evans-aristotle on relativism

Upload: oscar-leandro-gonzalez-ruiz

Post on 01-Jun-2018

221 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/9/2019 Evans-Aristotle on Relativism

    1/12

    Scots Philosophical Association

    University of St Andrews

    Aristotle on RelativismAuthor(s): J. D. G. EvansSource: The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 24, No. 96 (Jul., 1974), pp. 193-203Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the Scots Philosophical Association and theUniversity of St. Andrews

    Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2217933 .

    Accessed: 22/01/2015 09:51

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

     .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of 

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

     .

    Oxford University Press, Scots Philosophical Association, University of St. Andrews are collaborating with

    JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Quarterly.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:51:50 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ouphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=spahttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ustandrewhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2217933?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2217933?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ustandrewhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=spahttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=oup

  • 8/9/2019 Evans-Aristotle on Relativism

    2/12

    THE

    PHLOSOP

    QU RTERL

    VOL.

    24

    No. 96

    JULY

    1974

    ARISTOTLE

    ON

    RELATIVISM

    BY

    J. D.

    G.

    EVANS

    Let

    me first state

    dogmatically

    the dialectical situation

    which we shall

    be

    exploring

    in detail as this

    paper develops.

    For

    Aristotle,

    Plato

    was

    a

    realist,

    Protagoras

    a relativist. He

    could

    view each as

    presenting

    his

    position

    in conscious

    reaction

    to the other and in the belief that one or

    other of

    them

    is correct.

    Yet

    Aristotle

    regards

    the theories of each

    as

    seriously

    defective.

    What

    I

    want to consider is

    why

    Aristotle finds them

    inadequate,

    and

    what

    possible

    position

    is left for him if he will

    accept

    neither of the

    alternatives.

    The

    situation

    in which he finds

    himself

    is characteristic. Time

    and

    again

    he

    prefaces

    his

    accounts

    with a

    statement of the

    conflicting

    answers

    of his

    predecessors,

    in such a

    way

    that even

    though

    there is indeed

    good

    reason

    for thinking them all wrong, there seems to be no scope for any further

    answer.

    It is most

    important

    for our

    understanding

    of Aristotle's

    conception

    of

    philosophy

    to see the

    manner in

    which he views

    his

    problem

    and the method

    by

    which he resolves

    it. The

    following

    passage

    from the

    Eudemian

    Ethics

    (H

    2,

    1235b

    13-18)

    tells

    us much about this:

    We

    must

    adopt

    a

    line of

    argument

    which will both

    best

    explain

    to

    us the views

    held

    about

    these matters and will resolve the

    difficulties

    and

    contradictions;

    and we shall achieve this

    if

    we show

    that the

    conflicting

    views

    are held with

    good

    reason. For such an

    argument

    will most closely accord with the agreed facts; and it will allow the

    conflicting

    views

    to

    be retained if

    analysis

    can show

    that

    each

    is

    partly

    true and

    partly

    false.

    In other

    words,

    Aristotle

    wants

    to

    preserve

    the obvious truths

    of common

    sense,

    and

    at the

    same

    time

    to do

    full

    justice

    to those

    aspects

    of the

    philo-

    sophers'

    paradoxes

    which

    incline us

    to

    see

    something

    in them.

    He

    will

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:51:50 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Evans-Aristotle on Relativism

    3/12

    194 J. D.

    G.

    EVANS

    disarm

    the

    paradox,

    by

    separating

    the

    true

    insight

    from

    the

    outrageous

    conclusion which was built

    upon

    it. He will

    also eliminate

    from

    the

    com-

    bination

    of all

    the views the

    conflict which

    presently

    characterizes it:

    dis-

    agreement will be shown to be the consequence of the distortion of the

    importance

    of

    some

    single aspect

    of

    the case.

    We

    shall see

    in detail

    later

    how this

    method

    operates.

    The natural

    place

    to look

    for Aristotle's

    treatment of

    relativism is

    Meta-

    physics

    F. In fact

    I

    shall

    be

    concentrating

    more

    on certain

    other

    texts.

    But

    I

    want

    first to

    say

    something

    about the

    arguments

    in

    r

    and

    why

    I

    find them

    not

    so

    interesting

    as

    certain other

    discussions. He is

    here

    princip-

    ally

    concerned with

    thinkers who

    deny

    the

    law of

    non-contradiction.

    He

    includes

    under

    this

    heading

    Protagoras,

    on the

    ground

    that his

    relativization

    of truth enabled him

    to allow that

    p

    and

    not-p

    could each

    be

    true for different

    persons.

    Now Aristotle

    maintains

    that this law is

    the

    most

    fundamental

    principle

    in

    reasoning;

    and

    he

    argues

    that it

    follows

    from it

    that

    it

    is im-

    possible

    for

    anyone

    to

    believe that

    there

    is

    a

    counter-instance

    to it.

    For

    a

    belief that

    p

    is

    contrary

    to

    a

    belief

    that

    not-p;

    and so

    someone

    who,

    for

    any

    substitution

    for

    p,

    believed

    both,

    would

    be

    in

    two

    contrary

    states. That this

    is

    impossible

    is a

    consequence

    of the law

    of

    non-contradiction

    (Met.

    F

    3).

    This is

    not,

    of

    course,

    a

    proof

    of

    the law.

    What

    it

    does

    establish is that

    the law is fundamental; for it cannot be doubted by one who accepts it,

    whatever he claims to

    the

    contrary.

    If it

    cannot

    be

    doubted,

    it

    cannot be

    proved;

    and

    although

    Christopher

    Kirwan

    says

    that,

    despite

    saying

    this,

    Aristotle

    goes

    on to

    try

    to

    prove

    it in

    Met.

    1

    4-6,1

    he

    misconstrues

    Aristotle's

    purpose.

    Aristotle

    divides those who

    deny

    the law

    into

    two

    kinds,

    those

    who do

    it for

    the

    contentious

    reason

    of

    saying

    something

    paradoxical,

    and

    those

    who

    do

    it out

    of a

    genuine

    sense of

    perplexity.

    The

    former

    want

    to

    win

    an

    argument.

    Since

    their

    demand for

    a

    proof

    of the law

    cannot be

    met,

    their denial of it

    cannot be

    refuted.2

    Even

    the

    peritropic argument,3

    which

    is one of the

    strongest

    weapons

    in the arsenal of the

    opponent

    of

    relativism,

    is not

    conclusive.

    This

    argument

    claims

    that

    the

    statement

    all

    truth

    is

    relative to

    the

    individual who

    believes

    it

    must be

    itself

    an

    absolute

    truth

    -that

    is,

    true

    for

    everyone;

    and

    so if

    some

    person

    denies

    it,

    it

    must

    be

    false

    for him. It

    is,

    then,

    both true and

    false for

    him;

    and

    since

    the

    relativist

    thesis states that no

    one ever

    has a

    mistaken

    belief,

    the

    dissenter's

    denial

    of

    this

    thesis

    constitutes a

    counter-instance to

    it.

    The

    thesis

    cannot

    co-exist

    with someone

    who

    denies it. But

    the

    extreme

    relativist

    can

    break this

    argument by denying that his thesis is 'an absolute truth. He can claim

    that this

    thesis is true

    only

    for

    him;

    and

    that

    this

    is

    not in

    the

    least

    affected

    by

    the fact

    that it is

    false for

    someone

    else.

    In

    taking

    this

    stance the

    relativist

    assumes the

    life of a

    plant,

    as

    Aristotle

    says (1008b 10-12).

    His

    position

    1Aristotle's

    Metaphysics

    r, A,

    E

    (Oxford,

    1971),

    p.

    113.

    sSee

    Met.

    1009a

    16-23,

    1011a

    8-25,

    1012a

    17-21.

    3Met.

    1008a

    28-34,

    1012b

    13-18.

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:51:50 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Evans-Aristotle on Relativism

    4/12

    ARISTOTLE

    ON

    RELATIVISM

    195

    rules out

    the

    possibility

    of rational discussion

    and thus

    is

    trivialized.

    But

    the

    position

    is

    open

    to

    him if

    he wants

    it.

    So

    Aristotle is

    not

    concerned

    with an

    opponent

    of this

    type.

    His

    interest

    lies rather with the victim of honest perplexity who thinks he can see some-

    thing

    in the reasons for

    the relativist's

    position

    and thus is

    unable to

    sleep

    safely

    with the view of

    the committed realist.

    This man needs a

    therapeutic

    type

    of

    dialectic,

    which

    will enable him to see both the nature of the con-

    siderations

    which

    incline him to relativism and

    how

    those considerations

    do

    not in fact

    promote

    the conclusion

    which he

    is

    inclined

    to

    draw from them.

    The

    majority

    of the

    numerous

    arguments

    in

    Met.

    F

    4-6 are of a Platonic

    character and

    in

    many

    cases were first

    suggested

    by

    Plato's Theaetetus.

    In

    some

    ways they

    seem

    to

    go

    too far in the

    Platonic

    direction. Thus the victim

    of

    perplexity

    needs to be reminded that some

    things

    are

    intelligible

    and

    eternal: he

    has concentrated too

    much

    on

    perceptible changing

    things.

    Now

    this is redolent

    of

    Plato,

    with

    its

    suggestion

    that the nature of

    reality

    is to

    be

    discovered

    by attending

    to

    the

    eternal and that the world

    of flux

    can

    be

    dismissed

    as not

    relevant to the

    enquiry.

    Yet

    Aristotle's

    point

    cannot be

    quite

    this,

    since

    he asserts that

    the law of non-contradiction brooks no

    exceptions,

    not even

    among

    perceptible, changing things.

    His

    point

    must

    rather

    be

    to

    remind

    the victim

    of

    perplexity

    of

    something

    which

    he

    knows

    well, but has temporarily forgotten, in order to make him question whether

    the law

    of non-contradiction can be

    broken

    anywhere.

    Relativism,

    if it

    is

    pushed,

    tends to

    be

    supported

    by

    reasons of

    very

    general

    scope.

    So

    if a

    dent can

    be made

    in the

    position

    in

    one

    place,

    this

    will

    lessen

    its

    appeal

    in

    other

    areas

    also.

    Aristotle's

    major

    argument

    in these

    chapters

    is

    based

    on an

    appeal

    to

    the

    notion of essence

    (r4,

    1006a

    28-7b

    18).

    The burden of this

    difficult

    argument

    is that

    whatever

    may

    be the

    case with other

    modes

    in

    which

    subjects

    can be

    characterized,

    at the

    very

    least

    it cannot be

    the case that

    the

    definition,

    which

    gives

    the

    subject's

    essence,

    both is and is not true of it.

    I do not

    propose

    to

    go

    into this

    argument.

    I

    mention

    it now

    because

    it

    raises an idea which

    will

    recur

    in the

    following

    analysis.

    There

    is

    one set of

    remarks in

    F

    5 which are

    suggestive

    of

    a

    point

    which

    we

    will

    find

    developed

    in the

    passages

    to which

    I

    am

    going

    to

    turn next.

    Aristotle

    jokingly

    suggests

    that

    Homer must have been

    a

    relativist because

    he describes

    an

    unconscious Hector

    as

    lying

    with his mind

    on other

    things

    (this

    is an

    acceptable

    description

    of unconsciousness

    in

    Greek):

    Aristotle

    says

    as if those who are mindless have their minds on things, only on different

    things

    (1009b

    28-31).

    The

    point

    of

    this

    remark

    is

    that relativists do not

    admit that

    people

    make mistakes

    or

    misuse

    their faculties. For them what

    is,

    on the

    realist

    view,

    the difference

    between the

    good

    and the bad

    use

    of

    the faculties

    is

    just

    that-a

    matter of difference without

    any

    such

    accom-

    panying

    values as the

    realist

    imports.

    Aristotle's

    use

    of

    the

    word

    '

    mindless

    '

    is

    suggestive

    because while this

    word is used

    by

    the

    realist to describe

    some-

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:51:50 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Evans-Aristotle on Relativism

    5/12

    196

    J. D.

    G. EVANS

    one whose mind is

    functioning

    poorly,

    the

    relativist

    is

    able to

    appeal

    to

    its

    other-totally privative-sense

    to

    argue

    that

    the

    realist's

    use is

    self-contra-

    dictory:

    if the

    activity

    of mind is

    not

    present

    in

    just

    as

    satisfactory

    a

    form

    as it is in all other cases, then it is totally lacking.

    There

    is

    no

    question

    that Aristotle

    is

    a

    realist. He

    says

    it

    might

    seem

    that

    knowledge

    is a measure and

    the

    object

    of

    knowledge

    is measured . .

    .

    (but)

    in a

    way

    it is

    knowledge

    that is

    measured

    by

    the

    object

    of

    knowledge

    (Met.

    I

    6,

    1057a

    9-12).

    But he

    recognizes

    that

    realism can

    go

    to extremes

    which make

    it as

    unacceptable

    as

    relativism;

    and it

    is

    under this

    heading

    that the criticism

    of Plato comes.

    Where

    Plato

    goes wrong

    is

    well

    brought

    out

    by

    a

    passage

    in the

    Topics

    (Z

    8,

    146b 36-7a

    11),

    which is

    a

    development

    of

    a

    difficulty

    which

    Plato himself indicated in the Parmenides

    (133b-4e).

    In that

    work Plato

    presented

    an

    argument

    that

    if

    only

    objects

    of the same

    type

    are

    correlative with each

    other,

    and if Forms and

    perceptible particulars

    are indeed

    objects

    of different

    types,

    then the

    Forms,

    as

    objects

    of

    knowledge,

    must be

    objects

    of the Form

    Knowledge

    rather than of the instances

    of

    human

    knowledge

    which

    participate

    in

    that Form: those instances

    of know-

    ledge

    must

    be related

    to

    objects

    of the same

    type

    as themselves-that

    is,

    to

    the world

    of

    perceptible

    instances.

    I could

    argue

    that this

    lamentable conclusion

    does

    represent

    a

    serious

    difficulty for Plato, but not here.4 Aristotle's argument in the Topics runs

    as follows.

    Most

    of

    us

    would think

    inadequate

    a definition of

    desire as

    '

    appetite

    for the

    pleasant

    ';

    for it

    ignores

    the

    intentionality

    of

    desire,

    the

    fact

    that

    people

    may

    make a

    mistake

    and

    desire

    what

    appears

    to

    them

    pleasant

    when it

    is

    not

    really

    so. Therefore

    we must amend the definition

    to include

    a

    reference

    to

    appearances.

    But

    it is

    not

    open

    to the Platonist

    to make this

    common-sense

    move. For

    his definitions

    are

    considered to

    be

    definitions

    of

    Forms;

    and

    it is an

    axiom

    of

    his

    metaphysics

    that the cate-

    gories

    of

    the

    real and

    the

    apparent

    exclude

    each other. As

    a

    Form

    the

    object

    of desire must be

    real;

    and so to avoid what is for him the contradiction of

    admitting

    that there

    exists the real

    apparent

    good,

    he has to

    deny

    the

    name

    of

    '

    desire

    ' to what

    does not have the

    really

    pleasant

    as its

    object.

    If

    we

    strip

    this

    metaphysics

    of its

    ontological superstructure

    of

    Forms,

    we have

    an account

    which makes it

    a condition

    of

    being

    an

    exercise of a

    faculty

    that

    it does not

    err

    in

    its

    object.

    This

    consequence

    has

    the curious

    effect

    of

    assimilating

    Platonic realism

    to

    the relativism

    which it

    is

    designed

    to combat.

    This,

    with

    other

    aspects

    of the

    case,

    is

    well

    brought

    out

    in the

    discussion

    of

    the object of wish in E.N. F 4, to which I,now turn.

    A

    few

    preliminary

    remarks are

    needed.

    Aristotle

    regards

    wish

    (Bo6X7a7q)

    as

    the

    faculty

    which is

    concerned

    with

    the

    ultimate

    grounds

    for action.

    This makes

    it

    the

    more

    natural that the notion of

    good,

    the

    fundamental

    value

    notion,

    should

    figure

    centrally

    in his discussion.

    Secondly,

    Aristotle's

    4For

    this,

    see

    my

    Aristotle's

    Concept

    of

    Dialectic

    (forthcoming

    from

    Cambridge

    University

    Press).

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:51:50 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Evans-Aristotle on Relativism

    6/12

    ARISTOTLE

    ON

    RELATIVISM

    197

    ethics

    is

    eudaimonistic;

    and he

    would see no

    sense

    in

    the

    suggestion

    that a

    person

    could

    consciously

    and

    consistently

    fail

    to

    act in accordance

    with

    what he conceives

    to be

    the

    good

    life.5

    The account starts by recognizing two answers to the question what

    is

    the

    object

    of

    wish ? . Both answers

    seem to

    promote

    fatal

    objections;

    and

    yet

    between them

    they

    seem

    to

    represent

    all

    the

    possibilities.

    We

    are

    in

    a

    typical

    Aristotelian

    position.

    The first answer is

    that it is

    the

    good.

    This

    is the Platonic

    answer;

    and

    we have seen that

    it

    gives

    rise

    to

    the

    diffi-

    culty

    that someone

    who wishes

    something

    which is in fact other

    than the

    good,

    must

    be

    claimed not to

    be

    wishing

    at all. For his

    alleged

    wish

    is for

    something

    other than that for which

    all

    wishes,

    by

    definition,

    are.

    The

    second answer is

    that the

    object

    of wish is what

    appears

    to

    each

    person

    to

    be

    good.

    This answer has the

    consequence

    that it is

    impossible

    to

    distinguish

    different

    wishes in order of

    merit,

    since there is no common

    standard

    by

    which to measure

    them. On

    this view

    the

    object

    of

    wish has no definite

    nature,

    since

    anything

    might appear

    good

    to

    some individual. Now the

    man

    who has

    espoused

    relativism welcomes

    this

    consequence;

    for indeed

    it

    is

    just

    what

    he

    wants to assert.

    But

    Aristotle,

    in

    pointing

    it

    out,

    is

    concerned

    not with

    him but

    with the

    person

    who

    sees the

    difficulty

    in the

    Platonic

    account

    and

    thus

    has

    good

    reason

    to

    identify

    the

    object

    of wish with

    the

    apparent good.

    The basic

    inadequacy

    of both

    accounts

    is

    that

    they

    force

    us

    to obliterate

    a distinction

    which is

    recognized

    by

    common

    sense

    and,

    Aristotle

    believes,

    must

    be

    preserved

    in

    the

    true

    account of

    the

    matter.

    This is

    the

    distinction

    between the successful

    and the unsuccessful uses

    of the

    faculty

    of

    wishing.

    We

    must allow

    a use

    to

    such sentences

    as

    '

    he

    wishes,

    but his wish is

    wrong

    '.

    But

    this cannot

    be allowed on either of

    the

    contending

    accounts.

    For the

    realist such wishes

    are not wishes

    at

    all,

    since

    they

    are

    unrelated

    to

    the

    object

    of wish.

    Similarly

    the

    relativist,

    by making

    every

    act of

    wishing

    equally

    related to its

    object,

    makes all wishes

    equally

    good.

    In this

    way

    the

    two

    answers,

    which

    looked

    initially

    so

    very

    much

    opposed,

    end

    up

    in

    agree-

    ment on

    the

    cardinal matter

    of

    whether there is the

    possibility

    of

    distinguish-

    ing

    between wishes in

    respect

    of their success. This is ironic because the

    realist and

    the relativist believe themselves to

    be

    in

    conflict on this

    very

    point.

    By

    dialectically

    assimilating

    them,

    Aristotle shows not

    only

    that

    they

    are

    wrong

    as

    judged by

    the

    standards

    of common

    sense,

    but also that

    they

    fail in their intention.

    Clearly what is wrong is that due recognition is not being made of both

    the

    intensional

    and the extensional

    aspects

    of

    wishing

    and

    its

    objects.

    Granted

    that

    nobody

    would

    deny,

    if

    asked what

    he

    wishes,

    that

    he

    wishes

    the

    good,

    then

    this

    shows

    that

    intensionally

    there is

    just

    one

    object

    of

    wish

    5A

    third

    caveat

    is

    perhaps

    needed. None of

    the

    talk about 'the

    good'

    in what fol-

    lows

    conflicts with Aristotle's thesis in E.N.

    A

    6. The

    good may

    be

    enormously

    com-

    plex,

    and

    yet

    still

    have

    an

    utterly

    definite

    nature.

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:51:50 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Evans-Aristotle on Relativism

    7/12

    198

    J. D.

    G.

    EVANS

    -the

    good.

    But when we

    attend to the

    ways

    in

    which

    this

    opaque descrip-

    tion

    has to be filled

    in

    for

    varying

    individuals-that

    is,

    when

    we note

    the

    extensional

    aspect

    of the

    object

    of wish-we find

    diversity

    of nature in

    the object from individual to individual. Although Aristotle's account is

    not couched

    in

    this

    modern

    jargon,

    it does

    incorporate

    this

    insight.

    But

    to

    draw this

    analytic

    distinction

    is not

    to

    say

    which

    party-realists

    or

    relativists

    -are

    right.6

    Aristotle's

    analysis

    attempts

    to

    adjudicate

    on this

    issue.

    Before

    moving

    on to

    the substance of

    this

    analysis,

    let

    me

    emphasize

    once

    again

    what is

    and

    what

    is

    not to be

    expected

    from

    it.

    I

    have

    already

    drawn

    attention to Aristotle's

    remarks

    in

    Metaphysics

    F

    on

    the limits to

    provability

    in

    this

    area,

    and

    urged

    that

    his

    arguments

    in

    that work should

    be

    read

    in

    conjunction

    with

    those restrictions. This

    must also be

    borne

    in

    mind

    in connection

    with what follows.

    Those who are

    prepared

    to

    accept

    the

    unacceptable

    will not be moved

    by

    what Aristotle

    says;

    but it

    will,

    I

    maintain,

    be of interest to those

    who,

    recognizing

    the

    unacceptability

    of the

    alternative

    accounts,

    are disturbed

    by

    their

    inability

    to find

    anything

    more

    satisfying.

    Aristotle's

    own account

    of

    the

    nature of the

    object

    of wish

    consists

    in

    showing

    that

    the

    two

    opposing

    positions

    are

    not as

    incompatible

    as

    they

    at

    first

    seem. In order to do this he introduces a

    logical

    distinction,

    the

    usefulness of which in the present context had gone quite unappreciated by

    the

    proponents

    of

    the

    paradoxical

    views:

    this

    is the

    distinction between

    the

    qualified

    and the

    unqualified

    forms of a

    concept.

    He

    says

    that

    the true

    and

    unqualified

    object

    of

    wish is the

    good,

    but the

    object

    of each

    man's wish is

    what

    appears

    good

    to

    him.

    In

    the

    case of the

    good

    man

    appearance

    and

    reality

    coincide,

    so

    that

    what

    appears

    good

    to him

    really

    is

    so,

    whereas in

    the case of

    those other

    than

    the

    good

    man

    there

    is

    a distinction

    between

    what

    appears good

    to

    them

    and

    what

    is

    good.

    There

    are two

    components

    in

    this

    analysis.

    Firstly,

    there

    is the

    formal

    distinction

    between the

    object

    of

    wish

    in

    a

    general

    and

    unspecified

    form and the

    various

    objects

    which

    come into view

    when we consider the actual

    exercises

    of

    the

    faculty by

    individual

    persons,

    the

    objects

    of each

    man's

    wish.

    The two are

    not un-

    related.

    For the

    object

    of some individual's wish is

    the

    object

    of

    wish in a

    qualified

    form. It

    is what

    appears good

    to

    him;

    and

    the reason and

    justifica-

    tion

    for

    calling

    this-whatever

    it

    happens

    to

    be-the

    object

    of his

    wish,

    is

    precisely

    that the

    object

    of wish is

    the

    good.

    But

    while the two

    are

    not

    unrelated,

    neither

    are

    they

    identical.

    So

    Aristotle's first

    criticism of the

    contending parties is that by insisting that the object of wish is either the

    good

    or

    the

    apparent good,

    they

    oversimplify

    and

    reach

    a situation of

    false

    conflict.

    Both

    answers,

    hedged

    with the

    appropriate explanations,

    must

    find their

    place

    in

    the

    full and sober account

    of the matter.

    Secondly,

    6G.

    E. L.

    Owen,

    in Aristotle on

    Dialectic

    (Oxford, 1968),

    p.

    119,

    relies

    overmuch,

    I

    think,

    on the

    power

    of the

    intension/extension

    distinction to

    resolve

    the

    issue,

    and seems

    to be led

    by

    this

    over-reliance

    to

    the

    substantively

    wrong

    conclusion

    that Aristotle

    regards

    the

    apparent

    good

    as

    the

    object

    of

    wish.

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:51:50 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Evans-Aristotle on Relativism

    8/12

    ARISTOTLE

    ON

    RELATIVISM

    199

    Aristotle

    makes

    his

    pronouncement

    on

    the substantive issue when he

    says

    that

    the

    good

    is the true

    object

    of wish

    and

    the

    object

    of

    the

    good

    man's

    wish.

    With

    this

    further

    component

    of the

    analysis

    he

    firmly

    nails his

    colours

    to the realist mast; and he also shows that the object of wish is not to be

    understood

    simply

    as a

    general concept,

    to

    be

    specified

    only

    when we attend

    to

    details

    of

    individuals' wishes and determine the

    object

    of each man's

    wish,

    but

    rather

    as

    itself

    something

    utterly

    specific-the

    good.

    Indeed,

    in

    this

    area

    the

    vague

    and

    general

    concept

    is rather that of

    being

    the

    object

    of someone's

    wish,

    since

    there

    is

    no control over the

    diversity

    of

    objects

    which

    can

    satisfy

    this

    description.

    A

    parallel

    case

    will

    illustrate both

    the

    nature

    and the

    scope

    of Aristotle's

    reply

    to

    the

    extreme and

    paradoxical

    accounts

    of

    the

    relation between the

    faculty

    of

    wish

    and its

    object.

    In

    gunnery

    we have a connection

    of

    persons

    and

    objects

    by

    means of the

    faculty

    of

    shooting.

    In

    order

    for the

    letting

    off

    of

    guns

    to

    qualify

    as an exercise of

    shooting,

    there has to

    be a

    special

    object

    -the

    target-to

    which

    the

    guns

    are

    essentially

    related.

    So

    here we have two

    elements-shooting

    and a

    target-which

    are related

    to

    each other

    in

    the

    same

    way

    as are

    wishing

    and its

    object.

    Now realism and common sense

    tell us

    that

    there is

    scope

    for

    distinguishing

    between

    good

    and bad

    shooting,

    for

    allowing

    that

    while

    some shots

    may

    hit the

    target,

    others

    may

    miss

    it.

    But on the basis of certain aspects of the account of the relation between

    shooting

    and

    targets given

    above,

    it

    is not difficult to

    construct a thesis

    which

    disallows this

    possibility.

    On

    the

    one

    hand,

    the

    extreme realist main-

    tains that the

    object

    of

    every

    shot

    is

    the

    target.

    But it

    seems clear that the

    gun

    of the

    person

    who

    makes a

    poor

    shot is

    not

    in

    fact

    directed at

    the

    target,

    whatever

    he thinks

    or

    intends

    to the

    contrary;

    and

    so we

    have to

    say

    that

    whatever he thinks or

    intends,

    such a

    person

    is

    not

    in

    fact

    shooting.

    On the

    other

    hand,

    the extreme relativist maintains that the

    object

    of each

    shot,

    whatever

    it is

    directed

    at,

    is

    its

    own

    target.

    This

    thesis

    preserves

    the cor-

    relation of shots and

    targets,

    which had also been

    respected

    by

    the

    extreme

    realist,

    and

    preserves

    the

    claim that the

    poor

    shots are

    really

    shots,

    which

    the extreme realist had been

    forced

    to

    deny.

    But,

    of

    course,

    on

    this

    account

    every

    shot

    will hit its

    target;

    and

    so the

    scope

    for

    characterizing

    any

    shot

    as

    poor

    is removed.

    As with the

    conflicting

    accounts of

    the

    nature of the

    object

    of

    wish,

    both

    these

    accounts of the

    object

    of

    shooting

    obliterate the

    distinction

    between

    the successful

    and the unsuccessful

    performances

    of the

    exercise. Here

    also

    there are extremists who will not be disturbed to see shooting as an all-or-

    nothing

    matter and

    not,

    as most

    of

    us

    suppose,

    an exercise

    which is

    subject

    to variation in

    degree.

    But

    it

    is,

    I

    hope,

    less controversial

    than

    in

    the

    case

    of the

    object

    of wish that

    something

    has

    gone

    wrong

    here. Once

    again,

    to

    say

    that

    both accounts founder because

    they

    ignore

    the

    element

    of intention

    (the

    aim)

    in

    shooting

    is

    true

    but less

    than

    adequate.

    It

    is,

    in

    fact,

    only

    in

    areas where intention

    operates

    that

    paradoxes

    of

    this

    type

    can

    arise.

    Con-

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:51:50 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Evans-Aristotle on Relativism

    9/12

    200

    J.

    D.

    G.

    EVANS

    sider the

    following

    very

    different

    type

    of case.

    When

    a number of rivers

    flow

    from the heartland

    of a

    continent,

    some

    converge

    to enter

    the

    sea from

    the same

    mouth,

    but others make

    their

    way

    to the

    sea

    independently.

    Here

    we may speak of the rivers' object of seafall ; but there is no inclination

    here

    to

    produce paradoxical

    accounts

    of the

    nature

    of this or

    of these

    objects,

    or

    indeed

    to

    see

    any problem

    in this

    area.

    So

    we

    recognize

    that what

    gives

    rise to the

    problem

    in

    the

    problem

    cases

    with

    which we are

    concerned

    is

    the

    occurrence

    within

    them of aims and intentions.

    But even

    when we

    allow

    this,

    we still

    have

    a

    real

    problem

    in

    providing

    an

    analysis

    which

    will

    not

    disqualify

    the

    unsuccessful exercises

    of the faculties from

    being

    exercises of

    that

    faculty

    at

    all,

    irrespective

    of

    what is claimed for them

    by

    their

    per-

    petrators

    or

    by

    other observers.

    Aristotle's account

    suggests

    a

    way

    to do

    this.

    In

    the case of

    each of

    the

    poor

    shots

    we must

    say

    that it is related

    not

    to

    the

    target

    but

    to its

    target.

    Thus

    its

    object

    is not

    simply

    and

    without

    qualification

    the

    object

    of

    shooting;

    but neither is

    it

    something

    which is not

    in

    any

    way

    a

    target.

    Moreover,

    the relation between

    a

    qualified target

    of

    this

    sort and the

    target

    is

    a matter

    which is

    open

    to

    objective

    investigation.

    We can determine

    why

    some

    shots have

    gone

    wrong

    ;7

    and we

    can also

    rule

    that

    certain

    gun-firings

    are related

    to

    objects

    themselves so

    unconnected

    with the

    target

    that

    these are not shots

    at all. That

    is,

    we

    have

    the

    scope

    for distinguishing the problem cases-the poor shots-from, on the one

    hand,

    the

    good

    shots

    and,

    on the

    other,

    the non-shots.

    The

    account

    preserves

    the

    notion,

    so

    essential to

    a realist

    view,

    of the

    target,

    and thus

    preserves

    the

    distinction between

    good

    shooting,

    which hits the

    target,

    and

    bad

    shooting,

    which does

    not. It does not

    infringe

    the

    requirement

    that there

    must be an essential

    relation

    between

    a shot

    and

    a

    target.

    An

    oversimple

    interpretation

    of

    this

    requirement

    led the

    proponents

    of the extreme

    positions

    to

    their distorted

    views

    of the matter. But the distinction between

    the

    unqualified

    and the

    qualified

    forms

    of

    being

    a

    target

    enables

    us,

    following

    the

    indications

    provided

    by

    Aristotle's

    analysis

    of

    the

    object

    of

    wish,

    to take

    a

    more

    complex

    view of

    the

    relation

    between shots

    and

    targets.

    Now

    it is

    no

    longer

    essential

    that there should

    be a

    relation

    between

    every

    shot and

    the

    (unqualified)

    target,

    at

    least

    not

    the

    same relation

    as

    exists between

    the

    good

    shot

    and

    the

    target.

    My purpose

    in

    developing

    this

    account of

    shooting

    as a

    parallel

    to

    Aris-

    totle's

    account of

    wishing

    has been

    to show how

    moves similar to those made

    by

    the

    contending

    parties

    in

    the

    latter debate lead

    to

    positions

    which

    will

    immediately strike the victim of honest perplexity as unacceptable. How-

    ever,

    the effect of

    the

    comparison

    can be

    two-edged;

    and

    this

    promotes

    a

    consequence

    which is both unfortunate

    and

    interesting.

    The

    metaphysics

    of

    gunnery

    is,

    in

    a

    way,

    an area too

    little infested

    by

    controversy

    for

    the

    com-

    parison

    to be

    fully

    useful.

    The notion of

    the

    target-as

    the

    object

    which

    is

    7Aristotle

    suggests

    this idea

    in

    a

    very

    brief

    and

    general

    way

    at E.N. 1113a

    33-5;

    cf.

    also 1147b 6-9.

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:51:50 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Evans-Aristotle on Relativism

    10/12

    ARISTOTLE

    ON

    RELATVSM 201

    hit

    by

    some but

    not

    necessarily

    by

    all shots-is

    so

    well entrenched

    in our

    discourse that there is

    an

    implausibility

    both

    in the

    development

    of the

    paradoxical

    positions

    which

    make all

    shooting

    successful and in the

    presenta-

    tion of the notion of the qualified target, which is designed to disarm these

    implausible paradoxes.

    This

    is

    unfortunate insofar as it

    reduces the

    power

    of

    the

    comparison

    to

    illuminate the

    apparently

    more

    problematic

    area of

    wishing.

    But it

    is

    also

    interesting,

    in

    that it throws further

    light

    on a meta-

    philosophical

    issue which has

    been of central

    importance

    in

    this

    paper.

    Aristotle

    would,

    I

    am

    sure,

    regard

    the facts in the area

    of

    wishing

    as essen-

    tially

    no more

    problematic

    than

    they

    are with

    shooting.

    He

    would

    say

    that

    we are

    very

    well

    able to

    distinguish good

    from bad

    wishing,

    as

    we are

    good

    from bad

    shooting,

    even

    though

    in

    the case of

    wishing

    the

    target

    is

    not

    established

    by

    decree. But

    ordinary

    discourse does not

    supply

    an

    expression,

    analogous

    to

    'the

    target',

    to indicate

    the

    special

    and definite

    character of

    the

    object

    of

    wish;

    and

    this both

    opens

    the

    way

    for

    the contentious relativist

    to

    maintain

    that

    it has

    no

    definite

    character,

    and lulls the

    unwary

    into

    thinking

    that what

    he

    says may

    be

    right.

    The situation

    under

    analysis

    is one

    in

    which the

    roles

    of

    faculty

    and its

    object

    both

    need

    to

    be

    kept

    in

    proper

    perspective.

    The

    contending

    parties

    go wrong

    by

    overemphasizing

    one element

    of the relation at

    the

    expense

    of

    the other. The extreme realist is right to insist on the independence of the

    object

    of

    the

    faculty

    from

    any

    particular

    exercise

    of it.

    But

    this

    position

    can lead to one

    which divorces

    the

    object

    from all

    exercises

    of the

    faculty,

    as we have seen

    in

    connection with the

    difficulties in the Parmenides

    and

    the

    Topics.

    The extreme relativist

    overcorrects this

    defect

    by

    making

    the

    exercise of the

    faculty

    a

    defining

    criterion of its

    object.

    How

    much,

    and

    how

    little,

    Aristotle

    is

    prepared

    to

    concede to this

    position

    is indicated

    by

    his

    assertion

    that where

    the

    objects

    of human

    faculties are

    concerned,

    the

    good

    man is

    marked

    by

    his

    ability

    to see

    the truth and

    is

    like

    a standard and

    measure.8 The

    Protagorean

    echo here cannot be

    unintended;

    but Aristotle

    tempers

    the

    relativist

    position

    by

    speaking

    of the truth and the

    good

    man.

    The latter

    is, moreover,

    only

    like

    a

    standard measure.

    Now

    if Aristotle were

    defining

    the

    object

    of wish

    by

    reference

    to the

    good

    man,

    his

    account would

    be

    viciously

    circular,

    since we have no

    way

    of

    determining

    the

    identity

    of

    the latter

    except

    by

    reference to the

    former.

    Rather,

    he must be

    asserting

    that it

    is a

    necessary

    characteristic of the

    object

    of wish that

    it be the

    object

    of the

    good

    man's wish. To

    see the

    point

    of

    this,

    we have

    to remember the

    consequences of the extreme realist's ignoring this fact and of the extreme

    relativist's over-reaction

    to his

    opponent's position.

    It

    is an

    inevitable

    con-

    sequence

    of the

    type

    of

    therapeutic

    dialectic which Aristotle is

    practising

    in

    the

    present

    analysis

    that

    any

    of

    his

    remarks,

    when taken

    by

    itself and

    not

    thought through

    in

    terms

    of

    its

    part

    in

    the whole

    account,

    should seem

    to

    provide support

    for

    the

    position

    of either of the

    contending

    parties.

    8E.N.

    1113a 31-2.

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:51:50 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Evans-Aristotle on Relativism

    11/12

    202

    J.

    D.

    G. EVANS

    I

    noted

    earlier that the

    major

    argument against

    relativism

    in

    Metaphysics

    T

    is based on

    the notions

    of definition and

    essence.

    These

    notions

    have

    continued to be anathema to

    committed relativists and a

    stumbling-block

    to those whose commitment to realism is unsure. But they lie at the basis

    of the

    ontological expression

    which

    Aristotle

    gives

    to his

    realism;

    and

    I

    want to conclude

    by briefly

    considering

    a discussion

    in

    which Aristotle

    resolves a

    problem

    about

    definition

    in

    a

    manner

    similar to that

    in

    which

    he

    tackles

    the

    difficulties

    about

    wishing.

    The

    passage

    is from

    the

    Topics

    (Z

    4,

    141a 26-2a

    16);

    and as we

    would

    expect,

    given

    the

    character of the

    work,

    the

    dialectical

    aspect

    of the

    analysis

    is

    even more

    apparent

    than

    in

    the

    Ethics. Aristotle's advice

    at the end

    of

    the discussion to make

    precise

    each

    of

    such distinctions and use

    them to

    advantage

    in

    one's dialectic

    is

    not

    an

    invitation to the

    contentious to

    be

    self-serving

    but a

    reminder

    that

    one

    needs

    to be sensitive

    to the context of the

    dispute

    when one treats

    issues of

    this

    type.9

    The discussion takes its

    start from

    two

    basic theses about

    definition.

    The

    purpose

    of definition is to

    instruct us as to the nature

    of

    the

    thing

    under

    consideration,

    and

    definition must

    give

    an

    account of that

    thing's

    essence.

    An

    immediate

    consequence

    of

    this

    second

    requirement

    is that

    as each

    thing

    has a

    single

    essence,

    so it has

    only

    one definition.

    Thus insistence

    on

    the

    realism implicit in the essentialist thesis rules out the possibility that defin-

    itions of the same

    thing

    should be

    graded

    as better or worse:

    only

    the

    best

    will do

    at all.

    It should

    by

    now

    be clear that Aristotle

    will

    not

    be content to leave the

    matter

    there,

    with definition

    viewed

    simply

    as an

    all-or-nothing

    matter.

    For

    attention to the other

    requirement

    for

    definitions-that

    they

    be instructive

    -reveals a

    complexity

    which

    needs to be

    reflected

    in

    the full account. It

    is

    part

    of Aristotle's realism that he believes there

    to be a

    natural

    order

    in

    which

    certain

    things

    are more

    intelligible

    than

    others,

    and that the com-

    ponents

    of a

    thing's

    essence are

    prior

    in this natural order of

    intelligibility

    to the

    thing

    itself. The

    former are without

    qualification

    more

    intelligible

    than

    the

    latter;

    and

    they

    are

    also,

    as with the

    (unqualified)

    object

    of

    wish,

    more

    intelligible

    to the man of sound

    understanding.

    So

    far, then,

    there is

    no

    problem

    in

    an

    unadulterated realist

    account,

    since

    the man of sound

    understanding

    is instructed

    by

    the definition which

    presents

    the essence

    of

    the

    thing

    concerned.

    But

    what is without

    qualification

    intelligible

    may

    not

    be so to someone whose

    understanding

    is

    not sound.

    If

    he

    finds more in-

    telligible an account which describes the thing in terms other than its

    essential

    components,

    he

    will

    not be instructed-or will be less well instructed

    than he

    might

    be-by

    the

    only

    account to

    which the

    realist

    will

    allow the

    title of the definition

    .

    Aristotle

    will

    not

    relax

    the

    restriction on what

    may

    count

    as

    a definition.10 But

    he does

    recognize

    that

    such a

    sub-definitory

    9142a

    12-13.

    10142a 6-8.

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:51:50 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Evans-Aristotle on Relativism

    12/12

    ARISTOTLE ON RELATIVISM 203

    account should be

    provided

    where the

    audience

    is

    of

    less

    than

    sound under-

    standing,

    and he

    describes someone who does this as

    defining

    .11

    Aristotle is

    mainly

    concerned

    to

    combat a relativist view

    which,

    exploit-

    ing the fact that what is intelligible to one man may not be so to another,

    would call

    a

    definition

    any

    account which

    happened

    to

    instruct

    some

    individual,

    irrespective

    of

    the

    success

    with which

    it

    portrayed

    the nature of

    the

    thing

    concerned. This view is fatal to essentialism and

    unacceptable

    to

    the realist

    if he

    believes that

    things

    have definite natures which

    can be

    approached

    by

    a

    process

    of

    rational

    discovery,

    however

    haltingly

    and

    how-

    ever much

    provision

    has

    to be made

    along

    the

    way

    to

    discovery

    for accounts

    which cannot

    yet

    be

    regarded

    as the

    definition.

    But

    the realist who does

    not

    make this

    provision

    pays

    the Platonic

    price.

    He makes success an all-or-

    nothing

    matter,

    and has to

    say

    that the

    person

    who is not in

    complete

    contact with

    reality

    is

    not

    in

    contact at all. Aristotle is less exclusive as to

    which

    performances

    should be counted as

    defining.

    He

    makes more

    allow-

    ance for

    the

    part

    played

    by

    human faculties

    in

    the

    relation between them

    and

    their

    object

    than

    does

    the

    Platonist;

    and in

    doing

    so

    he

    shows

    the

    victim of

    honest

    perplexity

    that

    an

    unpalatable

    relativism is not the

    only

    alternative

    to an

    only

    slightly

    less

    unpalatable

    realism.

    I

    maintain that

    in

    these two accounts

    in

    the Ethics

    and the

    Topics

    we

    have a good example of the way in which the realist can deal with the

    relativist without himself

    going

    to

    unacceptable

    extremes. He cannot refute

    him;

    but he can

    disarm

    him. He can

    show

    the

    person

    who feels

    moved

    by

    the

    force

    of

    the

    relativist's

    argument

    that

    it

    does

    indeed force us

    to

    preserve

    the role of the

    cognitive

    subject

    when

    we

    discuss how

    things

    are,

    but

    that

    this does not mean that these

    subjects

    determinehow

    things

    are.

    The discussions

    are

    brief,

    and this

    disguises

    their

    importance.

    Some

    find

    them

    trivial,

    some

    find them false.

    This

    disagreement

    in

    itself shows

    their

    importance,

    and

    I

    think that Aristotle would

    reply

    to those who

    find

    them

    trivial that

    they

    have not

    sufficiently

    felt the lure of the extreme

    accounts,

    and to

    those who

    find them false that

    they

    have felt

    that lure all too well.

    My

    thesis is that

    they

    make an

    important

    philosophical

    contribution,

    as

    well as

    telling

    us much that

    is

    fundamental

    in

    Aristotle's

    philosophy

    and

    metaphilosophy.12

    Sidney

    Sussex

    College,

    Cambridge

    11141b 23.

    12Versions of

    this

    paper

    in its

    latest

    metamorphosis

    were

    given

    in

    1973

    at the

    Uni-

    versity

    of

    Georgia,

    Athens,

    the

    University

    of

    Oklahoma,

    Norman,

    and the

    University

    of

    California,

    Berkeley.

    I

    have

    benefited from comments on all those

    occasions.