decomposition of multiple attribute preference models

192
Copyright by Ying He 2013

Upload: ying-he

Post on 10-Dec-2015

25 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

DESCRIPTION

This dissertation consists of three research papers on preference models of decision making, all of which adopt an axiomatic approach in which preference conditions are studied so that the models in this dissertation can be verified by checking their conditions at the behavioral level.

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

Copyright

by

Ying He

2013

Page 2: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

The Dissertation Committee for Ying He Certifies that this is the approved version

of the following dissertation:

Decomposition of Multiple Attribute Preference Models

Committee:

James S. Dyer, Supervisor

John C. Butler

Kumar Muthuraman

J. Eric Bickel

Canan Ulu

Warren J. Hahn

Page 3: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE

MODELS

by

Ying He, B.Eco.; M.S.I.R.O.M.

Dissertation

Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of

The University of Texas at Austin

in Partial Fulfillment

of the Requirements

for the Degree of

Doctor of Philosophy

The University of Texas at Austin

December 2013

Page 4: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

Dedication

To my parents and my wife.

Page 5: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

v

Acknowledgements

I wish to take this opportunity to appreciate the people who helped me so much

during my doctoral study at The University of Texas at Austin.

I am extremely fortunate to have Professor James S. Dyer as my Ph.D advisor. I

owe my deepest gratitude to Professor Dyer for his continuous support, patient guidance,

and insightful inspiration throughout my entire Ph.D. study. He has set an example of

excellence as a researcher, mentor, instructor, and role model. I would also like to thank

Dr. John C. Butler, who always helps me think about my research from a new

perspective. I am also grateful to other member of my dissertation committee: Dr. Kumar

Muthuraman, Dr. J. Eric Bickel, Dr. Canan Ulu, and Dr. Warren J. Hahn for their helpful

comments on the dissertation and generous service on the committee.

I would like to thank my parents Yaowu He and Shulian Sun for their constant

support, continuous encouragement, and unconditional love, which makes me able to

finish my Ph.D. study in the USA.

Finally, I would like to thank my wife Ni Wang who accompanied me to the USA

and continuously provides me with her support and understanding.

Page 6: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

vi

Decomposition of Multiple Attribute Preference Models

Ying He, Ph.D.

The University of Texas at Austin, 2013

Supervisor: James S. Dyer

This dissertation consists of three research papers on preference models of

decision making, all of which adopt an axiomatic approach in which preference

conditions are studied so that the models in this dissertation can be verified by checking

their conditions at the behavioral level.

The first paper β€œUtility Functions Representing Preference over Interdependent

Attributes” studies the problem of how to assess a two attribute utility function when the

attributes are interdependent. We consider a situation where the risk aversion on one

attribute could be influenced by the level of the other attribute in a two attribute decision

making problem. In this case, the multilinear utility modelβ€”and its special cases the

additive and multiplicative formsβ€”cannot be applied to assess a subject’s preference

because utility independence does not hold. We propose a family of preference

conditions called th degree discrete distribution independence that can accommodate a

variety of dependencies among two attributes. The special case of second degree discrete

distribution independence is equivalent to the utility independence condition. Third

degree discrete distribution independence leads to a decomposition formula that contains

Page 7: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

vii

many other decomposition formulas in the existing literature as special cases. As the

decompositions proposed in this research is more general than many existing ones, the

study provides a model of preference that has potential to be used for assessing utility

functions more accurately and with relatively little additional effort.

The second paper β€œOn the Axiomatization of the Satiation and Habit Formation

Utility Models” studies the axiomatic foundations of the discounted utility model that

incorporates both satiation and habit formation in temporal decision. We propose a

preference condition called shifted difference independence to axiomatize a general habit

formation and satiation model (GHS). This model allows for a general habit formation

and satiation function that contains many functional forms in the literature as special

cases. Since the GHS model can be reduced to either a general satiation model (GSa) or a

general habit formation model (GHa), our theory also provides approaches to axiomatize

both the GSa model and the GHa model. Furthermore, by adding extra preference

conditions into our axiomatization framework, we obtain a GHS model with a linear habit

formation function and a recursively defined linear satiation function.

In the third paper β€œHope, Dread, Disappointment, and Elation from Anticipation

in Decision Making”, we propose a model to incorporate both anticipation and

disappointment into decision making, where we define hope as anticipating a gain and

dread as anticipating a loss. In this model, the anticipation for a lottery is a subjectively

chosen outcome for a lottery that influences the decision maker’s reference point. The

decision maker experiences elation or disappointment when she compares the received

Page 8: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

viii

outcome with the anticipated outcome. This model captures the trade-off between a

utility gain from higher anticipation and a utility loss from higher disappointment. We

show that our model contains some existing decision models as its special cases,

including disappointment models. We also use our model to explore how a person’s

attitude toward the future, either optimistic or pessimistic, could mediate the wealth effect

on her risk attitude. Finally, we show that our model can be applied to explain the

coexistence of a demand for gambling and insurance and provides unique insights into

portfolio choice and advertising decision problems.

Page 9: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

ix

Table of Contents

Table of Contents ................................................................................................... ix

List of Tables ......................................................................................................... xi

List of Figures ....................................................................................................... xii

CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION .............................................................................1

1.1. Overview ................................................................................................1

1.2. Preference for risk and time ...................................................................3

CHAPTER 2. UTILITY FUNCTIONS REPRESENTING PREFERENCE OVER

INTERDEPENDENT ATTRIBUTES .....................................................................8

2.1. Introduction ............................................................................................8

2.2. Third degree discrete distribution independence .................................13

2.3. Verification and Assessment................................................................22

2.3.1. Verification of the BLII condition .....................................24

2.3.2. Assessment of the TDI decomposition ..............................28

2.4. Generality of the TDI decomposition and its relationship with some

existing decompositions .......................................................................30

2.5. A family of utility functions implying BLII condition ........................33

2.6. Nth degree discrete distribution independence ....................................41

2.7. Conclusion ...........................................................................................46

2.8. Supplemental proofs and BLII verification .........................................47

2.8.1. Proofs .................................................................................47

2.8.2. Verification of the BLII condition for utility functions

satisfying mutual risk independence ...........................................62

CHAPTER 3. ON THE AXIOMATIZATION OF THE SATIATION AND HABIT

FORMATION UTILITY MODELS ....................................................................66

3.1. Introduction ..........................................................................................66

3.2. Shifted difference independence for a measurable value function ......69

3.3. A general satiation (GSa) model ..........................................................77

Page 10: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

x

3.4. Habit formation and satiation model with linear habit and satiation

functions ...............................................................................................84

3.4.1. A general habit formation and satiation (GHS) model ......84

3.4.2. Linear habit and satiation functions ...................................92

3.5. Axiomatization theory for risky preference .........................................98

3.6. Conclusion .........................................................................................100

3.7. Supplemental proofs ..........................................................................101

CHAPTER 4. HOPE, DREAD, DISAPPOINTMENT, AND ELATION FROM

ANTICIPATION IN DECISION MAKING .......................................................120

4.1. Introduction ........................................................................................120

4.2. The model ..........................................................................................125

4.3. The preference assumptions ...............................................................129

4.4. Risk Attitude ......................................................................................135

4.4.1. Optimism, pessimism, and risk attitude ...........................135

4.4.2. Wealth effect on risk attitude ...........................................140

4.5. Utility of Gambling ............................................................................143

4.5.1. Coexistence of gambling and purchasing of insurance....143

4.5.2. Stochastic dominance and transitivity .............................147

4.6. Decision making models ....................................................................149

4.6.1. Portfolio selection decision ..............................................149

4.6.2. Optimal advertising decision ...........................................155

4.7. Conclusion .........................................................................................159

4.8. Supplemental proofs ..........................................................................160

REFERENCES ........................................................................................................171

VITA. ....................................................................................................................180

Page 11: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

xi

List of Tables

Table 2.1: A comparison between the TDI decomposition and some other existing

decomposition formulas. ...................................................................... 12

Table 2.2: General form of Mutual Risk-Value decomposable utility functions which

mutually satisfy BLII ............................................................................ 39

Table 2.3: Mutual Risk-Value decomposable utility functions which mutually satisfy

BLII ...................................................................................................... 65

Table 3.1: Effects from satiation and habit formation on the Delta quantity .............. 77

Table 3.2: Abbreviated notations ................................................................................118

Page 12: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

xii

List of Figures

Figure 2.1: Third Degree Discrete Distribution Independence ................................... 15

Figure 2.2: Marginal utility functions and constants to be assessed for decomposition

(2.6) ...................................................................................................... 20

Figure 2.3: Eliciting 𝑃1, 𝑃2, and 𝑃3 ........................................................................ 25

Figure 2.4: The surface of utility function (2.8) .......................................................... 29

Figure 2.5: Relationships among different decompositions for utility function with

two attributes ........................................................................................ 33

Figure 2.6: Two indifferent lotteries with same expected values ................................ 64

Figure 3.1: Shifting value function under satiation and habit formation .................... 73

Figure 3.2: Endowed consumption and deprivation under satiation and habit

formation .............................................................................................. 75

Figure 3.3: The shifted value function in the Satiation Axiom ................................... 80

Figure 3.4: Comparison between additive independence and shifted additive

independence ........................................................................................ 99

Figure 4.1: The relationship of models (4.1) and (4.2) with some existing models . 129

Figure 4.2: Assumption 4.1: Shifted Utility Independence ....................................... 131

Figure 4.3: Assumption 4.2: Shifted Additive Independence ................................... 134

Figure 4.4: Optimistic vs. pessimistic anticipation levels ......................................... 139

Page 13: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

1

CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION

1.1. OVERVIEW

This dissertation consists of three research papers on the topic of preference

models in decision making. A common topic studied in all the three papers is about the

decomposition of a multiattribute utility function representing a preference order.

However, each paper studies this topic in a different application context focusing on

different decision making problems. The subsequent three chapters of the dissertation

correspond to each paper respectively, which are all self-contained and independent. In

all three papers, when a multiattribute utility function is decomposed, we propose the

conditions on the preference which imply the utility decomposition. Therefore, the three

papers adopt an axiomatic approach to study decision models, which means that the

models in this dissertation can be verified by testing the corresponding preference

conditions proposed here.

When there are multiple criteria that concern the decision maker (DM) in a

problem context, a multiattribute utility function is used to model the DM’s preference

over alternatives. To study a multiattribute utility function, it is desirable to decompose it

into a composite function of some single attribute utility functions. The merit of such a

decomposition can be justified as follows.

Page 14: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

2

First, in a real world decision making context with multiple attributes, a decision

analyst usually wants to assess the utility function of the DM and to base the subsequent

analysis of the problem on it. In such a case, a utility decomposition can be employed to

simplify the assessment process of the multiattribute utility function. Directly assessing a

multiattribute function is very tedious, even for a two attribute utility function. However,

if a decomposition formula can be applied to the multiattribute utility function, the

decision analyst can focus on assessing single attribute utility functions and synthesize

them into the multiattribute utility function, which makes the assessment process much

simpler. This is the problem which is discussed in the first paper.

Second, when we model some decision making phenomena by a multiattribute

utility function, a decomposition of a multiattribute utility function is associated with

some specific behavioral assumptions on preference in the decision making problem.

These behavioral assumptions usually reveal some insights about how people make

decisions. For instance, the discounted utility model (Koopmans 1960) in intertemporal

decision making assumes an additive decomposable utility function over the consumption

streams. This additive form is equivalent to the assumption that the preference over

consumption levels in one period is independent of the consumption levels in other

periods. In this case, studying the decomposition of a utility function is equivalent to

studying how people make decisions. This is exactly the approach we take in the second

and third papers in this dissertation, where utility functions are decomposed to capture

different behavioral assumptions on decision making in different contexts.

Page 15: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

3

1.2. PREFERENCE FOR RISK AND TIME

Based on multiattribute utility decompositions, the three papers address different

decision making problems in three different contexts.

The first paper focuses on decision making under risk involved with two

attributes. In this situation, we may want to assess a von Neumann Morgenstern utility

function with two attributes to represent the preference of the DM. For this problem, the

classical approach requires the preference conditions to be verified to make sure that the

multiattribute utility function can be decomposed into some more tractable forms such as

additive or multiplicative utility functions. In the two attribute case, the additive and

multiplicative decomposition is equivalent to assuming that the two attributes are

mutually utility independent (Keeney and Raiffa 1976). However, the mutual utility

independence implies that the risk attitude on one attribute is independent of the level of

the other attribute, which may not hold in many situations.

To account for the interdependence among the attributes, we propose a family of

preference condition called th degree discrete distribution independence that can

accommodate a variety of dependencies among two attributes. The special case of second

degree discrete distribution independence is equivalent to the utility independence

condition. When the third degree discrete distribution independence holds mutually on

both attributes, the condition leads to a decomposition formula called the third degree

discrete distribution independence (TDI) decomposition, which contains many other

decomposition formulas in the existing literature as special cases. To obtain a utility

Page 16: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

4

function by using this decomposition, the DM is required to assess the utility values of

four points obtained by arbitrarily choosing two levels on each attribute and the single

attribute utility functions on the four boundaries of the rectangle domain in the two

attributes space. Compared with the mutual interpolation independence decomposition

proposed by Bell (1979), the TDI decomposition provides a more general utility

assessment method with less effort required for the verification of the preference

condition. Furthermore, we show that for a special class of utility functions which can be

decomposed into the Risk-Value model (Jia and Dyer 1996, Dyer and Jia 1997), the

verification of the preference condition for the TDI decomposition can be simplified.

Finally, as the decomposition is more general than most existing decompositions in the

literature, it also provides a better approximate formula for two attribute utility function

when mutual utility independence condition does not hold.

The second paper focuses on the problem of decision making over time. We

consider a DM making a choice over a set of consumption streams. The classical model

in the existing literature to capture this preference is the discounted utility (DU) proposed

by Samuelson (1937) and Koopmans (1950). However, there have been many

documented experimental studies in the literature which challenge the descriptive validity

of this model (Frederick et al. 2002). It is believed that the independence axiom which

assumes that the preference over consumption levels in each period is independent of the

consumption levels in other periods is too strong to be true in many intertemporal choice

contexts. To increase the descriptive power of the DU model, this assumption is relaxed

Page 17: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

5

to allow the past consumption levels to influence the preference over consumption in the

current period, which motivates the ideas behind the habit formation utility model (e.g.

Pollak 1970, Wathieu 1997 2004, Carroll et al. 2000), the satiation utility model

(Baucells and Sarin 2007), and a utility model with both habit formation and satiation

(Baucells and Sarin 2010). Although the habit formation utility model was axiomatized

by Rozen (2010) in a recent work, the preference conditions for both the satiation model

and the utility model with both habit formation and satiation were still unclear.

In the second paper, we axiomatize both the habit formation and satiation utility

functions by decomposing the multiattribute utility function over consumption stream

vectors, where the consumption space for each period is treated as an attribute. We

consider a case where there is no risk and assume that the DM has a strength of

preference order over consumption streams, which is represented by a utility function

called a measurable value function in the literature (Krantz 1970, Dyer and Sarin 1979).

In this case, we generalize the difference independence condition (Dyer and Sarin 1979)

to a condition called shifted difference independence to axiomatize the habit formation

and satiation model. As the difference independence implies an additive structure of the

multiattribute measurable value function (Dyer and Sarin 1979), the shifted difference

independence implies the same additive structure with a shifting quantity in the utility in

each period, which turns out to be able to capture both the satiation and habit formation

effects in the utility function. When there is risk, by following an idea similar to the one

used for strength of preference, we show that the shifted utility independence generalized

Page 18: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

6

from utility independence (Keeney and Raiffa 1976) can be used to axiomatize satiation

and habit formation in this case. Finally, as both the satiation model and the habit

formation model are special case of the model with both satiation and habit formation

effects, our preference conditions proposed in this paper can also be used to axiomatize

these two models.

The third paper studies a decision problem where both time and risk are present.

In this problem, we consider decision making over two periods where a lottery is

resolved and paid in the second period and the DM could form an anticipation level for

the lottery in the first period. This modeling framework with two periods is consistent

with many decision problems, such as purchasing a lottery ticket or making a financial

investment. In these situations, a DM can derive utility from anticipating the payoff of the

lottery before it is resolved and paid in the second period. Forming a higher level of

anticipation for the outcome can increase the utility derived from anticipation, but it also

increases the probability of suffering from a disappointment. Therefore, the total utility a

DM experiences from this type of decision making depends on the tradeoff between

savoring a high anticipation and avoiding a high disappointment.

In the third paper, we employ the shifted utility independence condition proposed

in the second paper to decompose the total experienced utility from this two period

decision making problem into two parts. The first part captures the utility from

anticipating the payoff and the second part captures the expected utility from

experiencing both elation and disappointment based on the reference point determined by

Page 19: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

7

the anticipation level. We show that our model contains some existing decision models as

its special cases, including the disappointment models by Bell (1985). We also use our

model to explore how a person’s attitude toward the future, either optimistic or

pessimistic, could mediate the wealth effect on her risk attitude. Finally, we show that our

model can be applied to explain the coexistence of a demand for gambling and insurance

and that it provides unique insights into portfolio choice and advertising decision

problems.

Page 20: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

8

CHAPTER 2. UTILITY FUNCTIONS REPRESENTING

PREFERENCE OVER INTERDEPENDENT ATTRIBUTES

2.1. INTRODUCTION

Multiple attributes may need to be considered in many decision problems. The

multilinear utility function based on the utility independence condition developed by

Keeney and Raiffa (1976) has been applied widely to model preference in this situation.

For two attributes, the multilinear utility function can be reduced to either an additive or a

multiplicative utility function (Keeney and Raiffa 1976) which can be easily assessed.

However, utility independence may be a restrictive assumption for some decision

problems. For a two-attribute multilinear utility function, the mutual utility independence

condition requires that the risk aversion over one attribute is independent of the level of

the other attribute. Thus, the multilinear utility model fails to capture a decision maker’s

(DM’s) preference if her risk attitude on one attribute could be influenced by the outcome

of the other attribute.

As an example of this type of dependence, Eeckhoudt, Rey, and Schlesinger

(2007) proposed a functional form ( ) 2 ( ) [ 1] [ 1] as a

utility function over health and wealth, which exhibits increasing risk aversion on each

attribute when the other attribute is increased. In another paper on health economics, Rey

Page 21: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

9

and Rochet (2004) discussed a two-attribute utility function over health and wealth whose

risk aversion on one attribute decreases when the other attribute increases.

Several approaches have been proposed to assess or to construct a utility function

in more general situations to allow dependence between attributes. However, not all of

these approaches are a direct generalization of the multilinear model. Fishburn and

Farquhar (1982) proposed a very general family of conditions called n-degree utility

independence conditions, which include the generalized utility independence condition

(Fishburn and Keeney 1974, 1975) as 1-degree utility independence. However, the n-

degree utility independence conditions are mutually exclusive concepts and so one

condition is not a generalization of another. Also, since Fishburn and Farquhar (1982) did

not provide assessment methods for their n-degree utility independence decompositions,

it is unclear how their formulation can be applied to assess a utility function in practice.

Another exact decomposition approach is the mixex utility function proposed by Tsetlin

and Winkler (2009), which can be reduced to either additive or multiplicative aggregation

functions as special cases. Abbas’ (2009) utility copula may be classified as an

approximation method, since the utility function depends on the type of copula used to

generate the function, but the method to choose an appropriate copula to reflect the true

preference of the DM is unclear in the paper.

We will focus on utility decomposition formulas which are generalizations of the

multilinear utility model. Both the β€œbilateral independence” decomposition, i.e.,

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) , and the β€œgeneralized multiplicative” utility

Page 22: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

10

function, i.e., ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) proposed by Fishburn (1974, 1977) can

be reduced to either additive or multiplicative utility in special cases. Bell (1979) also

proposed a more general decomposition formula based on the idea of assuming mutual

interpolation independence, which contains the multilinear utility function, bilateral

independence decomposition, and general multiplicative utility as special cases. In this

approach, is interpolation independent of if the following relationship holds

( | ) ( ) ( | ) (1 ( )) ( | )

where ( | ) is called the conditional utility function and defined as ( | )

[ ( ) ( )] [ ( ) ( )] , and ( ) [

] [ ] . For any

( ) , we can always find a constant to satisfy ( | ) ( | ) (1

) ( | ), which depends on both and . However, Bell’s concept of interpolation

requires that this only depends on .

Recently, Abbas and Bell (2011) proposed a one-switch independence condition

as a generalization of the utility independence condition. They obtained a mutual one-

switch independence decomposition which is a special case of the mutual interpolation

independence model (Abbas and Bell 2011) and also contains the multilinear utility as a

special case. They also showed that the mutual one-switch independence decomposition

has overlaps with Fishburn’s generalized multiplicative decomposition and bilateral

independence decomposition (see Theorem 4 Abbas and Bell 2011), all of which are

special cases of Bell’s (1979) mutual interpolation independence decomposition.

Page 23: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

11

In this chapter, we generalize the concept of utility independence to allow for

dependence between the risk aversion over one attribute and the level of the other

attribute to derive a new decomposition formula for a two-attribute utility function, which

we call the third degree discrete distribution independence (TDI) decomposition. The

contributions of this development include the following. First, we show that this

decomposition contains Bell’s (1979) mutual interpolation independence decomposition

as a special case, but it is even more general and therefore may be used to assess many

forms of two-attribute utility functions that cannot be assessed using Bell’s

decomposition. Further, the additional questions required to assess this more general

utility model from the DM should not be overly burdensome. Table 2.1 summarizes some

utility decomposition formulas in the literature that are generalizations of utility

independence and compares them with the TDI decomposition developed in this chapter.

Second, this utility decomposition is based on an intuitively appealing preference

independence condition that seems similar to utility independence at first glance, but is

actually more general. We believe that this new independence condition has interesting

behavioral implications that may be worthy of additional research. Third, this

independence condition can be verified much easier by a DM than Bell’s (1979)

interpolation independence decomposition, which may only be verified numerically.

Thus, the TDI decomposition discussed in this chapter provides a more practical way to

assess a more general utility function than Bell’s (1979) approach.

Page 24: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

12

Decomposition

Name

Decomposition Formula

Multilinear

Utility (Keeney

and Raffia 1976)

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

This decomposition contains additive decomposition and multiplicative

decomposition as special cases.

Mutual

Interpolation

Independence

Decomposition

(Bell 1979)

( ) ( | ) ( | ) ( | ) ( | ) ( ) ( | ) ( |

) ( ) ( | ) ( | ) (1 ) ( | ) ( | )

This decomposition contains multilinear utility decomposition (Keeney and

Raiffa (1976), mutual one switch independence decomposition (Abbas and

Bell 2010), generalized multiplicative decomposition (Fishburn 1977), and

bilateral independence decomposition (Fishburn 1974) as special cases.

Third Degree

Discrete

Distribution

Independence

(TDI)

Decomposition

( ) ( )(1 ( ) ( )) ( ) (1 ( ) ( ))

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

This decomposition contains Bell’s (1979) mutual interpolation

independence decomposition as a special case. The functions ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) are composite functions of

( ) ( ) ( ) (

); and and are arbitrary

values in the domain [ ] [

].

Table 2.1: A comparison between the TDI decomposition and some other existing

decomposition formulas.

The reminder of this chapter is organized as follows. In section 2.2, we introduce

the third degree discrete distribution independence decomposition and define two new

independence conditions that are necessary and sufficient for this decomposition to hold.

Binary lottery independence is one of these two conditions. In section 2.3, we use an

example to show how to verify the binary lottery independence condition in general

situations by posing a series of questions to the DM. Section 2.4 discuss the generality of

Page 25: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

13

the TDI decomposition and its relationship with some other decomposition formulas in

the existing literature. In section 2.5, we discuss a special case which simplifies the

verification of this condition when the marginal utility functions can be decomposed into

risk-value models (Jia and Dyer 1996, Dyer and Jia 1997). In section 2.6, we generalize

the idea of the third degree discrete distribution independence condition to define a

family of th degree discrete distribution independence conditions, which implies even

more general utility functions. Section 2.7 concludes this chapter by summarizing the

relationships among the decomposition formulas developed in this chapter and some

other decomposition formulas in the literature. All the proofs are deferred to section 2.8.

2.2. THIRD DEGREE DISCRETE DISTRIBUTION INDEPENDENCE

In this chapter, we use the notation to denote both the name of an attribute and

the set of all the possible levels of this attribute. Suppose a DM has a risky preference

over two attributes and . We use the notation { ( ) (1 ) ( )} to

define a binary lottery which yields the outcome ( ) with probability and

( ) with probability (1 ). In a special case, when is fixed at the same level

for the two outcomes, we refer to this two-attribute lottery as a binary lottery

conditioned at , which is denoted by ( ) { ( ) (1 ) ( )}.

We now introduce a new decomposition of a utility function that is based on

independence conditions that are an extension of utility independence. To assess the

DM’s utility function ( ) over and using this new decomposition, we want to

Page 26: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

14

verify whether for any outcomes on , ( ), there exist two discrete

probability distributions such that two lotteries defined on two subsets of a binary

partition of { } are always indifferent conditioned at any level of . As

there are three arbitrarily chosen levels on , we call this third degree

discrete distribution independence.

Definition 2.1. For any three outcomes on , ( ), if there exist two

discrete probability distributions such that two lotteries defined on the two subsets of a

binary partition of { } are always indifferent conditioned at any level of ,

then is third degree discrete distribution independent (TDI) of .

This condition will be met if there are two probabilities and such that the

DM is indifferent between either { ( ) (1 ) ( )} and { ( ) (1

) ( )} or { ( ) (1 ) ( )} and { ( ) (1 ) ( )} conditioned

at any level . These two cases of indifference can be visualized in the lotteries on

the left side of Figure 2.1.

Page 27: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

15

Figure 2.1: Third Degree Discrete Distribution Independence

If the DM’s preferences satisfy the condition of being utility independent of

(Keeney and Raiffa 1976), there should be infinitely many pairs of and such that

these two binary lotteries and conditioned at on the left side of Figure 2.1

are indifferent at any level of . The condition we want to verify here is weaker than the

utility independence condition. It only requires the DM to confirm that only one such pair

of and exists. We refer to this condition as the binary lottery indifference

independence condition.

Definition 2.2. (Binary Lottery Indifference Independence) If there exist and

such that the two binary outcome lotteries ( ) and ( ) on the left side of Figure

2.1 are indifferent at any level of , we say that is binary lottery indifference

independent of , written as BLII .

(π‘₯𝑖 𝑦) ∼

(π‘₯ 𝑦)

(π‘₯ 𝑦)

𝑝

1 𝑝 π‘ž

(π‘₯𝑗 𝑦) π‘ž

βˆ€ 𝑖 {1 2} 𝑗 {1 2}\{𝑖}, do probabilities

𝑝 π‘ž exist such that the indifference always

holds for any level of 𝑦?

βˆ€ 𝑖 {2 3} 𝑗 {2 3}\{𝑖}, do probabilities

𝑝 π‘ž exist such that the indifference always

holds for any level of 𝑦?

Binary lottery indifference independence

(π‘₯𝑖 𝑦)

(π‘₯ 𝑦)

𝑝

1 𝑝

(π‘₯𝑗 𝑦)

(π‘₯ 𝑦)

π‘ž

1 π‘ž

∼ (οΏ½οΏ½ 𝑦) (οΏ½οΏ½ 𝑦)

Trinary lottery certainty equivalent

independence

Page 28: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

16

When the DM’s risk aversion on is influenced by the level of , her preference

does not satisfy the condition of being utility independent of ; and her certainty

equivalent for a lottery on conditioned at , defined by ( ) ( )

depends on the value of . However, it is possible that for some probabilities and ,

the DM believes that her certainty equivalents for the two binary lotteries are changed by

the same amount when the value of is varied so that she is always indifferent between

them at any level of . In section 2.3, we show how to verify this condition by eliciting

probabilities and for any ( ) conditioned at some level of

and asking the DM whether she is always indifferent between the two lotteries on the left

side of Figure 2.1 when is changed. In section 2.5, we further show that for a special

class of utility functions, this condition can be verified more easily.

The third degree discrete distribution independence condition will also be met if

one subset of a binary partition of { } contains one element and the other

subset contains three elements. In this case, the condition requires that the certainty

equivalent for a three outcome lottery on conditioned at is independent of the

level of , which is identified as the trinary lottery certainty equivalent independence.

This condition is illustrated on the right side of Figure 2.1.

We will provide some intuition for the implication of the two independence

conditions in Figure 2.1 by focusing on binary lottery indifference independence, but the

development for trinary lottery certainty equivalent independence would be similar. After

verifying the condition that BLII , we can write it as ( ) (1 ) ( )

Page 29: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

17

( ) (1 ) ( ), where we let 3 2 in Figure 1. For 2 3, the

reasoning is the same. Then, for any { 1 2 3}, we can solve for ( ) from this

equation. Suppose we solve for

( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ) ( ) (2.1)

where and (1 ) . Since we can solve for any ( ), equation

(2.1) provides a way to assess the utility function ( ) in a bounded space

[ ] [

]. To see this, we can rewrite (2.1) by dropping the subscript of and

using the notations ( ) and ( ) to indicate that these values are functions of ,

which results in the following equation

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( ) ( )) ( ) (2.2)

Without loss of generality, we assume that ( ) and ( ) 1 . We

evaluate (2.2) at and respectively to determine two equations so that we can solve

for ( ) and ( ) as follows

( ) ( )( (

) ( )) ( )( ( ) (

))

( )( ( ) ( )) ( )( ( ) ( )) (2.3)

( ) ( )( (

) ( )) ( )( ( ) (

))

( )( ( ) ( )) ( )( ( ) ( )) (2.4)

Both (2.3) and (2.4) are composite functions that only depend on marginal utility

functions ( ) and ( ). Thus, we can use (2.2) to assess the utility function

( ) by assessing five marginal utility functions ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

Page 30: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

18

and ( ). If the DM’s preference also satisfies the condition that BLII , we can

exchange and in (2.2) and derive (2.5) for any ( )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( ) ( )) ( ) (2.5)

where the equations for ( ) and ( ) can be obtained by switching and in the

formulas for ( ) given by (2.3) and for ( ) given by (2.4).

Evaluating ( ) and ( ) with (2.5) and substituting them into (2.2), we

have

( ) ( ) [ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( ) ( )) ( )]

( ) [ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

(1 ( ) ( )) ( )] (1 ( ) ( )) ( )

(1 ( ) ( )) [ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )]

(1 ( ) ( )) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

By using (2.3) and (2.4), we can verify that

[ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )] ( ) . Substituting this relationship into the

above equation, we obtain the decomposition formula for the utility function ( )

below.

Page 31: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

19

( ) ( )(1 ( ) ( )) ( ) (1 ( ) ( ))

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( )

(2.6)

Applying decomposition (2.6) to assess a utility function is straightforward. First,

we ask the DM to assess the marginal utility functions ( ), ( ), ( ), and

( ) on the boundaries of the attribute space [ ] [

] and the utility values

at the six black circles in Figure 2.2. These four constants ( ), ( ), ( ),

and ( ) may be assessed for any ( ) and any (

) After

we obtain these functions and values, we substitute them into the formulas for the

coefficients ( ), ( ), ( ), and ( ). Then, by substituting these coefficients

and the marginal functions into (2.6), we can obtain the assessed utility function ( ).

We showed that binary lottery indifference independence implies this

decomposition (2.6). Following a similar approach, it is easy to show (2.6) can also be

implied by the trinary lottery certainty equivalent independence. Thus, each of them is

sufficient to derive (2.6). To obtain the necessary and sufficient conditions for (2.6), we

notice that when (2.2) holds, there are two cases. If one of the three coefficients in (2.2)

(either ( ), ( ), or 1 ( ) ( )) is negative, then (2.2) is equivalent to the

binary lottery indifference independence condition. However, if all the three coefficients

( ), ( ), and 1 ( ) ( ) are positive, (2.2) is equivalent to the trinary

Page 32: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

20

lottery certainty equivalent independence condition. Therefore, the necessary and

sufficient condition for (2.6) is that third degree discrete distribution independence

mutually holds on both attributes.

Note: the utility values at the black circles are to be assessed; and the utility values

at the white circles are to be calculated from the assessed marginal utility functions

Figure 2.2: Marginal utility functions and constants to be assessed for decomposition (2.6)

Theorem 2.1. and are mutually third degree discrete distribution independent if and

only if the utility function can be decomposed by (2.6) on the bounded attributes space

[ ] [

].

Unlike the binary lottery indifference independence condition, the trinary lottery

certainty equivalent independence condition may not be easy to verify, since it is not

apparent what kinds of preferences would satisfy this condition. Thus, verifying the

necessary and sufficient conditions for decomposition (2.6) could be a demanding task, as

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 ) 1

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 ) 𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

𝑒(π‘₯ 𝑦 )

Page 33: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

21

it requires the DM to think about both conditions described in Figure 2.1. In the

following corollary, we specify a condition under which the mutual binary lottery

indifference independence condition is both necessary and sufficient for decomposition

(2.6).

Corollary 2.1. For any [ ] and [

], when the marginal utility

functions ( ), ( ), ( ), and ( ) are increasing functions, if both

[ ( ) ( )] [ ( ) ( )] and [ ( ) (

)] [ ( )

( )] are strictly monotonic functions of and respectively, the utility function

( ) can be decomposed by (2.6) if and only if the binary lottery indifference

independence condition holds mutually for both and .

This corollary gives us a way to simplify the verification of the necessary and

sufficient condition for decomposition (2.6) by asking the DM to focus on thinking about

the binary lottery indifference independence condition only. When assessing a utility

function, if the DM’s preference does not satisfy the mutual utility independence

condition, most existing assessment methods require the DM to assess four marginal

utility functions on the boundaries of the attributes space. Since these four marginal

utility functions will be needed to assess the utility function eventually, we may choose to

assess them first before verifying the preference condition. We can use these marginal

utility functions to calculate these ratios for both attributes in this corollary to see whether

they are strictly monotonic on each attribute space.

Page 34: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

22

If these utility ratios are strictly monotonic, we can verify the binary lottery

indifference independence condition for both attributes as the necessary and sufficient

conditions for the decomposition (2.6). If they are not, we could make partitions on each

attribute space such that they are strictly monotonic on each subset and then focus on

verifying the binary lottery indifference independence for each subset. However, based

on our empirical analysis of utility functions over two attributes that are mutually third

degree discrete distribution independent, we would expect the monotonic condition for

the ratio in the Corollary 2.1 to be satisfied for a large majority of practical applications.

2.3. VERIFICATION AND ASSESSMENT

Equation (2.1) is a mathematical representation of the BLII condition, so if the

two functions and in equation (2.1) depend on then the condition is not satisfied.

If we rearrange the terms and divide both sides by ( ) ( ) (2.1) can be

rewritten in the following form

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

(2.7)

For any , the ratio [ ( ) ( )] [ ( ) ( )] for {1 2 3}

in (2.7) can be interpreted as a probability 𝑃 ( ) that solves the equation ( )

𝑃 ( ) ( ) (1 𝑃 ( )) ( ) ; i.e., 𝑃 ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( ) for {1 2 3} .

Therefore, to verify whether and in (2.1) depend on , we can elicit 𝑃 ( )

Page 35: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

23

( ) ( )

( ) ( ) for {1 2 3} at different levels of and check whether they satisfy

(2.7) simultaneously for a unique pair of and . For each pair of and , we can

obtain a pair of and as we showed in section 2.2.

At different values of , i.e, , 𝑃 ( ) 𝑃 ( ), and 𝑃 ( ) give three

column vectors with dimensions.

(

𝑃 ( ) 𝑃 ( ) 𝑃 ( )

𝑃 ( )𝑃 ( )

𝑃 ( )𝑃 ( )

𝑃 ( )𝑃 ( )

𝑃 ( )𝑃 ( )

𝑃 ( )𝑃 ( )

𝑃 ( )𝑃 ( ) )

For any , the rank of the above matrix is 3. If the rank 1, there exist

infinitely many pairs of and such that one column is a linear combination of the

other two columns. In this case, (2.7) is true for infinitely many pairs of and ; and

thus there exist infinitely many pairs of and such that the two lotteries in Figure 2.1

are indifferent, which corresponds to the case when mutual utility independence holds. If

the rank 2, there exists a unique pair of and to express one vector as the linear

combination of the other two, which implies a unique pair of and such that one of

the two lottery pairs in Figure 2.1 is indifferent conditioned on any level of . If rank

3, the three vectors are linearly independent, and there exists no such pair of and

. Therefore, the number of pairs of and that can make the two lotteries in Figure

2.1 be indifferent is either zero, or one, or infinity.

Page 36: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

24

We will proceed as follows. First, we will assume that the DM’s preferences are

consistent with a specific form of a utility function that does satisfy the binary lottery

independence condition, and show how to verify this condition using the above idea.

Second, once the binary lottery independence condition has been verified based on

responses implied by this utility function, we will demonstrate how to recover that same

function using the assessment procedure illustrated in Figure 2.2.

2.3.1. Verification of the BLII condition

Suppose a DM needs to choose among different investment options for her

retirement pension. She believes that there are two attributes to be considered, wealth ( )

measured on the range [$0, $1] million dollars and health ( ) measured on the range [0

QALY, 80 QALY] where a QALY is defined as a quality adjusted life year. So, she

wants to assess her utility function over these two attributes to help her make a choice

over different risky plans. We assume that she can express her preferences based on the

following utility function that is otherwise unknown to her, which has been rescaled such

that ( ) [ 1] [ 1] and ( ) [ 1].

( )

( 32 11 ) ( 313 3 2 )

( 2 2 ) ( 3 3 3 )

(2.8)

Page 37: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

25

In order to verify the BLII condition for this DM, we will elicit 𝑃 for

{1 2 3}. First, we arbitrarily choose three levels of and one level of . For instance,

we can choose 2 [ ] [ 1 ],

and 32 [ ] . Then, we ask the DM to elicit the

probabilities 𝑃 𝑃 𝑃 such that the indifference relationships shown in Figure 2.3 will

hold.

Figure 2.3: Eliciting 𝑃 , 𝑃 , and 𝑃

If the DM specifies these probabilities according to her utility function (2.8), we

will obtain the following results.

𝑃 (32 ) 2 𝑃 (32 ) 2 𝑃 (32 ) ;

( 1𝑀 32 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ)

( 𝑀 32 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ)

𝑃

1 𝑃

( 2𝑀 32 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ) ∼

( 1𝑀 32 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ)

( 𝑀 32 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ)

𝑃

1 𝑃

( 𝑀 32 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ) ∼

( 1𝑀 32 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ)

( 𝑀 32 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ)

𝑃

1 𝑃

( 𝑀 32 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ) ∼

Page 38: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

26

Now, we arbitrarily change the value of to 2 , and ask the DM to elicit

these probabilities again. This time, the DM will identify the following probabilities

based on her utility function (2.8)

𝑃 ( 2 ) 31 𝑃 ( 2 ) 𝑃 ( 2 ) .

After we obtain these two sets of probabilities for two different health levels, we

can use the equations below corresponding to (2.7) to solve for the two variables and

.

𝑃 (32 ) 𝑃 (32 ) 𝑃 (32 )

𝑃 ( 2 ) 𝑃 ( 2 ) 𝑃 ( 2 )

Solving the above equations, we obtain 2 and 1 . Substituting

and into (2.1) and shifting the term ( ) to the left side, we have for

{32 2 }

( ) 1 ( 2 ) 2 ( ) 3 ( )

Notice that the coefficients on both sides of this equation sum to the same

constant, which in this case is 2 . So, we can divide both sides by 2 to obtain the

following equation.

1

2 ( )

1

2 ( )

2

2 ( )

3

2 ( )

This gives

1 and

for 2

[ 1 ] in (2.1). Thus, we know for

Page 39: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

27

{32 2 } , the DM is indifferent between the two lotteries

{ 1 ( ) ( 2 )} and { ( ) 1 ( )}.

Now, we ask the DM whether she will feel indifferent between these two lotteries

if we change the health level to other values. As implied by the assumed utility

function (2.8), the DM will answer β€œyes”. So, we can verify that the probabilities

1 and make the DM feel indifferent between these two lotteries for

any . Then, we should repeat this process by picking another set of , , and to

verify the existence of and again. Since we can always verify the existence of

and for different values of , , and for utility function (2.8), we are assured that

the DM’s preference represented by utility function (2.8) satisfies the BLII condition.

The preference condition verification process outlined above is simpler than that

required by Bell’s MII decomposition. Bell’s condition needs to be verified by eliciting

values of the conditional utility function ( | ) on a grid formed by choosing many

different levels on both attribute and and checking whether these values satisfy the

interpolation independence condition (see Figure 2, Bell 1979). To verify the condition

for the TDI decomposition, we still need to elicit values of the conditional utility function

at many different levels on . But, on attribute , we only need to choose two levels.

This eliminates almost half of the elicitation work required in the preference verification

process.

Page 40: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

28

2.3.2. Assessment of the TDI decomposition

When the BLII condition has been verified as illustrated above, we can assess the

TDI decomposition for the DM by following the logic of Figure 2.2. We would assess

this DM’s single attribute utility functions on the boundaries of the two attributes domain

and six constants based on responses that would be implied by (2.8). We ask the DM to

assess the values of ( ) and ( ) first. For instance, we can assess (

)

by eliciting a probability such that ( ) ∼ { (

) (1 ) ( )} .

Suppose the DM responds according to the utility function (2.8), and we would obtain

( ) and ( ) . Then, if we assess the four single attribute utility

functions in Figure 2.2 and rescale them such that ( ) , ( ) ,

( ) 1, and ( ) , we have the following utility functions.

( ) ( )

( ) 1

1 ( )

1

1

Then, we arbitrarily choose ( 1) and ( 1). With the marginal

single attribute utility functions assessed above, we can calculate ( ), ( ),

( ), and (

). Then, to assess ( ), ( ), ( ), and ( ),

we can follow the same idea. For instance, ( ) can be assessed by eliciting

probability such that ( ) ∼ { ( ) (1 ) ( )}. Then, ( )

can be calculated by ( ) ( ) (1 ) ( ). Finally, substituting

Page 41: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

29

these single attribute utility functions and constants into (2.6) gives (2.8), which is plotted

in Figure 2.4.

Figure 2.4: The surface of utility function (2.8)

In the above process, the assessment of the marginal utilities relies on the assessed

constants ( ) and ( ), so care should be taken to assess these values as

accurately as possible. Any errors in the assessment of these constants will be amplified

when assessing the marginal utility functions based on them.

Page 42: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

30

2.4. GENERALITY OF THE TDI DECOMPOSITION AND ITS RELATIONSHIP WITH SOME

EXISTING DECOMPOSITIONS

To gain some insights regarding the generality of our decomposition (2.6), we

rewrite it in the form of (2.9) shown below, which is obtained by substituting the

expressions for the four functions ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) into our decomposition

(2.6).

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (

) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) (

) ( ) ( ) ( )

(2.9)

where the for {1 2 3 } and for {1 2} and {3 } are coefficients

which depend on the six constants indicated by the black circles in Figure 2.2.

The multilinear utility function for two attributes (Keeney and Raffia 1976) is of

the form ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ), which is a special case of

(2.9). The bilateral independence decomposition (Fishburn 1974) and the mutual

interpolation independence decomposition (Bell 1979) also imply utility functions of the

form of (2.9). For the bilateral independence decomposition, the coefficients

and in (2.9) only depend on ( ) and ( )

(see section 5, Fishburn 1974). For the mutual interpolation independence decomposition,

they depend on ( ) , ( ) , and ( ) for arbitrary ( ) [

]

[ ] (See theorem 1, Bell 1979). In our model, these coefficients depend on the six

Page 43: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

31

assessed utility values indicated by the black circles in Figure 2.2. The result is that our

decomposition (2.6) is more general. In Proposition 2.1, we show that our decomposition

(2.6) contains the mutual interpolation independence decomposition developed by Bell

(1979) as a special case.

Proposition 2.1. Mutual interpolation independence decomposition implies

decomposition (2.6), but (2.6) does not imply mutual interpolation independence

decomposition.

Since the mutual interpolation independence decomposition is a very general

decomposition formula that contains many existing decompositions as its special cases

(see table 1, Bell 1979), Proposition 2.1 implies that all these decompositions identified

by Bell (1979) are also special cases of our decomposition (2.6). In the Appendix, we

show that decomposition (2.6) contains more general utility functions which cannot be

decomposed into the mutual interpolation independence decomposition, because

decomposition (2.6) allows the interpolation coefficients assumed by Bell (1979) to

depend on both and .

The generality of our decomposition (2.6) is important because it provides a

utility assessment approach that can more accurately represent the DM’s true preference

compared with the utility decomposition formulas which are special cases of this

decomposition. This point has been made by Keeney and Raiffa (see the beginning of

subsection 5.7.4, Keeney and Raiffa 1976). They also argue that a more general utility

Page 44: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

32

function decomposition may provide a better approximation for true utility functions

because of its degrees of freedom, which they define as the number of single attribute

utility functions and constants that need to be assessed in a decomposition formula. Our

decomposition (2.6) has ten degrees of freedom (four single attribute utility functions

plus six constants in Figure 2.2) which is more than the degrees of freedom of other

existing decomposition formulas discussed by Keeney and Raiffa (Figure 5.12, Keeney

and Raiffa 1976). Bell’s (1979) mutual interpolation independence decomposition has

seven degrees of freedom. Thus, decomposition (2.6) also should provide a better

approximation of a two-attribute utility function than any of these alternative models.

Of course, the generality of a decomposition formula cannot be obtained without

some cost. The disadvantage of a more general decomposition formula is the more

complex assessment procedure associated with it. Decomposition (2.6) asks the DM to

assess three extra constants compared with Bell’s (1979) mutual interpolation

independence decomposition, so we believe this keeps the assessment task within

acceptable bounds.

In Figure 2.5, we visualize the relationships among the decompositions we

developed in this chapter with some existing decompositions including those summarized

in Table 2.1. The biggest circle in the figure represents the decomposition implied by th

degree discrete distribution independence condition as a generalization of the third degree

discrete distribution independence condition, which is discussed in section 2.6.

Page 45: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

33

Figure 2.5: Relationships among different decompositions for utility function with two

attributes

2.5. A FAMILY OF UTILITY FUNCTIONS IMPLYING BLII CONDITION

The verification process for the BLII condition outlined in section 2.3 may be

simplified by focusing on a family of utility functions which can be decomposed into a

risk-value model (Jia and Dyer 1996, Dyer and Jia 1997) on each attribute. These risk-

value models were originally developed for single attribute utility assessments, but their

extension to the multiple attributes domain provides a variety of models that are

composed of linear and multiplicative forms that include terms commonly found in

popular multiattribute utility models, including power, exponential and logarithmic. As a

result, this development also demonstrates that there exist many different two-attribute

Mutual Interpolation Independence

Decomposition

General

Mutiplicative

Decomposition

Multi-linear Model

(Additive or Multiplicative)

(Mutual 2nd Degree Discrete

Distribution Independence)

Bilateral

Decomposition

Mutual One-Switch

Independence Decomposition

Mutual 3rd Degree Discrete Distribution Independence

Decomposition (2.6)

Mutual n-th Degree Discrete Distribution Independence

Decomposition for n>3

Page 46: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

34

utility models that do not satisfy mutual utility independence, but that do satisfy the BLII

condition and would be practical for use in preference modeling.

In the standard risk-value model (Jia and Dyer 1996), a normalized lottery is

defined as a lottery with zero mean that is obtained by subtracting the expected value

from the lottery , namely . The set of such normalized lotteries is

denoted by { | }, where is the set of arbitrary lotteries. For a

single attribute utility function ( ), when the preference of a DM satisfies a condition

called risk independence, the expected utility of a lottery can be decomposed as

( ) ( ) ( )[ ( ) ( )] where ( ) is defined as the standard measure

of risk (see theorem 3, Jia and Dyer 1996). This risk independence condition requires that

for any , if then for any . Furthermore, if

the utility function ( ) is continuously differentiable, then it must be one of the three

functional forms: ( ) ; ( ) ; and ( ) where

, , and are constants (see theorem 4, Jia and Dyer 1996).

For a two-attribute utility function ( ), if the DM’s preference satisfies the

risk independence condition on attribute given any level of and if we combine the

utility functions ( ) and ( ) into one case by allowing the

constant to be either zero or non-zero, we know the two-attribute utility function must

be one of two forms, namely either ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) or ( )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ), where ( ), ( ), ( ), and ( ) are functions of .

Page 47: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

35

These utility functions can be decomposed into a standard risk-value model on

conditioned at any level of . For example, the expected value of a lottery ( ) given

by the exponential utility function above can be written as

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( )( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) [ ( )( ) 1] ( )

( ) ( ) ( ) [ ( )( ) 1] ( )

where the standard measure of risk is ( ) ( )( ) , which depends on

.

When the standard measure of risk on is independent of , namely ( ) ,

the exponential utility function above satisfies the condition that BLII .1 The

intuition for this conclusion is that for any two binary lotteries and on the left side

of Figure 2.1, there exist probabilities and such that the two lotteries have the same

mean and standard measure of risk for either 2 3 or 3 2.

( ) ( )

(1 ) (1 )

(1 ) (1 )

1 Even though the standard measure of risk here is independent of , the utility function still allows

interdependence between attributes in the sense that the Arrow-Pratt risk measure on depends on .

Page 48: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

36

When both the mean and the standard measure of risk are the same for the two binary

lotteries, it is easy to see from the risk-value model that the utilities for these two lotteries

are always the same conditioned at any level of .

( ) ( ) ( ) [ ( ) 1]

( ) ( ) [ ( ) 1] ( )

Therefore, when the standard measure of risk on is independent of , i.e., ( ) ,

the exponential utility function ( ) can satisfy the condition that BLII . When

the utility function on is of the quadratic form, it can be verified that the standard

measure of risk on is independent of , so, this utility function also satisfies the

condition that BLII .

The relative risk value model is established using a similar development, except

that the measure of risk is based on the ratio of (Dyer and Jia 1997). If a DM’s

preference satisfies the relative risk independence condition on at any level of , by

allowing the constants in the functional forms of the single attribute utility function that

are implied by the relative risk independence to depend on the level of (theorem 2,

Dyer and Jia 1997), we can conclude that the two-attribute utility function ( ) must

be one of the forms: (i) ( ) ( ) ( ) ; (ii)

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ); (iii) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ); (iv)

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) for ( ) 1; (v) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

for ( ) 1; (vi) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) for ( ) 1; or (vii)

Page 49: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

37

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) for ( ) 1. Following the same idea above,

if we can further verify that the relative measure of risk is independent of , we can

conclude that the utility function satisfies BLII .

Therefore, if we can verify either risk independence or relative risk independence

on , we only need to verify that the measure of risk (standard or relative) is independent

of to determine the condition that BLII . This can be accomplished by presenting

a pair of lotteries ( ) and ( ) conditioned at some level that are indifferent

for the DM and have the same mean on , i.e., ( ) ∼ ( ) at with ,

and ask the DM whether she will be indifferent between this pair of lotteries when is

changed. If the DM still feels indifferent when is changed, we can conclude that the

measure of risk in the risk-value model must be independent of . Thus, we have the

following theorem.

Theorem 2.2. If the preference of a DM satisfies the (relative) risk independence

condition on at any level of , and if she feels indifferent between two binary lotteries

( ) and ( ) which have the same means for any , then the preference

of this DM satisfies the condition that BLII .

To apply the Theorem 2.2, we need to find a pair of lotteries ( ) and ( )

as required by the theorem for a DM. This can be accomplished by following a similar

approach to the one we used to elicit the probabilities and in section 2.3.

Page 50: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

38

Specifically, for the chosen ( ), we elicit 𝑃 𝑃 , and 𝑃 conditioned at

some level of . First, we set up one equation of and according to equation (2.7),

which requires that the two lotteries are indifferent given , i.e., ( ) ∼ ( ).

Then, by requiring the two lotteries to have the same mean on , , we can set up

another equation for and . By solving these two equations simultaneously, we can

obtain a pair of lotteries that meet the requirements of Theorem 2.2 at . Then, we

ask the DM to identify whether she will be indifferent between the two lotteries when

is changed. An example illustrating this approach is provided in the Appendix.

Compared with the verification process outlined in section 2.3, this process is

relatively easy to implement. Therefore, it is desirable to identify the utility functions that

mutually satisfy these requirements on both attributes.

From the functional forms of single attribute utility functions that can be

decomposed into either standard or relative risk-value models listed above, we can

confirm that any two-attribute utility function that satisfies the mutual BLII condition but

is not multilinear decomposable must be of the form of either ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) or ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) with ( ) ( ) and ( )

( ) , which are the generalized multiplicative and bilateral independence

decompositions proposed by Fishburn (1977, 1974); only these two types of utility

functions can match the marginal utility functional forms that are risk-value

decomposable.

Page 51: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

39

Now, by choosing either a linear, a logarithm, a multiplication of linear and

logarithm, an exponential, or a power function form for ( ), ( ), ( ), and ( ) in

both decompositions ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) and ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ), we can obtain all the mutual risk-value decomposable utility functions with

the measures of risk on one attribute being independent of the other attribute shown in

Table 2.2. If we eliminate the functional forms that can be obtained by simply switching

and in the functions in Table 2.2, there are fifty-six different utility functions, which

are fully listed in Table 2.3 at the end of the Appendix. For simplicity, we write power

utility functions in a general form ( ) . The constants

and take values such that all the marginal utility functions are increasing on both

attributes.

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( )( ) ( ) ( )

( ) { ( ) ( )

}

( ) { ( ) ( ) }

( ) ( )( ) ( ) ( )

( ) { ( ) ( )

}

( ) { ( ) ( )

}

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) { ( ) ( )

}

( ) { ( ) ( )

}

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) { ( ) ( )

}

( ) { ( ) ( )

}

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) { ( ) ( ) }

( ) { ( ) ( ) }

Table 2.2: General form of Mutual Risk-Value decomposable utility functions which

mutually satisfy BLII

Page 52: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

40

Since the utility functions listed in Table 2.2 are special forms of these two types

of Fishburn’s decomposition, they have overlaps with the mutual one switch

independence decomposable utility functions (Abbas and Bell 2011). For these utility

functions, we may either verify the mutual one switch independence condition or mutual

BLII condition to assess them, depending on which condition is easier for the DM.

However, there are also some utility functions in Table 2.2 which do not satisfy

the mutual one switch independence condition. For example, suppose a preference is

represented by ( ) ( ) ( ) with ( )

[1 ) [1 ). To examine whether this utility function satisfies the one switch

independence condition, we rewrite it as ( ) [1 ( )

( )

], which is

the form used by Abbas and Bell (2011). To satisfy the mutual one switch independence,

both functions ( )

and

( )

must be strictly monotonic (Theorem 4 Abbas and

Bell 2011). However, it is easy to verify that these two functions are not monotonic

functions on their respective domains.

Following the similar idea, we can verify that the mutual risk-value decomposable

utility functions, which are of the general multiplicative utility functional form ( )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) [1 ( )

( )

( )

( )], may not satisfy mutual one switch

independence. This is because the ratios ( )

( ) and

( )

( ) may not be strictly monotonic

functions on their respective domains. There are 20 utility functions listed in the

Page 53: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

41

Appendix which are of the functional form of ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) that do

not satisfy the mutual one switch independence condition. For these utility functions,

verifying the BLII condition as we outlined is the only way to determine its preference

condition non-numerically.

2.6. NTH DEGREE DISCRETE DISTRIBUTION INDEPENDENCE

In section 2.2, we defined the third degree discrete distribution independence

condition based on two lotteries involving changes in one attribute only; these two

lotteries feature a total of four outcome values, three of which can be arbitrarily chosen.

In this section, we generalize this idea to consider indifference between two lotteries over

one attribute which have a total of 1 outcomes and of them are free to be chosen.

To motivate this preference condition, we consider lotteries over more than three

levels of conditioned at some level of . For outcomes ( ) and a

permutation ( ) of the index { 1 2 } with ( ) , we can choose

{ 1 2 1} so that the outcomes on form a binary partition

{{ ( ) ( ) ( )} { ( ) ( )}} of the set { } For some

permutation ( ) and , if there exist two discrete probability distributions

( ( ) ( ) ( )) and ( ( ) ( ) ( )) such that the two lotteries defined

by these distributions are always indifferent to each other at any level of , then the

following equation holds for any :

Page 54: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

42

( ) ( ( ) ) ( ) ( ( ) ) ( ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( ) ( ( ) ) ( ) ( ( ) )

By letting an arbitrary ( ) , { 1 2 } and expressing ( ( ) )

using the other terms in the above equation, we can write ( ) as a linear combination

of these utility functions evaluated at the other points. Suppose we let ( ) , we have

( ) ( ( ) )

( )βˆ‘ ( ) ( ( ) )

( )βˆ‘ ( )

( ( ) )

Since ( ( ) ( ) ( )) and ( ( ) ( ) ( )) are two probability

distributions, we know that βˆ‘ ( ) 1 and βˆ‘ ( )

1 ( ) . So, we have

( )βˆ‘ ( )

( )βˆ‘ ( )

1. Thus, the summation of the coefficients on the

right side is one. Now, we replace the subscripts ( ) (1) ( 1) ( 1) ( )

with 1 2 1 . We have ( ( ) ) ( ) for 1 1 and

( ( ) ) ( )for 1 . If we treat as fixed values and

allow to vary, we can also redefine the coefficient of ( ) as ( ) for

{1 1}. Then, we can rewrite this equation as

( ) βˆ‘ ( ) ( ) (1 βˆ‘ ( )

) ( )

(2.10)

which is a more general form of (2.2) developed in section 2.2.

Page 55: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

43

Definition 2.3. is said to be th degree discrete distribution independent of if for

arbitrary ( ) where 2 , there exist two discrete probability

distributions such that two lotteries defined on the two subsets of a binary partition of

{ } conditioned at some level of are always indifferent for any level of

.

This definition gives a family of preference conditions that contain the preference

condition defined in Definition 2.1 as a special case. The second degree discrete

distribution independence is equivalent to the utility independence condition (Keeney and

Raiffa 1976) as stated in the following proposition.

Proposition 2.2. is second degree discrete distribution independent of if and only if

is utility independent of .

By following the idea used in section 2.2, this th degree discrete distribution

independence condition can be used to derive a more general decomposition formula. If

we evaluate (2.10) at 1 points of , , we can solve for ( )

1 2 1 in the same way we solved for ( ) and ( ) for (2.2). So, we have

for any {1 2 1} , ( ) ( ( ) ( ) ( )) . By

substituting them into (2.10), we have the more general decomposition formula.

Page 56: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

44

( ) βˆ‘ ( ( ) ( ) ( ))

( )

[1 βˆ‘ ( ( ) ( ) ( ))

] ( )

(2.11)

This decomposition requires the DM to assess 1 marginal utility functions

over and marginal utility functions over . Thus, we have the following theorem.

Theorem 2.3. is th degree discrete distribution independent of if and only if the

utility function can be decomposed by (2.11) on a bounded domain [ ] [

].

The verification of this condition becomes complicated since there are many

possible binary partitions for a set with a large number of outcomes. However, if a DM

can verify that the certainty equivalents for two non-degenerate lotteries defined on

1 outcomes on conditioned at some levels of would change by the same

amount when changing the level of , we can assess her utility function by using

decomposition (2.11).

This decomposition formula (2.11) was derived based on the assumption of the

preference condition on one attribute. Following the same idea as in section 2.2, we can

symmetrically define the condition of being th degree discrete distribution

independent of and derive a symmetric decomposition of (2.11). Then, by assessing

( ) in (2.11) with this symmetric decomposition, we obtain a decomposition based

Page 57: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

45

on the mutual independence condition, which can reduce the number of marginal utility

functions that need to be assessed.

Another decomposition which also requires many single attribute utility functions

to be assessed was proposed by Tamura and Nakamura (1983). They defined a condition

called being th order convex dependent of by the following mathematical relation

(2.12) without giving a preference interpretation

( | ) βˆ‘ ( ) ( | )

(1 βˆ‘ ( )

) ( | )

(2.12)

where ( | ) [ ( ) ( )] [ ( ) ( )] is the conditional utility

function originally defined by Bell (1979) in the development of the mutual interpolation

independence decomposition.

When 1 , the above relation is reduced to the interpolation independence

condition proposed by Bell (1979). For 1, this interpolation assumption requires the

DM to assess five marginal utility functions to determine ( ). This is the same

number of marginal utility functions required to be assessed by the third degree discrete

distribution independence condition defined in section 2.2. For the th order convex

dependence assumption (2.12), the number of marginal utility functions to be assessed is

equal to that required by the ( 2) th degree discrete distribution independence

condition. Proposition 2.3 states that for the same number of marginal utility functions to

Page 58: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

46

be assessed, our discrete distribution independence gives a more general decomposition

than the convex dependence decomposition.

Proposition 2.3. being th order convex independent of implies being (

2)th degree discrete distribution independent of .

For the preference condition on one attribute, the second degree discrete

distribution independence requires assessing three marginal utility functions (Keeney and

Raiffia 1976). The third degree discrete distribution independence requires assessing five

marginal utility functions. For nth degree discrete distribution independence condition on

one of the two attributes, there are 2 1 marginal utility functions to be assessed.

2.7. CONCLUSION

Decomposition (2.6) developed in this chapter is a general decomposition of a

two-attribute utility function that can be obtained by assessing four conditional utility

functions on the boundaries of the domain. This decomposition is equivalent to a

condition called the third degree discrete distribution independence. By generalizing the

third degree discrete distribution independence condition, we obtained a family of th

degree discrete distribution independence decompositions which contain the convex

dependence decomposition as a special case. However, with the increase of , the effort

required to verify the preference conditions and to assess the utility function increases

also. Therefore, we believe the decomposition (2.6) can be used as either an exact

Page 59: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

47

decomposition or as an approximation for a two-attribute utility function, since, to our

knowledge, it is the most general exact decomposition that only requires assessing four

conditional utility functions. Besides the improvement on the generality of the utility

assessment method, the work in this chapter also provides a hierarchy of decomposition

formulas that include many existing decomposition formulas as their special cases, which

makes a theoretical contribution to the existing knowledge of the multiattribute utility

assessment methods.

Although the ideas developed in this chapter can be extended to decompose utility

functions with more than two attributes, the assessment would become very tedious as

more marginal utility functions would be needed. However, for a problem with more than

two attributes, we may expect that most attributes would satisfy the mutual utility

independence condition, and this more general decomposition developed in this chapter

might be applied for pairs of the attributes when mutual utility independence is not

satisfied.

2.8. SUPPLEMENTAL PROOFS AND BLII VERIFICATION

2.8.1. Proofs

Theorem 2.1. and are mutually third degree discrete distribution independent if and

only if the utility function can be decomposed by (2.6) on the bounded attributes space

[ ] [

].

Page 60: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

48

Proof: β€œβ‡’β€ Under the assumption of mutual third degree discrete distribution

independence, we can conclude both (2.2) and (2.5) hold in section 2.2. The formulas for

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) are easy to verify. Here we show how to derive (2.6).

Evaluating ( ) and ( ) by (2.5) and substituting them into (2.2), we

have

( ) ( ) [ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( ) ( )) ( )]

( ) [ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

(1 ( ) ( )) ( )] (1 ( ) ( )) ( )

(1 ( ) ( )) [ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )]

(1 ( ) ( )) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

(2.13)

Based on (2.13), if we can prove [ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )]

( ), by substituting this relationship into (2.13), (2.13) becomes (2.6). We can verify

this is true by substituting ( ) and ( ) into ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ).

Thus, (2.6) holds.

β€œβ‡β€ Given (2.6), from the proof above, we can conclude that the first equation in

(2.13) holds, which can be written as follows.

Page 61: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

49

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( ) ( )) ( ) (2.14)

where ( ) [ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( ) ( )) ( )]

and ( ) [ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( ) ( )) ( )].

Given (2.14), for any ( ), we can show that there exist and

such that the following equation always holds for any .

( ) (1 ) ( ) ( ) (1 ) ( ) (2.15)

Evaluating ( ), ( ) and ( ) by (2.14) and substituting them as

well as (2.14) into (2.15), we have

[ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( ) ( )) ( )]

(1 )[ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

(1 ( ) ( )) ( )]

[ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( ) ( )) ( )]

(1 )[ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

(1 ( ) ( )) ( )]

By matching the coefficients for ( ), ( ), and ( ), we can see that for

any the above equation holds if the following two equations hold simultaneously for

some and .

( ) (1 ) ( ) ( ) (1 ) ( )

Page 62: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

50

( ) (1 ) ( ) ( ) (1 ) ( )

As the above equation system has unique solutions for and , we can

conclude that there always exist and such that (2.15) holds. When , 1 , ,

and 1 are all positive or two of them on different sides are negative, (2.15) implies

the condition of being binary lottery indifference independent of . Otherwise, (2.15)

implies the trinary lottery certainty equivalent independence holds. Thus, is third

degree discrete distribution independent of .

Finally, as (2.6) is symmetric in both and , (2.6) implies a symmetric

expression of (2.14), which can be obtained by switching and in (2.14). Thus, by

following the same reasoning above, we conclude that (2.6) also implies that is third

degree discrete distribution independent of .β–‘

Corollary 2.1. For any [ ] and [

], when the marginal utility

functions ( ), ( ), ( ), and ( ) are increasing functions, if both

[ ( ) ( )] [ ( ) ( )] and [ ( ) (

)] [ ( )

( )] are strictly monotonic functions of and respectively, the utility function

( ) can be decomposed by (2.6) if and only if the binary lottery indifference

independence condition holds mutually for both and .

Proof: We only prove the corollary for one attribute, the proof for the other

attribute follows the same idea.

Page 63: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

51

Given (2.6), we have (2.2). Without loss of generality, we can assume that

and . If the three coefficients ( ) , ( ) , and (1

( ) ( )) are all positive, they can be interpreted as probabilities and the trinary

lottery certainty equivalent independence holds. Now, we show that when ( ) ( β€² )

( ) ( β€² )

is a strictly monotonic function of for any [ ] , two of the three

coefficients are positive and one is negative. Thus, (2.6) implies the binary lottery

indifference independence.

In section 2.2, we assessed the following coefficients, where ( ) .

( ) ( ( ) (

))( ( ) ( )) ( ( ) ( ))( ( ) (

))

( ( ) ( ))( ( ) ( )) ( ( ) ( ))( ( ) ( ))

( ) ( ( ) ( ))( (

) ( )) ( ( ) (

))(( ) ( ))

( ( ) ( ))( ( ) ( )) ( ( ) ( ))( ( ) ( ))

It is easy to verify that

1 ( ) ( )

( ( ) ( ))( ( ) (

)) ( ( ) ( ))( ( ) ( ))

( ( ) ( ))( ( ) ( )) ( ( ) ( ))( ( ) ( ))

When ( ) ( β€² )

( ) ( β€² ) is strictly monotonic increasing in for any , we have

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( ), which implies the denominators of the above three

coefficients are all negative. Now, we check the signs of the numerators. Since

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( ), the numerator of ( ) is negative. Thus, ( ) .

Page 64: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

52

If , we have ( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( ), the numerator of

( ) is positive. Thus ( ) . Since , we have ( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( ). Since ( ) (

) the numerator of 1 ( ) ( )

is negative. So 1 ( ) ( ) .

If , we have ( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( ), the numerator of

( ) is negative. Thus ( ) . Since , we have ( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( ). Thus, the numerator of 1 ( ) ( ) is positive. So 1

( ) ( ) .

Thus, for , two of the three coefficients are positive and one is

negative. Similarly, we can prove this is also true when ( ) ( β€² )

( ) ( β€² ) is strictly

monotonic decreasing.β–‘

Proposition 2.1. Mutual interpolation independence decomposition implies

decomposition (2.6), but (2.6) does not imply mutual interpolation independence

decomposition.

Proof: We first prove that the mutual interpolation independence decomposition

implies (2.6). This can be proved by showing that the assumption of being

interpolation independent of implies being third degree discrete distribution

Page 65: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

53

independent of .

being interpolation independent of is defined by Bell (1979) as

( | ) ( ) ( | ) (1 ( )) ( | ) (2.16)

for some ( ) that only depends on and the conditional utility function is defined by

( | ) [ ( ) ( )] [ ( ) ( )].

Given (2.16), we can show that there always exist and such that (2.15)

holds for any ( ). By multiplying ( ) ( ) on both sides of

(2.16), we conclude that (2.16) is equivalent to

( ) ( ) ( | )( ( ) ( ))

( )[ ( | ) ( | )]( ( ) ( ))

(2.17)

Evaluating ( ), ( ) and ( ) by (2.17) and substituting them as

well as (2.17) into (2.15), we can prove that (2.15) always holds for some and by

following the same idea used in the proof for theorem 2.1. Then, the condition that

being third degree discrete distribution independent of follows as in the proof for

theorem 2.1.

The fact that (2.6) does not imply the mutual interpolation independence

decomposition can be shown as follows. As we shown in the proof of Theorem 2.1, (2.6)

can be written in the form of (2.14) below

Page 66: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

54

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( ) ( )) ( ) (2.14)

Then, it can be shown that ( ) in the interpolation condition ( | ) ( | )

(1 ) ( | ) depends on both and when utility function is of the form (2.14).

First, we solve for from ( | ) ( | ) (1 ) ( | ) to obtain

( ) ( | ) ( | )

( | ) ( | )

Then, rewrite (2.14) as

( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( )

( ) ( ) (2.18)

Since ( | ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ), using (2.18), we can obtain

( ) πœ™ ( )[

𝑔 (𝑦) 𝑒( 𝑦)

𝑒( 𝑦) 𝑒( 𝑦)

𝑔 (𝑦 ) 𝑒( 𝑦 )

𝑒( 𝑦 ) 𝑒( 𝑦 )] πœ“ ( )[

𝑔 (𝑦) 𝑒( 𝑦)

𝑒( 𝑦) 𝑒( 𝑦)

𝑔 (𝑦 ) 𝑒( 𝑦 )

𝑒( 𝑦 ) 𝑒( 𝑦 )]

πœ™ ( )[𝑔 (𝑦 ) 𝑒( 𝑦 )

𝑒( 𝑦 ) 𝑒( 𝑦 )

𝑔 (𝑦 ) 𝑒( 𝑦 )

𝑒( 𝑦 ) 𝑒( 𝑦 )] πœ“ ( )[

𝑔 (𝑦 ) 𝑒( 𝑦 )

𝑒( 𝑦 ) 𝑒( 𝑦 )

𝑔 (𝑦 ) 𝑒( 𝑦 )

𝑒( 𝑦 ) 𝑒( 𝑦 )]

Thus, the ( ) in the interpolation independence condition for utility functions of the

form (2.14) and (2.6) depends on both , which does not satisfy being II . β–‘

Theorem 2.2. If the preference of a DM satisfies the (relative) risk independence

condition on at any level of , and if she feels indifferent between two binary lotteries

( ) and ( ) which have the same means for any , then the preference

of this DM satisfies the condition that BLII .

Proof: We prove the case when the risk independence condition on can be

Page 67: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

55

verified. The case for the relative risk independence condition can be proved by

following a similar idea.

For a two-attribute utility function ( ), if we can verify the risk independence

condition on for any , the utility function ( ) can be decomposed into the

standard risk-value model on (theorem 3 Jia and Dyer 1996).

( ) ( ) ( )[ ( ) ( )]

When the utility function is continuously differentiable, we know the two-attribute utility

function ( ) is of the form either ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) or ( )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ), where ( ), ( ), ( ), and ( ) are functions of

(theorem 4 Jia and Dyer 1996).

For the exponential function, in section 2.5, we show that

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) [ ( )( ) 1] ( )

If the DM feels indifferent between two lotteries ( ) { ( ) (1 ) ( )}

and ( ) { ( ) (1 ) ( )} which have the same mean for

any , by equating the expected utility of these two lotteries in term of the above risk-

value model, we have ( ) ( ) for any , which further implies that :

( ) 3 (1 ) ( ) ( ) (1 ) ( )

for any . This only happens when ( ) is a constant. To see the reason, we define

𝐹( ) ( ) 3 (1 ) ( ) ( ) (1 ) ( ) . From the equation

Page 68: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

56

above, we know 𝐹( ) for any . Thus, it must be that 𝐹( ) for any ,

which implies the following identity for any

𝐹( )

( )

[

( ) 3 (1 ) ( )

( ) (1

) ( ) ]

Since we know ( ) 3 (1 ) ( ) ( ) (1 ) ( ) for

any , it is impossible that ( ) 3 (1 )

( ) ( ) (1

) ( ) for any , unless which is not true. Thus, it must

be that 𝑑 ( )

𝑑 , which implies that ( ) .

In this case, the exponential function becomes ( ) ( ) ( )

( ). With Lemma 2.1 proved below, we can conclude that both the quadratic function

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) and the exponential function ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) satisfy the condition BLII .

Lemma 2.1. If both ( ) and ( ) in ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) are

monotonic and there exists a strictly concave transformation 𝐹: β†’ between ( )

and ( ), then the preference represented by function ( ) satisfies BLII .

Proof: The condition that BLII is equivalent to the condition that for any

( ) there exist probabilities and for either 2 3 or

3 2 such that

Page 69: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

57

( ) (1 ) ( ) ( ) (1 ) ( )

for any holds. To prove this, we can prove that there always exits constants (may not

be probabilities) and such that the above equation holds under the conditions in

Lemma 2.1.

By substituting ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) into the above equation,

we can verify that this equation is equivalent to the condition that there exist constants

and such that the following two equations hold simultaneously for {2 3}

{2 3}\ . This is always true as there exist unique solution to this equation system. But, we

do not know whether the constants and can be interpreted as probabilities.

( ) (1 ) ( ) ( ) (1 ) ( ) (2.19)

( ) (1 ) ( ) ( ) (1 ) ( ) (2.20)

To show they are probabilities, we consider all the possible cases, namely (1) all

the coefficients (1 ) (1 ) are positive; (2) one of them is negative; (3) two

of them are negative on each side; (4) three of them are negative. Among these cases, by

moving the negative terms to the other side of the equation, (1) is equivalent to (3), and

(2) is equivalent to (4).

In the cases (1), if we multiply (2.19) by ( ) and (2.20) by ( ) and sum

them together, we have ( ) (1 ) ( ) ( ) (1 ) ( ). As

the constants in this equation are all positive, they can be interpreted as probabilities,

Page 70: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

58

which implies that BLII .

Now, we prove (2) and (4) are impossible under the conditions in the Lemma 2.1.

To show this, without loss of generality, we assume ( ) is more concave than ( ), so

we have 𝐹( ( )) ( ) for a concave function 𝐹 . Denote ( ) for

1 2 3. (2.19) and (2.20) become (1 ) (1 ) and 𝐹( )

(1 )𝐹( ) 𝐹( ) (1 )𝐹( ). If case (2) holds (if (4) holds, we convert it to

(2)), suppose (1 ) , these two equations become

π‘ž

π‘ž

( )

; 𝐹( )

π‘ž

𝐹( )

( π‘ž)

𝐹( )

( )

𝐹( )

As π‘ž

( π‘ž)

( )

1 , the above two equation imply that the certainty

equivalent of a lottery equals to its mathematical expectation under a concave utility

function 𝐹( ), which is impossible. β–‘

Proposition 2.2. is second degree discrete distribution independent of if and only if

is utility independent of .

Proof: By definition 2.3, the condition that being second degree discrete

distribution independent of is equivalent to the existence of ( ) such that

( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( )) ( ) for any and any

; and the condition that being utility independent of is equivalent to

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) f r any and .

Page 71: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

59

β€œβ‡’β€ Given the second degree discrete distribution independence ( )

( ) ( ) (1 ( )) ( ) , we have ( ) ( ) ( ) (1

( )) ( ) . To prove ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) holds, we can substitute

( ) and ( ) given by the discrete distribution independence condition into the

utility independence condition to get

( ) ( ) (1 ( )) ( )

( )[ ( ) ( ) (1 ( )) (

)] ( )

Which is equivalent to

( )[ ( ) ( )] ( )

( ) ( )[ ( ) (

)] ( ) ( ) ( )

If we define ( ) [ ( ) ( )] [ ( ) (

)] and ( )

( ) ( ) ( ), the above affine transformation relationship always holds.

Thus, given being second degree discrete distribution independent of , there exist

( ) and ( ) such that ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ).

β€œ ⇐ ” Given ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) , we have ( )

( ) ( ) ( ) and ( ) ( ) (

) ( ).

Suppose for some ( ) , ( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( )) ( ) is

equivalent to

Page 72: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

60

( ) ( ) ( )

( )[ ( ) ( ) ( )] (1 ( ))[ ( ) (

) ( )]

[ ( ) ( ) (1 ( )) (

)] ( ) ( )

Thus, for ( ) such that ( ) ( ) (1 ( )) (

) ( ), the

relationship ( ) ( ) ( ) (1 ( )) ( ) always holds.β–‘

Theorem 2.3. is th degree discrete distribution independent of if and only if the

utility function can be decomposed by (2.11) on a bounded domain [ ] [

].

Proof. This theorem can be proved by following the same reasoning in the proof

for Theorem 2.1. β–‘

Proposition 2.3. being th order convex independent of implies being (

2)th degree discrete distribution independent of .

Proof: From being th order convex independent of , we know that

( | ) βˆ‘ ( ) ( | ) (1 βˆ‘ ( )

) ( | ). By choosing arbitrarily many

different values of 1 2 2, we can have a by 2 matrix shown

below.

Page 73: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

61

(

( | ) ( | ) ( | )

( | ) ( | ) ( | )

( | ) ( | ) ( | )

( | ) ( | ) ( | ) ( | ) ( | ) ( | )

β‹± ( | ) ( | ) ( | )

( | ) ( | ) ( | )

( | ) ( | ) ( | ) ( | ) )

So, being th order convex independent of implies that the column vectors

are linearly dependent in the matrix. Thus, the rank of this ( 2) matrix must be

< 2. In the matrix, the column rank = row rank. Thus, the 2 rows in the matrix

must be linearly dependent, which means one row vector can be linearly expressed as a

combination of the other 1 row vectors. This is consistent with the definition of

being ( 2) th degree discrete distribution independent of , i.e., ( | )

βˆ‘ ( ) ( | ) . Thus, we can conclude that being th order convex independent

of implies being ( 2)th degree discrete distribution independent of . This

completes the poof.

But, the converse may not be true. If we know 2 rows are linearly dependent

from ( | ) βˆ‘ ( ) ( | ) , we know the 2 columns must be linearly

dependent, but we cannot prove the linear combination is a convex combination in

( | ) βˆ‘ ( ) ( | ) (1 βˆ‘ ( )

) ( | ). This gives the intuition why

our condition is more general than the convex independence condition. β–‘

Page 74: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

62

2.8.2. Verification of the BLII condition for utility functions satisfying mutual risk

independence

In this subsection, we assume a specific utility function for a DM and show how

to find a pair of lotteries required by Theorem 2.2 to verify the BLII condition.

Suppose the DM still faces the same retirement pension investment decision

problem described in section 2.3. But this time, we assume that the DM has a utility

function of the form ( ) (1 ) (2 ), which has been rescaled

such that ( ) [ 1] [ 1] and ( ) [ 1]. This function is from Table 2.3 at

the end of this section, and can be decomposed into standard risk value models on both

attributes.

After we verify the risk independence condition on , we pick four arbitrary

levels on the wealth attribute and one level on health . For example, we pick

1 , and 2 . Then, we ask

the DM to elicit three probabilities as we did when verifying the BLII in section 2.3. So,

we replace the values of and in Figure 2.3 with and

assumed here to elicit 𝑃 𝑃 𝑃 .

Suppose the DM announces these probabilities according to her utility function

assumed above. We can obtain the following probabilities.

𝑃 (2 ) 𝑃 (2 ) 𝑃 (2 ) 3

After we elicit these probabilities, we can have an equation for and by using (2.1).

Page 75: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

63

𝑃 (2 ) 𝑃 (2 ) 𝑃 (2 )

From the relationships π‘ž

and

π‘ž

in section 2.2, this equation can be written

as

𝑃 (2 )

𝑃 (2 )

1

𝑃 (2 )

Now, we can require the means of the two lotteries on in (2.1) to be equal,

and set up another equation for and . Replacing in (2.1) with

, we have

(1 ) (1 )

By substituting the values of 1

and 𝑃 (2 ) 𝑃 (2 ) 𝑃 (2 ) 3 into the

above two equations, we can solve for

and

9

. Thus, we have the following

relationship from (2.1) for the values of and chosen here.

( )

9

( )

9

( )

8

( )

We can rearrange the above equation to obtain

( )

8

( )

9

( )

9

( )

Since

8

9

9

, we can divide both sides by

and have

8

( )

8

( )

9

( )

8

( )

Page 76: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

64

Thus, we know the DM is indifferent between the following two lotteries, which

have the same expected value on .

Figure 2.6: Two indifferent lotteries with same expected values

After we find a pair of lottery that are indifferent at 2 with the same

expected value on , we only need to ask one further question to verify that BLII .

We present the above lotteries we found to the DM and ask β€œif the health level 2

is changed to any other values, will you still feel indifferent between the two lotteries?”

Under the assumed utility function, the DM can verify she is always indifferent between

these two lotteries. So, we can confirm that her utility function satisfies the BLII

condition.

( π‘š 2 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ)

( π‘š 2 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ)

2

11

11

(οΏ½οΏ½ 2 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ) ∼ (οΏ½οΏ½ 2 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ)

( π‘š 2 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ)

( 1π‘š 2 π‘„π΄πΏπ‘Œ)

11

1

11

οΏ½οΏ½ οΏ½οΏ½

Page 77: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

65

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( )( ) ( ( ) )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( ( ) )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( )

( ) ( )( ) ( ( ) )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( )

( ) ( ( ) )( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( ( ) )( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( )

( ) ( ( ) )( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ) ( )( )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ( ) )( ( ) )

( ) ( ( ) )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( )

( ) ( )( )

( ) ( ( ) )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( ( ) )

( ) ( )( )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ) ( ( ) )

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( )

Table 2.3: Mutual Risk-Value decomposable utility functions which mutually satisfy

BLII

Page 78: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

66

CHAPTER 3. ON THE AXIOMATIZATION OF THE

SATIATION AND HABIT FORMATION UTILITY MODELS

3.1. INTRODUCTION

The discounted utility (DU) model proposed by Samuelson (1937) has been a

dominant model of intertemporal choice for about half a century. One of the main reasons

can be attributed to the seminal work by Koopmans (1960) who showed that the model

could be derived from a set of appealing axioms. However, even Samuelson and

Koopmans had some reservations about the descriptive validity of the model (Frederick

et al. 2002). There have been a number of documented experiments challenging the

validity of the DU model as a descriptive model in the last two decades (Frederick et al.

2002). One of the primary mechanisms to improve the descriptive validity of the DU

model is to relax the independence axiom to allow past consumption to influence the

experienced utility derived from the current consumption. Prior consumption could

influence preference over current and future consumption in two distinct ways: habit

formation and satiation (Read et al. 1999).

During the last few decades, several models have been proposed to capture the

effect of habit formation on the utility derived from consumption (experienced utility) in

each period (e.g. Pollak 1970, Wathieu 1997 2004, Carroll et al. 2000). Lichtendahl et al.

(2011) showed that a correlation averse DM will exhibit habit-like consumption behavior

where the optimal consumption in each period depends on the consumption levels in past

Page 79: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

67

periods. Rozen (2010) axiomatized a habit formation model with linear habit functions

over an infinite time horizon.

The satiation effect on intertemporal utility functions has been modeled by

relatively few studies compared to habit formation (Bell 1974, Baucells and Sarin 2007).

Satiation captures the psychological phenomenon that people may feel satisfied by

previous consumption, so additional consumption of the commodity in the current period

provides less incremental utility. In short, habit formation may cause people to become

addicted to a previously consumed commodity, while satiation may lead to boredom due

to previous consumption. Each effect results from different influences of the past

consumption experience on current and future consumption.

Synthesizing ideas from the habit formation model (Wathieu 1997) and the

satiation model (Baucells and Sarin 2007), Baucells and Sarin (2010) proposed a hybrid

model of habit formation and satiation (HS) that combines the influence of both effects of

past consumption on the experienced utility in each period. This model assumes the

overall utility from a consumption stream can be represented by the following function.

( ) βˆ‘ [ ( ) ( )]

In the above utility function, ( ) , and ( ) and

( ) represent the satiation level and habit level in period respectively, both

of which depend on the past consumptions stream . The utility difference

Page 80: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

68

term ( ) ( ) is defined as experienced utility of period . We chose to

modify the original notation of Baucells & Sarin (2010) so that it is easier to recall each

symbol’s role in the model: we use for consumption rather than , for satiation

rather than , and for habit formation rather than . In their concluding remarks,

Baucells & Sarin (2010) identified the need for future research efforts to axiomatize the

habit formation (Ha) and satiation (Sa) model.

In this chapter, we propose a hierarchy of axioms to develop a General Habit

Formation and Satiation (GHS) model that can be reduced to either a General Satiation

(GSa) model or a General Habit Formation (GHa) model. These general models allow

more flexible functional forms for the satiation function and the habit formation

function . By assuming further restrictive axioms, we obtain models with a recursively

defined linear satiation function and a linear habit function .

The mathematical form of our habit formation model is similar to the model

axiomatized by Rozen (2010), but the behavioral assumptions underlying the preference

conditions are different. In Rozen’s theory, the main axiom is based on the concept of

compensation for the consumption under the assumption of ordinal preference, while the

main axiom in our paper is based on shifting the measurable value function that is used to

compare the strength of preference over consumption streams under the assumption of

cardinal preference. Our GHS model is axiomatized over a finite horizon which is

consistent with Wathieu’s (1997) assertion that it is essential for the habit formation

model to be finite (see section 3 Wathieu 1997).

Page 81: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

69

The reminder of the chapter is organized as follows. In section 3.2, we formally

define the main preference condition used to axiomatize the models in a measurable

preference context, which we refer to as shifted difference independence, and discuss the

implication of this condition. In section 3.3, we axiomatize a General Satiation (GSa)

model, which contains Baucells and Sarin’s satiation model (2007) and Bell’s

intertemporal preference model (1974) as special cases. Section 3.4 focuses on the

axiomatization of the General Habit Formation and Satiation (GHS) model including a

discussion of more restrictive axioms that support the linear satiation and habit functions.

In section 3.5, we discuss how our theory can be applied to axiomatize these models in a

risky preference context. Section 3.6 concludes the paper. All the proofs are provided in

section 3.7.

3.2. SHIFTED DIFFERENCE INDEPENDENCE FOR A MEASURABLE VALUE FUNCTION

We first motivate the main preference condition used to axiomatize habit

formation and satiation with a two day consumption example. For this purpose, we

denote a two period consumption stream by ( ) , where the consumption

space in each period is the real set, i.e. : ℝ and : ℝ. Levels of consumption in

each period are denoted by lower case letters, and the date of consumption is denoted by

the subscript; e.g., denote four different consumption levels at time

{1 2}. We assume a measurable preference order (Fishburn 1970, Krantz et al. 1971,

Dyer and Sarin 1979) over the set of consumption streams . The theory of

measurable preference assumes that a DM can not only compare two alternatives, but

Page 82: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

70

also can compare her strength of preference over exchanges of alternatives. This

measurable preference is essentially a binary relation on ( ) ( ). The

expression ( )( ) ( )( ) means that the strength of preference for

the exchange from ( ) to ( ) is greater than or equal to that from ( ) to

( ).

We assume the existence of a measurable value function ( ) to represent

in the sense that ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) if and only if

( )( ) ( )( ). Given this measurable preference order , we can

define the ordinal preference order on by requiring that ( ) ( ) if

and only if ( )( ) ( )( ) for any ( ) ( ) ( )

(see Dyer and Sarin 1979). Then, this ordinal preference order is also represented by

in that ( ) ( ) if and only if ( ) ( ) . Finally, we also

define the strict and indifference preference relations, , ∼ , and ∼, in the standard

way in the literature (Fishburn 1970, Krantz et al. 1971). There are different methods in

the literature to elicit the strength of preference and we refer readers to Farquhar and

Keller (1989) for a detailed discussion on this topic.

To motivate our new preference condition, let us first consider the following

example for consumption over two time periods. Assume a new cupcake vendor has

opened near your office. You are asked to evaluate streams of cupcake consumption over

two days. You may feel that your preference for consumption on day 2 may be influenced

by your consumption on day 1. To obtain more insight into your preference for cupcake

Page 83: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

71

consumption, you can compare a pair of consumption exchanges: from ( 2) to ( 3)

and from (1 2) to (1 3). In the first exchange, you plan to consume ( 2) but you have

an opportunity to exchange it for ( 3); in the second exchange, you plan to consume

(1 2) but you have an opportunity to exchange it for (1 3). After considering the two

situations, you ask yourself whether the value increase from the first exchange is larger or

smaller than that from the second exchange. The answer to this question may be different

in the following three cases.

First, it is possible that you feel the exchange from ( 2) to ( 3) produces a

larger satisfaction increase than the exchange from (1 2) to (1 3). In both

exchanges, the number of cupcakes on day 2 increases from 2 to 3, but consuming

1 cupcake on day 1 causes you to assign less value to the additional cupcake on

day 2 due to satiation. If we assume decreasing marginal utility for additional

cupcakes, we can create a new exchange from ( 2 π›₯ 𝑠) to ( 3 π›₯

𝑠) that

produces the same satisfaction as the increase from (1 2) to (1 3) for some

π›₯ 𝑠 . This quantity π›₯

𝑠 shifts the measurable value function to the left

(see Figure 3.1 A and B).

Second, if you develop a habit of consuming cupcakes after your first day of

consumption, you might feel that the exchange from ( 2) to ( 3) produces a

smaller satisfaction increase than the exchange from (1 2) to (1 3). In this case,

the higher consumption level on day 1 leads to the formation of a higher habit

level. A higher habit level causes a stronger craving for consumption on day 2,

Page 84: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

72

which makes the same increase on day 2 produce a larger value given the higher

consumption level of day 1. Following the analogy from the satiation case, we

may create a new consumption exchange from ( 2 π›₯ ) to ( 3 π›₯

) such

that the exchange from (1 2) to (1 3) is equivalent to an exchange from

( 2 π›₯ ) to ( 3 π›₯

) for some π›₯ . This quantity π›₯

also shifts

the measurable value function to the right (See Figure 3.1 C and D).

Third, it is also possible that both the satiation and the habit formation from the

day 1 consumption affect your preference over day 2 consumption. In this case, a

higher consumption on day 1 will have two opposing influences on your

preference for consumption on day 2, and the net effect is determined by the

relative strength of satiation compared to habit formation. If the effect of satiation

is stronger, more consumption on day 1 can decrease your satisfaction derived

from the same increase of day 2 consumption; otherwise increased consumption

may increase your satisfaction. In other words, you may feel an exchange from

(1 2) to (1 3) is equivalent to an exchange from ( 2 π›₯ ) to ( 3 π›₯ ) for

either π›₯ or π›₯ . In a special case, when the effect of satiation equals to

that of the habit formation, or if neither effect is present, π›₯ and the

measurable value function is not shifted.

Page 85: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

73

Figure 3.1: Shifting value function under satiation and habit formation

After verifying the existence of the shifting quantity π›₯ in the above example, if

you can further determine that the π›₯ produced by satiation and habit formation only

depends on the change of the consumption levels on day 1, i.e. from 0 to 1, and is

𝑉(1 3) 𝑉(1 2) 𝑉( 3 π›₯

𝑠) 𝑉( 2 π›₯

𝑠)

𝑉( 3) 𝑉( 2)

𝑉( 𝑐 )

𝑐

2

3

𝑉( 𝑐 )

𝑐

2

3

π›₯ 𝑠

𝑉(1 𝑐 ) A B

Satiation

Shifting quantity

π›₯ 𝑠

𝑉( 3) 𝑉( 2)

𝑉( 𝑐 )

𝑐

2

3

𝑉(1 3) 𝑉(1 2)

𝑉( 3 π›₯ )

𝑉( 2 π›₯ )

𝑉( 𝑐 )

𝑐

2

3

𝑉(1 𝑐 ) C D

Habit Formation

π›₯

Shifting quantity

π›₯ <0

Page 86: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

74

independent of the increase in consumption on day 2, your measurable preference

satisfies a more general condition called shifted difference independence which we

formalize as follows.

Definition 3.1. is said to be shifted difference independent of if for any

, there exists π›₯ ( ) ℝ such that for any , ( π›₯ ( ))

( π›₯ ( )) ∼ ( )( ).

This condition captures all three of the cases discussed in the example above.

When π›₯ ( ) is equal to zero, shifted difference independence is reduced to the

difference independence condition (Dyer and Sarin 1979), which implies an additive

multiattribute value function. The shifted difference independence condition also implies

that the value function ( ) has an additive structure, i.e., it is time separable. To

see this, we can write the preference relation assumed in the condition above in terms of

the measurable value function as ( ) ( ) ( π›₯ ( ))

( π›₯ ( )). This relation implies additive separability of the two attribute

measurable value function ( ) ( ) ( π›₯ ( ))

( π›₯ ( )) when and in the above relation. This is used as the main

axiom to obtain the additive structure of our satiation and habit formation model.

As we discussed in the cupcake example, under satiation, the effects of past

consumption may spill over into the current and future periods, and the decision maker

Page 87: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

75

may experience endowed consumption at a zero consumption level consistent with a left

shift of the value function. This endowed consumption can make the DM feel as if she

has already consumed an amount of the commodity due to her positive past consumption.

Because of this endowed consumption, the DM may become satiated leading to the

experienced utility on day 2 ( π›₯ 𝑠) (π›₯

𝑠) smaller than the experienced utility on

day 1 ( ) ( ) for the same consumption, namely ( π›₯ 𝑠) (π›₯

𝑠)

( ) when . Under habit formation, the DM has a desire to maintain a certain

amount of consumption due to past consumption. In this case, zero consumption is

perceived as a deprivation by the DM consistent with a right shift of the value function.

Deprivation produced by shifting the value function to right has also been discussed by

Hoch and Loewenstein (1991). Endowed consumption and deprivation are illustrated in

Figure 3.2.

Figure 3.2: Endowed consumption and deprivation under satiation and habit formation

𝑐

𝑣(𝑐 π›₯ 𝑠)

𝑣(𝑐 π›₯ )

𝑣(π›₯ 𝑠) 𝑣( )

Endowed consumption

𝑣( ) 𝑣(π›₯ )

Deprivation

Right shifted value function under

habit formation Left shifted value function

under satiation

( )

Page 88: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

76

When both satiation and habit formation are present, the shifting quantity π›₯

reflects the net effect of both satiation and habit formation resulting from first period

consumption. This quantity assumed in the shifted difference independence condition can

be elicited by asking a DM to compare the strength of preference over the same exchange

on day 2 consumption conditioned on different levels of day 1 consumption. To

determine whether there is a habit formation effect on consumption in the second period,

the DM can be asked to identify a neutral consumption level in this period. The β€œneutral”

level of consumption in each period can be elicited by asking the DM to identify a

consumption level which makes her feel neither satisfied nor dissatisfied (Baucells and

Sarin 2010, Baucells et al. 2011). This is the consumption level that makes the

experienced utility in each period equal to zero, i.e., which is obtained by

setting ( ) ( ) . In our two period context, this β€œneutral”

consumption in the second period is denoted by ( ). The satiation level in the second

period is denoted by ( ) and π›₯ ( ) can be simply denoted by π›₯ ( ).

In the first case of the cupcake example, we considered a situation where there is

no habit formation effect, so π›₯ ( ) totally reflects the satiation effect, thus ( )

and π›₯ ( ) ( ). In the second case, we considered a situation where there is no

satiation effect ( ) so the shifting quantity only reflects the habit formation

effect, i.e. π›₯ ( ) ( ); the negative sign on ( ) reflects the opposite effects

of satiation and habit formation on measurable preference. In the third case, there are

both satiation and habit formation effects and π›₯ ( ) ( ) ( ) . Thus,

Page 89: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

77

increasing satiation ( ) can increase π›₯ ( ) and increasing habit formation ( )

can decrease π›₯ ( ).

In Table 3.1, we summarize different combinations of habit formation level and

satiation level corresponding to the GSa, GHa, and GHS models axiomatized in this

paper. The habit level ( ) can be either positive or zero corresponding to the case

where habit formation is present or not. For satiation, the function ( ) is also allowed

to be negative. Baucells and Sarin (2010) identified this case as craving caused by

accumulated unmet need.

( )

(No habit formation is present)

( )

(Habit formation is present )

( ) (No satiation is present)

No satiation and habit formation

(DU model)

π›₯ ( )

Habit formation only

(GHa model)

π›₯ ( ) ( )

( )

(Positive satiation is present)

Satiation only

(GSa model)

π›₯ ( ) ( )

Both satiation and habit

formation

(GHS model)

π›₯ ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) if ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) craving

(Negative satiation is present

when there is accumulated unmet

need)

Satiation only

(GSa model)

π›₯ ( ) ( )

Both satiation and habit

formation

(GHS model)

π›₯ ( ) ( ) ( )

Table 3.1: Effects from satiation and habit formation on the Delta quantity

3.3. A GENERAL SATIATION (GSA) MODEL

To axiomatize a general satiation (GSa) model, we consider the measurable

preference of a DM on a set of multiple period consumption streams on a finite discrete

time horizon {1 2 }. We denote the set of all the possible consumption levels in

period by ℝ, the set of consumption streams that last from period to period

Page 90: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

78

as 𝑠 𝑠 , the set of consumption streams from 1 to period as

, and the set of consumption streams from 1 to as

. The vectors

in these consumption stream sets are denoted by 𝑠: ( 𝑠) 𝑠 ,

( ) , and ( ) respectively. We use different lower

case letters to denote different realizations of . So, 𝑠: ( 𝑠)

𝑠 and 𝑠: ( 𝑠) 𝑠 are two different consumption streams over the same

time horizon. The same lower letter with different subscripts, e.g., and 𝑠, should be

interpreted as realizations of consumption in different periods, which may or may not be

equal to each other. We use 𝑠 ( 𝑠) to denote zero consumption streams and

𝑠 .

The measurable preference order on the consumption set is assumed to

be represented by a continuously differentiable measurable value function

( ). To state our axioms, we extend the shifted difference independence

condition defined for a two period consumption space in the previous section to

conditional shifted difference independence for a multiple period consumption space,

where the future consumption is conditioned at a specific level when we shift the value

function.

Definition 3.2. is said to be conditional shifted difference independent of given

, if for any there exists shifting quantity π›₯ ( )

Page 91: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

79

which is independent of the future consumption after period such that βˆ€

, ( )( ) ∼ ( π›₯ ( ) )(

π›₯ ( ) ).

Now, we present our first axiom for the GSa model.

Axiom 3.1. (Satiation) For any {2 } , is conditional shifted difference

independent of with shifting quantity π›₯ ( ) defined in Definition 3.2,

given that .

This axiom says that given zero consumption levels in the future, the past

consumption levels produce an effect on the strength of preference at time only

through shifting the value function of the preference at period . Conditioning the

strength of preference comparison on zero future consumption levels allows the

possibility of non-negative consumption streams of different length. For a cupcake

consumption problem similar to the one in section 3.2 with more than two consumption

periods, this axiom assumes that when any period is evaluated as the last period of a

consumption stream, the changes in the previous consumption levels affect the preference

over the last period consumption by shifting its value function according to the

magnitude of the previous changes. For a DM whose preference satisfies the two period

condition described in the cupcake example in section 3.2, it is likely that her preference

may also satisfy the condition assumed in this axiom if she believes that extending a two

Page 92: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

80

period choice problem to a three (or more) period horizon would not change the way she

compares the consumption streams.

By shifting the value function to the left, the DM evaluates the consumption in the

last period on a flatter part of the value function. The shifting quantity in this axiom

works as a satiation level which depends on the past consumption: the more you feel

satiated from past consumption, the less you value the same consumption in the last

period of your consumption stream. In the Appendix, we show that by assuming the

existence of satiation for the last consumption period we can recursively prove the

existence of satiation for all previous periods.

Figure 3.3 depicts Axiom 3.1 by assuming that the past consumption stream is

changed from a zero vector to a non-negative vector. In the GSa model, the shifting

quantity π›₯ ( ) only reflects the satiation level, so we define a satiation function

as ( ) π›₯ ( ).

Figure 3.3: The shifted value function in the Satiation Axiom

𝑉( 𝑑 𝑐𝑑 𝑑 )

𝐢𝑑 𝐢𝑑

𝑉(𝑐𝑑 𝑐𝑑 𝑑 )

𝐢𝑑

𝐢𝑑

𝑉(𝑐𝑑 π‘₯𝑑 𝑑 )

𝑉(𝑐𝑑 𝑑 )

𝐢𝑑 π‘₯𝑑

𝑉( 𝑑 π‘₯𝑑 𝑠𝑑(𝑐𝑑 ) 𝑑 )

𝑉( 𝑑 𝑠𝑑(𝑐𝑑 ) 𝑑 )

𝑠𝑑(𝑐𝑑 ) 𝑠𝑑(𝑐𝑑 ) π‘₯𝑑 𝑠𝑑(𝑐𝑑 )

Shifted value function

Page 93: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

81

This axiom allows the satiation level of the last period of a consumption stream to

depend on all the previous consumption levels, or to depend only on a subset of the

previous periods’ consumption levels. Therefore, this axiom allows a situation where the

satiation may decay very quickly with the passage of time, with ( ) ( )

being the extreme case.

The second axiom for the GSa model is presented as follows.

Axiom 3.2. (Time Invariance) βˆ€ {1 } , for any 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 ,

( 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 )( 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 ) ( 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 ) ( 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 ) if and only if

( ) ( ) ( )( ) when 𝑠 , 𝑠

, 𝑠 , and 𝑠 for any {1 }. Moreover, βˆ€ {1 } and ,

if ( ) ∼ ( ) for some , then ( ) ∼

( ) when and .

The first part of this axiom states that, for a one period consumption stream, if the

strength of preference for 𝑠 over 𝑠 is greater or equal to that for 𝑠 over 𝑠 in period

when the consumption levels in other periods are zeros, the strength of preference

should be unchanged if the same consumption levels are compared in any other time

period {1 } given that you consume nothing at time periods other than . The

second part of the time invariance axiom simply assumes that if two levels of

consumption at two different periods are indifferent, they should be perceived to be

Page 94: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

82

indifferent when the consumption in both periods is advanced by the same amount of

time.

The spirit of this time invariance axiom has been assumed in other time

preference models. For instance, the first part of our axiom is a version of an

independence condition which says that the strength of preference comparison between

two exchanges is independent of the time index. In the time preference literature,

outcome monotonicity is usually assumed to axiomatize preference models (Fishburn and

Rubinstein 1982, Baucells and Heukamp 2012). Outcome monotonicity implies that the

outcome attribute is preferentially independent of the time attribute, but not vice versa.

So, outcome monotonicity is a special case of the more general independence condition.

The second part is similar to the assumption of stationarity of preference (Fishburn and

Rubinstein 1982, Baucells and Heukamp 2012).

Finally, the third axiom is about the impatience of preferences.

Axiom 3.3. (Impatience) For any {1 1} when for some

and , ( ) ( ).

This impatience axiom is also called time monotonicity and allows the

discounting of the value function in each period in the model. Fishburn and Rubinstein

(1982) and Baucells and Heukamp (2012) also assume impatience.

Page 95: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

83

Based on the Axioms 3.1, 3.2, and 3.3, we can show that there exists a general

satiation (GSa) model for the value function ( ) over all possible

consumption profiles.

Theorem 3.1. Axioms 3.1, 3.2, and 3.3 hold if and only if the measurable preference

over the consumption streams can be represented by the following model,

with [ 1]

( ) βˆ‘ [ ( ( )) ( ( ))]

where ( ): β†’ is called the satiation function with ( ) and

( ) .

Other models in the literature are special cases of this more general satiation

model (GSa). When the satiation function ( ) is always zero, i.e., ( ) , the

above model is equivalent to the DU model proposed by Koopmans (1960). When

( ) ( ( ) ), the GSa model is reduced to the Satiation Model (Sa)

proposed by Baucells and Sarin (2007). When ( ) ( ) , the GSa is

equivalent to the model proposed by Bell (1974).

In this section, we axiomatized the GSa model by assuming shifted difference

independence on consumption streams. In the next section, we show that the idea used in

this section can be extended to axiomatize a model with both satiation and habit

Page 96: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

84

formation. We also show that stronger forms of the shifted difference independence

imply linear satiation and habit formation functions in our framework.

3.4. HABIT FORMATION AND SATIATION MODEL WITH LINEAR HABIT AND SATIATION

FUNCTIONS

3.4.1. A general habit formation and satiation (GHS) model

Baucells and Sarin (2010) proposed a hybrid model of habit formation and

satiation (HS) which inherits the characteristics from both the satiation model and the

habit formation model. In this subsection, we propose axioms that are necessary and

sufficient for a general habit formation and satiation (GHS) model which admits general

functional forms for both satiation and habit formation. In the next subsection, we

provide stronger preference conditions to axiomatize linear satiation and habit formation

functions.

We consider a horizon with periods as the life time of a DM. In this horizon,

past consumption experience can develop into a consumption habit which has an

influence on the experienced utility. However, the habit developed from past

consumption may not last to the end of the life horizon. It is possible that the habit can be

β€œreset” (Wathieu 1997) or changed for some reason, either subjective or objective, such

that it only takes effect on finite periods less than . For example, a consumer may

develop a habit of drinking a glass of iced tea during lunch in a hot summer season, but

she may reset this habit and switch to drinking a glass of coffee during lunch when the

Page 97: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

85

cold winter comes. Here the habit developed from consuming iced tea during lunch in a

hot summer does not last until the end of , and it is terminated due to the change of the

season. In the context of habit formation, when the habit can only last for a number of

periods less than , this number of periods can influence the preference of a DM.

For simplicity, we consider a DM who consumes iced tea on a four period life

horizon , where each period is one day. Suppose the DM is evaluating a

consumption stream (2 2 2 ), where she consumes two glasses of iced tea on each of the

first three days but zero glasses of iced tea on the fourth day. Her satisfaction derived

from this consumption stream depends on how long the habit lasts. If all four days occur

during the warmer fall season, zero consumption on the fourth day will be perceived as

deprivation since the DM has established a habit for consumption of iced tea. However, if

the habit only lasts to the third day because the fourth day marks the start of winter, the

DM may reset her habit of consuming iced tea and initiate a habit for consumption of

coffee. In this case, the consumption of zero glasses of iced tea on the fourth day will be

perceived as neutral. We distinguish the number of periods a habit can last from the

number of periods in the life horizon by calling the former concept a habit horizon.

We need a richer set of consumption streams to accommodate the impact of the

different habit horizons on preference. Specifically, we use vectors with different lengths

to denote different habit horizons. We assume that the consumption levels are zeros after

the habit horizon is over until . For instance, ( ) denotes the consumption stream

on a two period habit horizon with zero consumption in future periods until the end of the

Page 98: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

86

life horizon ; while ( ) denotes a consumption stream with the same

consumption levels in each period but with a three period habit horizon. These two

consumption streams could be perceived differently in the habit formation context.

Formally, on a life horizon with periods, we denote a consumption stream with

a period habit horizon with non-negative consumption levels up to period and zero

levels after period by ( ). Comparatively, a consumption stream with

a 1 period habit horizon with non-negative consumption levels up to period and

zero levels after period is denoted by ( ) ( ). The set of all

consumption streams with habit horizon and 1 are denoted by and

respectively. Now, we define a set of consumption streams with all possible habit

horizons {1 2 } by ⋃ . We assume that there exists a measurable

preference order on this set which is represented by a continuously differentiable

measurable value function : β†’ ℝ . Thus, unlike the traditional theory where

preference is assumed on a set of vectors with the same dimension, our theory assumes a

preference order on a set of vectors with dimensions varying from 1 to , which

contains all vectors of the form {( ) ( ) ( ) ( )}. This setup,

where a preference order is assumed on a set of vectors with different lengths, is also

employed by Gilboa and Schmeidler (2001) to axiomatize a habit formation model with

linear utility functions in each period.

Page 99: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

87

As we argued above in the iced tea example, in the context of habit formation, a

DM will perceive the iced tea consumption stream (2 2 2) to be different from the

consumption stream (2 2 2 ). Since the DM will perceive deprivation from the zero

consumption in (2 2 2 ), she will prefer the first consumption stream to the second one,

i.e., (2 2 2) (2 2 2 ). Thus, by increasing the consumption level in the fourth period

of the second stream, we can find a quantity defined as the neutral consumption level

such that the DM feels (2 2 2) ∼ (2 2 2 ) . This quantity is the habit level that

makes the DM feel neutral under habit formation for consumption on a four period habit

horizon that is otherwise identical to the corresponding consumption stream on a three

period habit horizon.

We present our first axiom about the neutral consumption level for the GHS

model below.

Axiom 3.4. (Neutral Consumption) For any {1 1} and any , there exists

( ) ℝ such that ∼ ( ( )).

Axiom 3.4 assumes the existence of the neutral consumption level in the habit

formation context, which is also assumed by Gilboa and Schmeidler (2001). In a special

case, when there is no habit formation effect, ( ) for any and , ∼

( ), which is equivalent to the case of satiation only discussed in the previous

section.

Page 100: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

88

Axiom 3.5. (Satiation and Habit Formation) For any {2 }, the last period

consumption of is shifted difference independent of the past consumption.

Axiom 3.5 says that the strength of preference for the last period of any habit

horizon is not altered by exchanging the past consumption levels from to if

the value function in the last period of a habit horizon is shifted by π›₯ ( ).

Consider a multiple period cupcake consumption example where both satiation and habit

formation may impact preferences. The Satiation and Habit Formation axiom assumes

that no matter how long the habit horizon may last, the cupcakes consumed in previous

periods will produce an effect on the preference over the cupcakes consumed in the last

period of a habit horizon by shifting the value function. Although the changes in the past

consumption levels shift the value function in multiple future consumption periods up

to the end of the habit horizon, the Satiation and Habit Formation axiom only dictates

how the changes in past consumption influence the value function in the last period of a

habit horizon.

In the appendix, we prove that this condition is sufficient to show that all the

previous periods of a habit horizon are also subject to this shifting of the value function

induced by the changes of the past consumption levels. Again, a DM may think about a

simple two-period version of the cupcake example where the habit formed from the first

period consumption has an effect on her preference over the second period through

shifting the value function. If she can verify that the shifting quantity exists for the two

Page 101: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

89

period case, she may also have reason to believe that her preference should satisfy the

multiple period extension implied by the Satiation and Habit Formation axiom. In this

axiom, the shifting quantity π›₯ reflects the net effect on the value function produced by

both satiation and habit formation from the past consumption, so we refer to π›₯ as the

adjustment function in the rest of this paper.

Two additional axioms are based on the same motivation as the time invariance

and impatience axioms assumed in the previous section. The only difference is that in this

section we focus on non-zero consumption in the final period of a habit horizon.

Axiom 3.6. (Time Invariance) βˆ€ {1 } , for any 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 ,

( 𝑠 𝑠)( 𝑠 𝑠) ( 𝑠 𝑠) ( 𝑠 𝑠) if and only if

( )( ) ( ) ( ) when 𝑠 , 𝑠 , 𝑠 , and

𝑠 for any {1 } . Moreover, βˆ€ {1 }and if ( ) ∼

( ) for some , then ( ) ∼ ( ) when

and .

Axiom 3.7. (Impatience) For any {1 1} when for some

and , ( ) ( ).

Page 102: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

90

The following theorem states that the above four axioms are necessary and

sufficient to derive a GHS model for the measurable preference represented by

( ).

Theorem 3.2. Axioms 3.4, 3.5, 3.6, and 3.7 hold if and only if the measurable preference

on can be represented by the following model, βˆ€ {1 } for any ,

( ) βˆ‘ 𝑠 [ ( 𝑠 𝑠( 𝑠 ) 𝑠( 𝑠 )) ( 𝑠( 𝑠 ))]

𝑠

and 𝑠( 𝑠 ): 𝑠 β†’ ℝ , 𝑠( 𝑠 ): 𝑠 β†’ ℝ , with ( ) , ( ) ,

𝑠( 𝑠 ) , 𝑠( 𝑠 ) and [ 1].

As a general model that accounts for both satiation and habit formation, the GHS

model can be reduced to either the GHa or GSa model in our framework by requiring

more restrictive preference conditions. From the relation π›₯ ( ) ( )

( ), when π›₯ ( ) ( ) the satiation ( ) , and the GHS model is

reduced to GHa model.

To see how our GHS model can be reduced to a GSa model, we notice that the

main difference in the assumptions for the two models is that the consumption set

used to axiomatize GHS is a larger set that contains the consumption set used to

axiomatize GSa. The measurable preference on this larger set can be reduced to

the measurable preference on in section 3.3 when ∼ ( ) for any . If this

Page 103: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

91

relationship holds, different habit horizons do not influence preferences. The axioms in

this section are reduced to the corresponding axioms of the GSa model in section 3.3, and

the GHS model is reduced to the GSa model.

Finally, we compare the preference conditions we used in our paper to axiomatize

the GHS model with the preference conditions employed by Gilboa and Schmeidler

(2001) and by Rozen (2010). Our Axiom 3.4 is a condition similar to the neutral

continuation axiom proposed by Gilboa and Schmeidler (2001), which is used to

axiomatize a well-being model with a linear utility function in each period. Under some

conditions, their well-being model can also be interpreted as a consumption model with

habit formation. This neutral continuation condition is defined in the context of

consumption streams with different lengths, which provides a way to axiomatize the habit

level in each period.

In Rozen’s (2010) work on habit formation, each of the evaluated consumption

streams has the same infinite length. Thus, neutral continuation does not work in this

setup. Rozen (2010) introduced a condition called habit compensation for ordinal

preference. Our satiation and habit formation axiom is motivated by a similar idea

applied to the measurable strength of preference. In contrast to Rozen (2010), we also

permit the adjustment function π›₯ to be negative.

Shifted difference independence is defined for a measurable preference and

allows the adjustment function π›₯ to be either positive or negative. This is because we

also need to axiomatize a utility difference structure ( ) ( ) in order to

Page 104: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

92

model satiation in addition to habit formation. This utility difference is naturally

interpreted as a measure of strength of preference. Moreover, as both satiation and habit

formation are two independent effects, we employ both the neutral consumption (Axiom

3.4) and shifted difference independence (Axiom 3.5). Axiom 3.4 produces the habit

effect , and Axiom 3.5 produces the net shifting quantity π›₯ .

3.4.2. Linear habit and satiation functions

Linear habit functions have been widely assumed in different habit formation

utility models in the literature (Pollak 1970, Wathieu 1997, Carroll et al. 2000). Baucells

and Sarin (2007, 2010) also assume linear functions to model the habit formation and

satiation in their models. In the context of habit formation on an infinite horizon, Rozen

(2010) proposed a set of axioms that guarantee the existence of a linear functional form

for the habit function. However, we are not aware of any work on this topic in the context

of both habit formation and satiation. In this subsection, we propose a set of stronger

axioms that specify a linear habit formation and satiation model.

When axiomatizing linear satiation function in the GSa model, we assume a

preference order on the set as we did in section 3.3. Axioms 3.8 and 3.9 are

necessary and sufficient for a linear satiation function given by

( ) ( ( ) ) for any .

Page 105: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

93

Axiom 3.8. (Strong Shifted Difference Independence)

For any {1 }, βˆ€ , βˆ€ , and βˆ€ , there

exists a unique ( ) such that ( )( )

∼ ( ( ) )( ( ) ).

This axiom is stronger than the conditional shifted difference independence used

in Axiom 3.1, which only compares strength of preference over the last period of non-

zero consumption levels and assumes that the past consumption experience can only shift

the value function in the last period. In Axiom 3.8, the strength of preference is compared

in multiple periods. To illustrate, we return to the cupcake example in section 3.2 with

consumption streams of more than two periods; e.g., the DM may have a four period

consumption stream of cupcakes ( ) . For this four period consumption

problem, Axiom 3.8 states that if two consumption streams have the same level in period

1 but differ from period 2 on, the strength of preference over the two different streams is

unchanged under different period 1 consumption if the value function in period 2 is

shifted appropriately. In other words, it assumes that the past consumption levels before

period affect the future preference only through shifting the value function in period .

It is easy to verify that this is a necessary condition for the recursively defined linear

satiation function ( ) ( ( ) ) . But, to obtain the sufficient

condition for this satiation model, we also need the following assumption.

Page 106: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

94

Axiom 3.9. (Independence of Irrelevant Past Consumption)

For any and any 1 , if 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 , then

(( 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 ) ( 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 )) (( 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 ) ( 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 )) for

any 𝑠 𝑠.

This axiom says that if the two past consumption streams have the same

consumption level in some period , then the common consumption level in this period

does not affect how the value function is shifted in Axiom 3.8. In other words, the DM

only shifts the value function according to the changes in the past consumption levels; the

unchanged past consumption is irrelevant to the shifting of the value function. This is an

axiom similar to the one used by Rozen (2010) to axiomatize a linear habit formation

function. In our context, we show that the combination of Axiom 3.8 and Axiom 3.9 is

necessary and sufficient for the existence of a linear recursively defined satiation function

as in our GSa model.

Theorem 3.3. Under the assumption of the GSa model, Axioms 3.8 and 3.9 hold if and

only if the satiation function ( ) in the GSa model is recursively defined by

( ) ( ( ) ) for some ℝ and any {2 }.

This recursive satiation function reduces to the satiation function proposed by

Baucells and Sarin (2007, see equation (4)) when for any . With a given initial

Page 107: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

95

satiation level , the recursive relation implies a linear satiation function given by

the following formula.

For the GHS model, the preference order is assumed on the set as we did in

subsection 3.4.1. We need another version of the conditional shifted difference

independence condition to axiomatize linear habit formation and satiation.

Axiom 3.10. (Multiple Period Shifted Difference Independence) For any

{2 }, any , and any 𝑠 𝑠 𝑠 , there exists a unique vector

𝑠( ): ( ( ) ( ) 𝑠( )) 𝑠 such that

( 𝑠)( 𝑠) ∼ ( 𝑠 𝑠( )) ( 𝑠 𝑠( )).

Axiom 3.10 is stronger than Axiom 3.5 assumed in subsection 3.4.1; when ,

Axiom 3.10 reduces to Axiom 3.5. Unlike Axiom 3.5 which assumes that the changes in

the past consumption levels only shift the value function in the last period of a habit

horizon, Axiom 3.10 assumes that these changes can shift the value functions in multiple

future periods. In the cupcake example, if there are four periods in a habit horizon,

Axiom 3.10 assumes that the changes in consumption levels on days 1 and 2 can cause

the DM to shift her value functions on both days 3 and 4 such that her strength of

preference over the consumption levels on days 3 and 4 is unchanged. Furthermore, if the

habit horizon is extended, the following axiom assumes that this extension of the habit

Page 108: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

96

horizon will not change the 𝑠( ) in Axiom 3.10 on the shorter habit horizon

given that all consumption levels on the shorter habit horizon are unchanged.

Axiom 3.11. (Consistent Shifting) For any and

, 𝑠( ) is equal to ( ) from to { }.

Following the cupcake example, for a five day habit horizon, the changes in the

consumption levels on days 1 and 2 will cause the DM to shift her value functions for

days 3, 4, and 5. Axiom 3.11 says that if identical changes are made on days 1 and 2 for

both four day and five day habit horizons, the on days 3 and 4 should be equal for

both habit horizons.

Finally, we also need Axiom 3.12 assumed below, which is analogous to Axiom

3.9.

Axiom 3.12. (Independence of Irrelevant Past Consumption) For any and

and any 1 , if , then for any

𝑠 (( ) ( ))

𝑠 (( ) ( )) .

Page 109: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

97

Based on Axioms 3.10, 3.11, and 3.12, the habit function and satiation functions

in the GHS model become linear functions of past consumption, and the satiation

function is recursively defined.

Theorem 3.4. Under the assumption of the GHS model, Axioms 3.10, 3.11 and 3.12 hold

if and only if the satiation function and the adjustment function are given by the

following formulas

( ) (π›₯ ( ) ) for some ℝ;

π›₯ ( ) for some ℝ;

The habit function ( ) is linearly defined by the formula

( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) .

When for any , the satiation function reduces to ( )

( ( ) ( ) ) as assumed by Baucells and Sarin (2010). For the

habit formation, our linear functional form given in this theorem also contains the

functional form ( ) (1 ) ( ) for any as a special case.

This form for the habit formation function is assumed by Wathieu (1997, 2004) and

Baucells and Sarin (2010). To see this, setting in the habit formation function

given above, we have the following series of habit functions when π›₯ and .

Page 110: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

98

( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

……….

Let , we can write ( ) (1 ) . Then, substituting

and into ( ) ( ) ( ) , we have

. When (1 ) or ( ) (1 ), we

have ( ) (1 ) ( ) . We can continue this process to show that

( ) (1 ) ( ), for any , is a special case of our model.

3.5. AXIOMATIZATION THEORY FOR RISKY PREFERENCE

All the models we have developed in the previous sections are based on the

measurable preference order represented by a measurable value function .

However, we can axiomatize the same GSa, GHa, and GHS models for a von Neumann-

Morgenstern utility function representing a risky preference order over the

consumption profiles by following the same ideas.

First, we define shifted additive independence and conditional shifted additive

independence by following the same logic of Definitions 3.1 and 3.2. We apply the same

notation used for the value function development, except that we replace the measurable

Page 111: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

99

value function by . Also, we use {( ) ( )} to denote an even chance binary

outcome lottery on the two attribute space .

Definition 3.3. is said to be shifted additive independent of if for any ,

there exists π›₯ ( ) ℝ such that , {( ) ( π›₯ ( ))} ∼ {(

π›₯ ( )) ( )}.

We can compare this shifted additive independence condition with the additive

independence condition (Fishburn 1965) in the Figure 3.4.

Note: the left graph shows additive independence; the right one shows shifted additive

independence

Figure 3.4: Comparison between additive independence and shifted additive

independence

From Figure 3.4 above, we can see that shifted additive independence assumes the

two even chance binary lotteries with outcomes on the opposite angles of a parallelogram

𝐢

𝐢

{(π‘₯ 𝑦) (𝑧 𝑀)} βˆΌπ‘… {(𝑧 𝑦) (π‘₯ 𝑀)}

𝑧

π‘₯

𝑀 𝑦

𝐢

𝐢

π‘₯

𝑧

𝑀 𝑀 Ξ” (π‘₯ 𝑧) 𝑦 𝑦 Ξ” (π‘₯ 𝑧)

{(π‘₯ 𝑦) (𝑧 𝑀 Ξ” (π‘₯ 𝑧))} βˆΌπ‘… {(𝑧 𝑦

Ξ” (π‘₯ 𝑧)) (π‘₯ 𝑀)}

Page 112: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

100

are indifferent to each other. When the parallelogram is a rectangle, this condition is

reduced to additive independence (Fishburn 1965).

This condition has the same implication for the utility function as the shifted

difference independence condition has for the measurable value function. Therefore, we

can assume similar axioms for a utility function over consumption steams with more than

two periods and duplicate all the theorems developed in this paper for a utility function

.

3.6. CONCLUSION

In this chapter, we present a framework to axiomatize a general habit formation

and satiation utility model, which contains many existing models of satiation and habit

formation as special cases. The main axiom used in our framework is motivated by the

concept of shifting the measurable value function, which captures how the strength of

preference over current period consumption can be influenced by the past consumption.

Although we also axiomatize the linear satiation and habit formation functions in this

chapter, the GHS model admits more general forms of the satiation and habit formation

functions. Finally, the framework in this paper provides theoretical foundations for a

GHS model in both the measurable preference context and the risky preference context.

Page 113: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

101

3.7. SUPPLEMENTAL PROOFS

Theorem 3.1. Axioms 3.1, 3.2, and 3.3 hold if and only if the measurable preference

over the consumption streams can be represented by the following model,

with [ 1]

( ) βˆ‘ [ ( ( )) ( ( ))]

where ( ): β†’ ℝ is called the satiation function with ( ) and

( ) .

Proof: It is easy to verify that Axioms 3.1, 3.2, and 3.3 are all necessary

conditions of the GSa model. We only show they are also sufficient here.

To obtain the additive structure in the model, we consider the value increase from

zero consumption level to a positive consumption level in period , given that the

future consumption levels are zeros and past consumption levels are equal to . By

applying Axiom 3.1, we have

( ) ( ) ( π›₯ ( ) )

( π›₯ ( ) )

Define ( ) π›₯ ( ), we have

( ) ( ) ( ( ) ) ( ( ) )

Page 114: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

102

Denote ( ) by ( ) for any {1 }, where ( ) should

be understood as ( ) and ( ) should be understood as ( ).

The above equation can be written as

( ) ( ) [ ( ( )) ( ( ))] (3.1)

By assuming that the initial satiation is zero, i.e. ( ) , and setting

( ) , we can write ( ) as ( ( )) ( ( )). By noticing that the

first term on right side of (3.1) is of the same form as the left side of (3.1) with a different

time index, we can sum (3.1) for {2 } and simplify to obtain the following

equation.

( ) βˆ‘ [ ( ( )) ( ( ))] (3.2)

Now, we derive the relationship between the value functions in each period. From

the first part of Axiom 3.2, we know for any two periods {1 }, the value

functions and 𝑠 are strategically equivalent with each other. So, for any we have

( ) ( ) and ( ) ( ) for some ℝ . ( )

( ) for all implies that . Then, from the second part of Axiom

3.2 and the affine transformation relationship shown above, we can conclude that for

some there exists such that ( ) ( ) ( ) and ( )

( ) ( ) for any . Thus, we can conclude that ( ) ( )

( ), which implies . So, we know for any , ( ) ( ).

Page 115: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

103

Denote ( ) by ( ) . By applying the relationship ( ) ( ) for

{2 } in (3.2), we obtain

( ) βˆ‘ [ ( ( )) ( ( ))]

Finally, by using Axiom 3.3, we have ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ),

which implies , so ( 1). β–‘

Theorem 3.2. Axioms 3.4, 3.5, 3.6, and 3.7 hold if and only if the measurable preference

on can be represented by the following model, βˆ€ {1 } for any ,

( ) βˆ‘ 𝑠 [ ( 𝑠 𝑠( 𝑠 ) 𝑠( 𝑠 )) ( 𝑠( 𝑠 ))]

𝑠

and 𝑠( 𝑠 ): 𝑠 β†’ ℝ , 𝑠( 𝑠 ): 𝑠 β†’ ℝ , with ( ) , ( ) ,

𝑠( 𝑠 ) , 𝑠( 𝑠 ) and [ 1].

Proof: It is easy to verify that Axioms 3.4, 3.5, 3.6 and 3.7 are necessary

conditions of the GHS model, so we only verify that they are also sufficient here. The

idea of the proof is similar to that used in the proof of Theorem 3.1, except that we prove

the existence of the habit formation function by using Axiom 3.4.

Consider the value increase from zero consumption level to a positive

consumption level in period , given that after there is no habit formation effect and

Page 116: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

104

past consumption levels are equal to . By applying Axiom 3.5, for any

{2 3 } we have

( ) ( ) ( π›₯ ( )) ( π›₯ ( ))

Define π›₯ ( ): π›₯ ( ) and ( ) for {2 } , we

have

( ) ( ) ( π›₯ ( )) (π›₯ ( )) (3.3)

By adding and subtracting ( ( )) in (3.3), we obtain

( ) ( ) ( ( )) (π›₯ ( ))

[ ( π›₯ ( )) ( ( ))]

(3.4)

Assuming ( ) in (3.3) and defining ( ): ( ) π›₯ ( ),

(3.3) becomes

( ( )) ( ) ( ( )) (π›₯ ( )) (3.5)

Using Axiom 3.4, ( ( )) ∼ , we have ( ( ))

( ). Replacing ( ( )) by ( ) in (3.5) and substituting it into (3.4),

we have

( ) ( ) [ ( ( ) ( )) ( ( ))] (3.6)

Page 117: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

105

The first term on right side of (3.6) is of the same form as the left side of (3.6)

with a different time index (shorter time horizon). Following the same reasoning used in

the proof of Theorem 3.1, we can obtain the following additive value function for any

habit horizon , where ( ) and ( ) .

( ) βˆ‘[ 𝑠( 𝑠 𝑠( 𝑠 ) 𝑠( 𝑠 )) 𝑠( 𝑠( 𝑠 ))]

𝑠

(3.7)

From Axiom 3.6, using the same reasoning in the proof of Theorem 3.1, we can

conclude that for any , 𝑠( ) 𝑠 ( ) and 𝑠 ( ) 𝑠 ( ) . Thus, for any

{1 }, (3.7) can be written as

( ) βˆ‘ 𝑠 [ ( 𝑠 𝑠( 𝑠 ) 𝑠( 𝑠 )) ( 𝑠( 𝑠 ))]

𝑠

Finally, from Axiom 3.7, we conclude that ( 1). β–‘

Theorem 3.3. Under the assumption of the GSa model, Axioms 3.8 and 3.9 hold if and

only if the satiation function ( ) in the GSa model is recursively defined by

( ) ( ( ) ) for some ℝ and any {2 }.

Proof: To prove Theorem 3.3, we need Lemmas 3.1 and 3.2, which are proved by

adapting ideas from Rozen (2010) to our satiation and habit formation context.

Page 118: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

106

Lemma 3.1 says that the shifting effect in Axiom 3.8 produced by changing

the past consumption from to is equal to the cumulative effect of first

changing past consumption from to and then from to .

Lemma 3.1. (Triangle Equality) For any , , and ,

we have ( ) ( ) ( ) for any .

Proof: Applying Axiom 3. 8, we have

( )( ) ∼ ( ( ) )(

( ) ) ∼ ( ( )

( ) )( ( )

( ) ) ∼ ( ( ) )(

( ) )

From the last indifference relation and the uniqueness of the shift quantity

assumed in Axiom 3.8, we can conclude that ( ) ( )

( ). β–‘

Lemma 3.2 says that the shifting effect in Axiom 3.8 produced by a vector of

past consumption is the summation of the effects produced by the individual consumption

levels in each period.

Lemma 3.2. (Additive Separability) There exists functions : β†’ such

that ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ).

Page 119: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

107

Proof: By iteratively using the triangle equality, we have

( ) ( ( )) (( ) ( ))

(( ) ( ))

(( ) ( ))

(3.8)

Define ( ) ( ( )). Starting from the second term on the

right side of the above equation, we iteratively apply Axiom 3.9 to replace the common

past consumption levels with zero consumption levels. Then, define ( )

(( ) ( )) for 3 . Substituting ( ) into (3.8), we

obtain the additive separable expression for ( ). β–‘

Now, we prove Theorem 3.3. The necessary part is easy to verify, so we only

show the sufficient part here.

We first prove ( ) ( ) . For this purpose, we consider a strength

of preference relation where only ( ) and ( ) appear in the GSa model in

period t. Specifically, we consider the relation

( )( ) ∼ ( ( ) )(

( ) )

assumed by Axiom 3.8. Under the assumption of the GSa model, this relation can be

written as

Page 120: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

108

( ( )) ( ( )) ( ( ) ( ))

( ( ) ( )) (3.9)

The value difference on the left side of (3.9) reflects a consumption increase from

( ) to ( ) while the right hand side reflects an increase from

( ) ( ) to ( ) ( ) , both of which are

increased by the same amount . Under the assumption of a concave increasing

value function ( ) , (3.9) holds if and only if the following equation (3.10) holds.

Mathematically, this can be verified by taking derivatives with respect to (or ) on

both sides of (3.9) and then applying the monotonicity of ( ).

( ) ( ) ( ) (3.10)

When , (3.10) is reduced to ( ) ( ) . Thus, we

have ( ) ( ) ( ).

Now, to derive the relationship between ( ) and ( ) , we consider

another strength of preference relation assumed by Axiom 3.8,

( )( ) ∼ (

( ) )( ( ) )

As was true in equation (3.9) the value differences in period are equal on both sides of

the relation, and so the representation of this strength of preference relation in the GSa

model can be reduced to

Page 121: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

109

[ ( ( )) ( ( ))]

[ ( ( )) ( ( ))]

[ ( ( ( )))

( ( ( )))]

[ ( ( ( )))

( ( ( )))]

By the same logic used above, taking derivatives with respect to on both

sides of the above equation and using the monotonicity of ( ), we obtain the following

equation.

( ) ( ( )) (3.11)

From (3.10), we have ( ) ( ) ( ) . Substituting this

equation into (3.11), we obtain

( ) ( ( ) ( )) (3.12)

If we set , (3.12) becomes ( ) (

( )) since ( ) . Now, define 𝐹( ) ( ) , we have

( ) 𝐹( ( )).

Finally, from the fact that ( ) ( ) proved above and Lemma 3.2,

we know that ( ) is also additively separable, and ( ) ( )

Page 122: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

110

[ ( ) ( ) ( )]. Therefore, ( ) should be independent

of . Then, from ( ) 𝐹( ( )), we know that 𝐹( ) must be a

linear function. Otherwise, ( ) will depend on . Thus, for some

, ( ) ( ( )).

The above reasoning works for any , so the in the GSa model is a recursively

defined linear function. β–‘

Theorem 3.4. Under the assumption of the GHS model, Axioms 3.10, 3.11 and 3.12 hold

if and only if the satiation function and the adjustment function are given by the

following formulas

( ) (π›₯ ( ) ) for some ℝ;

π›₯ ( ) for some ℝ;

The habit function ( ) is linearly defined by the formula

( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) .

Proof: To prove Theorem 3.4, we need the following Lemmas 3.3, 3.4, 3.5, and

3.6. Lemmas 3.3 and 3.4 can be proved by the same idea used to prove Lemmas 3.1 and

3.2. We only prove Lemmas 3.5 and 3.6 here, which are proved by adapting the logic

from Rozen (2010) to accommodate both satiation and habit formation.

Page 123: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

111

Lemma 3.3. (Triangle Equality)

𝑠( ) 𝑠( ) 𝑠( ).

Lemma 3.4. (Additive Separability)

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) .

Lemma 3.5 says that the shifting effect produced by changing consumption in

one period from some level by some non-zero amount is independent of the level of

the starting point of consumption , when the consumption in the other periods are at

zero levels.

To simplify the discussion, we define the notation :

( ) for {1 1} . By this notation, ( )

denotes ( ).

Lemma 3.5. (Weak Invariance)

For any ℝ ℝ {2 1} ( ( )

) (

).

To prove the result, we consider a strength of preference relation where the same

shifting effect in period can be produced either by changing the past consumption

levels from periods 1 to 1 or by changing the past consumption levels from periods

1 to 1. This implies that the shifting effect in period in this relation only

depends on the consumption change before period . By Axiom 3.10, this strength of

preference relation is of the following form, βˆ€ {2 1},

Page 124: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

112

( )( ) ∼ ( 𝑠

( 𝑠 ) (

𝑠 )

( 𝑠 )) (

𝑠 ( 𝑠 )

( 𝑠 ) (

𝑠 ))

for some 1, where we assume the habit horizon is . The length of the habit

horizon does not matter here, as long as we consider a habit horizon with more than

periods.

Now, we treat the first 1 periods as past, which implies that the past

consumption levels are changed from ( ) to (

𝑠

( 𝑠 ) (

𝑠 )) in the strength of preference relation. This

implies

( 𝑠 ) (

( 𝑠 (

𝑠 ) ( 𝑠 )))

This equation holds for any , since the left side of the equation is the vector of shifting

effect produced by the changes of the consumption levels in the first 1 periods,

which should be independent of . Therefore, we have:

Page 125: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

113

( (

𝑠 ( 𝑠 ) (

𝑠 )))

( ( 𝑠 (

𝑠 ) ( 𝑠 )))

( ( 𝑠 (

𝑠 )))

(3.13)

Equation (3.13) says that the vector of shifting effect for period to only

depends on the marginal change ( 𝑠 ) for the past consumption change in

period , namely the change from to ( 𝑠 ), and is independent of the

base consumption level . To obtain the desired result, we apply the triangle equality

and Axiom 3.12 on both sides of (3.13) to replace the nonzero consumption levels in

periods other than , which results in the equality stated in the lemma.

By the triangle equality, the left side of (3.13) can be written as:

( (

𝑠 ( 𝑠 ) (

𝑠 )))

( ( (

𝑠 ))

)

(( ( 𝑠 ))

( 𝑠 (

𝑠 ) ( 𝑠 )))

(3.14)

Page 126: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

114

By applying Axiom 3.12 to the second term on the right side of (3.14), we can

replace ( 𝑠 ) by (

𝑠 ) in period . Then, (3.14) becomes

(3.15) as below

( (

𝑠 ( 𝑠 ) (

𝑠 )))

( ( (

𝑠 ))

)

( ( 𝑠 )

( 𝑠 (

𝑠 ) ( 𝑠 )))

(3.15)

By applying the triangle equality again to the right side of (3.13), we have:

( ( 𝑠 (

𝑠 )))

( ( 𝑠 )

)

( ( 𝑠 )

( 𝑠 (

𝑠 )))

(3.16)

Substituting (3.15) and (3.16) into (3.13), we can conclude that the right side of

(3.15) equals to the right side of (3.16). Then, by cancelling the like terms on both sides,

we have:

Page 127: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

115

( ( 𝑠 )

) ( ( (

𝑠 ))

).

Denote ( 𝑠 ) and . The equal relationship of the first

elements of the two vectors above leads to the desired result ( ( )

)

(

). β–‘

Lemma 3.6 says that the shifting effect ( ) not only additively

depends on as stated by Lemma 4 but also linearly depends on .

Lemma 3.6. (Linearity) For some ℝ {1 1} , ( )

βˆ‘ .

By Lemma 3.4, we have: ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ),

where ( ) is defined to be ( ) in the same way that we define ( ) in

the proof of Lemma 3.2. Then, by the triangle equality, we have βˆ€ {1

1} ℝ

( ) ( ( ) ) (

) (

( ) )

By applying Lemma 3.5, we have (

( ) ) (

) .

Thus, we conclude βˆ€ {2 1} ( ) ( ) ( ), which is a Cauchy

equation (AczΓ©l 2006). The solution to this equation is ( ) for some ℝ.

Page 128: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

116

Because we only prove the weak invariance for consumption level changes taking

place from period 2 to period 1 in Lemma 3.5, we can only obtain the linearity of

( ) for {2 1}. To obtain a linear function of ( ), we can consider our

model on a horizon starting from period . In this case, we obtain ( )

( ) βˆ‘ . If we take period as exogenous input in our model, we can take

( ) as the initial shifting effect for the value function, which depends on the previous

consumption experience before period 1. This is consistent with the assumption of the

existence of initial satiation and habit formation in the model by Baucells and

Sarin (2010). Therefore, if we absorb the initial shifting effect ( ) into the value

function, we have ( ) βˆ‘ . β–‘

Now, we prove the Theorem 3.4. The necessary part is easy to verify, we only

show the sufficient part here.

First, we define ( ) ( ) and prove π›₯ ( ) ( )

by following similar ideas used to prove ( ) ( ) in Theorem 3.3. We

consider the following strength of preference indifference relation assumed by Axiom

3.10.

( )( ) ∼ ( ( ))( ( ))

By the same logic used in the proof of Theorem 3.3, representing the above

relation by the GHS model and taking derivatives with respect to , we conclude that

Page 129: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

117

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) . From the relationship

π›₯ ( ) ( ) ( ), we have

π›₯ ( ) ( ) π›₯ ( ) (3.17)

When , we obtain π›₯ ( ) ( ) from (3.17). Since

( ) is a linear function by Lemma 3.6, π›₯ ( ) is also linear. Therefore, there

exist ℝ such that π›₯ ( ) .

Since satiation ( ) and habit formation ( ) are two independent

effects in our framework, given certain past consumption levels, the variation of one

effect does not influence the other effect. Therefore, for fixed , when there is no

satiation effect, π›₯ ( ) ( ) implies that ( ) is a linear function. Since

π›₯ ( ) is always linear, when there exists a satiation effect which implies ( ) is

nonzero, both ( ) and ( ) must be linear functions as well.

Now, to prove ( ) is a recursively defined function of π›₯ ( ),

we consider another type of strength of preference relation assumed by Axiom 3.10.

( )( ) ∼ ( ( )

( ))( ( ) ( ))

To express the above relations in a compact form of the GHS model, we use the

abbreviated notations shown in Table 3.2.

Page 130: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

118

Full Abbreviated Full Abbreviated

( ( )) ( )

( ( )) ( )

( ( ))

( )

( ( ))

( )

Table 3.2: Abbreviated notations

Since Axiom 3.11 implies that ( ) in the first strength of preference

indifference relation is equal to the ( ) in the second strength of preference

indifference relation, the first relation can be used to cancel the equal utility in period

in the second indifference relation. Thus, we can write the second strength of preference

relation as follows.

[ (

) ( )] [ (

) (

)]

[ ( ( )

) ( )]

[ ( ( )

) (

)]

(3.18)

Again, taking the derivative with respect to and respectively on both

sides of (3.18), we can conclude that

( )

and

( )

. These results reduce (3.18) to the

following equation.

(

) ( ) (

) (

) (3.19)

Page 131: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

119

Taking the derivative of both sides of (3.19) with respect to , we obtain

( )

( )

Since ( ( )) and

( ) are

both linear functions that have the same functional forms and differ only in the values of

the arguments, we conclude that

. This implies ( )

(

) , so we have

from the monotonicity of ( ) ,

which is

( ) ( ( )) (3.20)

By the reasoning similar to that used in the proof for Theorem 3.3, (3.17) and

(3.20) imply that there exists a function :ℝ β†’ ℝ such that ( ) (

π›₯ ( )). By the linearity of ( ), we conclude that there exists such that

( ) ( π›₯ ( )) . Finally, with the linear π›₯ ( ) and ( )

proved above, we can derive the expression for the linear ( ) given in Theorem 3.4

from the relationship ( ) ( ) π›₯ ( ). β–‘

Page 132: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

120

CHAPTER 4. HOPE, DREAD, DISAPPOINTMENT, AND

ELATION FROM ANTICIPATION IN DECISION MAKING

Hope itself is a species of happiness, and, perhaps, the chief happiness which this world

affords; but, like all other pleasures immoderately enjoyed, the excesses of hope must be

expiated by pain.

β€” Samuel Johnson

4.1. INTRODUCTION

When the mega millions jackpot prize reached its highest level of $656 million on

March 30 2012, the public experienced lottery fever. The topic

β€œ#IfIWonTheMegaMillions” was trending on Twitter during that week as people

anticipated how their life would change in the event that they won the jackpot2. Even

though the chance of winning the prize was minuscule – 1 in 175,711,536 as listed on the

website of www.megamillions.com –many people were still willing to pay a few dollars

to play it. With a few dollars, they bought hope, which allowed them to dream about what

they would do with hundreds of millions of dollars. Dreaming about winning in the days

between buying a ticket and learning the outcome of the lottery drawing may have

brought more pleasure to the players than using a few dollars to buy a snack or a cup of

coffee.

Lottery buyers in the Mega Millions lottery experience more utility by

anticipating a higher expected payoff from the lottery, because anticipating a favorable

2 See Yahoo news: http://news.yahoo.com/blogs/sideshow/mega-millions-hits-record-640-million-jackpot-

160916556.html

Page 133: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

121

result is in itself a pleasurable process. This type of behavior is consistent with the theory

of utility from anticipation, which is based on the assumption that people not only derive

utility when experiencing an outcome but also from anticipating the outcome (Akerlof

and Dickens 1982, Loewenstein 1987, Elster and Lowenstein 1992).

However, anticipating a higher expected payoff may also result in more

disappointment when a player does not win the lottery. Adopting the old saying, β€œBlessed

is he who expects nothing, for he shall never be disappointed” is consistent with lowering

anticipated expected payoff. The notion that a DM can subjectively change her

anticipation level for an uncertain payoff has been studied extensively in psychology and

behavioral science (Taylor and Shepperd 1998, Van Dijk et al. 2003, Carroll et al 2006).

In all of these studies, scholars confirmed that people tend to lower their expectations or

predictions for a self-relevant event as the event draws near. Van Dijk et al (2003)

hypothesize that people lower their expectations to protect themselves from suffering a

major disappointment when the uncertainty of a proximate self-relevant event is resolved.

Thus there are two competing cognitive strategies that a decision maker (DM)

might employ to increase her experienced utility: savoring a higher anticipated payoff

before the uncertainty of the payoff is resolved or anticipating a less desirable payoff to

avoid disappointment when the lottery is resolved. These two competing strategies have

been verified in experimental studies by Loewenstein and Linville (1986).

In this paper, we propose a decision making model to capture the tradeoff between

these two conflicting strategies that influence the DM’s total experienced utility from an

Page 134: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

122

uncertain outcome paid in the future. Besides the behavioral findings reviewed above, our

research is also closely related to the concept of disappointment (Bell 1985, Loomes and

Sugden 1986, Jia et al. 2001). In these disappointment models, a DM anticipates that she

will experience either elation or disappointment when the lottery is resolved and paid,

depending on whether the realized outcome is superior or inferior to her reference point.

The reference point against which the outcome is compared to form elation and

disappointment is assumed to be either the mathematical expectation of the lottery (Bell

1985, Jia et al. 2001) or the expected utility of the lottery (Loomes and Sugden 1986).

However, these models do not apply to a decision maker who subjectively chooses to

lower her expectation to avoid disappointment, as the expectations in these

disappointment models are based on objective probabilities.

Our model is a special case of a model proposed by Gollier and Muermann

(2010), hereafter the GM model, where a DM forms her expectation of the anticipated

outcome based on her subjective probabilities. Before the uncertainty of the outcome is

resolved, she can savor the anticipation; after the uncertainty is resolved, she experiences

either elation or disappointment by comparing the realized payoff with a reference point

determined by her subjective expectation. The GM model assumes that the DM chooses

an optimal subjective belief to balance the tradeoff between savoring higher expectation

and avoiding higher disappointment. This assumption in the GM model is related to the

line of research on optimal beliefs in expected utility introduced by Brunnermeier and

Parker (2005) and Brunnermeier et al. (2007). We allow for any possible anticipated

Page 135: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

123

payoff level in the decision making process rather than assume the DM is capable of

determining the optimal anticipation to maximize her utility. Savoring anticipation and

avoiding disappointment may be only two of many considerations that influence how

people form their beliefs about the future.

Our model asserts a different process of forming an anticipated outcome to savor

than GM, which results in different implications. For example, we show that in a

portfolio choice problem our model is consistent with the empirical finding that optimism

will lead to more investment in the risky asset relative to the risk free asset (Manju and

Robinson 2007, Balasuriya 2010, Nosic and Weber 2010). In contrast, the GM model

conflicts with these empirical findings. This conflict is addressed by an extension of the

GM model proposed by Jouini et al (2013). However, neither GM nor Jouini et al (2013)

propose preference conditions for their models. In contrast, we also develop an axiomatic

basis for our model with preference assumptions that can be evaluated for their

reasonableness.

We refer to the anticipated expected payoff based on a DM’s subjective

probabilities as the anticipation level. By changing her subjective probabilities over

outcomes, the DM could change her anticipation level for a lottery. This anticipation level

influences two types of utility derived from a lottery: utility of anticipation and

anticipated experienced utility. Utility of anticipation is the pleasure or pain that the DM

β€œconsumes” before the lottery is resolved, where anticipation can be interpreted as a

psychological state (Caplin and Leahy, 2001). Anticipated experienced utility is

Page 136: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

124

determined based on the DM’s prediction of how disappointed or elated she will feel

when the lottery is resolved. By incorporating these two types of utility into a unified

framework, our model captures four different emotions we may observe in a risky

decision context: hope, dread, elation, and disappointment.

While elation and disappointment have been modeled in disappointment theory

(Bell 1985, Loomes and Sugden 1986, Jia et al 2001, DelquiΓ© and Cillo 2006), there are

few studies that embed hope and dread in a decision model. One exception is Chew and

Ho (1994) who did model hope as the preference for the late resolution of the uncertainty

in a recursive utility framework. Caplin and Leahy (2001) proposed a very general model

that incorporates the utility derived from anticipatory feelings – such as anxiety, hope,

and suspense – in the decision making process. However, they did not allow the

anticipatory feelings to influence the decision maker’s reference point, thus emotions of

disappointment and elation are not captured by their model. We model hope as the

anticipation of a gain and dread as the anticipation of a loss consistent with Lowenstein

(1987).

The reminder of the chapter is organized as follows. In section 4.2, we introduce a

general model and show that this model contains the Risk-Value model (Jia and Dyer

1996) as a special case. We then make additional assumptions about the components of

this general model and obtain a model similar to GM, which also contains Bell’s (1985a)

disappointment model as a special case. In section 4.3, we propose preference conditions

to axiomatize the models discussed in section 4.2 while section 4.4 explains how the

Page 137: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

125

DM’s optimistic or pessimistic attitude toward the future may influence the risk attitude

of the DM in a manner consistent with empirical findings. Section 4.5 utilizes our model

to explain the coexistence of gambling and purchasing insurance, which provides an

intuitive interpretation to this widely recognized puzzle in decision theory. In section 4.6,

we apply our model to portfolio choice and the selection of the optimal advertising level

to demonstrate the variety of factors that might affect preference that our model can

accommodate. Section 4.7 concludes the paper. All the proofs are provided in section 4.8.

4.2. THE MODEL

In this paper, we use to denote a lottery of payoffs and to denote an

anticipation level. The bounded sets of payoffs and anticipation are denoted by ℝ

and ℝ respectively. In general, the anticipation level depends on the lottery, which

can be denoted by . Thus, is a function of consistent with Caplin and Leahy

(2001). However, when it is clear which lottery is associated with the anticipation level

we will drop the subscript and simply use .

We consider two periods in our model. In the first period, the DM chooses the

anticipation level of the lottery over monetary outcomes under consideration. She

derives utility from before the lottery is resolved by savoring it. In the second period,

the lottery is resolved and she experiences either elation or disappointment induced by

comparing the received outcome of the lottery with a reference point determined by .

Thus, the DM’s evaluation of a lottery in the first period is based on a two attribute

Page 138: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

126

vector ( ). The total ex ante utility derived from this lottery with an associated

anticipation is evaluated by the DM according to the following model with ( )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ( )) (4.1)

The total ex ante utility ( ) in this model is decomposed into two parts, the

utility of anticipation ( ) and the anticipated experienced utility ( ( )) .

Since the utility function is unique up to an affine transformation, we can rescale it such

that ( ) , ( ) , and ( ) . This rescaling leads to zero total ex ante

utility when she both anticipates and receives a zero outcome. The function ( ) is a

trade-off factor between the two components of the total ex ante utility. For a lottery , if

the DM anticipates , this positive anticipation creates hope for the DM; if the DM

anticipates , this negative anticipation creates dread. Since this anticipation is

the outcome the DM anticipates before the lottery is resolved, the reference point used

by the DM to form elation and disappointment should be influenced by this anticipation

level. Specifically, we assume the reference point depends on the anticipation level

through a function ( ). For any realized outcome , the DM experiences ( ) and

will be elated when ( ) and disappointed when ( ).

We do not address the psychological mechanisms that may form the anticipation.

Instead, we allow the DM to form the anticipation in many possible ways. If the DM

forms her anticipation level by using her subjective probability over the possible future

outcomes, then the anticipation level can be interpreted as the certainty equivalent of

Page 139: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

127

the lottery in a way consistent with the interpretation of anticipation in the GM

model. We also assume that this anticipation is bounded by the minimum possible

outcome and the maximum possible outcome of a lottery, namely min( ) and max( )

respectively, which is consistent with the argument by Jouini et al. (2013). If the DM’s

anticipation level for is the mathematical expectation of the lottery , ; and

she also chooses the anticipation as the reference point when determining the elation and

disappointment, i.e., ( ) , our model is reduced to ( ) ( )

( ) ( ). If we also assume ( ) ( ), our model (4.1) is reduced to a

Risk-Value model (Jia and Dyer 1996). In this sense, our model (4.1) can be considered a

General Risk-Value model where the risk is measured by the anticipated experienced

utility from elation and disappointment and value is measured by the utility of

anticipation.

Although model (4.1) can be obtained by assuming some weak preference

conditions as we show in the next section, it is not an easy model to study and it is more

general than other models considered in the literature. A more parsimonious model that

captures the tradeoff between anticipation and disappointment can be obtained by

assuming a constant tradeoff factor ( ) 1 and a linear reference point function

( ) for some constant [ 1].

( ) ( ) ( ) (4.2)

In Figure 4.1, we show that both of model (1) and (2) are special case of the GM

Page 140: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

128

model. The GM model and its extension proposed by Jouini et al. (2013) assumes that the

DM always adopts her optimal belief: the anticipation level that maximizes the total ex

ante utility derived from the lottery . In contrast, by adopting a descriptive perspective,

we do not assume that the DM is capable of optimizing her anticipation when facing a

lottery In this way, the anticipation level in our model reflects the DM’s optimistic or

pessimistic attitude toward the future as we discuss in subsequent sections.

For model (4.2), if both and are linear and the DM’s anticipation equals the

mathematical expectation of the lottery , this model reduces to the

disappointment model proposed by Bell (1985a). In another special case, if the DM’s

preferences are not affected by anticipation, elation, or disappointment, we have

and ( ) becomes a constant. In this case, model (4.2) reduces to the expected utility

model. In Figure 4.1, we illustrate the relationships between our models (4.1) and (4.2)

and other preference models in the literature.

Page 141: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

129

Figure 4.1: The relationship of models (4.1) and (4.2) with some existing models

4.3. THE PREFERENCE ASSUMPTIONS

In this section, we discuss the preference conditions that imply models (4.1) and

(4.2) in section 4.2. We assume that there is a risky preference over the two attribute

space , which is represented by a von Neumann and Morgenstern utility function

( ). Since the anticipation level can be interpreted as a psychological state which

reflects DM’s beliefs, this setup is consistent with the premise that people not only have

preferences over payoffs but also over their beliefs about payoffs as proposed by Akerlof

and Dickens (1982) and with the assumption that the DM could have a preference order

π‘ˆ(οΏ½οΏ½ π‘Ž) 𝑣(π‘Ž) 𝛽(π‘Ž)𝐸𝑒 (οΏ½οΏ½ 𝛾(π‘Ž))

General Risk Value Model (4.1)

π‘ˆ(οΏ½οΏ½ π‘Ž) 𝑣(π‘Ž) 𝐸𝑒(οΏ½οΏ½ π›Ύπ‘Ž)

Anticipation Disappointment Tradeoff Model (4.2)

π‘ˆ(οΏ½οΏ½ 𝐸��) 𝑒(𝐸��) 𝛽(𝐸��)𝐸𝑒(οΏ½οΏ½ 𝐸��)

Risk Value Model (Jia and Dyer 1996)

π‘ˆ(οΏ½οΏ½ π‘Ž) 𝐸𝑒(οΏ½οΏ½)

Expected Utility Model

π‘ˆ(οΏ½οΏ½ οΏ½οΏ½) 𝐸�� 𝐸𝑒(οΏ½οΏ½ 𝐸��)

Disappointment Model (Bell 1985)

Gollier and Muermann’s model (2010)

π‘ˆ(οΏ½οΏ½) maxπ‘Ž 𝑣(π‘Ž) 𝐸𝑒(οΏ½οΏ½ π‘Ž)

When π‘Ž 𝐸��, 𝑣 𝑒,

and 𝛾(π‘Ž) π‘Ž

When 𝛾(π‘Ž) π›Ύπ‘Ž,

𝛽(π‘Ž) 1

When 𝐸𝑒(𝑋 π‘Ž) 𝛽(π‘Ž)𝐸𝑒(𝑋 𝛾(π‘Ž))

and no max operation is applied to

determine a

When 𝛾 ,

𝑣 (π‘Ž)

When π‘Ž 𝐸�� 𝛾 1 𝑣(π‘₯) π‘₯ and

𝑒(π‘₯) 𝑒π‘₯ π‘₯ 𝑑π‘₯ π‘₯

Page 142: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

130

over the psychological states as proposed by Caplin and Leahy (2001). The set of simple

lotteries defined over is denoted by and different lotteries on the payoff space are

denoted by , , and so on. Given these definitions, the preference condition leading to

model (4.1) can be stated as follows.

Assumption 4.1. (Shifted Utility Independence) For any and any ,

( ) ( ) implies that there exists quantity π›₯( ) ℝ such that (

π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) ).

This assumption states that for lotteries resolved and paid in the second period, a

DM’s preference order over these lotteries is the same under different levels of

anticipation if the lotteries’ payoffs are adjusted by a constant amount that depends on the

two distinct anticipation levels. For instance, consider a gambler choosing between

betting on a pair of horse races where she anticipates winning $100 for each bet. She may

have the same risky preference over the two races if instead she anticipates winning $150

if all the possible payoffs are increased by an amount that depends on both $150 and

$100. In a simple special case, for example, this increase could be $50=$150-$100 if

preferences are linear in dollars. When the outcomes are dollars, the higher anticipation

may be completely compensated by the increased payoff levels in the lotteries, and any

possible disappointment and elation from each original lottery is kept the same in the

transformed lottery.

Page 143: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

131

In general, there may also exist situations where the required adjustment quantity

for the lotteries does not match the exact difference between the two levels of

anticipation. However since the adjustment is affected by the two different anticipation

levels, we expect it to be a function of both and , i.e., π›₯( ) in Assumption 4.1.

Figure 4.2 provides a graphical depiction of Assumption 4.1.

Figure 4.2: Assumption 4.1: Shifted Utility Independence

When π›₯( ) for any , Assumption 4.1 is equivalent to the

assumption that is utility independent of (Keeney and Raiffa, 1976). Utility

independence implies that, for example, the utility function over when anticipation is

is an affine transformation of the utility of when anticipation is , e.g. ( )

( ) ( ) ( )(Keeney and Raiffa 1976). Similarly, Assumption 4.1 implies that

( ) ( ) ( ) ( Ξ”( ) ) , since the preference order over ( ) is

strategically equivalent to the preference order over ( Ξ”( ) ). Assumption 4.1

leads to the additive representation of model (4.1) when and ( ) is defined to be

(οΏ½οΏ½ π›₯(π‘Ž 𝑏) 𝑏)

(οΏ½οΏ½ π‘Ž)

(π‘₯ π‘Ž)

(π‘₯ π‘Ž)

𝑝

1 𝑝

(οΏ½οΏ½ π‘Ž)

(𝑦 π‘Ž)

(𝑦 π‘Ž)

π‘ž

1 π‘ž

(οΏ½οΏ½ π›₯(π‘Ž 𝑏) 𝑏)

(𝑦 π›₯(π‘Ž 𝑏) 𝑏)

(𝑦 π›₯(π‘Ž 𝑏) 𝑏)

π‘ž

1 π‘ž

(π‘₯ π›₯(π‘Ž 𝑏) 𝑏)

(π‘₯ π›₯(π‘Ž 𝑏) 𝑏)

𝑝

1 𝑝

Page 144: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

132

( ) [π›₯( ) π›₯( )] . Therefore, we conclude that a utility function ( )

representing risky preference over can be decomposed into model (4.1) under

Assumption 4.1.

Theorem 4.1. Assumption 4.1 holds if and only if the utility function ( ) can be

decomposed into (4.1) with ( ) , ( ) , and ( ) .

As discussed in section 4.2, model (4.2) can be obtained as a special case of

model (4.1) by assuming ( ) 1 and ( ) for some [ 1]. To state the

preference assumptions for model (4.2), we denote {( ) ( )} as a binary lottery that

results in either ( ) or ( ) with even chances.

Assumption 4.2. (Shifted Additive Independence) For any and ,

there exists π›₯( ) such that {( ) ( )} ∼ {( π›₯( ) ) (

π›₯( ) )}.

This assumption describes a situation that may happen if a DM is uncertain about

her anticipation level. Caplin and Leahy (2001) adopted a similar assumption in their

anticipatory feeling model. In our paper, we can consider a DM who has an even chance

to obtain lottery or on day 2 and the lottery she receives will be resolved and paid

two weeks later. In this case, the DM will form her anticipation level for each lottery and

begin to savor it when she learns which lottery she will receive on day 2. But, on day 1,

Page 145: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

133

the DM is uncertain about her anticipation level. If the DM also forecasts that her

anticipation levels will be and for and respectively, the lottery she evaluates

on day 1 is {( ) ( )} . If we assume there exist and such that

( ) ∼ ( ) and ( ) ∼ ( ) , the lottery faced by the DM can be written as

{( ) ( )}, which is the lottery discussed in Assumption 4.2.

Specifically, Assumption 4.2 assumes that the DM faces two such options

{( ) ( )} and {( ) ( )} . Since and , ( ) is a lower payoff

associated with a higher level of anticipation and ( ) is a higher payoff associated

with a lower level of anticipation. Thus, the option produces either a large disappointment

or a large elation. The second option {( ) ( )} yields either a lower payoff

associated with lower anticipation or higher payoff associated with higher anticipation,

which produces neither high disappointment nor high elation. Put another way, the level

of anticipation and the outcome received are negatively correlated for option 1 and

positively correlated for option 2.

If the DM is correlation seeking in the sense defined by Eeckhoudt et al. (2007) in

the payoff-anticipation space, she may feel like playing it safe leading to the preference

relation {( ) ( )} β‰Ύ {( ) ( )} . This situation happens when the utility

function has the property of ( ) , the condition for disappointment

aversion (Gollier and Muermann, 2010). As a result, if the attractiveness of the second

option can be reduced by some amount, it is possible that the DM is indifferent between

the two lotteries. This can be achieved by spreading out the outcomes of the preferred

Page 146: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

134

lottery on the payoff attribute while holding the mean constant (mean preserving spread).

More formally, there may exist π›₯( ) such that {( ) ( )} ∼

{( π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) )} as illustrated in Figure 4.3. This preference condition

was proposed by He et al. (2013) to axiomatize a habit formation and satiation utility

function for intertemporal choice.

Figure 4.3: Assumption 4.2: Shifted Additive Independence

Using Assumption 4.2, we conclude that the trade-off factor in model (4.1) is

equal to 1. To obtain a linear reference point function ( ) so that model (4.1)

reduces to model (4.2), we also need the following technical assumption.

Assumption 4.3. (Linear Shifting Quantity) For any , there is a unique

π›₯( ) ( ) [ ] satisfying the condition in Assumption 4.2.

Under Assumptions 4.2 and 4.3, we can conclude that the utility function ( )

can be decomposed into model (4.2) as formally stated in Theorem 4.2.

𝑋 𝑦 π‘₯

π‘Ž

𝑏

Ξ”(π‘Ž 𝑏)

Ξ”(π‘Ž 𝑏)

𝑦 Ξ”(π‘Ž 𝑏)

𝐴

π‘₯ Ξ”(π‘Ž 𝑏)

Page 147: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

135

Theorem 4.2. Assumptions 4.2 and 4.3 hold if and only if the utility function ( )

can be decomposed into (4.2) with [ 1] ( ) ( ) .

4.4. RISK ATTITUDE

4.4.1. Optimism, pessimism, and risk attitude

When facing an uncertain outcome, a DM’s attitude toward the future outcome

may be classified into two categories, optimistic and pessimistic. When a DM’s

anticipation level increases, we say that she become more optimistic which also means

that she become less pessimistic, and vice versa. Intuitively an optimistic DM believes

better outcomes are more likely to occur and therefore will take more risks than a DM

who is pessimistic. This positive relationship between optimism and risk seeking

behavior has been modeled and tested in the literature (Misina 2005, Anderson and

Galinsky 2006, Dillenberger and Rozen 2011). However, there may be situations where

pessimistic people are more risk seeking; for instance, desperate people may take more

risky actions (Lybbert and Barrett, 2011). In another study, Mansour et al. (2008) found

that pessimism is positively correlated with the risk tolerance, implying that more

pessimistic people are more risk seeking. In this paper, we call these two types of

interaction between anticipation and risk attitude increased risk seeking behavior due to

optimism (pessism), respectively, and show that our model (4.2) can be used to describe

both.

Following convention, we define the risk attitude by comparing the expected

Page 148: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

136

utility of a lottery with the utility of its expectation. From this section on we denote the

anticipation level as to emphasize that the anticipation level is associated with a

particular lottery, . If ( ) ( ) ( 𝐸 ), we say the DM is risk seeking

(neutral, averse). For a certain outcome, we assume that a DM will anticipate the

outcome itself as it is the only feasible anticipation level, so that 𝐸 . The

certainty equivalent for a lottery when the DM anticipates receiving should clearly

depend on the anticipation level, which is denoted by 𝐂𝐄( | ) and solved from

(𝐂𝐄( | ) 𝐂𝐄( | )) ( ) . The risk premium for lottery under

anticipation is defined as ( ) 𝐂𝐄( | ) , which also depends on the

anticipation level .

We say that a DM becomes more optimistic if the DM’s anticipation level

increases; and we say a DM becomes more pessimistic if the DM’s anticipation level

decreases. In the economics literature (BΓ©nabou and Tirole 2002, Epstein and Kopylov,

2007), optimism (pessimism) is defined by assigning higher subjective probabilities over

better (worse) outcomes. If the DM’s anticipation is interpreted as the certainty

equivalent for the lottery based on her subjective probabilities as in GM, the optimism

and pessimism defined here is consistent with the concepts commonly used in the

literature.

In Proposition 4.1, we use , , and to denote the derivatives of , ,

and , respectively. The proposition states that, in our model, more optimism about a

Page 149: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

137

lottery (a higher level of anticipation) could either increase or decrease the risk premium

of a lottery. So, our model is consistent with increased risk seeking behavior due to

optimism (pessimism).

Proposition 4.1. Under the assumptions of model (4.2), for a given lottery when the

DM anticipates , the risk premium ( ) for depends on in the following

ways:

i. If ( ) ( ) , then ( ) The DM exhibits

increased risk seeking behavior due to optimism .

ii. If ( ) ( ) , then ( ) The DM exhibits

increased risk seeking behavior due to pessimism.

When risk premium ( ) is positive the DM is risk averse and case i describes

a situation where more optimism leads to less risk aversion. Since being less risk averse

implies that the DM is getting closer to risk seeking behavior, we refer to this increased

risk seeking behavior due to optimism in our paper. When ( ) is negative the DM is

risk seeking and case i describes a situation where more optimism leads to more risk

seeking as 𝐂𝐄( | ) increases. The results of case ii can be interpreted in the similar

way.

This proposition states that whether a DM exhibits increased risk seeking

behavior due to optimism or pessimism is determined by the comparison between the

Page 150: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

138

marginal utility of anticipation and the marginal anticipated experienced utility. When

( ) ( ), the utility from higher anticipation derived by the DM is

larger than the utility lost from the increase in disappointment, and thus the DM’s

increased risk seeking behavior is due to optimism.

Case i in Proposition 4.1 may be common for the Mega-millions lottery players

discussed in the introduction. The lottery ticket buyers derive more utility from a higher

anticipation than they lose from disutility due to the potential disappointment. This is

consistent with the observation that many people purchase a lottery ticket as a way to

acquire hope. Proposition 4.1 predicts that for DMs that gamble and buy lottery tickets,

high levels of optimism are associated with more risk seeking behavior. This also

explains why lottery companies spend money on advertising that depict people winning

the lottery to increase the anticipation level of the public such that they might become

more risk seeking and buy more tickets.

Similarly, in case ii of Proposition 1 a DM worries more about the possible

disappointment. If she is more pessimistic, her anticipation will be lower. Therefore, she

will be less worried about the possible utility loss from a larger disappointment

associated with higher anticipation. This is consistent with the empirical finding that a

negative emotional state may cause people to become more risk seeking (Zhao 2006,

Chuang and Lin 2007), because they value the chance of elation from receiving a better

than anticipated lottery outcome that would improve their negative emotional state.

Case ii cannot be explained by the EU model because shifting probability mass from the

Page 151: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

139

bad outcome to the good outcome will increase the expected utility of a lottery. Thus,

more optimistic always implies less risk averse behavior in the EU model.

The evaluations of a lottery in these two cases with different attitudes towards the

future can be illustrated in Figure 4.4.

Figure 4.4: Optimistic vs. pessimistic anticipation levels

For simplicity, we assume the utility model for a DM is of the form ( )

( ) ( ) where 1 in model (4.2). If this DM is optimistic about the future

(left side of Figure 4.4), she evaluates the lottery above by (1 ) (1 1 )

( 1 ) (1 ) ( ) ( 1 ). If she is pessimistic about the future,

she evaluates the lottery by ( ) (1 ) ( ) . Thus, risk seeking due to

optimism (pessimism) occurs when (1 ) ( ) ( 1 ) ( ) ( )

(1 ) ( ), which is equivalent to (1 ) ( ) ( ) [ (1 ) ( 1 )].

This relationship will hold if the DM is more (less) sensitive to anticipation than to the

anticipated elation and disappointment. Whether a DM exhibits risk seeking behavior due

to optimism or pessimism can be explained by the tradeoff between the two sources of

𝐿

1 1

2

1

2

𝐿

1

1

2

1

2

Optimistic Pessimistic

Anticipation

Anticipatio

n

Page 152: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

140

utility in our model.

4.4.2. Wealth effect on risk attitude

By allowing the DM to choose the level of anticipation, our model can also

capture how the DM’s anticipation mediates the wealth effect on her risk attitude. For any

anticipation level chosen by the DM for lottery at wealth level , there is a unique

certainty equivalent 𝐂𝐄 that solves the equation ( 𝐂𝐄 𝐂𝐄) (

). For a given , this certainty equivalent is a function of . In this subsection, we

use 𝐂𝐄( ) to denote the derivative of 𝐂𝐄 to emphasize this point. However, we

also use the notation 𝐂𝐄 to indicate this function for simplicity when no derivative of the

function is taken. Under model (4.2), the equation that defines the certainty equivalent

above can be written as

( 𝐂𝐄) ( 𝐂𝐄 ( 𝐂𝐄)) ( ) ( ( ))

(4.3)

We can investigate how the certainty equivalent is affected by the wealth level

at different levels of anticipation by taking the derivative with respect to on both sides

of (4.3), and solving for 𝐂𝐄( ) .

𝐂𝐄( ) 𝑣′( οΏ½οΏ½ ) 𝑣′( 𝐂𝐄) ( 𝛾)[𝐸 β€²( 𝛾( οΏ½οΏ½)) β€²( 𝐂𝐄 𝛾( 𝐂𝐄))]

𝑣′( 𝐂𝐄) ( 𝛾) β€²( 𝐂𝐄 𝛾( 𝐂𝐄))

Under the standard assumptions that and , the sign of 𝐂𝐄( )

Page 153: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

141

is determined by the numerator. Thus, we have the following proposition about the

sign of 𝐂𝐄( ) .

Proposition 4.2. When 1, ( ) , we have: 𝐂𝐄( ) ( ) if and only

if ( )𝐂𝐄; when [ 1), we have:

i. If , 𝐂𝐄 and (1 )𝐂𝐄

implies 𝐂𝐄( )

ii. If , 𝐂𝐄 and (1 )𝐂𝐄

implies 𝐂𝐄( ) .

iii. If , 𝐂𝐄 and (1 )𝐂𝐄

implies 𝑑𝐂𝐄( )

𝑑

iv. If , 𝐂𝐄 and (1 )𝐂𝐄

implies 𝐂𝐄( )

Moreover, if we replace with and ( )𝐂𝐄 with (

)𝐂𝐄, the sign of 𝐂𝐄( ) is unchanged.

When 1, the DM uses the anticipation as the reference point to predict the

level of disappointment and the sign of 𝐂𝐄( ) is determined by the sign of

𝐂𝐄. If we assume , a relatively optimistic DM who anticipates 𝐂𝐄

becomes more risk averse with an increase in wealth, 𝐂𝐄( ) ; and a relatively

pessimistic DM who anticipates 𝐂𝐄 becomes less risk averse with an increase in

Page 154: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

142

wealth, 𝐂𝐄( ) .

When 1, the sign of 𝐂𝐄( ) not only depends on the sign of 𝐂𝐄

but also depends on the sign of [(1 )𝐂𝐄 ] , as summarized by

Proposition 4.2. These four cases demonstrate that our model has the descriptive power to

capture many different ways that optimism and pessimism can mediate the wealth effect

on risk aversion. For instance, in case ii of Proposition 4.2, 𝐂𝐄 and

(1 )𝐂𝐄 implies 𝐂𝐄 (risk seeking). So, in this case, a DM who is

relatively pessimistic ( 𝐂𝐄) and risk seeking ( 𝐂𝐄) will become more risk

seeking at a higher level of wealth 𝐂𝐄( ) . Among these four cases, cases i

and iii are of special interest, as they describe two seemingly conflicting empirical

observations that people with lower levels of wealth can be either more risk averse or

more risk seeking (Caballero 2010, Vieider et al. 2012).

For case i, it is straightforward to show that 𝐂𝐄 implies both

𝐂𝐄 𝐂𝐄 𝐂𝐄 and 𝐂𝐄 . By combining these two

inequalities, we obtain (1 )𝐂𝐄. Recognizing that case i can be obtained

from 𝐂𝐄 , we can conclude that a DM with an anticipation level lower than

the certainty equivalent of the lottery 𝐂𝐄 and exhibiting risk averse behavior

𝐂𝐄 will become more risk averse when her wealth level decreases, i.e., 𝐂𝐄( )

. This is consistent with the observation that people with lower levels of wealth

are often more risk averse than people with higher levels of wealth and are therefore less

Page 155: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

143

likely to participate in high return investment activities which are usually associated with

high risks, resulting in the β€œpoverty trap” (Mosley and Verschoor, 2005, Yesuf and

Bluffstone 2009).

Similarly, if the condition 𝐂𝐄 is satisfied then using the result of case

iii, we can conclude that a DM with anticipation level higher than the certainty equivalent

𝐂𝐄 and exhibiting risk seeking behavior 𝐂𝐄 will become more risk seeking

when her wealth level is decreased, i.e., 𝐂𝐄( ) . The result of this case

matches the observation that DMs with lower levels of wealth may be more involved in

gambling than DMs with higher wealth levels (Lesieur 1992). When gambling, people

may anticipate favorable results; in our terms, gamblers are optimistic about the payoff of

the lottery, i.e., 𝐂𝐄. Thus, the certainty equivalent of the lottery for a high wealth

gambler is smaller than that for a low wealth gambler, which results in relatively less

gambling for high wealth DMs. Bosch-Domenech and Benach (2005) found that people

with lower levels of wealth are more risk seeking than people with higher levels of

wealth when facing lotteries with large absolute payoffs. This empirical finding may also

be explained by case iii, since a lottery with large payoffs is more likely to induce a high

anticipation leading to more risk seeking behavior for people with lower levels of wealth.

4.5. UTILITY OF GAMBLING

4.5.1. Coexistence of gambling and purchasing of insurance

A widely recognized puzzle that cannot be explained by standard utility theory is

Page 156: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

144

the coexistence of gambling and insurance purchasing, implying that people are

simultaneously risk seeking and risk averse (Friedman and Savage 1948). This puzzling

problem can be traced back to the work of von Neumann and Morgenstern who believed

that gambling behavior is inconsistent with expected utility theory (von Neumann and

Morgenstern 1944, p. 28 and Bleichrodt and Schmidt 2002). Only a few studies have

axiomatized the utility of gambling (e.g. Diecidue, et al. 2004) and typically, the utility of

gambling is modeled by appending an extra utility term to the standard expected utility

model or applying different utility functions to non-degenerate and degenerate lotteries

(Fishburn 1980, Conlisk 1993 Schmidt 1998, Diecidue et al. 2004). A common weakness

of these studies is that they do not provide a psychological explanation for why people

would use different utility functions to evaluate risky lotteries and certain outcomes.

In this subsection, we show that our model not only explains the coexistence of

these two seemingly conflicting behaviors, but also provides intuitive psychological

motivations for the choices: in different choice contexts, a DM might form anticipation in

different ways. When purchasing a lottery ticket, a DM may focus on imagining a future

based on winning the prize of the lottery after hearing stories of the lucky players who

have won large prizes. This leads to anticipating a good outcome from the lottery even if

she knows that the chance of winning is very small. However, when facing a possible

loss, e.g., the destruction of her house by a tornado, a DM is influenced by the horrible

images of a tornado from the media, which leads to focusing on imagining the large loss

she may suffer if a tornado hits her house. In this case, a DM may anticipate an extremely

Page 157: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

145

bad situation when the loss occurs. This explanation is consistent with the research on

affect in decision making which shows that positive affect usually induces optimistic

beliefs and less perceived risk, and negative affect usually induces pessimistic beliefs and

more perceived risk (Johnson and Tversky 1983, Slovic et al. 2005, VΓ€stfjΓ€lln et al.

2008).

To simplify the illustration, we consider a special case of model (4.2) with ,

which implies a DM who does not anticipate elation or disappointment, but a similar

analysis can be obtained for . First, we consider a DM with a wealth level of

who is facing a loss of 𝜏 ℝ with probability . She faces a lottery that yields 𝜏

with probability and with probability 1 . We denote the premium for a full

coverage insurance policy by . According to our model, the utility from purchasing the

insurance is given by ( ) ( ) and the utility from not insuring is given by

( ) ( 𝜏) (1 ) ( ). Then, the condition of purchasing the insurance is

( ) ( 𝜏) (1 ) ( ) ( ) ( )

which is equivalent to

( ) ( ( 𝜏) (1 ) ( )) ( ) ( ) (4.4)

Under the assumption , the left hand side of (4.4) is positive as long as the

insurance premium is not greater than the price of fair insurance 𝜏. Therefore, if the

anticipation level for the lottery is not too high, (4.4) always holds and the DM

prefers to buy insurance. Even when the anticipation reaches its highest level and she

Page 158: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

146

anticipates losing nothing, i.e., , the DM may still choose to buy insurance when

the utility difference on the right hand side of (4.4) is smaller than the utility difference

on the left side. But, if the DM always anticipates , which seems plausible,

the right hand side of (4.4) is always negative. Thus, when the DM will

always buy insurance under the standard assumptions that , , and .

Now, we consider the utility from gambling for a DM. Suppose that a lottery with

a large payoff ℝ with small probability and a zero payoff with probability

1 is available for purchase at its expected payoff . According to our model, a DM

that anticipates the nonzero payoff will buy the lottery when the following condition

holds

( ) ( ) (1 ) ( ) ( ) ( )

which is equivalent to

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (4.5)

The left hand side of (4.5) is the utility difference from anticipation and the right

hand side is the utility difference from anticipated experienced utility. The DM may buy

the lottery because the utility difference ( ) ( ) may not be very large.

However, when is large and is small, the difference ( ) ( ) could be very

large. In other words, anticipating a large prize from a lottery may produce much more

marginal utility than anticipating the certain payoff of the expectation of the lottery;

( ) ( ) ≫ ( ) ( ) ( ) [ ( ) (1 ) ( )].

Page 159: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

147

4.5.2. Stochastic dominance and transitivity

A widely recognized problem in modeling the utility of gambling is that stochastic

dominance is usually violated by the proposed models (Fishburn 1980, Schmidt 1998,

and Diecidue et al. 2004). Stochastic dominance is a desirable rationality requirement

that should not be violated by a preference model from both normative and prescriptive

perspectives. To remedy this problem, Bleichrodt and Schmidt (2002) propose a context

dependent model that does not violate stochastic dominance, but does violate another

desirable property: transitivity of preference (Luce 2000, MacCrimmon 1968). Stochastic

dominance or transitivity is violated by these models in part because they apply different

utility functions to represent the unique preference order on a set including both risky and

riskless alternatives (see Bleichrodt and Schmidt 2002, Table 1). In our model, under the

appropriate assumptions, the violation of both stochastic dominance and transitivity can

be avoided.

By definition (Bleichrodt and Schmidt 2002, Diecidue et al. 2004), a preference

order satisfies stochastic dominance if for any degenerate or non-degenerate lottery

, any two certain outcomes , and any ( 1] , if , then

(1 ) (1 ) . Under model (4.2), the preference relation is

represented by ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ). Since both functions ( ) and

( ) are monotonically increasing, we know . Compounding lottery with

will have a total ex ante utility greater than or equal to that from compounding lottery

Page 160: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

148

with in many cases, but it will depend on how a DM forms her anticipation for the

compound lotteries. In Assumption 4.4, we describe a situation where the larger the

payoff compounded with a lottery, the higher the anticipation formed by the DM. This

assumption implies that when an outcome of a lottery is improved the anticipation level

should not decrease, which seems to be reasonable.

Assumption 4.4. (Consistent Compounding) A DM is said to be consistently

compounding in anticipation if for any and , her anticipation levels for the

compound lotteries (1 ) and (1 ) satisfy the condition

( ) ( ) .

Proposition 4.3 states that under Assumption 4.4, the preference in our model

satisfies stochastic dominance when is small enough, i.e., the DM is not very sensitive

to the potential disappointment.

Proposition 4.3. Under Assumption 4.3, there exists πœ€ ℝ, such that when [ πœ€],

( (1 ) ( ) ) ( (1 ) ( ) ) for any and any

.

A smaller indicates that the gambler is not sensitive to disappointment, which

may be true in practice. A gambler may be driven by the hope created by a large

anticipated outcome. If the effect of disappointment is also strong (large ), the utility of

Page 161: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

149

anticipation could be reduced by the disappointment, which would further reduce the

motivation for gambling. Since we observe many people repeating gambling activities,

we may infer that is small for these DMs.

Finally, by introducing the anticipation level in the choice set, our model can

avoid the problem of intransitivity encountered by Bleichrodt and Schmidt (2002). This is

apparent since the total ex ante utility ( ) is a representation of a transitive

preference order defined on the two attribute space .

4.6. DECISION MAKING MODELS

4.6.1. Portfolio selection decision

As previously discussed, a major difference between our model and the GM

model is that we do not assume that the DM optimizes her anticipation level to maximize

the total ex ante utility in decision making. Instead, we allow the anticipation level to be a

parameter that can be influenced by both exogenous and endogenous factors. This leads

to different implications for optimal decision making in the context of the portfolio

choice problem.

The portfolio choice problem involves the following choices. A decision maker

has initial wealth denoted by ℝ. She selects ℝ to invest in the risky asset which

has a random gross return . Her remaining wealth is invested in a risk free asset

which has a gross return . The objective is to select an optimal to maximize her

utility from holding both risky and risk free assets.

Page 162: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

150

In the GM model, for any given level of the allocation to the risky asset, the DM

selects her anticipation level so that her total ex ante utility is maximized. Thus, this

optimal anticipation level is a function of the allocation to the risky asset. Then, under the

optimal anticipation, the DM optimizes the allocation to the risky asset to maximize her

total ex ante utility. By solving a problem set up in this circular way, GM obtained the

result that optimism is negatively related to allocation to the risky asset, which seems to

be counterintuitive. They acknowledged that their result is somewhat surprising and that

it conflicts with the results predicted by optimal expectations models (Brumnermeier and

Parker 2005, Gollier 2005). Empirical studies have also confirmed that more optimistic

investors tend to hold more risky assets (Manju and Robinson 2007, Balasuriya 2010,

Nosic and Weber 2010). This shortcoming of the GM model is also addressed by Jouini

et al. (2013) in an extension of the GM model.

In the extended GM model (Jouini et al. 2013), the feasible domain of the

anticipation level is modified to show that the GM model can be consistent with the result

of the empirical studies on the relationship between optimism and investment in risky

asset. In this paper, we provide an alternative explanation and propose that the surprising

result in the GM model can be induced by the optimal anticipation assumption. It may be

true that in some cases a DM will intentionally adjust her anticipation level for the lottery

she chooses when she tries to increase her total ex ante utility, but this may not be a

general rule that applies to all situations. The belief of a DM, which we model as the

anticipation level, may be influenced by the context of the decision. For instance, in a

Page 163: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

151

bear market, no matter how optimistic an investor used to be, she may not be able to form

an optimistic anticipation level for money invested in stocks. Moreover, as we discussed

above, the circular set up of GM assumes that a DM can forecast how the allocation

decision will influence the total ex ante utility through the optimal anticipation, which

seems challenging in practice. In our development we relax this demanding requirement

that the DM will be able to optimize her anticipation level intentionally when facing such

a portfolio selection problem.

We allow the anticipation level to be influenced by contextual factors and set up

the portfolio decision model as follows. Influenced by the economic environment, the

DM forms anticipation for the random risky return, which is bounded by the

minimum and maximum possible outcomes of , i.e, [min max ]. Then, her

anticipated total wealth is given by ( ) ( ) . The utility of

anticipation is ( ( ) ) and the anticipated experienced utility is

(( ) (( ) ))

( (1 ) [( ) ( )] )

Utilizing these components in (4.2), the DM optimizes the allocation of her wealth to

risky asset by solving the following problem

max

( ) ( ( ) ) ( (1 ) [( ) ( )] )

(4.6)

Page 164: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

152

If we assume that both and are concave functions, ( ) is also a concave

function of as the sum of concave functions is still concave. Then, it is easy to obtain

the following result.

Proposition 4.4. The optimal investment in the risky asset in (4.6) is ( ) if

and only if 𝑣′( π‘Ÿ)( οΏ½οΏ½ π‘Ÿ)

β€²( π‘Ÿ( 𝛾)) ( )[ ( ) ( )] .

We expect a DM who invests in the financial market to anticipate that the risky

asset return exceeds the risk free return ; otherwise the investor would not

choose to invest in the risky asset. In this case, we can rewrite the optimal investment

condition in Proposition 4.4 as if and only if ( ) ( (1 ))

( ) ( ). Since the risk premium of the risky asset, , is positive,

when the anticipated return is low , ( ) ( ) is always negative

because [ 1] . In this case ( ) ( (1 )) ( ) ( )

always holds as and are both positive. Recall that the anticipation level can be

interpreted as a certainty equivalent of the lottery from anticipation based on subjective

probabilities. Thus, under the assumption of concave , when the subjective

probabilities become closer to the objective probabilities. So, the above results implies

that if the DM holds more rational beliefs that are closer to the objective probabilities, she

will always invest in the risky asset.

If the anticipated return is relatively high, e.g. , ( ) ( )

Page 165: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

153

is always smaller than one. If the marginal utility ratio ( ) ( (1 )) is

always larger than one, then and the DM always invests in the risky asset. In this

case, the inequality can be explained as the result of optimistic beliefs that

deviate significantly from objective probabilities. Thus, this result implies that when a

DM is very optimistic, she will invest in the risky asset only if the marginal utility she

derives from anticipation is large enough to counter the potential disappointment.

Now, we treat the anticipated return as a choice parameter and analyze how it

influences the optimal investment level which we will denote as ( ).

Proposition 4.5. There exists a ℝ such that 𝑑 ( οΏ½οΏ½)

𝑑 οΏ½οΏ½

if and only if (

( ) ) .

This proposition states that when the marginal utility from anticipation is large

enough at the optimal investment level, i.e., ( ( ) ) , the DM will

invest more given a higher anticipation level. This is a very intuitive result. The DM

will only increase the investment in a risky asset when the marginal utility she derives

from anticipation is large enough to offset the utility loss from the potential

disappointment.

Besides being consistent with the empirical finding that more optimistic DMs will

invest more in risky assets, our model can also be employed to explain the equity

premium puzzle, which can be described as follows: In order to explain the much higher

Page 166: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

154

available returns of risky assets (stocks) compared to riskless assets (bonds), investors

must have extremely high levels of risk aversion. GM noticed that the literature on

optimal expectations (Brunnermeier and Parker 2005, Gollier 2005) assumes the DM

always optimizes her beliefs and selects a risker portfolio, reinforcing the equity premium

puzzle, while their model implies that optimism of a DM is negatively related to the

investment in a risky asset, reducing the equity premium puzzle. However, empirical

studies suggest that a more optimistic DM will invest more in the risky asset (Manju and

Robinson 2007, Balasuriya 2010, Nosic and Weber 2010). Thus, although the GM model

is consistent with the equity premium puzzle, it conflicts with both our intuition and the

empirical finding that optimism should induce more risk taking behavior and more

investment in risky asset.

Our model can explain the equity premium puzzle and accommodate behavior

consistent with the notion that optimistic investors invest more in the risky asset. As

shown by Proposition 4.4, our model can be used to represent preferences with either

( ) or ( ) depending on functional form used to

model utility from anticipation. To be consistent with the empirical finding on the

relationship between optimism and risk taking, we should assume preferences exhibit

( ) , implying that a more optimistic DM will invest more in risky asset.

To explain the equity premium puzzle, we propose that if DMs in the financial market are

generally pessimistic, i.e., anticipate a lower level of , the model proposed here

implies a decrease in the demand for the risky asset, which increases the equity premium.

Page 167: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

155

Finally, we should emphasize that this descriptive flexibility comes from the relaxation of

the optimal anticipation (belief) assumed by models in the literature (Brunnermeier and

Parker 2005, Gollier 2005, Gollier and Muermann 2010).

4.6.2. Optimal advertising decision

In this section, we explore the optimal advertising level for a marketer facing a

consumer who trades off the utility of anticipation and the utility from anticipated

disappointment consistent with model (4.2). We will model the consumer’s decision to

purchase or not to purchase a single unit of a product. Further, we assume that the

customer will not know the quality of the product until after it is purchased and will

model the predicted quality as a simple lottery defined on a bounded payoff set

ℝ. However, we assume that the consumer has some knowledge about the probability

distribution of this uncertain quality level. Before purchasing the product, the consumer

anticipates the quality of the product [min max ] . Under the assumption of

model (4.2), the total ex ante utility derived from purchasing one unit of this product is

given by ( ) ( ) while the total ex ante utility from not purchasing the

product is .

Following the convention in the economics literature (e.g. Shogren 1994), we

assume the consumer has additive utility over wealth and her consumption of the product,

i.e., ( ) ( ) ( ) . The consumer’s willingness to pay ( ( )) is

determined by solving equation (4.7)

Page 168: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

156

( ) ( ) ( ( ) ) ( ) (4.7)

where ( ) is the utility function over her wealth.

For this problem, we can show that the maximum willingness to pay is obtained at

an interior level of the anticipation in the domain [min max ] under some standard

assumptions.

Proposition 4.6. Under some standard assumptions,

,

(min ) ( min ) and (max ) ( max ) , there

exists an interior optimal anticipation (min max ) such that ( ) is

maximized.

This proposition states that if a consumer derives utility from both anticipation

and the anticipated experienced utility, the optimal level to anticipate should be neither

too high nor too low.

Now, we consider a seller who is attempting to sell a new product to a collection

of consumers, each with a concave willingness to pay function ( ) due to the

tradeoff between high anticipation and high disappointment. To model the heterogeneity

of the consumers in the market, we assume the willingness to pay of each customer is

given by π‘Š 𝑃( ) ( ) πœ– , where πœ– is a mean zero random variable with

cumulative density function 𝐹 that captures the uniqueness of a consumer’s preferences.

If the seller sets the price of the product at 𝑃, the consumer will buy the product if

( ) πœ– 𝑃 . Therefore, the response function is given by (𝑃 ) 1

Page 169: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

157

𝐹(𝑃 ( )), which depends on both the price 𝑃 and anticipation . Further, the

seller can influence the anticipated quality of the product through her advertising effort,

, measured in dollars. We assume that the consumer’s anticipated quality of the product

is positively related to the advertising effort and is given by the linear relationship

𝜌 πœ”, where [ ] with (max πœ”) 𝜌, which is the effort level

that will cause the consumer to anticipate the highest possible quality. In this linear

relationship, πœ” is the base anticipation level of the consumer when no advertising effort

is exerted; and 𝜌 is the anticipation increase produced by one marginal unit of

advertising effort. This assumption of a positive relationship between the anticipated

quality of the product and the advertising effort has been documented by Deighton

(1984). Kirmani and Wright (1989) also verified that the perceived advertising expense

has a positive relationship with consumers’ expectation of product quality in a laboratory

setting.

It has been argued that increasing the expected quality of a product can increase

the demand for the product (Goering 1985) and that advertising is a likely mechanism to

increases the consumers’ quality expectation and therefore product sales (Simon and

Arndt 1980, Bagwell 2005, Erdem et al. 2008). However, as we show in Proposition 4.7,

the response function in our context is maximized at an β€œappropriate” level of advertising

effort , because a high anticipation level of product quality produced by the

advertising can also induce high anticipated disappointment, decreasing the consumer’s

willingness to pay. In other words, advertising can raise a consumer’s expectation so high

Page 170: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

158

that she would prefer not to purchase the product for fear of being disappointed with its

actual quality.

Proposition 4.7. For fixed price 𝑃, the response function is maximized at an advertising

effort level οΏ½οΏ½ πœ”

𝜌 , when ( ) , ( ) ( ) .

Finally, we consider a problem where a seller determines the optimal advertising

effort for a given price 𝑃 to maximize her profit πœ‹( ) . Each unit of product is

assumed to have a constant cost of production .

max

πœ‹( ) (𝑃 ) (1 𝐹(𝑃 (𝜌 πœ”)))

The first order condition of the above problem is (𝑃 )𝐹 (𝑃 (𝜌

πœ”)) (𝜌 πœ”)𝜌 1 3. Since attains its maximum at οΏ½οΏ½ πœ”

𝜌, we know

that the optimal advertising effort to maximize the total profit is πœ‹ , so that

(𝜌 πœ‹ πœ”) [ (𝑃 )𝐹 ( (𝜌 πœ‹ πœ”))]

>0. Therefore, we have the

following proposition.

Proposition 4.8. For fixed price 𝑃, the profit is maximized at an advertising effort level

that is lower than the effort level maximizing the willingness to pay, πœ‹ .

This result implies that sellers of a product should not always seek to increase

3 We also assume the second order condition is satisfied:

𝑑 πœ‹( )

𝑑 .

Page 171: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

159

consumers’ willingness to pay. When willingness to pay is above (𝜌 πœ‹ πœ”), the

marginal cost of the advertising effect ─ the unit cost in our model ─ outweighs the

marginal contribution to the profit produced by the increase in willingness to pay, which

further reduces the total profit. Again, increasing the anticipated quality level of a product

via advertising can reduce sales when customers grow concerned that their high

expectations cannot be satisfied and choose to abstain from a purchase.

4.7. CONCLUSION

In this chapter, we propose preference conditions for a decision making model

which incorporates both the utility of anticipation – hope and dread – and the anticipated

experienced utility – elation and disappointment – in a decision making process. This

model captures optimism and pessimism by allowing the DM to choose to anticipate a

high or low outcome of a lottery. The level of anticipation serves two roles in our model:

it is the source of the utility of anticipation in the period before the lottery is resolved as

well as the reference point used to form elation and disappointment after the lottery is

resolved.

We show that our model can account for how optimism could influence both the

DM’s risk attitude as well as the wealth effect on that risk attitude. This optimism can

explain the coexistence of gambling and purchasing of insurance without violating

stochastic dominance and transitivity. Finally, we discuss the applications of this model in

both finance and marketing contexts. In a simple setting with one risky and one risk-free

asset, we show that our model can capture the widely observed behavior that investor

Page 172: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

160

optimism is positively correlated with investment level in the risky asset. It also provides

an explanation for the equity premium puzzle without conflicting with the empirical

finding that optimism leads to more investment in a risky asset. In a marketing context,

we show that using advertising to increase the customer’s anticipation level of product

quality with the intent to increase her willingness to pay does not always increase the

demand for a product. This result conflicts with the intuition that product demand is

increasing with advertising and it should be studied in more detail with controlled

experiments.

4.8. SUPPLEMENTAL PROOFS

Theorem 4.1. Assumptions 4.1 holds if and only if the utility function ( ) can be

decomposed into

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ( )) (4.1)

with ( ) , ( ) , and ( ) .

Proof: Sufficiency: by Assumption 1, we have ( ) ( ) ( ) (

π›₯( ) ) ( ) ( ) ( [π›₯( ) π›₯( )] π›₯( ) ) , since ( ) and

( π›₯( ) ) are strategically equivalent to each other. Let and define

( ) [π›₯( ) π›₯( )] , ( ): ( ) , and ( ): ( π›₯( ) ) in

( ) ( ) ( ) ( [π›₯( ) π›₯( )] π›₯( ) ) , we have (1). By

definition of ( ) , we have ( ) . Since utility function is unique up to affine

Page 173: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

161

transformation, we can rescale the utility function ( ) such that (π›₯( ) )

and ( ) . Thus, we have ( ) and ( ) .

Necessity: for any and any , if ( ) ( ) , from model (4.1)

we have,

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ( )) ( ) ( ) ( ( )) ( )

which implies ( ( )) ( ( )) . For any , since βˆ€ ,

( ) , this inequality is equivalent to

( ) ( ) ( ( ) ( ) ( ))

( ) ( ) ( ( ) ( ) ( ))

Define Ξ”( ) ( ) ( ), so we have ( Ξ”( ) ) ( Ξ”( ) ). β–‘

Theorem 4.2. Assumptions 4.2 and 4.3 hold if and only if the utility function ( )

can be decomposed into

( ) ( ) ( ) (4.2)

with [ 1] ( ) ( ) .

Proof: Sufficiency: Assumption 4.2 implies ( ) ( ) (

π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) ) . Let and rescale ( ) such that

( ) , we have ( ) ( π›₯( ) ) (π›₯( ) ) . Define ( )

Page 174: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

162

Ξ”( ) , ( ) (π›₯( ) ) , and ( ( )) ( ( ) ) , we have

( ) ( ) ( ( )).

Now, we prove ( ) is linear. According to Assumption 4.2, for any

and , we have {( ) ( )} ∼ {( π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) )} .

Expressing this condition in term of ( ), we have

( ) ( ) ( π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) )

Let π›₯( ), the above equation is equivalent to

( ) ( ) ( π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) )

Similarly, we have for

( ) ( ) ( π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) )

( π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) )

( π›₯( ) π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) π›₯( ) )

Thus, we have

( ) ( ) ( π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) )

( π›₯( ) π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) π›₯( ) )

According to Assumption 4.3, this π›₯( ) is unique which is a function depends

on the difference between and , namely π›₯( ) ( ) is unique. Thus, from

the uniqueness of this π›₯( ), we have

Page 175: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

163

( ) ( ) ( )

By setting in above equation, we have ( ) ( ) ( ) . Let

, we have ( ) ( ) ( ), which is a Cauchy functional equation

(AczΓ©l 2006). The solution to this equation is ( ) for ℝ . Because

Assumption 4.3 states that ( ) [ ] for , we have [ 1]. Since

we defined ( ) Ξ”( ) ( ) , we have ( ) . Finally, from π›₯( ) ,

( ) (π›₯( ) ), and ( ( )) ( ( ) ), it is easy to conclude that

( ) and ( ) .

Necessity: Given ( ) ( ) ( ), we have

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ( ) ) ( ) ( ( ) )

( ( ) ) ( ( ) )

Define π›₯( ): ( ) , since [ 1] , we know there exits π›₯( )

( ) [ ] such that Assumption 4.2 holds. This also proves π›₯( )

[ ] in Assumption 4.3.

Finally, to prove the uniqueness of π›₯( ) stated in Assumption 4.3, suppose

there exists another π›₯ ( ) π›₯( ) such that ( ) ( ) (

π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) )

Let π›₯( ) , we have

Page 176: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

164

( π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) )

( π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) )

( π›₯( ) π›₯( ) ) ( π›₯( ) π›₯( ) )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

Since are arbitrary, are also arbitrary. Denote utility function

( ) by ( ). The last equation above is equivalent to ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) for any . Taking derivative with respect to , we have ( ) (

) . Then, taking derivative with respect to , we have ( ) , which

implies ( ) ( ) is a linear function in . This violates the law of diminishing

marginal utility. Thus, the π›₯( ) is unique. β–‘

Proposition 4.1. Under the assumptions of model (4.2), for a given lottery when the

DM anticipates , the risk premium ( ) for depends on in the following

ways:

i. If ( ) ( ) , then ( ) The DM exhibits

increased risk seeking behavior due to optimism .

ii. If ( ) ( ) , then ( ) The DM exhibits

increased risk seeking behavior due to pessimism.

Proof: According to the definition ( ) 𝐂𝐄( | ), ( ) ( )

if and only if 𝑑𝐂𝐄( | οΏ½οΏ½)

𝑑 οΏ½οΏ½

( ). By definition (𝐂𝐄( | ) 𝐂𝐄( | )) ( )

Page 177: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

165

and model (4.2) ( ) ( ) ( ) , we have (𝐂𝐄( | ))

((1 )𝐂𝐄( | )) ( ) ( ). Thus, we have:

[ (𝐂𝐄( | )) (1 ) ((1 )𝐂𝐄( | ))] 𝐂𝐄( | )

( ) ( )

It is easy to verify that 𝑑𝐂𝐄( | οΏ½οΏ½)

𝑑 οΏ½οΏ½

( ) if and only if ( ) (

) ( ). β–‘

Proposition 4.2. When 1, ( ) , we have: 𝐂𝐄( ) ( ) if and only

if ( )𝐂𝐄; when [ 1), we have:

i. If , 𝐂𝐄 and (1 )𝐂𝐄

implies 𝐂𝐄( )

ii. If , 𝐂𝐄 and (1 )𝐂𝐄

implies 𝐂𝐄( ) .

iii. If , 𝐂𝐄 and (1 )𝐂𝐄

implies 𝑑𝐂𝐄( )

𝑑

iv. If , 𝐂𝐄 and (1 )𝐂𝐄

implies 𝐂𝐄( )

Moreover, if we replace with and ( )𝐂𝐄 with (

)𝐂𝐄, the sign of 𝐂𝐄( ) is unchanged.

Page 178: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

166

Proof: From (4.3) in the text, we know

𝑑𝐂𝐄( )

𝑑

𝑣′( οΏ½οΏ½ ) 𝑣′(𝐂𝐄 ) ( 𝛾)[𝐸 β€²( 𝛾( οΏ½οΏ½)) β€²( 𝐂𝐄 𝛾( 𝐂𝐄))]

𝑣′(𝐂𝐄 ) ( 𝛾) β€²( 𝐂𝐄 𝛾( 𝐂𝐄))

When 1, since , the sign of 𝑑𝐂𝐄( )

𝑑 is determined by the comparison

between and 𝐂𝐄. When [ 1). We only show case i here. The other cases can be

obtained by following the same idea. When , from , by

Jensen’s inequality, we can conclude ( ( )) (

( )) . From , (1 )𝐂𝐄 implies (

(1 ) ) ((1 )𝐂𝐄 (1 ) ). Thus, we have

( ( )) ( 𝐂𝐄 ( 𝐂𝐄))

( ( )) ( 𝐂𝐄 ( 𝐂𝐄))

Moreover, from and 𝐂𝐄 , we have ( ) (𝐂𝐄 ) .

Therefore, we can conclude the numerator of the above equation is positive. Since we

also assume and , we conclude that 𝐂𝐄( ) in this case.β–‘

Proposition 4.3. Under Assumption 4.4, there exists πœ€ ℝ, such that when [ πœ€],

( (1 ) ( ) ) ( (1 ) ( ) ) for any and any

.

Proof: Since the lottery X is the common part for both compounding lotteries

Page 179: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

167

considered here, we simply denote the anticipation by ( ) indicating that the

anticipation depends on , which is the certain payoff compounded with . Stochastic

dominance requires that when :

( (1 ) ( )) ( ( )) ( ( )) (1 ) ( ( ))

( ( )) ( ( )) (1 ) ( ( )) ( (1 ) ( ))

Under the assumption of consistent compounding in anticipation, we have ( )

( ) for any , namely ( ) ( ) , stochastic dominance is

satisfied by our model when ( (1 ) ( )) , which is equivalent to

the condition

( ( )) ( ) ( ( ))(1 ( )) (1 ) ( ( )) ( )

Without loss of generality, we assume that marginal utility is bounded, i.e.,

[ β€² β€²]. Then, let πœ€ solves the following equation

( ( )) ( ) β€²(1 πœ€ ( )) (1 ) β€²πœ€ ( )

πœ€ ( ( )) ( ) β€²

[ β€² (1 ) β€²] ( )

when ( ) , ( ) , and ( ) .

Then, we have for any [ πœ€],

Page 180: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

168

( ( )) ( ) ( ( ))(1 ( ))

( ( )) ( ) β€²(1 πœ€ ( )) (1 ) β€²πœ€ ( )

(1 ) ( ( )) ( )

which implies that the stochastic dominance holds. β–‘

Proposition 4.4. The optimal investment in the risky asset in (4.6) is ( ) if

and only if 𝑣′( π‘Ÿ)( οΏ½οΏ½ π‘Ÿ)

β€²( π‘Ÿ( 𝛾)) ( )[ ( ) ( )] .

Proof: Taking derivative with respect to in (4.6), we have:

( )

( ( ( ) )( )

[( ) ( )] ( (1 ) [( ) ( )] )

Since we assume and are concave, ( ) is also concave. Thus, π‘‘π‘ˆ( )

𝑑 |

( ) is equivalent to ( ), which leads to the result. β–‘

Proposition 4.5. There exists a ℝ such that 𝑑 ( οΏ½οΏ½)

𝑑 οΏ½οΏ½

if and only if (

( ) ) .

Proof : When no derivative of ( ) is taken, we keep using for simplicity.

By differentiating the first order condition with respect to for (4.7), we can solve for

Page 181: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

169

𝑑 ( οΏ½οΏ½)

𝑑 οΏ½οΏ½

as follows

𝑑 ( οΏ½οΏ½)

𝑑 οΏ½οΏ½

𝛾𝐸[( π‘Ÿ) 𝛾( οΏ½οΏ½ π‘Ÿ)] β€²β€²(𝑄( )) 𝛾𝐸 β€²(𝑄( )) 𝑣′(𝑍( )) ( οΏ½οΏ½ π‘Ÿ)𝑣′′(𝑍( ))

( οΏ½οΏ½ π‘Ÿ) 𝑣′′(𝑍( )) 𝐸[( π‘Ÿ) 𝛾( οΏ½οΏ½ π‘Ÿ)]

β€²β€²(𝑄( ))

where we define two functions ( ) (1 ) [( ) ( )] and

𝑍( ) ( ) to simplify the expression above. Under the assumption that

and , the denominator of the right hand side is negative. Therefore, a

negative numerator is equivalent to a positive 𝑑 ( οΏ½οΏ½)

𝑑 οΏ½οΏ½

. A negative numerator is

equivalent to the condition: [( ) ( )] ( ( )) ( ( ))

(𝑍( )) ( ) (𝑍( )) . Finally, define [( ) (

)] ( ( )) ( ( )) ( ) (𝑍( )), we can get the result in the

proposition. β–‘

Proposition 4.6. Under some standard assumptions,

,

(min ) ( min ) and (max ) ( max ) ,

there exists an interior optimal anticipation (min max ) such that ( ) is

maximized.

Proof: Note that the consumer’s willingness to pay is a function of her

anticipation for this one unit of the product. Differentiating both sides of (4.7) with

respect to aX,

( ) ( ) ( ( ) ) ( ) (4.7)

Page 182: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

170

we find ( ) 𝑣′( οΏ½οΏ½) 𝛾𝐸 β€²( 𝛾 οΏ½οΏ½)

𝑀′ ( ( οΏ½οΏ½))

. When , ( ) (

) , and ( ) ( ) , we have ( )

and ( ) . If we take the derivative of (4.7) with respect to twice, we

can solve for

( ) ( ) ( ) ( ( ))

( ( ) )

( ( ))

Under the assumption of , and , we can verify that ( )

. Thus, we can conclude the result stated in the proposition. β–‘

Proposition 4.7. For fixed price 𝑃, the response function is maximized at an advertising

effort level οΏ½οΏ½ πœ”

𝜌 , when ( ) , ( ) ( ) .

Proof: By taking the derivative of (𝑃 ) 1 𝐹(𝑃 (𝜌 πœ”)) with

respect to , we have (𝑃 ) 𝐹 (𝑃 (𝜌 πœ”)) (𝜌 πœ”)𝜌. Since 𝐹 ,

we know from Proposition 4.6 that when 𝜌 πœ” , , and (𝑃 ) ,

sales are increasing with ; when 𝜌 πœ” , and (𝑃 ) , sales are

decreasing in . β–‘

Page 183: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

171

REFERENCES

AczΓ©l, J. 2006. Lectures on Functional Equations and Their Applications. Dover

Publication. Mineola, New York. 31-32.

Abbas, A. E., D. Bell. 2011. One-Switch Independence for Multiattribute Utility

Functions. Operations Research. 59(3) 764-771.

Abbas, A. E. 2009. Multiattribute Utility Copulas. Operations Research. 57(6) 1367-

1383.

Akerlof, G. A., W. T. Dickens. 1982. The Economic Consequences of Cognitive

Dissonance. American Economic Review. 72(3) 307–319.

Anderson, C., A. D. Galinsky. 2006. Power, Optimism, and Risk-taking. European

Journal of Social Psychology. 36(4) 511-536.

Bagwell, K., 2005. The Economic Analysis of Advertising. Discussion Papers 0506-01,

Columbia University, Department of Economics.

Balasuriya, J., Y. G. Muradoglu, P. Ayton. 2010. Optimism and Portfolio Choice.

Working paper Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1568908 or

http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1568908

Baucells, M., F. H. Heukamp. 2012. Probability and Time Trade-Off. Management

Science. 58(4), 831-842..

Baucells, M., R. K. Sarin. 2007. Satiation in Discounted Utility. Operations Research.

55(1) 170-181.

Baucells, M., R. K. Sarin. 2010. Predicting Utility under Satiation and Habit Formation.

Management Science. 56(2) 286-301.

Baucells, M., M. Weber, F. Welfens. 2011. Reference-Point Formation and Updating.

Management Science. 57(3) 506-519.

Page 184: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

172

Bell, D. E., 1974. Evaluating Time Streams of Income. Omega. 2(5) 691-699.

Bell, D. E., 1979. Consistent Assessment Procedures Using Conditional Utility

Functions. Operations Research. 27(5) 1054-1066.

Bell, D. E., 1985 Disappointment in Decision Making Under Uncertainty, Operations

Research. 33(1) 1-27.

BΓ©nabou, R., J. Tirole, 2002. Self-Confidence and Personal Motivation. The Quarterly

Journal of Economics. 117(3) 871-915.

Bleichrodt, H., U. Schmidt. 2002 A Context-Dependent Model of the Gambling Effect.

Management Science. 48(6) 802-812

Bosch-Domenech, A., J.S. Benach, 2005. Ready to Take Risks? Experimental Evidence

on Risk Aversion and Attraction. CREI working paper:

http://www.crei.cat/research/opuscles/op16ang.pdf

Brunnermeier, M. K., J. A. Parker. 2005 Optimal expectations. American Economic

Review. 95(4) 1092–1118.

Brunnermeier, M. K., C. Gollier. J. A. Parker. 2007. Optimal beliefs, asset prices, and the

preference for skewed returns. American Economic Review. 97(2) 159–165.

Caballero, G.A. 2010. Risk Preferences Under Extreme Poverty: A Field Experiment.

SSRN working paper. Documento CEDE No. 2010-33. Available at SSRN:

http://ssrn.com/abstract=1720983 or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1720983

Caplin, A., J. Leahy. 2001. Psychological Expected Utility Theory and Anticipatory

Feelings. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 116(1) 55-79.

Carroll, P. J., K. Sweeny, J. A. Shepperd. 2006. Forsaking Optimism. Review of General

Psychology. 10(1) 56–73.

Carroll, C. D., J. Overland., D. N. Weil. 2000. Saving and Growth with Habit Formation.

American Economic Review. 90(3) 341-355.

Page 185: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

173

Chew, S. H., J. L. Ho. 1994. Hope: An Empirical Study of Attitude Toward the Timing of

Uncertainty Resolution. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 8(3) 267-88.

Chuang, S. C., H. M. Lin. 2007. The Effect of Induced Positive and Negative Emotion

and Openness-to-Feeling in Student’s Consumer Decision Making. Journal of

Business and Psychology. 22(1) 65-78

Conlisk, J. 1993. The Utility of Gambling. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 6(3) 255-

275.

Deighton, J. 1984. The Interaction of Advertising and Evidence. Journal of Consumer

Research. 11(3) 763-770.

DelquiΓ©, P., A. Cillo 2006 Disappointment Without Prior Expectation: a Unifying

Perspective on Decision under Risk. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 33(3) 197-

215.

Diecidue, E. U. Schmidt. P.P. Wakker. 2004. The Utility of Gambling Reconsidered.

Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 29(3)241-259.

Dillenberger, D., K. Rozen, 2011. History-Dependent Risk Attitude. PIER Working

Paper No. 11-004.

Dyer, J. S., R. K. Sarin. 1979. Measurable Multiattribute Value Function, Operations

Research. 27(4) 810-822.

Dyer, J. S., J. Jia. 1997. Relative Risk-Value Models. European Journal of Operational

Research. 103(1) 170–185.

Eeckhoudt, L., B. Rey, H. Schlesinger. 2007. A Good Sign for Multi-variate Risk Taking.

Management Science. 53(1) 117–124.

Epstein, L. G., I. Kopylov, 2007. Cold feet. Theoretical Economics 2(3) 231–259

Page 186: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

174

Erdem, T., M. Keane. B.H. Sun. 2008. The Impact of Advertising on Consumer Price

Sensitivity in Experience Goods Markets. Quantitative Marketing and Economics,

6(2) 139-176.

Farquhar, P. H., R. L. Keller. 1989 Preference Intensity Measurement, Annals of

Operations Research. 19. 205-217.

Fishburn, P.C. 1965. Independence in Utility Theory with Whole Product Sets.

Operations Research. 13(1) 28-45.

Fishburn, P.C. 1970. Utility Theory for Decision Making. Publications in Operations

Research, No. 18. New York: John Wiley and Sons.

Fishburn, P. C. 1974. von Neumann-Morgenstern Utility Functions on Two Attributes,

Operations Research. 22(1) 35-45.

Fishburn, P. C. 1977. Approximations of Two-attribute Utility Functions. Mathematics of

Operations Research. 2(1) 30-44.

Fishburn, P. C. 1980. A Simple Model of the Utility of Gambling. Psychometrika 45

435-448.

Fishburn, P. C., R. H. Farquhar. 1982. Finite-Degree Utility Independence, Mathematics

of Operations Research, 7(3) 348-353.

Fishburn, P. C., R. L. Keeney, 1974. Seven Independence Concepts and Continuous

Multiattribute Utility Functions. Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 11(3) 294-

327

Fishburn, P. C., R. L. Keeney, 1975. Generalized Utility Independence and Some

Implications. Operations Research. 23(5) 928-940.

Fishburn, P. C., A. Rubinstein. 1982. Time Preference. International Economic Review.

23(3) 677-694.

Page 187: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

175

Frederick, S., G. Loewenstein, T. O'Donoghue. 2002. Time Discounting and Time

Preference: A Critical Review. Journal of Economic Literature. 40(2) 351-401

Friedman, M., L. J. Savage. 1948. The Utility Analysis of Choices Involving Risk.

Journal of Political Economy. 56(4) 279–304.

Gilboa, I., D. Schmeidler. 2001. A cognitive model of individual well-being. Social

Choice and Welfare, 18(2) 269-288.

Goering, P. A. 1985. Effects of Product Trial on Consumer Expectations, Demand, and

Prices. Journal of Consumer Research. 12(1) 74-82.

Gollier, C., A. Muermann. 2010. Optimal Choice and Beliefs with Ex Ante Savoring and

Ex Post Disappointment. Management Science. 56(8) 1272-1284.

He, Y., J. S. Dyer, J. C. Butler. 2013 On the Axiomatization of Satiation and Habit

Formation Utility Function. Operations Research, forthcoming

Hoch, S. J., G. F. Loewenstein. 1991. Time-Inconsistent Preferences and Consumer Self-

Control. Journal of Consumer Research, 17(4) 492-507.

Jia, J., S. Dyer 1996 A Standard Measure of Risk and Risk-Value Models, Management

Science. 42(12) 1691-1705

Jia, J., J. S. Dyer, J. Butler 2001 Generalized Disappointment Models. Journal of Risk

and Uncertainty. 22(1) 59-78

Johnson, E. J., A. Tversky. 1983. Affect, Generalization, and the Perception of

Risk. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 45 (1) 20-31.

Jouini, Elyes, Karehnke, 2013. Paul and Napp, Clotilde, On Portfolio Choice with

Savoring and Disappointment. Management Science, forthcoming. Available at

SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2291836

Keeney, R. L., H. Raiffa. 1976. Decisions with Multiple Objectives: Preferences and

Value Tradeoffs, Wiley, New York

Page 188: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

176

Kirmani, A., P. Wright. 1989. Money talks: Perceived advertising expense and expected

product quality. Journal of Consumer Research. 16(3) 344–353.

Koopmans, T. C. 1960. Stationary Ordinal Utility and Impatience. Econometrica. 28(2)

287–309.

Krantz, D. H., R. D. Luce, P. Suppes, A. Tversky. 1971. Foundations of Measurement.

Vol. 1. Academic Press. New York. 136-198.

Lesieur, H. R., 1992 Compulsive Gambling. Society 29(4) 43-50.

Lichtendahl Jr., K. C., R. O. Chao, S. E. Bodily. 2012. Habit Formation From Correlation

Aversion. Operations Research. 60 (3) 625-637.

Loewenstein, G. 1987. Anticipation and the Valuation of Delayed Consumption. The

Economic Journal. 97(387) 666-684.

Loewenstein, G., & Linville, P. (1986). Expectation formation and the timing of

outcomes: A cognitive strategy for balancing the conflicting incentives for savoring

success and avoiding disappointment. Unpublished manuscript

Loomes, G., R. Sugden. 1986. Disappointment and Dynamic Consistency in Choice

under Uncertainty. Review of Economic Studies. 53(2) 271-282.

Lybbert, T. J., C. B. Barrett, 2011. Risk-Taking Behavior In The Presence Of Nonconvex

Asset Dynamics. Economic Inquiry, Western Economic Association International.

49(4) 982-988.

Manju, P., D. T. Robinson, 2007. Optimism and Economic Choice, Journal of Financial

Economics. 86(1) 71-99.

Mansour, B. S., E. Jouini, J. M. Marin, C. Napp, C. Robert. 2008. Are Risk Averse

Agents More Optimistic? A Bayesian Estimation Approach. Journal of Applied

Econometrics. 32(6) 843–860.

Page 189: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

177

Misina, M. 2005. Risk Perceptions and Attitudes. Bank of Canada Working Papers 05-

17. http://www.bankofcanada.ca/2005/06/publications/research/working-paper-

2005-17/

Mosley, P., A. Verschoor, 2005 Risk Attitudes and the β€œVicious Circle of Poverty”.

European Journal of Development Research. 17(1) 59-88

Nosic, A., M. Weber. 2010. How Risky Do I Invest: The Role of Risk Attitudes, Risk

Perceptions, and Overconfidence. Decision Analysis, 7(3) 282-301.

Pollak, R. A. 1970. Habit Formation and Dynamic Demand Functions. The Journal of

Political Economy. 78(4) 745-763.

Read, D., G. F. Loewenstein, M. Rabin. 1999. Choice Bracketing. Journal of Risk

Uncertainty. 19(1-3) 171-197.

Rey B., J. C. Rochet. 2004. Health and Wealth: How do They Affect Individual

Preferences? The Geneva papers on Risk and Insurance-Theory. 29(1) 43-54.

Rozen, K. 2010. Foundations of Intrinsic Habit Formation. Econometirca. 78(4). 1341-

1373.

Samuelson, P. 1937. A Note on Measurement of Utility. The Review of Economics Study.

4(2) 155–161.

Schmidt, U. 1998. A Measurement of the Certainty Effect. Journal of Mathematical

Psychology. 42(1) 32-47.

Shogren, J. F., S.Y. Shin, D. J. Hayes, J. B. Kliebenstein. 1994. Resolving Differences in

Willingness to Pay and Willingness to Accept. The American Economic Review.

84(1) 255-270.

Simon, J. L., & Arndt, J. (1980). The Shape of The Advertising Response Function.

Journal Of Advertising Research, 20(4), 11.

Page 190: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

178

Slovic, P., E. Peters, M. L. Finucane, D. G. MacGregor. 2005. Affect, Risk, and Decision

making. Health Psychology. 24(4) S35-S40.

Tamura, H., Y. Nakamura. 1983. Decompositions of Multiattribute Utility Functions

based on Convex Dependence. Operations Research. 31(3) 488-505.

Taylor, K. M., J. A. Shepperd. 1998. Bracing for the Worst: Severity Testing, and

Feedback Timing as Moderators of the Optimistic Bias. Personality Social

Psychology Bulletin. 24(9) 915–926.

Tsetlin I., R. L. Winkler. 2009. Multiattribute Utility Satisfying a Preference for

Combining Good with Bad. Management Science. 55(12) 1942-1952.

van Dijk, W.W., M. Zeelenberg, J. van Der Pligt. 2003 Blessed are Those Who Expect

Nothing: Lowering Expectations as a Way of Avoiding Disappointment. Journal of

Economic Psychology. 24(4) 505-516

VΓ€stfjΓ€ll, D., E. Peters, P. Slovic. 2008. Affect, Risk Perception and Future Optimism

after the Tsunami Disaster. Judgment and Decision Making. 3(1) 64-72.

Vieider, F. M., T. Chmura. P. Martinsson. 2012. Risk Attitudes, Development, and

Growth: Macroeconomic Evidence From experiments in 30 Countries, No SP II

2012-401, Discussion Papers, WZB Junior Research Group Risk and Development,

Social Science Research Center Berlin (WZB),

http://EconPapers.repec.org/RePEc:zbw:wzbrad:spii2012401.

Wathieu, L. 1997. Habits and the Anomalies in Intertemporal Choice. Management

Science. 43(11) 1552–1563.

Wathieu, L. 2004. Consumer Habituation. Management Science. 50(5) 587-596.

Yesuf, M., R. A. Bluffstone, 2009 Poverty, Risk Aversion, and Path Dependence in Low-

Income Countries: Experimental Evidence from Ethiopia. American Journal of

Agricultural Economics. 91(4) 1022-1037.

Page 191: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

179

Zhao, J. 2006. The Effects of Induced Positive and Negative Emotions on Risky Decision

Making. Talk presented at the 28th Annual Psychological Society of Ireland Student

Congress, Maynooth, Ireland.

http://www.princeton.edu/~jiayingz/pdfs/BAThesis06.pdf

Page 192: DECOMPOSITION OF MULTIPLE ATTRIBUTE PREFERENCE MODELS

180

VITA

Ying He was born in Xianyang, Shaanxi Province, People Republic of China, on

March 31th, 1982, the son of Yaowu He and Shulian Sun. After graduating from

Xianyang Shi-Yan High School in July 2000, he entered Xian Jiaotong University, where

he spent eight years before came to the USA. He received his bachelor degree in

economics from School of Economics and Finance at Xi’an Jiaotong University and

entered a Ph.D. program in School of Management to study management science in July

2004. In Aug 2008, he entered the Ph.D. program in the department of Information, Risk,

and Operations Management at The University of Texas at Austin to pursue his Ph.D.

degree. In Dec 2010, he received a M.S. degree in Information, Risk, and Operations

Management from The University of Texas at Austin.

Permanent Address: IROM department, 2110 Speedway Stop B6500, Austin, TX 78712

This manuscript was typed by the author