescriptions and concluded that all 17

    amount to “no more than advice to abide by existing principles of law and self-interest” (p. 324).

    More specifically, 4 prescriptions are said to be consistent with both principles: do not market

    harmful or dangerous products, deceive the customer, coerce other members of the distribution

    channel, or disparage competitors. Three prescriptions are said to be consistent with act in your

    self-interest only: customer is entitled to receive fair value for the money spent, provide easily

    accessible channels for customer complaints, and do not over-recommend product quality level

    to the customer. Finally, 10 prescriptions are said to be consistent with obey the law only;

    including: do not engage in price fixing, predatory pricing, or bribery.

    Of course, consistency of an ethical principle with the law or self-interest does not mean

    that its content is limited only to what the law or self-interest would dictate. From a Kantian

    perspective, one could agree that “do not kill” is consistent with existing law and self-interest

    and yet think that this prescription is not reducible or equivalent to obey the law and/or act in

    your self-interest. However, Gaski’s interest lies specifically in whether the marketing ethics

    literature offers guidelines for marketing management practice that cannot adequately be

    substituted by the prescriptions of obey the law or act in your self-interest (Gaski 1999, p. 317).

    In this reply, the emphasis will be on this narrower interpretation of Gaski’s central proposition,

    ignoring the broader claim that the content of marketing ethics is reducible to or equivalent to

    obey the law and act in your self-interest.

    Although verbal logic alone should be sufficient for Gaski’s purposes, he also offers

    empirical corroboration in the form of surveys of a business school faculty and of marketing

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    6/33

    4

    practitioner members of the American Marketing Association. His respondents generally

    agreed with his classification of the ethics principles as consistent with obey the law and/or act

    in your self-interest, but the study has methodological problems.ii

    Yet by logic alone we can swiftly dismiss Gaski’s claims as stated. He sets up a ‘straw

    man’ argument that is readily apparent to any careful reader. Let us accept, for the moment, the

    premises on which his argument is based and its many explicit and implicit limitations and

    assumptions, as later discussed. On his terms, then, Gaski’s central proposition is easily

    exposed as fallacious. Even without the limitations that Gaski himself imposes, it seems

    inconceivable that he could have found support for his null hypothesis. Any possible ethical

    prescription for marketing (or business in general) would be consistent with act in your self-

    interest if, as Gaski appears to believe (pp. 324-325), ‘good ethics is good business’. As he

    states: “As long as there is an expectation of economic loss from bad behavior, that should be a

    deterrent…” (p. 318). He is not interested in whether, in fact, there is much likelihood of this

    expectation being realised or whether managers can identify their self-interest (as later

    discussed). If we allow for the prospect of boycotts, negative publicity and other harms to a

    firm’s reputation and brand image, as well as possible litigation, as Gaski suggests (pp. 317-

    318), any unethical conduct can be viewed as potentially subject to sanction in the marketplace

    and elsewhere. Hence, Gaski may claim that any unethical activity could result in economic loss

    and, thus, is not in the firm’s interest. If an activity is not in a firm’s interest, Gaski would

    argue, any ethical prescription governing that activity is redundant.

    There are other examples of this type of circular reasoning. For example, Gaski excludes

    any ethical prescriptions that do not address activities widely considered unethical. More than

    this, he establishes consensus by recourse to the law. So, he writes (p. 331, his emphasis): “To

    the extent that bribery is not prohibited… there is apparent lack of consensus that it is wrong or

    unethical.” There are a number of instances of Gaski mistaking ‘is’ for ‘ought’ (e.g., ethics of 

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    7/33

    5

    tobacco marketing) that are later discussed. For now, let us consider the argument made that the

    legality of an act is indicative of whether it is ethical and note again that, thus, Gaski would

    argue, any ethical prescription governing that activity becomes redundant. Indeed, he admits the

    tautology, acknowledging that “if legality indicates a necessary consensus that the behavior in

    question is also ethical, then, analytically, there is no empirical opportunity to identify

    exceptions to the legal/ethical consistency” (p. 326, his emphasis).

    Consider yet one more example of flawed logic. Gaski accepts the foundational role of 

    ethics in formulating the law and, however misguided, believes that we are “at a juncture,

    possibly rare, in which law and prevailing ethics are in close alignment” (p. 326). He then

    suggests (p. 330, his emphasis) that “normal commerce under democratic law reconciles so

    closely with accepted ethics as to render contemporary marketing ethics, per se, practically

    unnecessary.” Yet, by his own argument, ethics must play an important role in ensuring the

    continuity of this claimed alignment.

    There might well be little reason for a reply to Gaski to go much further. However, it is

    both fair and useful to play out the various stated and implicit limitations to his proposition and

    this will be done. Moreover, this paper has a more extensive purpose than replying to Gaski.

    While Gaski’s central proposition has little merit, it is not unusual to hear managers and students

    argue that obedience to the law and self-interest are key to analyzing many purported ethical

    issues in marketing. Hence, this paper considers the relevance of these maxims and shows why

    they are inadequate, notwithstanding limitations of the type that Gaski attempts to employ. In so

    doing, the paper also examines the role of ethical prescriptions in marketing and, more broadly,

    the contributions of the field of marketing ethics to marketing practice.

     Acknowledged Limitations of Gaski’s Critique and Central Proposition

    Gaski’s central proposition and his critique of marketing ethics are bounded, as he

    directly or indirectly acknowledges, in the following ways.

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    8/33

    6

    1. The distinction between normative and descriptive marketing ethics.   The field of 

    marketing ethics is a subset of business ethics, which in turn is a subset of ethics. At each level,

    there are contributions that might broadly be classified as normative ethics, descriptive ethics, or

    metaethics. Smith (1995, p. 86) observes that a “key distinction in the literature is between

    descriptive and normative approaches to marketing ethics… Normative approaches to ethics are

    prescriptive, identifying moral principles and methods of moral reasoning that justify rules and

     judgements of what is right and wrong.” Gaski (1999, p. 316) defines marketing ethics as

    “standards of conduct and moral judgment applied to marketing practice.” Although it could be

    more comprehensive, this is a reasonable definition of normative marketing ethics.

    The majority of contributions to marketing ethics fall within the category of descriptive

    (or positive) ethics (evident, for example, in the review by Tsalikis and Fritzsche 1989). These

    contributions might use empirical research to identify ethical beliefs of marketers (e.g., Akaah

    and Riordan 1989), or develop a model to describe how marketers are believed to make

    decisions with ethical content (e.g., Hunt and Vitell 1993) and offer and perhaps test

    explanations for these judgements (e.g., Sparks and Hunt 1998). Generally, they do not attempt

    to prescribe how managers should act when faced with a marketing decision that has ethical

    content.

    Towards the end of his article, Gaski (1999, p. 326) acknowledges his “utmost respect

    for the scientific contributions of the positive ethics subfield of marketing” (his emphasis).

    Also, he admits, in a footnote to his (later) operational definition that “strictly, normative

    marketing ethics is defined, as distinguished from the positive science of marketing ethics” (his

    emphasis, p. 330). Unfortunately, this important clarification is not evident from the article’s

    title or abstract and many of its more sweeping criticisms of the field.

    As important, Gaski fails to acknowledge that positive marketing ethics does offer

    ‘pragmatic behavioral guidance’ for marketing managers. Positive marketing ethics does not

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    9/33

    7

    speak to the ethics of particular practices, such as whether bribery is morally justifiable.

    However, it can, for example, speak to the conditions under which bribery might arise and

    measures that individuals and organizations might take to reduce its likelihood. This is evident

    from the most cursory review of Chonko’s (1995, p. x) Ethical Decision Making in Marketing

    and his examination of “how marketing professionals make decisions and the factors and

    conflicts involved in those decisions.” By way of illustration, consider the research by one

    major contributor to this area, O.C. Ferrell (and his colleagues).

    Ferrell and Gresham’s (1985) model of ethical decision making identifies the potential

    influence of significant others, opportunity, social and cultural factors, and the individual’s

    makeup. It suggests, for example, that decisions about what type of behavior is appropriate in any

    given situation are influenced by the opportunity for the individual to engage in ethical or unethical

    behavior, where opportunity is a function of organizational culture, professional codes, corporate

    policy and rewards and punishments. Ferrell and Weaver (1978) show that individuals differ in

    their assessment of the extent to which a marketing decision has ethical content, while Weaver

    and Ferrell (1977) highlight the influence of top management on ethical decision making in

    organizations. Hence, all three of these papers provide guidance to marketing managers on

    ethical issues in marketing and yet are included in the review by Tsalikis and Fritzsche (1989)

    that was used by Gaski to develop his marketing ethics bibliography.

    2. Normative marketing ethics as applied to marketing managers in their strictly

    marketing decision making.  Gaski limits his analysis to prescriptions intended to provide

    guidance to marketing managers only. He states that it is “guidelines for marketing management

    practice that are at issue” (his emphasis, p. 317), but it is the value of this guidance specifically

    to marketing managers that is discussed (e.g., p. 328). The field of normative marketing ethics

    has roles other than informing practice. However, in this capacity alone, it may provide

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    10/33

    8

    guidance to other decision-makers in a corporation, to those affected by their decisions, to policy

    makers and to researchers, as well as to marketing managers.

    Moreover, Gaski excludes the “disjunct, stand-alone body of literature on marketing

    research ethics” (his emphasis, p. 317). Hence, guidelines for marketing researchers and,

    indeed, guidelines for marketing managers about marketing research are ignored. Yet this area

    of marketing activity has received the most attention in the marketing ethics literature and, for

    various reasons, has the most ethical prescriptions (Laczniak and Murphy 1993; Malhotra 1996;

    Smith and Quelch 1993). Most of the professional marketing research associations have quite

    extensive codes of conduct that are now available on the Web (e.g., www.aapor.org;

    www.casro.org; www.esomar.nl). A cursory review of these codes readily reveals that they

    contain prescriptions that reflect law and self-interest. However, they also include prescriptions

    that reflect essentially ethical obligations, for example, to respondents. Indeed, one reason these

    professional associations are keen to promote their codes is because the researcher’s self-interest

    is an inadequate constraint on unethical practices involving respondents that might harm the

    industry as a whole or result in legislation that the industry would prefer to avoid (e.g., regarding

    data privacy).

    Gaski also excludes marketing managers’ decisions about “the ethics of 

    intraorganizational behavior (e.g., accurate representation of education, confidentiality, etc.)”

    (his emphasis, footnote on p. 331) and ethical guidelines on these decisions in the AMA code

    and elsewhere. This exclusion is notwithstanding the significance of these issues to marketing

    managers themselves, as confirmed in survey research by Chonko and Hunt (1985).

    Apparently, Gaski also largely limits his proposition to U.S. marketing managers that are

    engaged in domestic marketing, notwithstanding the ever-increasing globalisation of business,

    including U.S. business. This is not explicitly stated, but he does refer only to specific U.S. laws

    as a basis for claiming the redundancy of ethical prescriptions. His rejection of “ethical

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    11/33

    9

    imperialism by imposing domestic ethics abroad” (p. 317) presumably also excludes the

    application of guidelines evident in U.S. laws to marketing practices overseas. In a footnote,

    Gaski observes that “most examples, and surrounding discussion relate to the context of U.S.

    law and, therefore, would apply similarly to other market economies with similar commercial

    and legal environments” (p. 331). However, in another footnote, Gaski further explains that

    “detailed examination of the ethics-law/self-interest relation for every individual nation would

    require as many different papers as there are countries” (p. 331). There may be less divergence

    than Gaski imagines. Nonetheless, this is acknowledgement of another important limitation to

    his proposition.

    3. Ethical prescriptions for marketing practice evident in the extant (largely pre-1990)

    marketing ethics literature. Gaski makes it unambiguous that his paper “deals with what is

    actually found in the marketing literature… not hypothetical findings or literatures” (p. 327) and

    only “definite, explicit prescriptions” (p. 317) within that literature. Clearly, testing his

    proposition against a hypothetical literature or set of ethical propositions would be difficult,

    even if it were worth attempting. However, there are inevitably limitations associated with the

    content and extensiveness of the literature reviewed and the prescriptions derived.

    The literature relied upon, for the most part, is dated. The primary sources were

    literature reviews conducted at least ten years ago (Murphy and Laczniak 1981; Murphy and

    Pridgen 1991; Tsalikis and Fritzsche 1989). Although supplemented by an additional review by

    Gaski, there is only one cite in the list of references later than 1993 and only 10 cites of a total of 

    70 published in the 1990s. This lack of attention to the more recent marketing ethics literature

    may in part explain Gaski’s failure to recognize the contributions of positive marketing ethics to

    ethical decision-making, many of which have appeared in the last decade. Nonetheless—and

    regardless of any weaknesses of the extant literature—Gaski (p. 330) also implies doubts about

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    12/33

    10

    the prospective normative marketing ethics literature, suggesting that the law “reconciles so

    closely” with contemporary marketing ethics that the latter is unnecessary.

    In addition to the above limitations, Gaski also identifies some specific exceptions on the

    basis that they do not constitute definite and explicit prescriptions or because of a perceived

    absence of consensus about the prescription or because they are a special case (e.g., deception in

    political promotion). Also, judging from his comments about special cases, it should be noted

    that Gaski appears to believe that ethics is a matter of public opinion. For example, he states

    that “the general public does not consider deception of a political audience to be unethical

    marketing” (p. 319). He also appears to conclude that tobacco marketing is ethical on the basis

    of majority opinion expressed through representative democracy (and not withstanding special

    interests that for many years have prevented effective legislation curtailing tobacco marketing in

    the U.S.).

    Finally, Gaski is not interested in motives for good conduct: “Ethics may offer an

    additional underlying motive for a particular behavior (beyond law or self-interest), but covers

    the same material ground” (p. 320). Moreover, in a footnote, he observes that the “issue is not

    one of enforcement or successful prosecution… obedience to law and self-interest should

    promote behavior indistinguishably different from self-consciously ethical behavior” (p. 331).

    However, obedience to the law may be colored by beliefs about whether others obey the law and

    the possibility of being caught, which raises one of a number of possible effectiveness

    limitations (discussed further below), even if motives for good conduct are treated as

    unimportant.

     Further Limitations of Gaski’s Critique and Central Proposition

    It is not suggested that Gaski’s proposition is unreasonably circumscribed. Indeed, it

    would be completely untenable without some of the above limitations. However, the following

    largely unacknowledged limitations and assumptions also bound Gaski’s critique and central

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    13/33

    11

    proposition. They suggest compelling grounds for rejection of the idea that it would be

    sufficient for a marketing manager faced with a decision that has ethical content to rely on

    obeying the law and acting in his or her long-run commercial self-interest, without regard to

    marketing ethics.

    1. Moral judgement and ethical prescriptions.  Normative marketing ethics is far more

    than ethical prescriptions. Moral reasoning may identify ethical prescriptions but this is only

    one role of the normative marketing ethics field among a number. For example, consistent with

    Gaski’s definition of marketing ethics, moral judgement may be applied to marketing practice

    using theories of moral philosophy. Indeed, many of the more complex issues of marketing

    ethics cannot adequately be addressed by recourse to simple ethical prescriptions and require

    these theories. Nonetheless, Gaski ignores prescriptions that might be developed through moral

     judgement and the use of ethical theory that is widely discussed in the marketing ethics literature

    (e.g., Duke et al. 1993; Ferrell, Gresham and Fraedrich 1989; Fritzsche 1985; Laczniak 1983;

    Laczniak and Murphy 1993; Robin and Reidenbach 1986; Smith 1995; Smith and Quelch 1993;

    Thompson 1995; Williams and Murphy 1990).

    A key assumption, apparently, is that it is the principal role of normative marketing

    ethics to develop prescriptions for marketing managers and that, indeed, this is possible to any

    great extent and sufficient for marketing decision-making. Consider an ethical dilemma that

    might present a manager with a choice between two alternative courses of action, both of which

    would be consistent with the law and self-interest, but one alternative might be more ethical than

    the other. However, this determination may not be the outcome of some formulaic application

    of simple and extant ethical prescriptions, it is possible that it could only be reached through

    moral judgement.

    Ethical prescriptions are a small part of the nature and scope of marketing ethics overall.

    A positive marketing ethicist might well argue that developing understanding of organizational

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    14/33

    12

    ethical decision-making from a behavioral and social viewpoint is as important as trying to

    determine normative prescriptions.

    2. Self-Interest and Duties.  Although Gaski may be able to point to moral duties evident

    in the law, he can not so easily make this claim with respect to self-interest. Appeals to self-

    interest are inevitably consequentialist. To suggest a marketing manager should not engage in

    an act, such as not providing fair value for money spent, because it is contrary to his or her

    economic self-interest, is an argument relying upon the adverse consequences of this behavior.

    It ignores the deontological position that there may be duties independent of consequences.

    From a deontological perspective, it could be claimed that a marketing manager has the moral

    obligation of concern for the welfare of customers and others affected by his or her decisions.

    Meeting this obligation may or may not be in the marketer’s self-interest. Regardless, there is a

    moral duty to be fulfilled.

    3. Where the law ends: assumptions made about the scope of the law. If the law is to

    serve as a substitute for ethics, there must be assumptions made about its adequacy. Generally,

    the law provides minimal standards, often prescribing negative injunctions, specifying what

    should not be done that might otherwise lead to harm to others, rather than positive mandates

    about what and how much should be done to improve human welfare. There are limits to what

    the law can, has yet to, and should prescribe (Stone 1975). In most areas of public and private

    life we expect individuals to go beyond the dictates of the law.

    Gaski argues that many of the ethical prescriptions he identified are redundant with

    specific U.S. laws. However, marketing managers are notoriously ill-informed about the law, in

    part, as Petty (1999) notes, because of the relative scarcity of marketing law courses. Moreover,

    in terms of parsimony, communicating its prescriptions may be a lengthier task than providing

    simple ethical prescriptions that do not require legal details. The spirit of the law is often easier

    to communicate than the letter of the law.

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    15/33

    13

    Gaski largely avoids discussion about the effectiveness of managerial reliance on his

    obey the law and/or act in your self-interest prescription. (Although at one point he does refer to

    marketing managers making “more correct and efficient” decisions [p. 328].) However, if the

    law is to serve as a substitute for ethical prescriptions, we might question its potential

    effectiveness in promoting good conduct and doubt the supposed parsimony that Gaski claims.

    This may also hold if reliance is placed on self-interest.

    4. Limits to the imperative of customer satisfaction: assumptions made about an

    alignment of the marketer’s self-interest with customer interests. Gaski also makes certain

    assumptions about marketing in practice and ignores or understates the possibility of what

    economists refer to as “market failures” and “externalities”. In particular, he relies on the

    imperative of customer satisfaction, which may only hold under certain conditions, particularly

    competitive markets. So, for example, in relation to customer entitlement to receive fair value

    for money spent, Gaski observes that “it is in the marketer’s self-interest to provide value

    proportional to price… customer satisfaction, which grows out of a satisfactory value/price ratio,

    is almost universally necessary for marketer success” (p. 319). Many markets today are very

    competitive, but this is not true of all markets. Monopolistic industries or quasi-monopolistic

    positions in certain markets are more common, say, in Europe or Latin America but are not so

    rare in the U.S., particularly in the more specialised areas of business-to-business marketing.

    There is also an assumption of firms attempting to maximize customer satisfaction. We

    may agree that “intentionally dissatisfying customers is incompatible with the definition of 

    marketing” (p. 319), but intentionally dissatisfying is not the same as less completely satisfying.

    Firms are always trading-off potential profit and customer value as a function of competitive

    conditions and other factors.

    Moreover, Gaski specifically excludes situations where the marketer is not interested in

    repeat purchase or where there are difficulties for potential customers to learn from dissatisfied

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    16/33

    14

    customers. These situations also may not be so rare (e.g., a company exiting a business may

    exploit short-term opportunities) and limit self-interest as a constraint on unethical conduct. He

    also acknowledges that “marketing managers can make mistakes” (p. 328). Again, an

    assumption that this situation is also relatively rare may not be warranted, as illustrated by the

    mistakes about customer preferences of even the best-managed companies (e.g., New Coke).

    5. Stakeholders other than customers: assumptions made about an alignment of interests

    among stakeholders.  Another set of problems arises from the possibility of a poor alignment of 

    interests. Customer satisfaction is no guarantee of good conduct where there are adverse

    consequences for others (“stakeholders”) who are not party to the exchange (e.g., environmental

    impacts of products and packaging). Acting in your economic self-interest is less effective as a

    guideline when effects on stakeholders other than customers are considered. Further, individual

    marketing manager self-interest and company self-interest may not be consistent, so a marketing

    manager may make decisions that are counter to the requirement for customer satisfaction but

    are in his or her own best interest (a perennial problem with brand managers).

     Assessment of Gaski’s Proposition and Critique

    Identifying the above limitations clarifies the extent to which Gaski’s proposition may be

    appropriately applied and the validity of his critique of marketing ethics overall. In short, after

    careful dissection, we must reject his proposition that the standard ethical prescriptions in the

    field of marketing can be replaced by ‘obey the law’ and ‘act in your own self-interest’ as advice

    to marketing managers. Aside from Gaski’s circular reasoning and acknowledged limitations,

    we would need to make unwarranted assumptions about the scope of the law and an alignment

    of manager self-interest with the customers and other stakeholders’ interests. We would also

    need to assume that managers never face ethical dilemmas calling for moral judgement and

    ignore their moral duties that exist independent of possible consequences. Accordingly, many of 

    Gaski’s inferences about the field and related criticisms also seem unwarranted.

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    17/33

    15

    It is not disputed that many of the standard ethical prescriptions in the field of marketing

    have substantial overlap with the law and enlightened self-interest and that the guidelines ‘obey

    the law’ and ‘act in your own self-interest’ have some merit as advice to marketing managers.

    Hence, Gaski’s proposition should not be entirely dismissed to the extent that it recognizes a

    role for law and enlightened self-interest. The law and self-interest as guides to good conduct

    are discussed further in the next section.

    THE LAW AND SELF-INTEREST AS GUIDES TO GOOD CONDUCT

     Ethics, the Law and Self-Interest Often Do Coincide

    Marketing managers often are well advised to obey the law and act in their own long-

    term commercial self-interest; indeed, they are more likely to engage in good conduct if they

    heed this advice. Marketing would be less frequently associated with unethical practices if these

    guidelines were more commonly considered. In other words, ethics, the law and economic self-

    interest often do coincide.

    The general consistency of the law with ethics should not be surprising, as Gundlach and

    Murphy (1993, p. 39) observe: “much of the law addressing exchange is drawn from and

    formalizes moral principles.” Indeed, Gaski writes that “ethics may frequently pre-exist and

    ground law” (p. 331). Given this role of ethics in forming a basis for the law, it seems

    remarkable that Gaski should so summarily dismiss it.

    That ethics may be consistent with self-interest is also not too surprising a claim. This

    consistency is also well established and may be seen to pre-date the field of business ethics. The

    first business ethics texts appeared in the late 1970s. Prior to business ethics courses, most

    discussion in business schools of the moral problems of business was in business and society

    courses. In vogue between the late 1960s and early 1980s, in both these courses and in business

    itself, was the concept of corporate social responsibility.

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    18/33

    16

    Concern about the moral problems of business is as old as business itself: Adam Smith's

    The Wealth of Nations is a moral, as well as economic, treatise; Roman philosopher Cicero's De

    Officiis discusses the moral duties of merchants. Not surprisingly, then, the notion that business

    has social responsibilities was familiar to business leaders of the early 20 th century, if not earlier.

    Frederick (1994, p. 151) writes:

    By the mid-1920s, business representatives and executives were beginning to speak of theneed for corporate directors to act as trustees for the interests, not just of stockholders, butother social claimants as well… Corporate philanthropy, the history of which stretchedback into the 19th century, was accompanied by a growing belief that business andsociety were linked together in organic, if not yet well understood, ways.

    What differentiates the modern-day concept of corporate social responsibility from

    earlier notions of social responsibility in business, is the recognition that business has an

    obligation to society that goes beyond obedience to the law and the production and distribution

    of goods and services at a profit. Further, it amounts to more than acts of philanthropy. This

    distinction is evident from the summary of the central ideas of the CSR concept by Buchholz

    (1991, p. 19):

    While various definitions of social responsibility have been advocated, there seem to befive key elements in most, if not all, of these definitions: 1) corporations haveresponsibilities that go beyond the production of goods and services at a profit; 2) theseresponsibilities involve helping to solve important social problems, especially those theyhave helped create; 3) corporations have a broader constituency than stockholders alone;4) corporations have impacts that go beyond simple marketplace transactions; and 5)corporations serve a wider range of human values than can be captured by a sole focuson economic values.

    Hence, analysis of social responsibility in business was largely concerned with identifying

    the obligations of business to society. Enlightened self-interest was the rationale to which its

    proponents appealed, including business leaders. Firms were encouraged to practice corporate

    social responsibility, even where it could not be clearly justified on the basis of cost and revenue

    projections, because it was believed to be in their best long-term interest. Accordingly, some

    proponents of corporate social responsibility have advanced a very broad conception of enlightened

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    19/33

    17

    self-interest. It has been suggested, for example, that firms should try and solve social problems

    completely unrelated to their business activities, such as providing jobs to the hard-core

    unemployed, because these problems might otherwise become detrimental to the overall business

    climate (Simon, Powers and Gunnemann 1972).

    CSR and the related concepts of corporate social responsiveness and corporate social

    performance remain central considerations within the business and society field. Moreover, in

    the late 1990s, many businesses have exhibited a renewed interest in CSR under the rubric of 

    “corporate citizenship”, with a focus on giving back to the societies of which they are part

    through efforts to help solve pressing social problems, such as unemployment and inner-city

    decay. Meanwhile, many issues of corporate social responsibility have become subsumed

    within the broader topic of business ethics. The rationale of enlightened self-interest is recognized

    within the field of business ethics and in practice, with many managers subscribing to the maxim

    ‘good ethics is good business’.

     Limitations of a Reliance on the Law and Enlightened Self-Interest

    While obey the law and act in your own long-term economic self-interest are, under most

    circumstances, necessary, they are not sufficient as guidelines for good conduct in marketing. It

    matters little whether few if any of the actual ethical prescriptions to be found in the extant

    marketing ethics literature do reveal the inadequacy of reliance on Gaski’s law and self-interest

    prescription. Without doubt, if marketing practice were to be solely guided by law and self-

    interest, as Gaski appears to suggest, the likelihood of good conduct would be substantially

    reduced. Marketing managers must also be guided by ethics.

    In part, this is evident from the limitations to Gaski’s central proposition identified

    above, particularly the unacknowledged assumptions about the adequacy of the law (its scope as

    well as enforcement), the imperative of customer satisfaction, and effects on stakeholders other

    than the customer. It is also evident from ethical prescriptions that can be found in the

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    20/33

    18

    marketing ethics literature that go beyond the law and self-interest, as discussed below. Further,

    in some circumstances, the guidelines ‘obey the law’ and ‘act in your own self-interest’ may

    even conflict with sound ethical prescriptions, extant or otherwise, and reduce the likelihood of 

    good conduct.

    NORMATIVE MARKETING ETHICS AND GOOD CONDUCT

     Ethical Prescriptions that Go Beyond the Law and Self-Interest

    We might agree with Gaski were he to suggest that the ethical prescriptions he identifies

    are largely consistent with the law and/or self-interest. The question then arises as to whether

    there are ethical prescriptions that go substantially beyond the law and self-interest. Below are

    some candidates from the extant marketing ethics literature that Gaski may have overlooked.

    The purpose here is not to offer another inventory of the literature, but merely to offer examples

    of ethical guidelines that can be found in the marketing ethics literature that clearly reflect

    something more than the law or self-interest and, more important, explain in the following

    section why that should be.

    The American Marketing Association has a Code of Ethics for Marketing on the internet,

    in addition to the general code that Gaski cites. This code, consistent with Goodwin (1991) and

    others, refers to a consumer right to privacy. More specifically, it states: “Information collected

    from customers should be confidential and used only for expressed purposes” (see

    www.ama.org). This provision would appear to preclude undisclosed secondary use of data

    collected from consumers, yet it is not a legal requirement nor is it necessarily consistent with

    the individual marketer’s self-interest.

    Robin and Reidenbach (1987) propose an approach whereby social responsibility and

    ethics become part of the strategic marketing planning process through developing or

    reformulating the corporate culture. Although their purpose is to identify a process for

    introducing ethical and socially responsible core values into an organizational culture, they do

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    21/33

    19

    offer some normative guidelines, including the following: “by using the culturally established

    values of an average family as a guide in determining what its reaction to society ought to be, an

    organization can develop reasonable standards” (1987; emphasis in the original).

    In line with this broad guideline of consistency with family values, Robin and

    Reidenbach (1987) offer the following more specific guideline: “make and market products you

    would feel comfortable and safe having your own family use.” This guideline is substantively

    different from the guideline on product safety (“do not market harmful or dangerous products”)

    that Gaski considers equivalent to a requirement to obey the law and/or act in your self-interest.

    He writes in relation to this guideline: “As long as there is an expectation of economic loss from

    bad behavior, that should be a deterrent augmenting the legal inhibition” (p. 318). Consider, for

    example, a marketer who decides on ethical grounds not to market violent or sexually explicit

    videogames. This decision may well be consistent with Robin and Reidenbach’s prescription

    (and conceivably a result of the marketer attempting to reconcile his business life with his family

    values). However, it is not necessarily consistent with the ethical prescription that Gaski

    examines (the marketer may not believe that the videogames are harmful) or legal and/or self-

    interest considerations.

    Williams and Murphy (1990) suggest that ethical analysis in marketing could be

    improved with a focus on the theory of virtue. Central concerns of such a theory are “what sort

    of person am I shaping?” and “what sort of organization am I shaping?” (Williams and Murphy

    1990, p. 24). Accordingly, Williams and Murphy (1990, p. 26) write: “The theory of virtue thus

    highlights the need for marketers to consider how consumers are being affected by each product.

    We suggest that marketers should not sell products that retard character or virtue development.”

    Again, with the videogames example in mind, we might envisage how this guideline might go

    beyond the requirements of the law and self-interest.

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    22/33

    20

    Thompson (1995) proposes a contextualist approach to marketing ethics. He rejects out

    of hand the entire premise on which Gaski’s (1999) argument is based. He writes (1995, p. 187)

    that “ethics is an orientation, that is, a way of thinking about and acting on ethical dilemmas…

    moral reasoning cannot be reduced to a formulaic process of applying abstract principles that

    guarantee moral outcomes.” Nonetheless, in identifying normative implications of his analysis,

    Thompson (1995, p. 187) writes of “the need to foster a caring orientation in the conduct of 

    marketing ethics” (his emphasis), consistent with the work of Carol Gilligan. He writes (1995,

    p. 187) of “a desire to be responsive to the interests of those likely to be affected.” This desire

    will not necessarily be consistent with self-interest and the law.

    Smith (1995) has proposed the consumer sovereignty test (CST) as a guideline that

    managers can use to evaluate the ethics of many marketing decisions. In essence, the CST claims

    that marketers have an obligation to consider whether consumers are capable of exercising

    informed choice. Its domain is limited to corporate impacts on customers; therefore, the framework 

    does not directly address marketing impacts on other stakeholders. Moreover, it is not claimed that

    the CST alone is a sufficient basis for evaluating the ethics of a marketing decision (see Smith 1995

    for further limitations as well as the rationale for the CST).

    Smith (1995, p. 92) writes that “the CST requires marketing managers to fulfill the promise

    of marketing ideology; i.e., promoting the consumer’s interests… even without market pressure to

    do so.” More specifically, the CST creates an obligation for marketers to examine whether

    consumers whom their marketing programs target have capability, information, and choice. The

    consumer capability dimension of the CST requires the manager to examine whether consumers are

    vulnerable, perhaps due to age, education, or income. Hence, the manager would establish, for

    example, whether a target market was fully capable of understanding the risks associated with a

    product, going beyond legal requirements and perhaps to the firm's economic disadvantage by

    excluding some potential consumers. The information dimension generally requires the manager to

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    23/33

    21

    determine whether the quality and availability of information to consumers is sufficient for them to

     judge whether their expectations at purchase will be fulfilled. The choice dimension requires

    managers to consider whether consumers have the option of going elsewhere, a function mainly of 

    the level of competition in the market and of any switching costs.

    Consider the ethics of tobacco marketing. It is ethically problematic under two if not all

    three dimensions of the CST. Most people start smoking in their early teens and thus there is

    diminished consumer capability. Further, the addictive nature of tobacco diminishes consumer

    choice. Finally, although there is generally abundant information about the adverse health effects

    of smoking in developed countries, this is not so true of lesser-developed countries where many

    tobacco companies are now focusing their marketing efforts.

    Brenkert (1998) is also interested in consumer capability and the marketer’s obligations.

    He has offered a particularly thoughtful analysis of the ethical issues raised by the unfairness

    that can result from targeting vulnerable consumers. He advances the following guideline:

    “marketers may not target those who are specially vulnerable in ways such that their marketing

    campaign depends upon the vulnerabilities of that specially vulnerable group” (1998, p. 15). So,

    in relation to marketing to children, he writes (1998, p. 16): “because children are cognitively

    vulnerable due to their undeveloped abilities, any marketing done to children must be done in

    ways that do not presuppose those vulnerabilities.” He argues that legal restrictions on

    advertising to children are inadequate in the following way: “the FCC’s limit on the amount of 

    advertising on children’s television programming does not directly address this issue… the

    content of those advertisements must be monitored” (p. 16).

    The Need for Ethics

    There is a need for ethics regardless of whether ethical prescriptions for marketing that

    go beyond the law and self-interest can be identified (and regardless of whether ethics serves as

    a foundation for the law). Another way of illustrating this need is to consider situations where

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    24/33

    22

    ethics, the law and self-interest are inconsistent, including situations where the law and self-

    interest are not enough and ethics demands more of the marketing practitioner. This can be

    illustrated very simply with a 2X2 matrix (see Figure 1). As shown in Cell A, decisions that are

    inconsistent with ethics, and inconsistent with the law and/or self-interest are unlikely (though

    marketing managers may be unsure of the law or their self-interest, managers’ decisions may

    serve their interests but not those of the firm, and they do make mistakes). Decisions consistent

    with ethics and consistent with the law and/or self-interest are unproblematic, as shown in Cell

    D. However, more difficult are decisions that are consistent with the law and self-interest, but

    might be unethical (Cell B). Also difficult are decisions that are consistent with ethics, but may

    not be in one’s self-interest and/or may be inconsistent with the law (Cell C).

    (See Figure 1 at the end of the document)

    For examples of Cell B decisions consider advertising to children and testing products on

    animals. Although there are legal restrictions on advertising to children, it is not generally

    illegal. Nonetheless, as Paine (1993) shows, there are good ethical reasons for the criticism of 

    child-oriented television advertising. Paine questions whether young children (under the age of 

    eight) are appropriate targets for advertisers because they lack the conceptual abilities required

    for making consumer decisions. Their immature conceptions of self, time, and money, mean

    that children know little about their wants and preferences and how to use their economic

    resources to satisfy them. Testing products on animals is not illegal and is often carried out even

    when there is good knowledge about the product ingredient in question. However, there are

    moral duties associated with the treatment of animals, not least because of their capacity for

    suffering (Regan 1992). Other examples of Cell B decisions might include price gouging,

    marketing of tobacco and firearms, and environmentally harmful products and packaging.iii

    For examples of Cell C decisions consider the well-known recall of Tylenol by Johnson

    and Johnson. At the time of the recall, it appeared to be a costly decision ($100 million) that

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    25/33

    23

    would kill the brand and was contrary to the advice of the FBI (Tedlow 1990). The recall was

    not legally prescribed (though certainly it was not illegal) and did not appear to be in the firm’s

    self-interest. It is only with hindsight that we know of the economic benefits to Johnson and

    Johnson of the recall and can refer to this as a celebrated example of the maxim ‘good ethics is

    good business’. As Ciulla (1991, p. 218) writes in relation to this example: “Doing the morally

    right thing may be difficult and costly, but in the end, you win back the kingdom.”

    As an alternative, consider the lesser-known example of Merck’s development and

    distribution of an ‘orphan drug’ for river blindness (Business Enterprise Trust 1996). River

    blindness, or onchocerciasis, is caused by a parasitic worm found by fast-flowing rivers in

    certain parts of lesser-developed countries. In 1978, the World Health Organization estimated

    that 340,000 people were blind because of onchocerciasis and 18 million or more were infected

    with the parasite. There were no safe treatments and no financial incentives to develop drugs for

    some of the world’s poorest populations. Merck’s discovery of ivermectin as a possible

    treatment for river blindness, posed a dilemma. If development of the drug was successful, it

    would generate little if any revenues and yet it could substantially improve the lives of many

    people. Merck successfully developed the drug, known as Mectizan and then, unable to find

    funding for its distribution, organized this as well. Again, the company’s actions in this instance

    were not a result of following what the law or self-interest might appear to dictate.

    Clearly, there is scope for content in marketing ethics that goes beyond the law and self-

    interest. However, this content may not be most evident in the form of ethical prescriptions.

    Ethical prescriptions may be useful as a starting point and in certain, relatively straightforward

    situations. The complexity of many ethical issues in business often demands ethical theory,

    from which, after all, the prescriptions were likely developed in the first place. Consider the

    issue of bribery. Gaski observes, correctly, that “do not commit bribery” is an ethical

    prescription that can be found in the marketing ethics literature and that bribery is generally

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    26/33

    24

    illegal.iv  Nonetheless, there are occasions where bribery is morally defensible, as only the

    application of ethical theory can reveal.

    Deontological, consequentialist and social contract approaches have been used to show

    that bribery is generally unethical. However, these ethical theories also reveal when bribery may

    be morally permissible (Dunfee, Smith, and Ross 1999). From a deontological perspective, we

    can identify a prima facie duty not to engage in bribery, but this duty might be overridden by

    other more compelling duties (Pastin and Hooker 1980; Philips 1984). From a consequentialist

    perspective, it has been argued that engaging in bribery may be morally justifiable for smaller

    firms that would otherwise be subject to large harms (Green 1991). Dunfee, Smith and Ross

    (1999) claim that bribery is much less likely to be morally permissible when analyzed using

    Integrative Social Contracts Theory (than, say, deontological or consequentialist theories).

    However, they allow that the payment of bribes under duress (extortion) may still be morally

    permissible where corruption is widespread, weakly prosecuted and often associated with threats

    of physical harm.

    CONCLUSIONS

    Despite his provocative critique of marketing ethics, Gaski explains that “it is not

    asserted here that marketing ethics is universally coextensive with the law. Nor is it held that

    marketing ethics is the same as self-interest. The conclusion is that the normative ethical rules

    found in the existing marketing literature are sufficiently accounted for by the guidelines of law

    and self-interest combined or aggregated” (his emphasis, p. 327). He does not dismiss ethics

    out-of-hand either, suggesting that the “applicability of ethics… to other realms of human

    activity is not being contested” (p. 327). Yet if his purpose is really to highlight the failings to

    date of marketing ethics as a field, Gaski is still not convincing.

    Nonetheless, and more important perhaps, Gaski’s critique may lead to serious

    misconceptions about a field that is still not well understood by the broader field of marketing.

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    27/33

    25

    First, while obey the law and act in your enlightened self-interest have some merit as guidelines

    to marketing managers, they merely point to a moral minimum—and even thus treated, have

    exceptions, where ethics might point to decisions inconsistent with the law or self-interest.

    Second, most societies expect their members to make decisions that go beyond the law and self-

    interest and to include ethical considerations. Third, marketing managers are mature adult

    members of society and sophisticated decision-makers who are surely capable of some moral

    deliberation and this is often called for in marketing. Fourth, in terms of informing practice, it is

    more important for normative marketing ethics to enable decision-makers to make better moral

     judgements applicable to the specific and often complex situation they face than to offer an

    inevitably limited list of general ethical prescriptions. Fifth, practice will be better informed

    through ethical theory. To view the content of normative marketing ethics as ultimately

    reducible to a series of ethical prescriptions fundamentally mistakes its role. Ethical

    prescriptions are only one way of many by which both normative and positive marketing ethics

    may inform marketing practice.

    To be sure, there is much work to be done in normative marketing ethics. The emphasis

    on positive ethics in the marketing ethics literature may well reflect the empirical orientation of 

    the marketing ethics field (particularly given the scope for empirical research of positive

    theories), but the imbalance could usefully be redressed. These efforts could include the

    development of ethical prescriptions that might offer some general advice to marketers, perhaps

    along the lines of the examples identified above. However, more important is the development

    of theories of marketing ethics that provide a basis for moral deliberation by practitioners and

    others of the many complex and often troubling ethical issues found in marketing.

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    28/33

    26

    Figure 1: Ethics, the Law, and Self-Interest

    Decision Consistent with the Lawand/or Self-interest

    DecisionConsistentwith Ethics

    No

    Yes

    No Yes

    Unlikely

    E.g., RiverBlindness drug,Tylenol recall

    E.g., animal testing,advertising to

    children

    Unproblematic

     A B

     C D

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    29/33

    27

    REFERENCES

    Akaah, Ishmael P. and Edward A. Riordan (1989), “Judgments of Marketing Professionals

    About Ethical Issues in Marketing Research: A Replication and Extension,” Journal of 

    Marketing Research XXVI (February), 112-20.

    Brenkert, George G. (1998), “Marketing and the Vulnerable,” Business Ethics Quarterly Ruffin

    Series, Special Issue 1, 7-20.

    Buchholz, Rogene A. (1991), “Corporate Responsibility and the Good Society: from Economics

    to Ecology; Factors which Influence Corporate Policy Decisions,” Business Horizons 34

    (4), 19-31.

    Business Enterprise Trust (1996), “Merck and Company, Inc.” in Thomas Donaldson and Al

    Gini, ed., Case Studies in Business Ethics, Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 299-

    308.

    Chonko, Lawrence B. (1995), Ethical Decision Making in Marketing, Thousand Oaks, CA:

    Sage.

    --------- and Shelby D. Hunt (1985), "Ethics and Marketing Management: An Empirical

    Investigation," Journal of Business Research 13, 339-59.

    Ciulla, Joanne B. (1991), “Business Ethics as Moral Imagination,” in R. Edward Freeman, ed.,

    Business Ethics: The State of the Art, New York: Oxford University Press, 212-220.

    Dunfee, Thomas W., N. Craig Smith, and William T. Ross, Jr. (1999), “Social Contracts and

    Marketing Ethics,” Journal of Marketing 63 (July), 14-32.

    Duke, Charles R., Gregory M. Pickett, Les Carlson, and Stephen J. Grove (1993), “A Method for

    Evaluating the Ethics of Fear Appeals,” Journal of Public Policy and Marketing 12

    (Spring).

    Ferrell, O. C., and Larry G. Gresham (1985), “A Contingency Framework for Understanding

    Ethical Decision Making in Marketing,” Journal of Marketing 49 (Summer), 87-96.

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    30/33

    28

    --------- and Mark Weaver (1978), “Ethical Beliefs of Marketing Managers,” Journal of Marketing

    42 (July), 69-73.

    ---------, Larry G. Gresham, and John Fraedrich (1989), "A Synthesis of Ethical Decision Models

    for Marketing," Journal of Macromarketing 9 (Fall), 55-64.

    Frederick, William C. (1994), “From CSR1 to CSR2: The Maturing of Business-and-Society

    Thought,” Business and Society 33 (2), pp. 150-64.

    Fritzsche, David J. (1985), “Ethical Issues in Marketing Management,” in Marketing Ethics:

    Guidelines for Managers, Gene R. Laczniak and Patrick E. Murphy, eds. (Lexington,

    MA: Lexington Books).

    Gaski, John F. (1999), “Does Marketing Ethics Really Have Anything to Say?—A Critical

    Inventory of the Literature,” Journal of Business Ethics 18 (February), 315-334.

    Goodwin, Cathy (1991), “Privacy: Recognition of a Consumer Right,” Journal of Public Policy

    and Marketing 10 (Spring), 149-166.

    Green, Ronald M. (1991) “When is `Everyone’s Doing It’ a Moral Justification?” Business

    Ethics Quarterly 1 (January), 75-94.

    Gundlach, Gregory T. and Patrick E. Murphy (1993), “Ethical and Legal Foundations of 

    Relational Marketing Exchanges,” Journal of Marketing, 57 (October), 35-46.

    Hunt, Shelby D. and Scott J. Vitell (1993), “A General Theory of Marketing Ethics: A

    Retrospective and Revision,” in Ethics in Marketing, N. Craig Smith and John A.

    Quelch, eds. Homewood, IL: Irwin, 775-784.

    Laczniak, Gene R. (1983), “Framework for Analyzing Marketing Ethics,” Journal of 

    Macromarketing, 1 (Spring), 7-18.

    --------- (1993), “Marketing Ethics: Onward Toward Greater Expectations,” Journal of Public

    Policy and Marketing 12 (Spring), 91-96.

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    31/33

    29

    --------- and Patrick E. Murphy (1993), Ethical Marketing Decisions: The Higher Road (Needham

    Heights, MA: Allyn and Bacon).

    Malhotra, Naresh K. (1996), Marketing Research: An Applied Orientation. Upper Saddle River,

    NJ: Prentice Hall, Inc.

    Murphy, Patrick and Gene R. Laczniak (1981), "Marketing Ethics: A Review with Implications for

    Managers, Educators and Researchers," in Ben M. Enis and Kenneth J. Roering (ed.),

    Review of Marketing (Chicago: American Marketing Association, 1981), 251-66.

    --------- and Pridgen, M. D. (1991), “Ethical and Legal Issues in Marketing,” in Paul N. Bloom, ed.,

    Advances in Marketing and Public Policy 2, Greenwich, CT: JAI Press Inc., 185-244.

    Paine, Lynn Sharp (1993), “Children as Consumers: The Ethics of Children’s Television

    Advertising,” in Ethics in Marketing, N. Craig Smith and John A. Quelch, eds.

    Homewood, IL: Irwin, 672-686.

    Pastin, Mark and Michael Hooker (1988), “Ethics and the Foreign Corrupt Practices Act,” in

    Ethical Issues in Business, Thomas Donaldson and Patricia H. Werhane, eds. Englewood

    Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Philips, Michael (1984), “Bribery,” Ethics, (July), 621-36.

    Petty, Ross D. (1999), “Introduction: The What and Why of Marketing Law,” American Business

    Law Journal 36 (Winter), 239-254.

    Regan, Tom (1992), “Treatment of Animals,” in Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker,

    Encyclopedia of Ethics, New York: Garland Publishing, 42-46.

    Robin, Donald P. and R. Eric Reidenbach (1986), “A Framework for Analyzing Ethical Issues in

    Marketing,” Business and Professional Ethics Journal 5 (2), 3-22.

    --------- and --------- (1987), “Social Responsibility, Ethics, and Marketing Strategy: Closing the

    Gap Between Concept and Application,” Journal of Marketing, 51 (January), 44-58.

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    32/33

    30

    --------- and --------- (1993), “Searching for a Place to Stand: Toward a Workable Ethical

    Philosophy for Marketing," Journal of Public Policy and Marketing 12 (1), 97-105.

    Simon, John G., Charles W. Powers, and Jon P. Gunnemann (1972), The Ethical Investor:

    Universities and Corporate Responsibility, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Smith, N. Craig (1990), Morality and the Market: Consumer Pressure for Corporate Accountability,

    London: Routledge.

    -------- (1995), “Marketing Strategies for the Ethics Era,” Sloan Management Review 36 (Summer),

    85-97.

    -------- and John A. Quelch (1993), Ethics in Marketing (Homewood, IL: Richard D. Irwin).

    Sparks, John R. and Shelby D. Hunt (1998), “Marketing Researcher Ethical Sensitivity:

    Conceptualization, Measurement, and Exploratory Investigation,” Journal of Marketing 62

    (April), 92-109.

    Stone, Christopher D. (1975), Where the Law Ends (New York: Harper and Row).

    Tedlow, Richard S. (1990), “James Burke: A Career in American Business (A).” Case study.

    Boston: Harvard Business School Publishing.

    Thompson, Craig J. (1995), “A Contextualist Proposal for the Conceptualization and Study of 

    Marketing Ethics,” Journal of Public Policy and Marketing 14 (Fall), 177-91.

    Tsalikis, John and David J. Fritzsche (1989), "Business Ethics: A Literature Review with a Focus

    on Marketing Ethics," Journal of Business Ethics 8 (September), 695-743.

    Weaver, Mark and O.C. Ferrell (1977), “The Impact of Corporate Policy on Reported Ethical

    Beliefs and Behavior of Marketing Practitioners,” in Contemporary Marketing Thought:

    Proceedings of the American Marketing Association 41, Chicago: American Marketing

    Association, 477-481.

    Williams, Oliver and Patrick E. Murphy (1990), “The Ethics of Virtue: A Moral Theory for

    Marketing,” Journal of Macromarketing, 10 (Spring), 19-29.

  • 8/19/2019 Craig Marketing

    33/33

    ENDNOTES

     i This reply will not speculate on possible reasons for the tone of some of Gaski’s comments. Suffice to note thatwhile it can be useful to be provocative, overstating the case weakens the argument overall.ii The methodological problems include concerns about demand effects that Gaski refers to but does not adequatelyaddress. Respondents were asked to classify each ethical rule by indicating which of 4 categories best applies to it:(A) rule is essentially a matter of ‘obey the law’; (B) rule is essentially a matter of ‘act in your self-interest,’ i.e., if you don’t act ethically it will catch up with you; (C) both A and B; (D) neither A nor B. One concern is simply thatrespondents were not given an explicit opportunity to categorize an ethical prescription as essentially a matter of ethics; another is that, apparently, the categories were not rotated among respondents.iii For some of these examples it might be argued that firm self-interest is threatened by the possibility of consumerboycotts. However, this may not be a credible or serious threat under many circumstances (see Smith 1990, pp.257-266).iv Though as Noonan’s (1984) historical account shows, bribery was ethically proscribed long before legalrestrictions.