exploring the aspects of law’s “goodness” in ronald

25
* Petar Popović, Ph. D., Assistant Professor, Faculty of Canon Law, Pontifical Univer- sity of the Holy Cross, Piazza di Sant’Apollinare 49, 00186 Rome, Italy; [email protected]; ORCID ID: orcid.org/0000-0001-5282-0850 EXPLORING THE ASPECTS OF LAW’S “GOODNESS” IN RONALD DWORKIN’S CRITIQUE OF THE STRONG NATURAL-LAW THEORY Assist. Prof. Petar Popović, Ph. D.* UDK: 34.01 340.12 929 Dvorkin, R. DOI: 10.3935/zpfz.70.4.04 Izvorni znanstveni rad Primljeno: srpanj 2020. The scope of this paper is to explore certain aspects of Ronald Dworkin’s critique of the so-called “strong” natural-law theory. The author focuses on those aspects of Dworkin’s critique that gravitate toward the perspective of law’s “goodness”, namely, the question of how and to what extent Dworkin and the “strong” natural-law theory, each in its own way, allow the overlap between the concept of law and the evaluative viewpoint according to which substantive aspects of human moral good are pertinent to legal issues. In the first section of the paper, the author presents the central arguments of Dworkin’s legal theory by highlighting those theoretical elements that are often considered to be similar to the claims of the natural-law theory in a broad sense. The author then presents Dworkin’s main objections to the “strong” natural-law theory, as well as the evaluation of Dworkin’s “minimalist” natural-law account through the lens of the proponents of the “strong” theory. In the last section, the author analyses certain aspects of law’s “goodness” that have remained mostly implicit or underdeveloped in the debate between Dworkin and the “orthodox” natural lawyers. Key words: Dworkin; natural-law theory; legal interpretivism; political morality

Upload: others

Post on 02-Mar-2022

4 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

* PetarPopović,Ph.D.,AssistantProfessor,FacultyofCanonLaw,PontificalUniver-sityoftheHolyCross,PiazzadiSant’Apollinare49,00186Rome,Italy;

[email protected]; ORCIDID:orcid.org/0000-0001-5282-0850

EXPLORING THE ASPECTS OF LAW’S “GOODNESS” IN RONALD DWORKIN’S CRITIQUE OF THE

STRONG NATURAL-LAW THEORY

Assist. Prof. Petar Popović, Ph. D.* UDK:34.01 340.12

929Dvorkin,R. DOI:10.3935/zpfz.70.4.04

Izvorniznanstvenirad Primljeno:srpanj2020.

The scope of this paper is to explore certain aspects of Ronald Dworkin’s critique of the so-called “strong” natural-law theory. The author focuses on those aspects of Dworkin’s critique that gravitate toward the perspective of law’s “goodness”, namely, the question of how and to what extent Dworkin and the “strong” natural-law theory, each in its own way, allow the overlap between the concept of law and the evaluative viewpoint according to which substantive aspects of human moral good are pertinent to legal issues. In the first section of the paper, the author presents the central arguments of Dworkin’s legal theory by highlighting those theoretical elements that are often considered to be similar to the claims of the natural-law theory in a broad sense. The author then presents Dworkin’s main objections to the “strong” natural-law theory, as well as the evaluation of Dworkin’s “minimalist” natural-law account through the lens of the proponents of the “strong” theory. In the last section, the author analyses certain aspects of law’s “goodness” that have remained mostly implicit or underdeveloped in the debate between Dworkin and the “orthodox” natural lawyers.

Key words: Dworkin; natural-law theory; legal interpretivism; political morality

540 PetarPopović:ExploringtheAspectsofLaw’s“Goodness”inRonaldDworkin’sCritiqueof...

1. INTRODUCTION

Istheconceptoflawinextricablyconnectedtomoralitytotheextentthatthereferencetosubstantivehumangoodsomehownecessarilyentersintothedefinitionoflaw?Canwepositavalidstandpointfromwhichitmaybeaffir-medthatlawis–initsessence,aswellasaccordingtothecontentofconcretelegalrules–substantivelygood?Islaw as it ought to besomehowalreadyinbuiltintotheverynotionoflaw as it is?Insum,towhatdegreeisitconceptuallypermissibletoestablishanessentialoverlapbetweentheconceptof lawandtheconceptofgood?

Anyanswer,affirmativeornegative,totheabovesetofquestionsrepresentsaviewpointen routetoastructuredunderstandingofwhatlawis,conceptually,ontologically,andfunctionally.AccordingtoH.L.A.Hart’snegativeanswertothesequestions,therearenonecessaryconceptualconnectionsbetweenlawasitisandlawasmorallyitoughttobe;atbestwecanspeculateabout“merelycontingent”1overlapsorlaw’stangentiallycontingent“goodness”.Theso-called“nonecessaryconnection”argumentinfavourofessentiallyseparateordersoflawandmoralitypermitsus,atbest,topostulateamerelyformal2orsystemic3 conceptionof law’sgoodness.From legalpositivismto recentendeavoursoftheartefactual legal theory4, law isconceptuallyorontologicallyenvisioned

1 SeeHart,H.L.A.,Introduction,in:Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy,OxfordUni-versityPress,Oxford, 1983, p.8.SeealsoHart,H.L.A.,The Concept of Law (3rded.),OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford, 2012, pp.187–200.

2 InHansKelsen’sview,theconceptoflawmayoverlapwiththeconceptofgoodonlyifwethoroughlyreconstructthe“good”accordingtoapurelyformalconcep-tionofitsjuristicrelevancewhollydependentonthevaluesoriginatinginpositivelegalnorms.Accordingtothisposition,theconceptofjuristicgoodisessentiallyunderstoodasthat which legally ought to beor“thatwhichconformstoasocialnorm;andiflawisdefinedasnorm,thenthisimpliesthatwhatislawfulis‘good’”.SeeKelsen,H.,Pure Theory of Law(translatedbyM.Knight),TheLawbookExchange,Ltd.,Clark,NewJersey,2005,p.66.

3 AccordingtoJosephRaz’saccountofpurelysystemicmoralpropertiesoflaw,theonlynecessaryconnectionbetween lawandmoralityamounts to theclaimthatlaw, envisioned at the level of an abstract institution, has the essential task tosecurea stateofaffairswhereincertainmoralgoals– likehavingacoordinatedstructureofauthority–arerealizedthatcouldnothavebeen(orwouldbeunlikely)achievedwithoutit.SeeRaz,J.,About Morality and the Nature of Law,in:Between Au-thority and Interpretation: On the Theory of Law and Practical Reason,OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford,2009,pp.178–179.

4 Forexample,seeBurazin,L.;Himma,K.E.;Roversi,C.(eds.),Law as an Artifact,OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford,2018.SeealsoBurazin,L.,Can There Be an Artifact Theory of Law?,RatioJuris,vol.29,no.3,2016,pp.385–401.

Zbornik PFZ, 70, (4) 539-563 (2020) 541

exclusivelyasasource-based–i.e.,essentiallyidentifiablethroughsociallyre-cognizedlegalsources–socialfactorartefact.Thismeansthatlaw(what law is)isstructurallyseparatedfromclaimsaboutwhat law ought to beaccordingtovarioussubstantivemoralaspectsofthehumangoodthataredeemedultimatelyirrelevantfortheidentificationofthelaw.

Thescopeofthispaperistoexploreaspectsoftheanswertotheabovesetofquestionsregardinglaw’s“goodness”thatareoutlinedormayotherwisebecontextualizedinRonaldDworkin’s(1931–2013)critiqueofwhathereferredtoasthe“strong”5natural-lawtheory.Dworkin’scritiquecamefromapeculiartheoreticalposition,sincehehimselfwasfrequentlyaccusedbyhiscriticsfor“professing”certainargumentsthatareclassicallyattributedtothenatural-lawtradition,suchastheargumentthattheconceptoflawnecessarilycontainsareferencetonormativeorevaluativestandardsandis,thus,irreducibletopuresource-basedsocial facts.6Dworkinwasalwaysquiteclear inhisargumentsthatthestandardsoflaw’s“goodness”arehigherthanthosethatarecontainedintheclaimsformerelycontingent,formalisticorsystemicmoralpropertiesoflaw.Therealquestionis:howmuchhigher?Heclearlyarguesthat“whatthelawisdependsin some wayonwhatthelawshouldbe”7:

“IfthecrudedescriptionofnaturallawIjustgaveiscorrect,thatanytheorywhichmakesthecontentoflawsometimesdependonthecorrectanswertosomemoralquestionisanaturallawtheory,thenIamguiltyofnaturallaw”.8

Dworkin’scritiqueofthe“strong”versionofanatural-lawtheory,aswellashisqualificationofthelink(“insomeway”)betweenlaw as it isandlaw as it ought to be, reveal thatthe“necessaryconnection”argumentregardingthelaw-moralityintersectionmaybedefendedbydifferent–evenmutuallyirre-ducibleandirreconcilable–theoreticalpositions.Itisevident,evenfromtheseintroductoryremarks,thatDworkin’slegaltheoryaimsataconceptuallink

5 SeeDworkin,R.,Law’s Empire, TheBelknapPress ofHarvardUniversity Press,Cambridge,1986,p.102.

6 FortworelativelyrecentexamplesofidentifyingDworkin’slegaltheoryasasui ge-nerisanti-positivistapproachthatatthesametimeinvitesandresistsclassificationasanatural-lawtheory,seeLyons,D.,Moral Limits of Dworkin’s Theory of Law and Legal Interpretation,BostonUniversityofLawReview,vol.90,no.2,2010,pp.595–602;Priel,D.,Description and Evaluation in Jurisprudence,LawandPhilosophy,vol.29,no.6,2010,pp.633–667.

7 Dworkin,R.,“Natural Law” Revisited,UniversityofFloridaLawReview,vol.34,no.2,1982,p.165.Emphasisadded.

8 Ibid.

542 PetarPopović:ExploringtheAspectsofLaw’s“Goodness”inRonaldDworkin’sCritiqueof...

betweenlawandmoralitythatiscertainlybelowthelevelofanalysisthatheconsiderstobe“strong”.

InthefirstpartofthispaperIwillshowwhatIconsidertobethemostobvioussimilaritiesbetweenDworkin’spositionandthecentralclaimsofthenatural-lawtheoryoflawandjuridicity.IwillsubsequentlypresentDworkin’sreasonsfordissociationfromthestrongnatural-lawtheory.Mynextaimistobrieflypresentsomeofthemostprominentnaturallawyers’argumentsagainstDworkin’sassociationwiththenatural-lawtheory.InthefinalpartofthepaperIwillexplorecertainaspectsofthequestionregardinglaw’s“goodness”thatinhabitthefieldbetweenDworkin’s legal theoryandthestrongnatural-lawtheory,butwhichgobeyondtheirexplicitmutualcritiques.

Forthepurposesofthispaper–andinaccordancewithwhatIbelievewereDworkin’sintentionswhenhecriticizedaversionofthenatural-lawtheorythathedeemed“strong”–Iwillhenceforthpresumethatthecoreclaimofthestrongnatural-lawtheoryiscontainedintheargumentthataspectsofsubstantivehu-manmoralgoodenterintotheverydefinition–theconceptortheontologicalstatus–ofwhatlawis.

2. A DWORKINIAN ACCOUNT OF LAW’S “GOODNESS” AND ITS PROXIMITY TO A NATURAL-LAW LINE OF ARGUMENT

AlthoughDworkinseldomexplicitlyaddressestheissueoftheconceptualin-terconnectednessoflawandmoralityintermsoftheoverlapbetweenthenotionoflawandthenotionof“goodness”,itisquiteclearthatthisoverlapoccupiesastrategicpositionontheconceptualmapofhisviewsonthenatureoflaw.

“Wecannotidentifythecorrecttestsfordecidingwhatthelawreallyiswithoutdeployinganddefendingaconceptionoflegality,andwecannotdothatwithoutdecidingwhat,ifanything,is really good about legality.Jurispru-denceisanexerciseinsubstantive political morality.[…]Thecuttingedgeofajurisprudentialargumentisitsmoral edge.[…]Westrivetounderstandlegalitybyunderstandingwhatisdistinctlyimportantandvaluableinit”.9

9 Dworkin,R.,Justice in Robes,TheBelknapPressofHarvardUniversityPress,Cam-bridge, 2006, p. 178. Emphasis added. A conception of legality is, according toDworkin,“ageneralaccountofhowtodecidewhichparticularclaimsoflawaretrue”.Ibid.,p.170.Itmaybesaidthat“legality”denotesthejuristicphenomenonat thehighest levelofanalysis, caught in itsaxiologicalperspectiveof thepointforhavinglawasaninstitutionandasapracticeatall,whilealsoembracinglaw’sconcretesocial-factualinstantiations.Seeibid.,pp.168–171.

Zbornik PFZ, 70, (4) 539-563 (2020) 543

Inordertounderstandthefullmeaningandlegal-philosophicalimpactofthesearguments–especiallytheitalicizedparts–ontheneedtoestablishthesenseinwhichlawmay(ormaynot,ormust)besaidtooverlapwith“goodness”,itwillbehelpfultorevisitthecrucialclaimsofDworkin’saccountofthenatureoflaw.Theselectionandpresentationoftheseclaimswillbefilteredthroughthequestionofwhether,andtowhatextent,theyresemblethekeyfeaturesofanatural-lawapproachtotheconceptoflaw.

ThefirstimportantclaiminDworkin’stheoryoflawishisthesisthat“lawincludesnotonlythespecificrulesenactedinaccordancewiththecommunity’sacceptedpracticesbutalsotheprinciplesthatprovidethebestmoraljustificationforthoseenactedrules”.10Thisclaimisdevelopedasacritiquetothecentralthesisoflegalpositivism,whichDworkincallsthe“rule-book”conception11,accordingtowhichlawisenvisionedexclusivelyasasetofsource-basedsocialfacts“explicitlysetoutinapublicrulebookavailabletoall”.12Incontrasttolegalpositivism’srejectionoftheideathat“legalrightscanpre-existanyformoflegislation”13,Dworkinarguesthat,besidestheexclusiveappealtoenactedlegalrules,lawincludesalsothejustifying legal principles.14

Thesejustifyingprinciples,identifiedbeyond(oratthefoundationsof)so-urce-basedlegalrules,pointtothe“politicalormoralconcernsandtraditions”ofthepoliticalcommunitythatsupportandtherebyjustifythecontentoftheenactedrules.15However,thecontentofsaidprinciplesisnotexhaustedbyde-notingpurelymotivationalorexplanatorybackgrounddataforenactedrules;accordingtoDworkin,thejustifyingprinciplespointtoclaimsaboutrightsthatcitizenshave.Theprinciplesjustifyalegalenactmentfromthe“rulebook”by“showingthat[it]respectsorsecuressomeindividualorgroupright”.16Despite

10 Dworkin,R.,Justice for Hedgehogs,TheBelknapPressofHarvardUniversityPress,Cambridge,2011,p.402.Emphasisadded.

11 Dworkin,R.,A Matter of Principle,HarvardUniversityPress,Cambridge,1985,p.11.12 Ibid.13 Dworkin,R.,Taking Rights Seriously(2nded.),HarvardUniversityPress,Cambridge,1978,p.xi.

14 Ibid.,p.46.“Thelawthenalsoincludestherulesthatfollowfromthosejustifyinglegalprinciples,eventhoughthosefurtherruleswereneverenacted”.Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.10),p.402.

15 Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.13),p.67.16 Ibid.,pp.82,343–344.Dworkinprovidestheexampleofanti-discriminationstat-utesthatarejustifiedbythelegalprincipleaccordingtowhichaminorityhasarighttoequalconcernandrespect.Seeibid.,p.82.Elsewhere,Dworkinwillrefertoargumentsofprincipleas“right-based”.SeeDworkin,op. cit.(fn.11),p.3.

544 PetarPopović:ExploringtheAspectsofLaw’s“Goodness”inRonaldDworkin’sCritiqueof...

thefactthatthey(1)maylacktheexplicitmentionintherulebook,(2)pre-existtherule-booklegislation,and(3)belongtoaspecificgroupof“principlesofpersonalandpoliticalmorality”,therightsinquestionarefullylegal.17Thus,inDworkin’sview,the“rule-book”conceptionoflawmustbeexpandedtoinc-ludethe“rights”conceptionwhichsecurestheidentificationofcitizens’moralandpoliticalrightsthatare,evenifnotexplicitlyandentirelycontainedintherule-book,alsoincludedintheconceptoflawaslegalrights.18Atthesametime,althoughDworkin’sconceptionofrightsthatoriginateinjustifyinglegalprinci-plesdeniesthat“therulebookistheexclusivesourceofrights”,it“concedesthattherulebookis[…]asourceofmoralrights”19inthesensethatenactedrulesincludeanecessaryreferencetoaspecifickindofpolitical-moraljustification.

Dworkinadmitsthatthebackboneofthisaccountoftheconceptoflawbearsstrongresemblancetooneofthecentralfeaturesofthenatural-lawthe-ory,namely, theargument that the identificationof law(ordecidingwhichpropositionsof lawaretrue)gravitatestoward“criteriathatarenotentirelyfactual,butatleasttosomeextentmoral”.20Inotherwords,Dworkinadvocatessomethingverysimilartothecoreclaimsofthenatural-lawtheorywhenhepostulatesthenecessityofextendingtheconceptoflawalsotoaspecificgroupofnormativemoralprinciplesthatarenotcontainedinthesocial-factualrulebookofpubliclyrecognizedlegalsources.

InDworkin’sadjudication-centredlegaltheory,theinsufficiencyoflegalposi-tivism’srule-bookapproach,andtheneedtoconsultjustifyinglegalprinciplesintheprocessoftheidentificationofthelaw,ismadeparticularlymanifestinthecourseofreflectiononhowtoresolveissuesthathereferstoas“hardcases”.Wehaveahardcasewhen(1)anissuethatcausestheneedtoidentifytherelevantlawdoesnotcorrespondtoastateofaffairsdescribedinanyoftheenactedrulesfromtherulebook(“therulebookissilent”),orthe“wordsintherulebookaresubjecttocompetinginterpretations”21,and(2)thelawmaybesettledonlythroughachoicebetweeneligibleinterpretationsbasedontheassessmentthatthisparticularchoice“showsthecommunity’sstructureofinstitutionsanddecisions[…]inabetterlightfromthestandpointofpoliticalmorality”.22Thus,

17 Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.5),p.96.18 SeeDworkin,op. cit.(fn.11),pp.11–13.19 Ibid.,p.16.20 Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.5),p.35.21 Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.11),p.16.Weareconfrontedwithahardcasewhen“nosettledruledictatesadecisioneitherway”.Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.13),p.83.

22 Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.5),p.256.

Zbornik PFZ, 70, (4) 539-563 (2020) 545

theresolutionofissuesqualifiedashardcasesisnotjustamatterofdecidingatone’sowndiscretionandtherebyexpandingtherulebook,noramatterofchoosing,allenactedrulesconsidered,thecorrectintra-systemic(i.e.,intrarulebook)interpretationofpertinentsource-basedrules.AccordingtoDworkin,it isamatterofdecidingbetweencompeting conceptions of political morality.23 Inotherwords,itisamatterofprinciples,includingcorrespondingrights,thatprovidethebestpolitical-moraljustification(orconstructiveinterpretation)ofthelegalnorms,institutionsandpracticesinaparticularpoliticalcommunity.24

Toillustratetheweightofponderationinhardcases,Dworkinintroducestheidealofanimaginaryjudgewithsuperhumanintellectualpowerandpatience,whomhenamesHercules.Inordertoreachthebestpossiblepolitical-moraljustificationoflawandthepointoflegalpracticeasawhole,Herculesmust,forexample:(1)elaborate,inadvance,acoherentoverarchingsetofthoseprinciplesofpoliticalmoralitythatbestjustifyenactedrulesinagivencommunity,soastobeabletoenforcetheminfreshcases25,(2)recognizethe“easycases”asjusta“specialcaseofhardones”towhichheknowsboththerule-bookanswerandtherelevant justification26, (3)harmonizethe justifyingprincipleswithotherapplicableprinciplesaswellaswiththerulebookitselfintoaconsistentretrospectiveandforward-lookingunfoldingpoliticalnarrative27,(4)bepreparedtore-examinesomepolitical-moralelementsofhisjustificatorysystemoflegalreasoningfromtimetotime(thoughhecan“neverbesure,inadvance,whenandhow”)28,and(5)askwhat is the legal relevanceofdisagreementamonglawyersandlegalscholarsonaparticularissue,evenifitiseasytoidentifytherelevantenactedrulesand“allthefactsaboutwhatinstitutionshavedecidedinthepast”(i.e.,ask:ifthisissettledlaw,then“whatintheworldaretheydisagreeingabout?”).29

23 Ibid.24 SeeDworkin,op. cit.(fn.13),pp.84,340;Dworkin op. cit.(fn.7),p.165;Dworkin,R.,A Reply by Ronald Dworkin,in:Cohen,M.(ed.),Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence,Duckworth,London,1983,pp.247,254;Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.11),pp.3,11,75,77;Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.5),p.262;Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.9),pp.144,248;Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.10),p.402.

25 Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.5),p.243;Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.9),pp.54,189n5,247–248.26 Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.5),p.266.27 Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.11),p.17;Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.5),pp.225,227–228.28 Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.9),p.56.29 Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.9),p.163.Tothecriticwhomightobjectthatordinaryreal-lifelawyersandjudgesmayreasonaboutconcretelegalissues,evenhardcases,onlythroughpartialjustificationandfromtheinside-out–i.e.,bystartingfromspecific

546 PetarPopović:ExploringtheAspectsofLaw’s“Goodness”inRonaldDworkin’sCritiqueof...

WhenreflectingupontheargumentsthatheprojectsontoHercules’sjobdescription,Dworkinassertsthat:

“Itisobviouswhythistheoryofadjudicationinvitesthechargeofnaturallaw.Itmakeseachjudge’sdecisionabouttheburdenofpastlawdependonhisjudgmentaboutthebestpoliticaljustificationofthatlaw,andthisisofcourseamatterofpoliticalmorality”.30

Besidesthepurportedsimilaritywithhisunderstandingofthecoreargu-mentofnatural-lawtheory–namely,thatwhat the law is (i.e.,thecontentoflaw)dependsinsomewayonwhat the law should be (i.e.,onthebestpolitical-moraljustification at the foundations of enacted lawwhich includes normativeprinciplespointingtoexistinglegalrights)31–Dworkinseemstoshowsometheoreticalsympathyfortheconceptionofnaturalrightsaswell.Rightsthatthejustifyinglegalprinciplespointtofunctionasinterest-basedtrumps“overotherwiseadequatejustificationsforpoliticalaction”andevenover“policiesthatwouldindeedmakepeopleasawholebetteroff”.32

The crucial element for understandingDworkin’s theory of rights is hisdistinction–“adistinctionofcapitalimportancetolegaltheory”33–betweenjustifyinglegalprinciplesandpolicies.Apolicyisacollectivegoalthat,allthingsconsidered,advancesorprotectsthe(economic,political,social,etc.)goodofthecommunityaccordingtosomeconceptionofgeneralwelfare,commonflo-urishingorsomesortofpublicinterest.34Ontheotherhand,individualshaverightswhenaprincipleofpoliticalmoralityjustifiestheirbenefitsorinterests,evenifthatmeansquashinganotherwisevalidcollectivegoalthat,directlyorindirectly,damagesthesebenefitsorinterests.35SinceDworkinarguesthatinissuesqualifiedashardcasesthelawshouldbeidentified,inadditiontocon-

problemsandnotfromoverarchinggrandtheoriesofpoliticalmorality–DworkinrespondsthattheprinciplesthatareoperativeinHercules’sreasoningmaybehelp-fulto“mortal”lawyers,who“cansetnoapriorilimittothejustificatoryascent”intowhichaproblemwilldraweitherthemorthepoliticalcommunityanditslegalofficials.SeeDworkin,op. cit.(fn.9),pp.55,68;Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.7),p.166.

30 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.7),p.166.31 Ibid.,p.165.32 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.10),p.329.SeealsoDworkin, op. cit.(fn.13),p.xi;Dworkin,R.,Rights as Trumps,in:Waldron,J.(ed.),Theories of Rights,OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford,1984,p.153.

33 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.11),p.2.34 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.13),pp.22,82,90–94,294;Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.11),pp.2-3,11;Dworkin,R.,op. cit.(fn.32),p.166.

35 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.13),pp.xi;294;Dworkin,R.,op. cit.(fn.32),p.166.

Zbornik PFZ, 70, (4) 539-563 (2020) 547

sultingtherulebook,bydeterminingthejustifyingprinciples,heobviouslymaintainsthattherelevantlawshouldbesettledbydetectingexistingindividualrightsandbygivingthempriorityovercollectivegoalsorpolicies,eventothedetrimentofwhatmaybeperceivedascommunity’sflourishing.36

Dworkin’saccountofrightsisrelevantalsoincasesthatcouldbequalifiedas“easy”,especiallyinthosesituationswheretherulebookleavesnodoubtonhowtoapplythelawoncertainstatesofaffairs,butwheretheenforcementofenactedruleswouldbemanifestlyunjustandimmoral.Inaccordancewiththepremisesofhis legal theory,he firstdistinguishes and stratifies variousstages inthe identificationof therelevant law incasesofmanifestlyunjustrule-booksolutions,andthenevaluates,throughthosepremises,theaspectsofthevalidityandlegalormoralobligatorinessofsuchlaws.Dworkinmaintainsthat“evillaws”,suchas,forexample,“Naziedicts”,cannotbesaidtoconstitutedownrightinvalidorinexistentlawsinonesense,namely,inthepre-interpretivesenseinwhichweidentifythetextualcontentoftherulebookasrecognizedsocial-factualsourcesoflegalobligation.Ontheotherhand,ifweincludeintheconceptoflawalsotheinterpretivestageinwhichwedetecttheunderlyingprinciplesofpoliticalmoralityandthecorrespondingrights,eveninthefaceofclarityofenactedunjustrules,thenthesepolitical-moralrightsmaybesaidtotrumpeach“legal”rule-bookrightthatisgroundedinanunjustlaw,andinthissensethe“Naziedicts”werenot law.37

Dworkin’stheoryofrightsisnot,accordingtohisownwords,dependentuponany“specialmetaphysical”foundationthatwouldbeunacceptableforaliberallegaltheory.38AtthispointofourpresentationofthemaintraitsofDworkin’slegaltheory,itshouldbeclearthathistheoryofrightsisgroundedpreciselyintheircapacitytotrumpanyargumentbasedonapolicyorcollectivegoal,evenifadvancedthroughappealstometaphysicaltruthsregardingindivi-dualorcommon-goodmorality.Histheoryoflawandrightsfindsitsultimatepointofreferencenotinmetaphysicsorphilosophical-anthropologicaltruths,butinthenatureoflawasasocialinstitution,namely,in“somefundamentalassumptionsaboutthequalityofadecentsocialorganization”.39

Dworkin’sargumentonrightsastrumpsrestsonthefundamentalpostulateofliberalpoliticalmoralitythatitiswrongtolegallyenforceprivatenon-political

36 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.24),p.263;Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.11),pp.3,75.37 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.5),pp.102–104;Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.10),pp.410–412.38 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.13),pp.xi–xii.39 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.24),p.266.

548 PetarPopović:ExploringtheAspectsofLaw’s“Goodness”inRonaldDworkin’sCritiqueof...

moralbeliefsthroughstatepoliciesandcorrespondingrule-bookenactedlaws.40 Thus,theinstitutional–notmetaphysical–foundationsofhisconceptionoflawaremodelledby“themostfundamentalofrights”:the right to equal concern or respect.41

“Governmentmusttreatthosewhomitgovernswithconcern,thatis,ashumanbeingswhoarecapableofsufferingandfrustration,andwithrespect,thatis,ashumanbeingswhoarecapableofformingandactingonintelligentconceptionsofhowtheirlivesshouldbelived.Governmentmustnotonlytreatpeoplewithconcernandrespect,butwithequalcon-cernandrespect.Itmustnotdistributegoodsoropportunitiesunequallyonthegroundthatsomecitizensareentitledtomorebecausetheyareworthyofmoreconcern.Itmustnotconstrainlibertyonthegroundthatonecitizen’sconceptionofthegoodlifeisnoblerorsuperiortoanother’s”.42

Theright toequalconcernandrespectmaybesaidtobeanatural rightinsofarasitisnottheproductoflegislationorconvention43,butis,instead,embeddedinaliberaltheoryoflawasaninstitution.Itisa“fundamentalandaxiomatic”rightinthesensethatitisthesourceofallotherparticularrights.44

Thebasicrighttoequalityisthecorevalueatthecentreofthelegal-institu-tionaldomainofpoliticalmorality.Thelawasaninstitution“benefitssociety”notonlythroughinstrumentalproperties,suchas“predictabilityorproceduralfairness”,butalso“bysecuringakindofequalityamongcitizens”that“impro-vesitsmoraljustificationforexercisingthepoliticalpoweritdoes”.45Thevalueofequality,orequalconcernandrespect,providestheinstitutionoflawwiththeviewpoint–the“pointoflaw”–thatsetsthelimitontheextenttowhich“citizens’andofficials’viewsaboutjustice[…]figureintheiropinionsabout

40 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.11),p.205.SeealsoDworkin, op. cit.(fn.5),pp.173–175.41 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.13),p.xii.42 Ibid.,pp.272–273.43 Seeibid.,pp.176–177.InthissectionofTaking Rights Seriously,DworkinactuallypositstherighttoequalconcernandrespectasthefundamentalrightimplicitinJohnRawls’stheoryofjusticeasfairness.However,itmaybesaidthatDworkinreallyonlyreadshisownargumentsintoRawls’stheory,asissuggestedbyRawls’sexplicitdenialofimplyingsuchnaturalrightasfoundationalforhisconceptionofjustice(“ThisisaningenioussuggestionbutIhavenotfolloweditinthetext”).SeeRawls,J.,Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical,PhilosophyandPublicAffairs,vol.14,no.3,1985,p.236.

44 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.13),p.xv;Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.10),p.330.45 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.5),pp.95–96.

Zbornik PFZ, 70, (4) 539-563 (2020) 549

whatlegalrights”personshaveaccordingto“pastpoliticaldecisions”.46Thus,therighttoequalityhasthecharacteristicofapolitical-moralsubstantivevaluethathasafoundationalroleintheidentificationofthelawinapoliticalcommunity.ThismeansthatDworkin’saccountoflaw’s“goodness”isnotpurelyformalistic,aslegalpositivismsustains,norisitfoundeduponmetaphysicalclaimsabouthumangood,astheclassicalnatural-lawtheoryfirmlyholds.Instead,aDwor-kinian“goodness”of lawismanifestedinthe institutionalviewpointofthejuridicalmeaningofequalityfromwhichlawshouldbeidentified,interpreted,andultimatelypositivizedintherulebooks.

Thecrucialquestionthatmustnowbeansweredis:whatdoesthisstateofaffairs–thatattherootsofDworkin’sideaofthelegalsystemwefindafoundationalvaluethatbelongstothesphereofpoliticalmorality–sayabouttheconceptoflaw?

ItcertainlyconfirmsDworkin’sobjectionstolegalpositivismfor“mistakingpartofthedomain”oftheconceptoflaw,namely,thepositivizedrule-bookdomain,“forthewhole”.47Ontheotherhand,Dworkin’sconceptoflawresiststhecompleteoverlapbetweenthecontentofprinciple-basedrightsandtheratio ofgoal-basedpoliciesrootedinnon-politicalorprivatemorality.Aswewillseeinthenextsection,thislatterclaimrepresentsthemainlineofcritiquethatDworkinadvancesagainstthestrongnatural-lawtheory.

Intheimmediateaftermathofhisfirstbook,Taking Rights Seriously,Dworkinwonderswhetherthetwoquestions–“whatrightsdopersonshave”and“whichpoliciesmakethecommunityflourish”–couldbe,fromsomeviewpoint,consi-deredtoconstituteaspectsofthesamequestion.Hisresponseisthat,althoughthislineofinquiryisnotaltogetherincoherent,itis“veryimplausible”48,pre-ciselyonaccountofbothhissystematicbifurcationofprinciplesandpoliciesandthepredominantlycontrastingconceptionsoflawthatcorrespondtothepreferenceforeachofthosestandards.

Towardtheendofhisacademiccareer,Dworkinrevisitedthemainthreadofthe“principlesaspolicies”lineofanalysisinhisreassessmentofwhathecallsthe“two-systemspicture”,whereintheconceptoflawisdeterminedbyenvisioninglawandmoralityastwoseparatesystemsofnormsthatsomehow,onlyoccasionally, interact.49Atthisstageofhisthought,Dworkinseemstohavereachedamorearticulateall-encompassingviewofthelineofargument

46 SeeDworkin, op. cit.(fn.5),p.98.47 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.13),p.47.48 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.24),pp.265–266.49 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.10),p.402.

550 PetarPopović:ExploringtheAspectsofLaw’s“Goodness”inRonaldDworkin’sCritiqueof...

hehasbeen,somewhatimplicitly,claimingallalong.Healwaysunderstoodlawasaninterpretiveconcept50“whoseelucidationrequirestakingastandonissuesofpoliticalmorality”.51Inthefinal,perhapsmostmature,stageofhisthought,Dworkiniscertainthatthequestionof“howdoesthecontentofeachsystem[namely,lawandmorality]affectthecontentoftheother”52mustbeansweredinthefollowingfashion:

“Wehavenowscrappedtheoldpicturethatcountslawandmoralityastwoseparatesystemsandthenseeksordenies,fruitlessly,interconnectionsbetweenthem.Wehavereplacedthiswithaone-systempicture:we now treat law as a part of political morality”.53

Hence,thereisoneplausiblewaytotreatthequestionssuchas“whatrightsdopersonshave”,“whatmakesthecommunityflourish”,“whatisthelawofapolitical community”under the samedoctrinalumbrellaof thenatureoflaw.Thisistheway:insteadofstartingfrom“theessenceorveryconceptoflawtotheoriesaboutrights”,accordingtoDworkin,“ourjourneymustbeintheoppositedirection”54,namely,bystartingfromtheequality-basedtheoryofrightsthatisembeddedintheinstitutionoflaw.Itispreciselyinthiswaythat,asDworkinsays,“decidingwhatlawshouldbelikehelpsustoseewhat,initsverynature,itactuallyis”.55Thus,aDworkinian“goodness”oflaw–thevalue-fuelledideaofwhatlaw,asaninterpretiveconcept,shouldbelike–isdeterminedbypositingequalityasthefundamentalinstitutionalviewpointoflegalityfromwhichtointerpretandidentifythesettledlawinapoliticalcom-munity.ThisiswhyDworkinreferstohisownlegaltheoryas“interpretivism”.56 Legal reasoning–theidentificationofthelawordeterminingwhichpropositionsofthelawaretrueinagivencaseatagiventime–anddefining law conceptually bothpresupposethecomplexenterpriseofinterpretationandjustificationof

50 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.9),pp.10–12,168–171,221–222.SeealsoDworkin, op. cit. (fn.5),pp.87–89,410–411.

51 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.9),p.31.52 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.10),p.401.53 Ibid.,p.405.Emphasisadded.Thisargument, fromDworkin’s2011book Justice

for Hedgehogs,isalreadyprefiguredinhisintroductiontothe2006bookJustice in Robes:“Wemightdobetterwithadifferentintellectualtopography:wemighttreatlawnotasseparatefrombutasadepartmentofmorality.[…]Wemighttreatlegaltheoryasaspecialpartofpoliticalmoralitydistinguishedbyafurtherrefinementofinstitutionalstructures”.Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.9),pp.34–35.

54 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.10),p.407.55 SeeDworkin, op. cit.(fn.9),p.145.56 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.10),pp.401–402.

Zbornik PFZ, 70, (4) 539-563 (2020) 551

enactedrule-booknormsagainstthebackdropofexistingrightswhich,inturn,representmoralkindsof reasons for actionbecause theyultimately restonconsiderationsofpoliticalmorality.57

3. DWORKIN’S “NATURALIST” CRITIQUE OF THE STRONG NATURAL-LAW THEORY

Dworkinseemstofindnothingproblematicinhiscritics’accusationthattheless-than-metaphysicalinterpretivelegaltheoryhedevelopedacrosshiscareerrepresentsaradicalturninthedirectionoftheclassicaltheoryofnaturallawandnaturalrights:“Supposethisisnaturallaw.Whatintheworldiswrongwithit”?58Whenidentifyingtheplaceofhisowntheoryonthebroadconceptualmapofthenatural-lawapproachestotheconceptoflaw,Dworkinfindsnoprobleminoccasionallylabellinghisbrandoflegal“interpretivism”as“naturalism”.59

However,Dworkinisverycarefultohighlighttheincompatibilitybetweenhis“naturalism”andwhatheconsiderstobea“strong”60,an“orthodox”61,oradownright“extreme”62versionofthenatural-lawtheory.Hefindstheselatterunacceptableandimplausiblefortwointerrelatedsetsofreasons.

Hisfirstobjectiontothese,ashemaintains,orthodoxnatural-lawtheoriesisthattheydenyany“differencebetweenprinciplesoflawandprinciplesofmorality”63intheidentificationofthelaw,or,inotherwords,thatthey“denythedifferencebetweenlegalandmoralargumentinhardcases”.64Intheschemawherejusticeisunderstoodasa“matterofthecorrectorbesttheoryofmoralandpoliticalrights”settledatthelevelofpersonalnon-politicalconvictions,whilelawisamatterofidentifying“whichsupposedrights[…]areincludedinorimpliedbyactualpoliticaldecisionsfromthepast”,thestrongnatural-lawtheory“insiststhatlawandjusticeareidentical”.65Whereaslegalpositivismpostulatesathoroughseparationbetweenlegalandmoralrules,thenatural-law

57 SeeDworkin, op. cit.(fn.24),p.256.SeealsoDworkin, op. cit.(fn.9),p.56.58 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.7),p.165.59 Ibid.60 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.5),p.102.61 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.13),p.339.62 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.13),pp.342,344;Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.5),p.35.63 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.13),p.342.Emphasisadded.64 Ibid.,p.344.65 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.5),pp.35,97.

552 PetarPopović:ExploringtheAspectsofLaw’s“Goodness”inRonaldDworkin’sCritiqueof...

theorythatistheobjectofDworkin’scritiquetreatsthem,inhisview,asauniquesetofrulesunitedintheconceptoflaw.66Thelogicalconsequenceofthestrongnatural-lawlineofargumentisthat“nounjustpropositionoflawcanbetrue”67,or,inotherwords,that“aschemeofpoliticalorganizationmustsatisfycertainminimalstandardsofjusticeinordertocountasalegalsystematall”.68

Dworkin’ssecondobjectiontostrongnatural-lawtheoriesisthattheyarguefortheinclusionofnon-politicalprinciplesofprivatemoralityintheprocessofidentificationofthelawonthepremisethattheseprinciples“existinvirtueofobjectivemoraltruthratherthanhistoricaldecision”,andarethereby“objecti-velyrequiredbytheprinciplesofanidealpoliticalmorality”.69Saiddifferently,theargumentsofthestrongnatural-lawtheoryreston“ontologicalluxury”70 thatisunacceptabletoa“metaphysicallyunambitious”71liberallegaltheory,beitlegalpositivismorDworkin’sinterpretivism.

Insum,accordingtoDworkin’sreadingofthestrongnatural-lawtheory,lawcannotbesaidtobe“good”inthesubstantivesensethatisinvokedbythattheory.Inhisview,itisunacceptabletoholdthatcertainsubstantiveaspectsofhuman(individualorcommon)goodmustnecessarilyenter,asevaluativestandards,intotheprocessofidentification,interpretation,orjustificationofthelaw.Suchapositionwouldhavetopresuppose–erroneously,inDworkin’sopinion–thatthepointofreferencefortheinterpretationofthelawconsistsingoal-basedpoliciesforcommunity’sflourishingratherthanontheunderlyinglegalprinciples thatpoint to individualorgrouprights filtered through thearchitectonicrighttoequality.

Dworkin’scritiqueadvocatestheviewthatneithertheconceptoflawnorthelegalsystemofaparticularpoliticalcommunitymaybepredicatedupon–orderiveitsidentityorvalidityfrom–ontologicallyvalidobjectivetruthsaboutvaluesextracted“directlyfromtheordinaryrequirementsofindividualperso-nalmoralitymostofusacceptforourselvesandothersinnon-politicallife”.72 Instead,hesays,what“wealltogetheroweothersasindividuals”whenweact,especiallythroughlaw,onbehalfofthepoliticalcommunity–thisishisdefi-

66 Ibid.,p.98.67 Ibid.,p.35.68 Ibid.,p.102.69 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.11),p.147.70 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.13),p.xi.71 Ibid.,p.177.72 SeeDworkin, op. cit.(fn.5),p.173.

Zbornik PFZ, 70, (4) 539-563 (2020) 553

nitionofpoliticalmorality73–isequal concern and respect,andnotmetaphysicallyambitiousobjectivemoraltruthsenforceableascommon-goalpolicies.Thelawofapoliticalcommunityisfullyidentified–andtheconceptoflawdetermined–whentheviewpointoftheimperativetograsptheunderlyinginfrastructureofrightspermissiblebythestandardofequalconcernandrespectfindsthebestdiachronic justificationofthepoliticalcommunity’spastdecisionsandlegalnorms.Thisviewpointis,accordingtoDworkin,thecentralcaseandthelimitoflaw’s“goodness”.

4. THE RESPONSE OF THE STRONG NATURAL-LAW THEORY: DWORKIN’S MINIMALIST “NATURALISM”

Theproponentsof the strongnatural-law theory tend toarticulate theirviewsonDworkin’scritiquebychallengingtheadequacyofthe“naturallaw”labelthatissometimesattachedtohis“interpretivism”,ratherthanbydirectlyaddressinghisobjectionstotheexcessive“strength”oftheirmetaphysicalposi-tions.InthissectionIwillonlysummarilyhighlightthemainelementsofthenaturallawyers’critiqueofDworkin’slegaltheory.InthenextsectionIintendtomovebeyondtheestablishedlociofthediscussionbetweenDworkinandthenatural-lawtheoristsinordertoexplorecertainlesscontemplatedaspectsofthequestionsregardinglaw’s“goodness”thatarecontextualizedinthisdiscussion.

Regardlessoftheirsharpcritiqueofhisviews,natural-lawtheoristsdonothesitatetocomplimentDworkinonanumberof issuesonwhichhisthesesprovetobeproximatetosomeoftheirowncoreclaims.Thus,JohnFinnispra-isesDworkin’sefforttointroducethepracticalviewpointofwhat law should be likeintheinterpretationofthesources“inwhichthatlawsubsists”aswellasintheveryconceptoflaw–i.e.,inwhat law,notonlysocial-factually,butalsoconceptually,is.74Dworkin’senterpriseisnotthatdissimilar,atleastinsomeaspects,toFinnis’saccountoflaw’s“duallife”.Finnisarguesthatlaw,atthelevelofitsontologicalstatus,includesnotonlythesource-basedsocial-factualexistence,butalsotheevaluativeviewpointfromwhichlegalrules–withregardtotheircontentandtotheentirelegallyrelevanthistoryoftheirsocial-factualexistence–maybesaidtostillprovidesufficient reasons foraction,among

73 SeeDworkin, op. cit.(fn.10),p.327.74 SeeFinnis,J.,Reason and Authority inLaw’sEmpire,in:Philosophy of Law. Collected

Essays: Volume IV,OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford,2011,pp.280–281.

554 PetarPopović:ExploringtheAspectsofLaw’s“Goodness”inRonaldDworkin’sCritiqueof...

othercriteria,alsoinlightofcertainfundamentalprinciplesofpracticalreaso-nablenessormorality.75

Ontheotherhand,natural-lawtheoristscriticizeDworkin’spreferencefor“poor”metaphysicalresourcesatthefoundationofhiscaseforlaw’sinherentlypracticalorevaluativeviewpoint. InFinnis’sassessment,Dworkin’sarchite-ctonicrighttoequalconcernandrespectinbuildsintheveryconceptoflawasystematicallyneutralstandpoint“abouteventhebasicelementsofthehumangood”.76Fromtheperspectiveoflaw’ssubstantivegoodness,Dworkin’stheoryrestsuponthe“reductionofgoodsforwhichlawisneededtoequality”.77

Howdoesthisreductiontoequality,combinedwithsystematicneutralityregardingotheraspectsofthehumangood,affecttheoverallcategorizationofDworkin’stheoryasanatural-lawposition?

InVeronicaRodriguez-Blanco’sunderstanding,despiteDworkin’sattentiontotheinterpretivepointoflaw,hisaccountcannotbeclassifiedasadvocatingagoods-basedoverlapoflawandmorality.Consequently,shequestionswhetherthecoreofhislegaltheorymayevenbesaidtorestonadeliberativeviewpointofpracticalreasonandintentionalaction,sinceitobviouslycannotbeassessed,eveninprinciple,intermsofhumangoods.78RobertP.Georgedevelopsasimi-larlineofcritiquetoDworkin’sconceptionofrights.Inhisview,Dworkinianrights–including the abstract general right to equality–arederivedinawaythatiswhollydetachedfromconsiderationsofwhatistrulygoodforhumanbeings.79 IthasbeenpointedoutthatthereisgoodreasontoconsiderDworkin’srighttoequalitytobefoundedpredominantlyupontheformal-institutionalcharacteroftheequalpersonalsovereigntyoverone’sownprivateautonomy,ratherthanonsubstantiveequalityofpersonalworth.80

InRussellHittinger’sview,Dworkin’snatural-lawaccountis“minimalist”.Itrestson“thin”ontologicalassumptionsonequalitythataresufficienttosecure

75 See,forexample,Finnis,J.,A Grand Tour of Legal Theory,in:Philosophy of Law,op. cit.(fn.73),pp.101–102,107.

76 Finnis,J.,Introduction,in:Human Rights and the Common Good. Collected Essays: Volume III,OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford,2011,p.11.

77 Finnis,J.,The Nature of Law,in:Tasioulas,J.(ed.),The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Law,CambridgeUniversityPress,Cambridge,2020,p.51.

78 Rodriguez-Blanco,V.,Law and Authority Under the Guise of the Good,HartPublishing,Oxford,2014,pp.176,210–213.

79 George,R.P.,Making Men Moral: Civil Liberties and Public Morality,ClarendonPress,Oxford,1993,p.85.

80 Finegan,T.,Dworkin on Equality, Autonomy and Authenticity,TheAmericanJournalofJurisprudence,vol.60,no.2,2015,pp.143–180.

Zbornik PFZ, 70, (4) 539-563 (2020) 555

theconnectionbetweenthecentralvaluesofpoliticalmorality,legalreasoning,andtheappealtoindividualrightsastrumpsthatstructurallyprecedeorunderlytheenactedlegalrules.81However,insteadofavoiding“metaphysicalswamps”82,Dworkin’slegaltheory,atleastimplicitly–fromthestandpointoflaw’sonto-logyandlegalreasoning–containselementsthatrevealamoredeterminateandcomplexjuridical-philosophicalanthropologythanDworkiniswillingtoadmit.HittingerarguesthattheDworkinianrighttoequalpersonalsoverei-gntyoverone’sownprivateautonomy–which,inprinciple,trumpsallothersubstantivegoods-basedtelicviewpointsoflaw–mustnecessarilypresupposeasufficientlystructuredphilosophicalviewthatsketchesaliberalimageofthehumanperson.83Inotherwords,Hittingerandtheotherproponentsofthestrongnatural-lawtheoryarguethatDworkin’sconceptionofthelaw-moralityoverlapthatgroundslawinpoliticalmoralityandinvokesequalityasthearchitectonicvalue-rightcannotaltogetheravoidontologicalpremises.

5. THE ASPECTS OF LAW’S “GOODNESS” IMPLICIT IN THE DISCUSSION BETWEEN DWORKIN AND THE NATURAL LAWYERS

Dworkin’scentralargumentforlaw’s“goodness”isthattheidentificationoflaw–andthedeterminationoftheveryconceptoflaw–necessarilyincludestheviewpointthattakesintoconsiderationthevalueorthegoodoflegality,namely,theviewpointofwhatisreallygoodaboutlawasaninstitution.Whatisreallygoodaboutlaw,its“goodness”,isthenidentifiedasasetofvaluesthatpertainto,ashesays,“substantivepoliticalmorality”84,andthatare,assuch,ultimatelyharmonizedwiththehigherrequirementsofthefundamentalrighttoequality.Dworkincriticizesthestrongnatural-lawtheoryforexpandingthisviewpointoflaw’s“goodness”byincludingnon-political(andnon-institutional)moralstandardsthatarebasedonobjectivemetaphysicaltruth-claimsregardingtheaspectsofthehumangood.

InthissectionIwanttochallengeDworkin’scritiqueofthestrongnatural-lawtheory.Myaimistoshowthatatleastinoneimportantaspecttheclassical

81 SeeHittinger,R.,Varieties of Minimalist Natural Law Theory,TheAmericanJournalofJurisprudence,vol.34,no.1,1989,pp.144,149–152.

82 Hittinger,R.,Liberalism and the American Natural Law Tradition,WakeForestLawReview,vol.25,1990,pp.476–477,481–482.

83 Seeibid.,p.477.84 Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.9),p.178.

556 PetarPopović:ExploringtheAspectsofLaw’s“Goodness”inRonaldDworkin’sCritiqueof...

natural-lawtheorycannotbesaidtoconfusemoralandlegalprincipleswhendescribingtheconceptoflawandidentifyingthecontentofsettledlaw.Afterthat,IwillarguethatDworkin’slegaltheorymayitselfbefoundguiltyofin-sufficientattentiontodetaileddistinctionsbetweenmoralandlegalargumentsinitscoreclaim.

Dworkinholds that the strongnatural-lawtheoriesdenyany“differencebetweenprinciplesoflawandprinciplesofmorality”85intheidentificationofthelaw.Ibelievethereissomethingtobelearnedaboutplurallevelsoflaw’s“goodness”fromshowingwhereexactlyDworkin’scritiquefails.Theclassicalnatural-lawtheory–perhapsparadigmaticallyrepresentedbythetraditionofThomasAquinas’sjuridicalrealism–argues,inawayquitesimilartoDworkin’s,thatlawandthejuridicalphenomenoningeneralisaspecializeddomainwithinmorality.Accordingtothistheory,thelawofapoliticalcommunityisneitherreducibletomoralprinciples(asDworkinclaimsinhiscritique),norisitwhollydetachedfrommetaphysicalassumptionsregardingaspectsofthehumangood.Themoralprinciplesthatpointtocertainaspectsofthehumangood–i.e.,theprinciplesofnaturallawortheprinciplesofpracticalreasonableness–do not enterintotheframeworkoflegalreasoningasmetajuridicalmoralstandardsofevaluationofpositivelaw.86Instead,theyentertheviewpointoflaw’s“goodness”intheformofnatural rightsasjuridical goodsthataretheobjectsoftheprinciplesofnaturallaw.LetmebrieflyexplainwhatImeanbythis.

Althoughtheysharetheontologicalidentitywiththehumanmoralgoodspickedoutbytheprinciplesofnaturallaw–forexample,humanlifeasanaturalrightisalwayshumanlifeidentifiedasabasichumanmoralgood–natural rights arenotprimarilymoralentities,butgenuinelyjuridical goodsthatstructurallyprecedeenactedpositivelegalrules.AccordingtoaThomisticnatural-lawac-count,naturaljuridicalgoodsorrightsdifferinscopeandextensionfrombasichumanmoralgoodsaccordingtoaprecisesetofcriteriathatmustbesatisfiedfortheirinclusioninthejuridicaldomainandinlegalreasoning.

85 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.13),p.342.Emphasisadded.86 Dworkinmaybeexcusedforhislackofawarenesstothislineofargumentofthenatural-lawtheory,sincemanynaturallawyersaresometimesinsufficientlyatten-tivetothedistinctionbetweenmoralandjuridicallevelsofanalysisintheirpre-dominantlymetajuridicalpresentationsofthelegalrelevanceofnatural-lawargu-mentsonmoralprinciplesandrights.See,forexample,thefollowingclaim:“Thisnatural-lawtheoryofindividualrightsandcollectiveinterestshastheadvantage[…]ofprovidingarationalaccountofthemoralfoundationsofrightsbyunder-standingthemasimplicationsofintrinsichumangoodsandbasicmoralprincipleswhichrationallyguideandstructurehumanchoosing inrespect forsuchgoals”.George,op. cit.(fn.79),p.93.

Zbornik PFZ, 70, (4) 539-563 (2020) 557

First,naturalrightsdonotowetheirjuridicalcharacterandtheirinclusioninlegalreasoningtotheveryfactthattheyrefertovaluesthataremorallygoodandmetaphysicallyorobjectivelytrue.ThemoralstatusofbasichumangoodsdoesnotofitselfgeneratejuridicalorlegalobligationsinawayenvisionedbyDworkin.Rather,thejuridicalcharacterofnaturalrightscomesfromadiscretelevelof“goodness”thatisconnectedtotheattainmentofendssetbytheope-rativeprincipleofjustice.Wehaveseenthat,inDworkin’stheoryoflaw,justiceisunderstoodasa“matterofthecorrectorbesttheoryofmoralandpoliticalrights”settledatthelevelofpersonalnon-politicalconvictions.87IntheparlanceofThomisticlegaltheory,justiceistheoperativeprinciplethatconstitutesanaxiologicalframeworkwhoseoverarchingendis“renderingtoeachpersonhisownright”.88Inthistelicframework,“things”,entities,orstatesofaffairs–inthecaseofnaturalrights:basichumangoods–thatareattributedbytheprinciplesofnaturallaworpositivelawtotheirdesignatedtitleholdersareintroducedinaspecificorderof“goodness”notbecauseoftheirmoralstatus,butbecauseoftheirattributionasrightsandcorrespondingdebtsinjustice.Thus,althoughtheThomisticaccountofjuridical goodnessisnotaltogetherdetachedfromtheperspectiveofmoralgoodness–torespectlifeassomebodyelse’srightinclu-desrespectinglifeasamorallyperfectiveaspectofthewholehumangoodofanotherpersonandofhumanityingeneral–itisclearlydistinguishedfromit.

Secondly,naturalrightsdonotcomprehendthewholedomainofbasichumanmoralgoods.Rather,theyreferonlytothedomainofthatgoodthatissusceptible to outward and other-directed (interpersonal) potential interferencebyanotherindividualorgroupwho,becauseoftheverypossibilityofinterferencewiththetitleholder’slived-outattainmentofthegoodinquestion, owehimthedeterminateactionthatessentiallyconsistsin“giving”or“respecting”theratioofthatgood.89

87 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.5),p.97.88 Theargumentontheright(ius)asthe“justthingitself”(ipsa res iusta)–namely,theverything,stateofaffairsoractionthatconstitutestheobjectoftheoperativeprincipleofjustice–istakendirectlyfromAquinas.SeeS. Th.,II-II,q.57,a.1–2;q.58,a.1.FortheEnglishtranslationofthetextsfromAquinas’sSumma Theologiae,IhaveconsultedAquinas,T.,Summa Theologiae: First Complete American Edition in Three Volumes(translatedbyFathersoftheEnglishDominicanProvince),BenzigerBrothers,NewYork,1947-1948.

89 FormoredetailsonthisinterpretationoftheThomisticjuristicargumentregardingthegenesisofnatural rights, seeHervada, J.,Critical Introduction to Natural Right (translatedbyM.Emmons),Wilson&LafleurLtée,Montréal,2020,pp.7–30.SeealsoPopović,P.,The Concept of “Right” and the Focal Point of Juridicity in Debate Between Villey, Tierney, Finnis and Hervada,PersonayDerecho,vol.78,no.1,pp.65–103.

558 PetarPopović:ExploringtheAspectsofLaw’s“Goodness”inRonaldDworkin’sCritiqueof...

Insum,theoperativeprincipleof justiceestablishesa sui generisorderofhumanactionthatisessentialfortheconstitutionofthejuridicalphenome-non,atthehighestlevelofanalysis.Accordingtothistelicorder,athing,anentity,orotherfactualoroperativestateofaffairsisjuridicalwhenitis–initsoutwardandother-directeddomain–attributedandconsequentlyowedtoitsdesignatedtitleholderashisright(juridicalgoodness).Thisisdifferentfromtheoperativeprincipleofpracticalreasonableness(i.e.,thenatural-lawmorallevelofanalysis)thatengagesalsotheinternalsubjectivedispositionsoftheagentsinviewofattainingcertainself-referentialorother-directedobjects–i.e.,goods–becausetheyaremorallyperfectiveofhumanpersons,understoodindividuallyorcollectively(moralgoodness).

InThomisticjuridicalrealism,naturalrightsenterintolegalreasoninginawaythatissimilartoDworkin’sjustifyinglegalprinciplesandcorrespondingindividualrights.Theyformpartof law’sontologyasanessentialaspectofthepracticalviewpointthatisoperativeintheprocessoftheidentificationofthelaw.Ofcourse,sincetheThomisticlegaltheoryconsidersthecontentofnaturalrightstobeinclearontological continuity–thoughwithout full identity in evaluative range –withthebasichumanmoralgoods,legalreasoningwillprovidedifferentresultsthantheonepromotedbyDworkin.However,theforegoinganalysisshouldbesufficienttoestablishthatinatleastoneimportantaspectthenatural-lawtheory’scoreclaimsonlegalreasoning–andthecorrelativedistinctionbetweenmoralandjuridicaldomains–isfarmorenuancedthanDworkin’scritiquewouldsuggest.

Notwithstandingtheobviousdifferencesbetweenthetwoapproachesregar-dingthefunctionofrightsinlegalreasoning,IamconvincedthatDworkin’slegaltheoryandthestrongnatural-lawtraditionaredoctrinalalliesinatleastonemoreimportantargument,besidesthealreadyhighlightedattentiontothepracticalviewpointinlegalreasoningandtheclaimthatlawisaspecializeddomainof(political)morality.Anothercommongroundofbothlegaltheoriesiscoveredbythegeneral lineofinquirythatleadstotheconclusiononthenatureoflaw.WehaveseenthatDworkininsistsonstartingourinquiryonthenatureoflawnotfromtheessenceoftheconceptoflawtowardtheoriesaboutrightsthatpeopleactuallyhave,butintheoppositedirection:“decidingwhatlawshouldbelike”–bytakingintoconsiderationthejuristicphenomenasuchasrights–“helpsustoseewhat,initsverynature,itactuallyis”.90ThislineofinquiryisstronglyechoedinauthorsfromtheThomisticnatural-lawtraditionwhoclaimthattheconceptoflawisnotanaprioristicconcept,butaresult–a

90 SeeDworkin, op. cit.(fn.9),p.145.

Zbornik PFZ, 70, (4) 539-563 (2020) 559

pointofarrival–oncealltherelevantjuridicalphenomena,especiallynaturalrights,andthepropertiesthatrenderthemjuridicalhavebeenconsultedandwell-researched.91

Next,IwanttoarguethatDworkin’scritiqueofthestrongnatural-lawtheoryforconfusingmoralandlegalargumentsintheidentificationofthelawmightbackfireonhim.Heclaimsthatthe“goodness”oflaw,whatisreallygoodaboutlegality,isdecidedinthecontextofsubstantivepoliticalmorality,andthat“thecuttingedgeofajurisprudentialargumentisitsmoral edge”.92Hislineofargumentontheunderlyinglegalprinciplesthatpointtorightsamongwhichtherighttoequalityhastheoverarchingsignificanceis,inmyreading,thatmoraledge.ItissufficientlyclearthatDworkinenvisionstherighttoequalityofpersonalsovereigntyoverone’sownprivateautonomyasaninstitutionalless-than-me-taphysicalvalueofpoliticalmoralitythatrepresentsanessentialmoralmoduleintheconceptoflaw.IamawarethatDworkinconsiderstheincorporationofamoralmoduleintolegalreasoningtobecompletelylegitimate.Iamalsoawarethathisobjectionstothenatural-lawtheoryconcernthefull identification of all moralandlegalprinciplesindeterminingwhatthelawis.

But I do not see how a value of politicalmorality can have immediatejuridical relevanceandconstituteanessentialaspectof theveryconceptoflaw–onthesolemeritofamoralargument–andescapethesameobjectionthatDworkin directs at natural lawyers: the confusion betweenmoral andlegalarguments.Dworkin’sone-systemparadigmrestsonthethesisthat“legaltheory[is]aspecialpartofpoliticalmoralitydistinguishedbyafurtherrefi-nementofinstitutionalstructures”.93However,Idonotseewhatthis“furtherrefinement”addstohisessentiallymoral,orcertainlymetajuridical,defenseofthevalueofequalitythat,soitseems,pre-existsandmodelsthelegalorder.94 WehavealreadyquotedDworkin’s evidentlydecisivequestionof “how thecontentofeachsystem”,namely,lawandmorality,“affectsthecontentoftheotherasthingsactuallystand”.95Itiseasytonoticehow,inDworkin’stheory,moralnorms“affect”theinterpretationoflegalnorms.Itislessobvioushowlegalnorms,andlegalityitself,affectthecontentofrelevantmoralnormsand

91 SeeHervada,J.,Problemas que una nota esencial de los derechos humanos plantea a la filo-sofía del derecho,in:Escritos de derecho natural,EUNSA,Pamplona,2013,pp.155–159.

92 SeeDworkin,op. cit.(fn.9),p.178.Emphasisadded.93 Ibid.,pp.34–35.94 Dworkinoftendescribestherighttoequalityasthemainformativeprincipleforthedesignofthepoliticalorderandlegalinstitutions.SeeDworkin,op. cit.(fn.13),pp.180–182;Dworkin,op. cit.(fn.7),p.185.

95 Dworkin, op. cit.(fn.10),p.401.

560 PetarPopović:ExploringtheAspectsofLaw’s“Goodness”inRonaldDworkin’sCritiqueof...

influencethejuristicanalysisandelaborationofmoralarguments.Dworkinseemstopreferbendinghisargumentsonprinciple-basedrightstowardtheiroverlapwithcommon-goodpolicies– i.e.,therighttoequalityasthecentralpolicyofthepoliticalcommunity–ratherthanexplaininghowcommon-goodpoliciesmaybesaidtopossessajuristiccharacter.Inotherwords,Dworkinhasgonemuchfurtherthanlegalpositivistsinexplainingthe“goodness”oflaw,buthehasnotgoneveryfarinclarifyingtheprerequisitesforadiscourseonthejuridicityof“goodness”.

ItismoreprobablethattherealdifferencebetweenDworkin’slegaltheoryandthestrongnatural-lawpositionisthemetaphysicalreachoflaw’s“goodness”andmodesofexpressingthatreachinanauthenticallyjuridicallineofargument.Dworkinclaimsthatwhat“wealltogetheroweothersasindividuals”inourinstitutionalpractices,includinglegalreasoning,isthepolitical-moralvalueofequalconcernandrespect.96Thestrongnatural-lawtheoryarguesthatwhatweowetoeachother,eveninthecontextofthepoliticalcommongood,istherespectandsecuringofnaturalrightsasjuridicalgoodswhichalsoinclude–asonerightamongothers–thereferencetothevalueofequality(equalworthofpersons,equalopportunities,equalityinprocedures,etc.).Perhapsthereadercouldhaveintuitedthecrucialimportanceofaversionofthisdifferenceevenbeforereadingthispaper.Thereissomethinginsightfultobefound,however,inunderstandingtheprecisestagesoftheitineraryen routetoestablishingtheexactdifferencesandcommongroundsbetweenDworkinandnaturallawyersregardingtheaspectsoflaw’s“goodness”.Or,toparaphraseBlaisePascal,thereissomethingofvaluealsointhesearchitself,notonlyinthe“thingsthemselves”thataretheobjectofthesearch.97

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Aquinas,T.,Summa Theologiae: First Complete American Edition in Three Volumes (translatedbyFathersoftheEnglishDominicanProvince),BenzigerBrothers,NewYork,1947-1948.

Burazin,L.,Can There Be an Artifact Theory of Law?,RatioJuris,vol.29,no.3,2016,pp.385–401;https://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12134

Burazin,L.;Himma,K.E.;Roversi,C.(eds.),Law as an Artifact,OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford,2018;https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198821977.001.0001

96 Seeibid.,p.327.97 SeePascal,B.,Thoughts, Letters, and Minor Works(translatedbyW.F.Trotter,M.L.Booth,andO.W.Wight),P.F.Collier&SonCorporation,NewYork,1910,p.52.

Zbornik PFZ, 70, (4) 539-563 (2020) 561

Dworkin,R.,Taking Rights Seriously(2nded.),HarvardUniversityPress,Cam-bridge,1978.

Dworkin,R.,“Natural Law” Revisited,UniversityofFloridaLawReview,vol.34,no.2,1982,pp.165–188.

Dworkin,R.,A Reply by Ronald Dworkin, in:Cohen,M.(ed.),Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence,Duckworth,London,1983,pp.247–300.

Dworkin,R.,Rights as Trumps,in:Waldron,J.(ed.),Theories of Rights,OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford,1984,pp.153–167.

Dworkin,R.,A Matter of Principle,HarvardUniversityPress,Cambridge,1985.

Dworkin,R.,Law’s Empire,TheBelknapPress ofHarvardUniversityPress,Cambridge,1986.

Dworkin,R.,Justice in Robes,TheBelknapPressofHarvardUniversityPress,Cambridge,2006.

Dworkin,R., Justice for Hedgehogs,TheBelknapPress ofHarvardUniversityPress,Cambridge,2011.

Finegan,T.,Dworkin on Equality, Autonomy and Authenticity,TheAmericanJournalofJurisprudence,vol.60,no.2,2015,pp.143–180;https://doi.org/10.1093/ajj/auv014

Finnis,J.,Introduction,in:Human Rights and the Common Good. Collected Essays: Volume III,OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford,2011,pp.1–16;https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199580071.003.0001

Finnis, J.,A Grand Tour of Legal Theory, in:Philosophy of Law. Collected Essays: Volume IV,OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford,2011,pp.91–156;https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199580088.003.0006

Finnis,J.,Reason and Authority inLaw’sEmpire,in:Philosophy of Law. Collected Essays: Volume IV,OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford,2011,pp.280–298;https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199580088.003.0013

Finnis,J.,The Nature of Law,in:Tasioulas,J.(ed.),The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Law,CambridgeUniversityPress,Cambridge,2020,pp.38–58;https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.003

George,R.P.,Making Men Moral: Civil Liberties and Public Morality,ClarendonPress,Oxford,1993.

Hart,H. L.A., Introduction, in:Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy,OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford, 1983,pp.1–18;https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198253884.003.0001

Hart,H.L.A.,The Concept of Law (3rded.),OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford, 2012.

562 PetarPopović:ExploringtheAspectsofLaw’s“Goodness”inRonaldDworkin’sCritiqueof...

Hervada, J.,Problemas que una nota esencial de los derechos humanos plantea a la filosofía del derecho, in:Escritos de derecho natural,EUNSA,Pamplona,2013,pp.151–164.

Hervada,J.,Critical Introduction to Natural Right(2nded.,translatedbyM.Em-mons),Wilson&LafleurLtée,Montréal,2020.

Hittinger,R.,Varieties of Minimalist Natural Law Theory,TheAmericanJournalofJurisprudence,vol.34,no.1,1989,pp.133–170;https://doi.org/10.1093/ajj/34.1.133

Hittinger,R.,Liberalism and the American Natural Law Tradition,WakeForestLawReview,vol.25,1990,pp.429–499.

Kelsen,H.,Pure Theory of Law(translatedbyM.Knight),TheLawbookExchange,Ltd.,Clark,NewJersey,2005.

Lyons,D.,Moral Limits of Dworkin’s Theory of Law and Legal Interpretation,BostonUniversityofLawReview,vol.90,no.2,2010,pp.595–602.

Pascal,B.,Thoughts, Letters, and Minor Works(translatedbyW.F.Trotter,M.L.Booth,andO.W.Wight),P.F.Collier&SonCorporation,NewYork,1910.

Popović,P.,The Concept of “Right” and the Focal Point of Juridicity in Debate Between Villey, Tierney, Finnis and Hervada,PersonayDerecho,vol.78,no.1,pp.65–103;https://doi.org/10.15581/011.78.65-103

Priel,D.,Description and Evaluation in Jurisprudence,LawandPhilosophy,vol.29,no.6,2010,pp.633–667;https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-010-9081-y

Rawls, J., Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical, Philosophy andPublicAffairs,vol.14,no.3,1985,pp.223–251.

Raz,J.,About Morality and the Nature of Law,in:Between Authority and Interpretation: On the Theory of Law and Practical Reason,OxfordUniversityPress,Oxford,2009,pp.166–181;https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199562688.003.0006

Rodriguez-Blanco,V.,Law and Authority Under the Guise of the Good,HartPubli-shing,Oxford,2014.

Zbornik PFZ, 70, (4) 539-563 (2020) 563

* Dr.sc.PetarPopović,docentFakultetakanonskogprava,PapinskosveučilišteSvetogKriža,PiazzadiSant’Apollinare49,00186Rim,Italija;[email protected];

ORCIDID:orcid.org/0000-0001-5282-0850

Sažetak

Petar Popović*

PREISPITIVANJE VIDIKA “DOBROTE” PRAVA U DWORKINOVOJ KRITICI “SNAŽNE” TEORIJE NARAVNOG PRAVA

Cilj ovog rada preispitivanje je određenih vidika kritike američkog filozofa prava Ronalda Dworkina upućene “snažnoj” teoriji naravnog prava. Za žarišnu točku preispi-tivanja autor je odabrao perspektivu “dobrote” prava, odnosno pitanje na koji način i do koje granice Dworkin i predstavnici “snažne” teorije naravnog prava, svatko u okvirima vlastitog pristupa, dopuštaju preklapanje pojma prava sa stajalištem prosuđivanja prava sukladno moralnim vidicima ljudskog dobra. U prvom dijelu rada prikazani su ključni argumenti Dworkinove teorije prava s naglaskom na one elemente zbog kojih se Dworkina često smatra predstavnikom teorije naravnog prava u širem smislu. Nakon toga predstavljene su temeljne tvrdnje Dworkinove kritike upućene “snažnoj” teoriji naravnog prava, s poseb-nim naglaskom na Dworkinovo razlikovanje “snažne” teorije od njegova naravnopravnog pristupa. U nastavku su opisani osnovni smjerovi argumentacije kojima su predstavnici “snažne” teorije naravnog prava upozorili na otklon Dworkinova “minimalističkog” jus-naturalizma od klasičnih postavki naravnopravne teorije. U posljednjem dijelu analizirani su vidici “dobrote” prava koji proizlaze iz predmetne rasprave, s naglaskom na određene manjkavosti Dworkinove kritike “snažne” teorije naravnog prava. Pritom se upućuje i na teorijske sastavnice prema kojima se, unatoč uzajamnoj kritici, ova dva pravno-filozofska pristupa mogu smatrati srodnima.

Ključne riječi: Dworkin, teorija naravnog prava, interpretacijska teorija prava, politička moralnost