kant's history and theory of heaven

Upload: mark-julyan

Post on 05-Apr-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    1/17

    Kan t ' s H i st o r y and Theo r y o f Heaven Pa r t Th r ee Show Per f o r m ance

    (End les s J ok e . B i g Prob lem. Poe t r y Genera t i on . )

    By Mark Julyan

    ..the incongruity between the sophistication of Kants gelastic theory on t he one hand, and his idea of a good joke, on t he other,

    is itself funny. The incongruity inherent in his incongruity t heory of humour amounts t o an instance and il lustration of t he t heory.The fact that one of the most sophisticated theories of humour in history would be supported by such a weak joke is itself the

    incongruity. Justin E.H. Smith. 'Kant on Jokes'

    Si len t Speech , Canc e l l a t i on , Pos s ib l e Wor l ds

    I

    Kant's idea of a good joke may well have been funny itself and it would appear he played out for high audiences. One cross-

    categorized performative utterance, defined in terms of such 'freewheeling witty displays', is situated in the opening statement of

    the appendix which treats of t he inhabitants of the stars to his early work the Universal Natural History and Theory of the

    Heavens (Allgemeine Naturgeschichte und theorie des Himmels) . Where an even further dilemma for the modern reader exists, it

    is in the way Kant's own incongruity is thrown into relief through its cancellation by Ian Johnson who physically interacts with the

    body of the text by inverting Kant's meaning so as to erase out the incongruity in his mistranslation of Kant's publication from

    German into English and where we can see the difference:

    Kant: In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-

    wheeling witty displays having some apparent truth, if we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this

    only as an amusement.

    Johnson mistranslating Kant: In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a

    kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty displays having some apparent truth, unless we are immediately willing to explain

    that we are doing this only as an amusement.

    Weil ich dafr halte, dass es den Charakter der Weltweisheit entehren heisse, wenn man sich ihrer gebraucht, mit

    einer Art von Leichtsinn freie Ausschweifungen des Witzes mit einiger Scheinbarkeit zu behaupten, wenn man sich

    gleich erklren wollte, dass es nur geschhe, um zu belustigen

    A footnote is attached to the passage where the entire explanation for this re-imaging of the text is that:

    Kants text has if rather than unless, which seems clearly wrong in the context of the entire sentence."

    Johnson informs us in the first preface to his otherwise superlative translation (1998), in a passage missing from the most recent

    edition (2008), that Kant's original footnotes with translators footnotes now attached have been moved from their immediacywithin and alongside the text to the end of the book, in a passage which stated: all footnotes have been moved to the end, thus

    deferring to the end his willingness to immediately explain before then later deleting this explanation of the non-immediate

    explanation in the later edition.

    And in this down the rabbit hole move then where Johnson like a play within a play, plays out a joke within incongruity in Kant;

    where we have the contrast between the 'if' that revels in philosophical impropriety with the presumption of an 'unless' that migh

    resolve it with a fake in translation; between the immediacy of the 'immediately willing to explain' in Kant and the deleted

    explanation which once explained the deferment of the non-immediate explanation in Johnson; between the apparency of the

    'some apparent truth' in Kant with the various apparencies and non apparencies of the 'seems clearly wrong' in Johnson - as well

    as Johnson's assumption that 'unless' operates as the only or necessary alternative to a disjunctive 'if', in spite of an endless

    variety of equally coherent alternative options; and his assertion that the 'context of the entire sentence' is sufficient in itself to

    fully understand the meaning.

    But then as the first introduction to various kinds of the 'seems clearly wrong' in philosophical language, and particularly with Kant

    in mind, it was John L. Austin (1962) who first outlined the differing interpretational enlivenments that such a statement 'despite

    an unexceptionable grammatical form', might function relative, if not in truth, then with at least possible felicities or happiness

    fulfilled in meaning or event when, with his emphasis he writes:

    First and most obviously, many 'statements' were shown to be, as KANT perhaps first argued systematically, strictly

    nonsense, despite an unexceptionable grammatical form: and the continual discovery of fresh types of nonsense,

    unsystematic though their classification and mysterious though their explanation is too often allowed to remain, has

    done on the whole nothing but good. Yet we, that is, even philosophers, set some limits to the amount of nonsense

    that we are prepared to admit we talk: so that it was natural to go on to ask, as a second stage, whether many

    apparent pseudo statements really set out to be 'statements' at all. It has come to be commonly held that many

    utterances which look like statements are either not intended at all, or only intended in part, to record or impart

    straightforward information about the facts: for example, 'ethical propositions' are perhaps intended, solely or partly,

    to evince emotion or to prescribe conduct or to influence it in special ways. Here too KANT was among the pioneers.

    We very often also use utterances in ways beyond the scope at least of traditional grammar. It has come to be seen

    that many specially perplexing words embedded in apparently descriptive statements do not serve to indicate some

    specially odd additional feature in the reality reported, but to indicate (not to report) the circumstances in which the

    statement is made or reservations to which it is subject or the way in which it is to be taken and the like... Along

    these lines it has by now been shown piecemeal, or at least made to look likely, that many traditional philosophical

    perplexities have arisen through a mistake - the mistake of taking as straightforward statements of fact utterances

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    2/17

    which are either(in interesting non-grammatical ways) nonsensical or elseintended as something quite different. [1]

    Which brings us to the idea that what seems clearly wrong if not exceptional grammatical form, is rather a necessary and signal

    violation of appropriateness or politeness criteria and as such to the idea that whatever implications or categorically inappropriate

    juxtapositions we find may have been 'intended as something quite different' and not merely 'something quite different' or 'seems

    clearly wrong'. In which case, the thought that Kant's work necessitates re-writing in order to make the clause connections

    somehow acceptable to standards of correctness in speech and politeness is indeed quite the focus of our amusement and thereby

    perfectly the origin of our project.

    I I

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-

    wheeling witty displays having some apparent truth, if we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing thisonly as an amusement.

    The incongruity, which is to say the seems clearly wrong elements within this statement, emerge relative to the wider contexts of

    an inappropriate juxtaposition in terms of the possible worlds we are asked to contemplate and emerges (the cognitive dissonance

    moment where we are invited to confront unexpected cross categories) through the use and placement of the word 'if'. Teun A.

    Van Dijk (1979) writes:

    ..if is a conditional which so to speak selects the possible world or situation in which the consequent is asserted (or

    asked) to be true. Contrary to the usual logical analysis, both for material and strict implications, we take i f. . . (then)

    to be a general modal conditional; that is, there is a conditional relation between facts, but at the same time the if

    indicates that the relation only holds in specific possible worlds (viz. those where the antecedent is true).

    Observing in particular, the relationship between 'if, or and unless', and their comparative relationships to the appropriateness of

    possible world situations relative to the context of preceeding statements Van Dijk continues:

    .. we again see that pragmatic or, if and unlessare closely related. In all cases they pertain to the - often rhetorical,

    and/or polite questioning of appropriateness conditions (or sometimes semantic conditions) of a neighbouring, mostly

    preceding, speech act.

    It is notable here that if IF and UNLESS are closely related, the relationship is of such a kind as to fulfill a specific function where

    UNLESS is essentially an expression whose semantic conditions are set by IF followed by a negation - IF + NEG = UNLESS:

    if + NEG, is expressed by unless: Where: p unless q = if not q, then p.

    All of which is to say that if Kant's statement seems clearly wrong, it is in the first instance wrong because it is considered

    inappropriate as to the possible worlds we are asked to envisage relative to what we have been enjoined to expect. And it is

    precisely here, in this particular expanding non-space of individual unities and ruptures, the orders of implied scales of quantity

    and quality and the inherent circularities between various social, metaphorical, linguistic and conceptual possible worlds, as

    conjoined and exploded by the 'if', that we can observe the first array of differences within this particular incongruity. These are

    the differences in speech that separate the silent from the scream; the implied from the stated; the continuity of social semblance

    or politeness from rupture and dissemblance. The differences that inaugurate conflict between the elements in Peter Veatch's

    incongruous and endlessly repudiated anti-Hobbesian description of humour as emotional pain that doesn't hurt; or those

    relationships between the social nature of actual worlds with the sensuality of the body in Mary Douglass anthropological account

    of humour described as the irruption of the body' into social situations in which it is supposed to remain hidden.

    Where language is a complex phenomena with discrete communicative elements that function alongside and merge into oneanother, any of those individual elements may potentially at some point dis-function so as to detonate a snapping point in

    incongruity. For a joke to be triggered by the mis-placement of a logical connective suggests a complex joke and for the

    disjunction to be triggered by the use of a hypothetical connective such as IF, seems particularly inflammatory. This suggests the

    unleashing of incongruity within the ensnaring terms of a dilemma - the dissonance in imagined possible worlds we thereafter

    bridge but cannot bridge in the attempt of negotiating the snapping point over the chasm, back and forth, back and forth,

    between IF and UNLESS.

    If the unleashing of humour continues involuntarily as physiology after the event, the dissonance or incongruity wrought over a

    logical connective such as IF continues potentially also in terms of hypothetical possibilities. It continues in it's persisting

    involuntary oscillation through a connective which still concernsas to the nature of the connection. In this, in it's ambiguous

    joining function it brings us immediately to the possibility of parataxis - that use of language that operates in the absence of,

    through or across points of connective specification. As an example of continuous aphoristic play through opposition forces, in a

    passage from his essay Sentence, Image, History, Jacques Ranciere defines continuous bodily linking or paratactic immediacy

    through the role of what he calls the sentence-image, as the phrasal power of continuity against the imaging power of rupture.

    The sentence function is still that of linking. But the sentence now links in as much as it is what gives flesh. And this

    flesh or substance is, paradoxically, that of the great passivity of things without any rationale. For it's part, the image

    has become the active, disruptive power of the leap that of the change of regime between two sensory orders. Thesentence-image is the union of these two functions. It is the unit that divides the chaotic force of the great parataxis

    into phrasal power of continuity and imaging power of rupture. As sentence, it accommodates paratactic power by

    repelling the schizophrenic explosion. As image, with it's disruptive force it repels the big sleep of indifferent triteness

    or the great communal intoxication of bodies. The sentence-image reins in the power of the great parataxis and stands

    in the way of its vanishing into schizophrenia or consensus. (p46)

    These are the continuing and disruptive forces through which in Kant we might understand the way that the sentence links the

    virtuality of implied possible worlds with the absolute immediacy of the body. As if in the formulation of the dilemma: 'If I stay

    inside I will die immediately through burning by fire: If I jump from the window I will die immediately from the leap - therefore I

    will die immediately'; but where instead it becomes possible for the continuity which unites the EITHER and the OR to become

    BOTH in the apotheosis of the immediate. We collapse the space inwards and bounce inwardly off the recurring jump and burn

    imperatives and in a fashion both alternative and endless. In the possible world where we both leap and burn in the repulsion of

    the schizophrenic explosion, this is the interplay of the IF and the IF + NEG, or UNLESS synthesized as BOTH in terms of both

    disgrace and amusement fulfilled through the free-wheeling witty display and the immediacy of the announcement. The

    combination at once of continuity in language and rupture in image. And it is these differences that emerge into the silence of the

    silent speech where on the next page Ranciere temporalizes in cinematic terms, through a comic misunderstanding, his description

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    3/17

    of the sentence-image:

    This could put us in mind of those nets stretched over chaos by which Deleuze and Guattari define the power of

    philosophy or of art. But since we are talking about cinematic histories here, I shall instead illustrate the power of the

    sentence-image by a famous sequence from a comic film. At the beginning of A Night in Casablanca, a policeman looks

    with a suspicious air at the strange behaviour of Harpo, who is motionless with his hand against a wall. He asks him to

    move on. With a shake of the head, Harpo indicates that he cannot. The policeman then observes ironically that

    perhaps Harpo wants him to think that he is holding up the wall. With a nod, Harpo indicates that that is indeed the

    case. Furious that the mute should make fun of him in this way, the policeman drags Harpo away from his post. And

    sure enough, the wall collapses with a great crash. This gag of the dumb man propping up the wall is an utterly apt

    parable for making us feel the power of the sentence-image, which separates the everything hangs together of art

    from the everything mergesof explosive madness or consensual idiocy. p46.

    The muted show performance in this instance is that outspokeness of a forbidden possible world silenced through the irruption of

    an affirmation and made alive through a mistranslation. A performance where the policeman transcribes a flippant nod as a simpleyes or a simple yes as a flippant nod or both together or as if to create some other comic confusion, but where it still enforces the

    invasion and re-situation of the mute.

    Yet if the first array of circularities that emerge through the the use of the IF were theatrical yet still seeming silent in colliding

    the social forces of disgrace and amusement, the second array invites us to read them musically or colourfully, as if on

    contrasting and resonating scales of reference. Kant's own analysis of a joke uses the metaphor of a string snapping with

    involuntary oscillations continuing through both mental movement and the body ( Critique of Judgement SS 54):

    It is observable that in all such cases the joke must have something in it capable of momentarily deceiving us. Hence,

    when the semblance vanishes into nothing, the mind looks back in order to try it over again, and thus by a rapidly

    succeeding tension and relaxation it is jerked to and fro and put in oscillation. As the snapping of what was, as it

    were, tightening up the string takes place suddenly (not by a gradual loosening), the oscillation must bring about a

    mental movement and a sympathetic internal movement of the body. This continues involuntarily and produces

    fatigue, but in so doing it also affords recreation.

    This underline of the metaphor, this qualifying 'as it were', is not surprising where we most often use metaphors that relate

    language to the idea of it's being like a kind of string, perhaps but not only a musical string but with various kinds of transitions

    or scales between the various extremes or end notes. Colloquialisms for communicative particularity in sender function, intention,context, interpretation or consequence might be described as to 'string along', 'embroider an account', 'spin a yarn', 'weave a

    tale', 'harp about', 'deliver a punch line', 'pick up the wrong end of the stick' or 'tongue lash' where all insist upon a complex

    duality of string or line metaphor to different circumstances; and where we might even observe in terms of entire theories the

    broad idea of truth statements being defined as point to point correspondance or Richard Rorty's complex description of his

    linguistic philosophy as 'walking a thin line'.

    In the particular statement we are exploring here, the opposing sets of strings are those that play upon the analogies and

    dissemblances between 'disgrace', 'amusement, 'kind of flippancy', 'free-wheeling', 'witty displays', 'some apparent truth' and

    'amusement'. For the 'some apparent truth' Kant's German has ' einiger Scheinbarkeit', which literally means 'some apparency or

    claim' (which strongly implies that truth is it's object but which refrains from stating this explicitly). The word 'some' is a naturally

    ambivalent term in that it tends to be used to signify various kinds of implied, partially spelled out ambiguity on either

    quantitative or qualitative transitional scales and is a word whose meaning has generated a lot of literature. [2] Some is a complex

    word that can and very often does function as ambiguous on more than one scale of contextual reference at the same time. Used

    before a plural noun as in 'some apparencies', the word functions most obviously on a quantitative scale and implies that we mean

    some and onlysome of the apparencies, whilst still remaining logically compatible with a variety of other potential meanings. In

    this sense, it is similar to the term 'a kind of', in the implication that 'a kind of flippancy' suggests something less than being

    entirely flippant, but as understatement might still imply a comprehensive amount. When used before a singular noun as in Kant'sstatement, 'some apparency' might, depending on context or intonation, suggest a derogatory sense of what is apparent, or

    exemplary one or in ironic usage both senses at the same time.

    But as 'some' tends to implicate meanings on more than one scale in simultaneous implication, there are other potential

    complexities or ambiguities. As an example, the response 'there is some' to the specific question 'how much is there?', might

    either in terms of enormity or scarcity underwrite and/or ambiguate the fact that the actual amount is beyond or below

    anticipation terms in being either a lot, not very much or alternatively and/or simultaneously also suggest a somewhat ambiguous

    unwillingness to impart the information due to the question violating politeness conditions.

    Even if we take it in the strong sense that truth is the object of the apparency here, it

    remains that 'some apparent truth', is equally and logically and semantically coherent in

    either actually true or false statements. 2+2=5 is not true, but it might as geometry through

    e.g. some apparency in optical illusions, be made to seem that way and vice versa.

    And then we have ".. with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty displays..". If Kant says it

    was a kind of flippancy, then which kind is implied and what are the transitional phases we

    might envisage on the scale between this and other kinds? The German is "mit einer Art von

    Leichtsinn freie ausschweifungen des w itzes", which in literal translation, suggests 'a kind of

    careless suicidal liberality or reckless dissolution through wit'.

    On a visual scale similarly mixing suicides and liberalities or free-wheels and flippancies and

    published just seven years after the Universal Natural History, William Hogarth illustrates a

    set of transitions on a scale which runs from suicide madness in the lower to raving madness

    at the epiphany. In the print Credulity, Superstition and Fanaticism - A Medley, the

    teleological continuity of experience runs on a barometer protruding out of the brain of one

    of Hogarth's denomenational adversaries with Despair, AGONY, Sorrow, Love Heat, LUST,

    EXTACY (sic) and Convulsions somewhere in between the end points.

    Conceived in the first instance and amongst other things as a critique of connoisseurship in

    general Hogarth provides us, in what can scarcely be called a depiction of silent speech, with

    another scale immediately above this one in the form of a volume meter depicted as scream

    and bull roar. This time the scale is one of vociferation levels and is indicated as emanating

    from the preacher and as such is linked to the orders on the barometer of audience

    experience just described. Contextualizing speech modes are linked into the forms of the

    flesh in a form which generates future development. The sacred cadences of the Methodist Chapel are relayed in this instance in

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    4/17

    satirical terms in a way that conflates enthusiasm (a derogatory phrase in the 18th Century) with excessive rhetoric.

    Illustrating perfectly the complex nature of parataxis through cross-categorization in this collision of music, teleology and humour,

    Hogarth ruptures and conjoins font choices between the title and sub-title so as to continue and add complexity to the meaning

    as these are etched onto the paper. Where the words in the title are in light inks, the 'and' that joins them is dark and links into

    the boldness in the sub-title to spell out 'and A MEDLEY'. The pre-dominance of the title thus becomes subordinated in a process

    where the 'and A MEDLEY' underwrites and thrusts into emphasis the immediacy of the sub-title. The 'and A MEDLEY' is the most

    obvious element a viewer perceives from across the room as they stand back and survey the print as a whole. Beyond our

    immediate focus the elements of humour resound through linguistics and flesh and announce themselves as doing so. Hogarth

    thus underscores the immediate nature of his explanation in a way which makes the sense of his whole work resound with the

    directness of force of the incongruous paratactic 'and A MEDLEY'.

    Fig's 1, 2 & 3. William Hogarth, Credulity, Superstition and Fanaticism A Medley. 1762. London, British Museum

    Kant's statement is clearly wrong and overlapping complexities make it seem so in multiple ways. Kant's statement seems to point

    towards one expectation and then circle back in and defeat the eventuality. Kant's statement reinforces and underwrites the

    rationale and sensibilities it seems always determined to defeat. It evokes the unity of an 'in my view' at the outset and conjoins

    this with the principled and emphatic disavowal of the disgrace, yet seems destined to make a self referential disintegration of all

    this through the colourful and elaborate descriptions of the kinds of flippancy in the free-wheeling witty displays. Where the

    explicit criteria of the disavowal in the 'we immediately explain', emerges according to one set of rational expectations, it seems

    thereafter to function as that explanation and therefore as both detachment and implication. The 'we immediately explain' is the

    explanation. In this, the disgrace, whilst explicitly contained at the level of semantics, re-emerges as pragmatic eruption in the

    most incredible kind of implication - yet whilst still implying a kind of reservation. If we accept, as per The Critique of Judgement

    that 'the joke must have something in it capable of momentarily deceiving us', one possibility for all this is that a complex

    incongruity may legitimately be used to deceive us into momentarily doubting the seriousness of the task ahead. We joke becauseto do so underwrites the seriousness of the actuality. We joke thus we are serious. To introduce the incongruity of the joke as

    contextualization underscores and thrusts into emphasis through the absurdity of the complexity, the fact that we really are in

    earnest. But there are shades of grey left within and concerns that remain. Through it's explication here as outside theusual

    frames of acceptable philosophical discourse, what follows perhaps escapes reprehension and therefore of genuine disgrace

    or uncontextualized bewilderment at some later stage in writing.

    And whether or not instances of humour are continuous and oscillate through the body in involuntarily movements afterwards,

    they can, as indeed all statements might through additional statements, inform us that a later statement has modified, reinforced

    or cancelled the earlier one. Kant does exactly this, except part of the criteria of his statement is the excess of wit or freie

    ausschweifungen- and the cancellation event begins with a logical connective in the form of 'thus':

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-

    wheeling witty displays having some apparent truth, if we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this

    only as an amusement. Thus, in the present essay I will not introduce any propositions except those which can really

    expand our understanding and which are at the same time so plausibly established that we can scarcely deny their

    validity.

    Weil ich dafr halte, dass es den Charakter der Weltweisheit entehren heisse, wenn man sich ihrer gebraucht, miteiner Art von Leichtsinn freie Ausschweifungen des Witzes mit einiger Scheinbarkeit zu behaupten, wenn man sich

    gleich erklren wollte, dass es nur geschhe, um zu belustigen: so werde ich in gegenwrt igem Versuche keine

    anderen Stze anfhren, als solche, die zur Erweiterung unseres Erkenntnisses wirklich beitragen knnen, und deren

    Wahrsc heinlichkeit zugleich so wohl gegrndet ist, dass man sich kaum entbrechen kann, sie gelten zu lassen.

    Thus' derives a meaning consequentiallyfrom prior conditions usually established in an earlier passage. Where an earlier

    statement contains incongruity, aside from involuntary physiology and mental movement, a linking word such as 'thus'

    immediately following will act so as to continue the earlier problematic logically, even if it makes an explicit claim to dissolve it;

    and this is indeed an excess in dissolution.

    To illustrate how a statement may function through more than one intentional aspect albeit in a different context, consider how

    Wittgenstein observes firstly that there are transitions on the scale between truth functional statements and expressive cries; and

    secondly that the placement of single elements on such a scale might be variously unsituated, even in simple phrases.

    Wittgenstein with his emphasis writes: 'A cry is not a description. But there are transitions. And the words "I am afraid" may

    approximate more, or less, to being a cry. They may come quite close to this and also be far removed from it'. (Philosophical

    Investigations IiiX). And this suggests also the kind of embedded nuance in different simultaneous meanings that Austin reports

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    5/17

    when he speaks of language used to suggest forms such as an implied reservation, or something else, to which a statement might

    possibly be or might possibly not be entirely subject.

    Or there again consider how and with insistence in an early episode of an American animation series, the figure Cartman combines

    language with visual effect in incongruous theatricality to accentuate this emphatic yet still multi-functional property of the

    dissolution. In this instance, the unease revolves around the inevitability of the cancellation over and above both politeness criteri

    and the nature of the event. Thus at his birthday garden party Cartman uses the literary device of a set of disco lights of

    impressive size to spell out, for the exaggerated instructive purpose of the guests, the words 'PARTY ON'. The disco lights

    however, are connected to an impressive 'ON/OFF' lever set at child size height. Within moments of the party beginning, Cartman

    pulls the switch. The music abruptly ends and the party status notification spelled out by the lights implodes into 'PARTY OFF'.

    Univ er s a l Na tu ra l H i s t o r y - Sec t i on Three Append i x

    Kant thus introduces the final part of his Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens. Published in March 1755 it was the

    first book in an astonishingly productive decade. In this work Kant presents for the first time in history the modern view of nature

    as a dynamic force throughout the universe as self organizing complexity. According to Martin Shnfeld (2008) here nature

    streams outward in a wavefront of organization, generating worlds, biospheres and sentience, and finally reason, human and

    otherwise. Organization is fragile, and spontaneity, pushed far enough, invites chaos. Mature cosmic regions decay, chaos sets in,

    and entropy follows in the wake of complexity. But entropy provides the very conditions that allow the cosmic pulse to bounce

    material points back to order. Thus the expanding chaos curdles at its center into order, followed by chaos, by order, by chaos.

    Like a rising and burning phoenix, nature cycles between life and death. [3]

    The book was part of a single focused pre-critical project which attempted to unify a version of Newton's mechanistic vision with a

    natural teleology. The ambition was to produce a grand theory that accounted for the purposive development of complexity in

    nature, moral freedom in persons and the nature of God. For some (Beck:1969 and Shea:1986), it was in this work that Kant

    'out-Newtoned' Newton. Although Kant's early accomplishments in science now seem unprecedented, his scientific apercus

    brilliantly correct and the development of his conceptually centred approach well documented, Stanley Jaki (1981), in contrast

    claims that Kant's enterprise was primarily a philosophical one from the outset and furthermore that his science amounts to an

    education conducted in public. [4] Then Jaki goes on to tell us what Kant really ought to have said as an editorial insertion in hisown translation by suggesting in embryonic form in brackets the influential alteration of the text later adopted by Johnson:

    Since I hold that the character of philosophy is dishonoured when one uses it to assert with levity (and) with some

    appearance (of plausibility) free flights of fancy, if [unless] one also declares that all this is merely to entertain; [5]

    For the initial reception, only a few copies of the Universal Natural History survived the week. If Kant had been released from the

    university by Martin Knutzen seven years earlier after publication of Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces (1747), here

    he demonstrated less freie ausschweifungenofficially and published the Universal Natural History anonymously. Perhaps an

    inspired if ironic long-term career break however, Kant's biographers tell us the publisher was declared bankrupt upon printing and

    the books were sealed in the warehouse. Within days the building was mysteriously engulfed by fire with creditors being paid off

    through the insurance. [6] Anonymous or not the cover names a local company Petersen as the printer and Kant got either found

    out or discovered. On Mayday the following year he was named author in the classifieds section of the Knigsberg newspaper

    Wchentlichen Frag und Anzeigungs-Nachrichten(1 May 1756), in a note which stated: Book printer Driest sells: Magister Kant's

    Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens. Kant was even lucky considering the incendiary content and his intention to

    pursue an academic career thereafter, but with the edition out of circulation any danger was minimized. [7] He withheld the

    appendix from publication himself some forty years later when he supervised printing the second edition. [8] This shortened

    version, with the last 56 pages missing, became the standard copy until the original reappeared in 1902 in Georg Reimer's 29

    volume Complete Works of Immanuel Kant (The German 'Akademie' Edition), but was replicated afterwards in future translations,such as William Hastie's 1900 and 1969 editions. All of which, along with the analytic focus in modernism and the general lack of

    interest in Kant's early work, explains why the appendix remained so obscure while the hypothesis in the main text became

    renowned in cosmology. Presenting his translation as the first English edition to contain the full text in 1981, Jaki concludes his

    introduction by printing an image of the original, dramatizing logical complexity through 'unless' and quibbling with Kant as to the

    nature of the disgrace as he takes issue with form of language and typography on two different kinds of cover: [9]

    The disgrace of the Universal Natural History is rather that boastful attitude in the face of grave scientific and

    philosophical difficulties, which at times did not even take cover under protestations of diffidence and modesty, unless

    an unclear style, no small problem for the translator, was the cover itself. (p76)

    Let us just dwell for a brief moment by means of no interlude as one with an interest in language and typography and focus on

    this interest in the covers. As if we might observe beneath the header of the 'Disco POST' a corresponding analytic across

    conceptual and graphic categories where a semi-disguised, bandaged and grinning Martin Kippenberger emerges in the classifieds

    section of his newspaper print DI SCO BOMBSfrom Mut Zum Druck (Courage to Print). Combining full prisms across and therefore

    as thus to form an expressive mix of inflammatory harmonics with performative implications alongside a paratactic sense in

    language where, as if to unify elements in freie ausschweifungen, we might anticipate a disco whose progression literally crashes,

    falls down to earth, implodes or 'bombs out'. Where (as enter and approach Johnson) "Show-Time lockt Gste!" And where asthough to relate intention, mind and act in both speech and typography, we see a thoroughly modern unity of form through music

    and dance such as that of the disco in Kippenberger's universe, become presentable through an archaic header utilizing the very

    exact typographic font such that the printing of the Disco POSTseems to act itself as prime suspect in both dissolution and

    exposure of the disco and the force behind Kippengerger's burgeoning sarcasm.

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    6/17

    Fig 4: Im manuel Kant. Universal Natural histor y of t he Heavens. Published Johann Friederich Petersen, 1755

    Fig 5: Martin Kippenberger. Disco Bombs. From the portfolio Mut Zum Druck (courage to print). Screen print. 1989. London, Tate

    Gallery.

    Typography and publishing-event developments aside, the major scientific accomplishments in the Universal Natur al History were

    to correctly account for the disc-like shape of the Milky Way and the development of the planets and solar system from

    homogenous gaseous origins according to Newton's laws of gravity in a theory which became famously known as the

    Nebularhypothese. The hypothesis was confirmed in essentials in 1944 by the astrophysicists von Weizsacker and Kuiper. More

    recently Kant's evolutionary theory of the universe has become the essence of modern models in cosmology (Coles 2001, 240).

    The cosmologist R.L Oldershaw (2010) presenting Kant and Johann Lambert in 'post Big-Bang' cosmology as originators of the

    infinite hierarchical or 'fractal' universe writes that the most natural version of Inflation theory is Eternal Inflation in which

    Inflation is, was and always will be occurring on an infinite number of size scales. The new paradigm that cosmologists have

    arrived at by several routes is an infinite fractal hierarchy that has universes within universes without end.. The general

    paradigm that nature is an infinite hierarchy of worlds within worlds has fully arrived, and will probably be our dominantcosmological paradigm for the foreseeable future.

    The term Kant uses to describe this concept of 'worlds within worlds' is the 'great chain of being', a description borrowed from the

    poetry of Alexander Pope. Section One begins with a excerpt from Pope's Essay on Manand there are passages from this

    throughout as well as from poetry by Joseph Addison and Albrecht Von Haller. Biographer Manfred Kuehn tells us that Kant was

    offered the position of Professor of Poetry at Berlin University in 1764, but declined. If without editing, say in the manner of

    Jacques Ranciere's cinematic philosophical parataxis, we arrange the poetry from the whole of the Universal Natur al History into a

    single frame, we have:

    Is the great chain, that draws all to agree,

    And drawn supports, upheld by God, or thee?

    See plastic Nature working to this end,

    The single atoms each to other tend,

    Attract, attracted to, the next in place

    Formd and impelld, its neighbour to embrace.

    See Matter next, with various life endud

    Press to one centre still, the genral Good.

    Eternity! Who knows you?

    For you worlds are days and humans moments.

    Perhaps the thousandth sun is now turning

    And thousands still remain behind.

    Like a clock animated by a weight,

    A sun rushes by, moved by the power of God.

    Its impulse comes to an end, and another throbs.

    But you remain and do not count them.

    Who sees with equal eye, as God of all,

    A hero perish, or a sparrow fall,

    Atoms or systems into ruin hurld,

    And now a bubble burst, and now a world.

    When then a second night will bury this world,

    When from everything nothing remains but the place,

    When still many other heavens bright with other stars

    Will have completed their course,

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    7/17

    You will be as young as now, just as far from death

    As eternally alive as now.

    When Nature fails, and day and night

    Divide thy works no more,

    My ever grateful heart, O Lord,

    Thy mercy shall adore.

    Through all Eternity to Thee

    A joyful song Ill raise;

    For, oh! Eternitys too short

    To utter all Thy praise.

    He, who through vast immensity can pierce,

    See worlds on worlds compose one universe,

    Observe how system into system runs,

    What other planets circle other suns,

    What varied Being peoples every star,May tell why Heaven has made us as we are.

    Superior beings, when of late they saw

    A moral Man unfold all Natures law,

    Admird such wisdom in an earthly shape,

    And shewd a NEWTON as we shew an Ape.

    Vast Chain of Being! Which from God began,

    Natures ethereal, human, angel, man,

    Beast, bird, fish, insect, what no eye can see,

    No glass can reach! From Infinite to thee,

    From thee to nothing.

    The stars perhaps enthrone the exalted soul

    As here vice rules, there virtue has control. [10]

    The major philosophical accomplishment - which is to say that accomplishment which lies in the appendix of the third section

    immediately after the statement mistranslated by Johnson, lies in it's anticipation that cognitive experience depends on and

    emerges through the material substance and form of the body - the solution to Descartes mind/body problem. This formulation is

    now acknowledged as pre-cursor to those sciences and philosophies of embodied cognition recently emerging in the neurosciences,psychology and computation. Cognition is not as Descartes thought primarily related to formal operations on abstract symbols

    where the body is a simple accessory merely necessary for the reception of outer impressions. It is instead absolutely necessary

    for the act of thinking. Kant is concise:

    The human being is created to take in the impressions and emotions which the world is to arouse in him through that

    very body, which is the perceptible part of his being. The bodys material serves not only to impress on the

    imperceptible spirit which lives inside him the first ideas of the external world but also is indispensable in its inner

    working for repeating these impressions and linking them together, in short, for thinking.

    Although this clearly amounts to much more than a deterministic fate in terms of either ideal or attainable potential for human

    beings, in 1755 there nevertheless remained for Kant a pessimistic actuality for the majority of such creatures:

    When we consider the life of most people, it seems that this creature has been created to absorb liquids, like a plant,

    to grow, to propagate the species, and finally to grow old and die. Among all living things, human beings are the

    poorest at realizing the purpose of their existence, because they exhaust their excellent capabilities in those pursuits

    which other creatures, with far less capability, nonetheless attain more confidently and conveniently. The human being

    would even be the creature most worthy of contempt among all of them, at least from the point of view of true

    wisdom, if the hope for the future did not elevate him and if the time for a full development of the powers closed upinside him did not lie in store.

    Kant doesn't say what hope the powers closed up inside human beings might elevate us towards in future until his conclusion.

    What we do find however is not just that the mind is dependent upon the material substance of the body, but also the much more

    intriguing idea that the nature and level of rationality in creatures depends upon the type of matter on their planet of origin. The

    teleological purpose of planets is the development of life and those planets which are not inhabited now will be teeming with life in

    future. Everything in the universe is interconnected and the links in the chain are equal in necessity and importance. Human

    beings are neither the sole purpose of creation or the pinnacle:

    Thus, everything in the total extent of nature holds together in an uninterrupted series of stages through the eternal

    harmony which makes all the steps related to each other. The perfections of God have clearly revealed themselves at

    our levels and are no less beautiful in the lowest classes than in the more lofty ones.

    In his attempt to unify the sensible and the intelligible within a single ontological domain, Kant rejected Descartes dualism of a

    mental substance that thinks without extension or a material substance that is extended without thought. He presented his project

    in the preface as one extremely reluctant to develop a natural teleology out of material causes - now he throws caution to the

    wind and does just that. Kant reasoned that matter is not distributed evenly throughout the solar system. Because in Newton's

    formula gravity is directly proportional to mass and inversely proportional to distance, he proposed that the gravitational power ofthe sun had attracted the heavier, more dense materials towards its centre when the planets had originally formed. The material

    structure of persons on Mercury is thus of a denser type than the finer material bodies found on Jupiter or Saturn and this

    relationship functions correspondingly in terms of cognitive potential:

    I summarize all this in one general idea: the material stuff out of which the inhabitants of different planets, including

    even the animals and plants, are made must, in general, be of a lighter and finer type, and the elasticity of the fibres

    as well as the advantageous construction of their design must be more perfect in proportion to their distance away

    from the sun.

    Because the spiritual or life force element in matter is of an expansive nature, it originally manifested itself in greater quantities

    on the outer planets. Those creatures living in the outer spheres consequently attain a finer spiritual perfection than those existing

    nearer to the sun:

    We will not extrapolate these assumptions beyond the limits prescribed for a physical treatise; only we do once again

    take note of the above mentioned analogy that the perfection of the spiritual as well as the material worlds in the

    planets from Mercury right up to Saturn, or perhaps beyond Saturn (insofar as there are still other planets), grows and

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    8/17

    advances in an appropriate sequence of stages proportional to their distance from the sun.

    If Kant's Universal Natural History was almost entirely without mention in subsequent literature and very rarely available in it's

    entirety for almost another 150 years, Kant tells us it's planetary theory of being was itself somewhat influenced by Fontenelle's

    Conversations on the Plurality of Worlds (1686). Possibly if it had been more widely read through modernism, the nearest

    indication we have to what it's influence could have been, in its celebration of the centrality of the sun as the definer of being,

    combined with an embodied if pessimistic view of dependent 'plant like' creatures, is perhaps found in art-works such as those by

    the painter Turner. But in any case, this explains how and why Kant thought human beings existed on the middle rung of a sun-

    centred, cosmically ordered hierarchical scale of creation. The dense material and spiritual substances that define being on Mercur

    and Venus are only able to manifest themselves through living creatures in a crude fashion where the results produce relatively

    inactive or sluggish cognitive faculties. With Earth and Mars in the twilight zone, the finer spiritual material substances on Jupiter

    and Saturn result through the powers of the sun in beings who are more sublime, more elastic in their thoughts and ultimately

    more lively in their appreciation of the good.

    If the idea of the most sublime classes of sensible creatures living on Jupiter or Saturn provokes the jealousy ofhuman beings and discourages them with the knowledge of their own humble position, a glance at the lower stages

    brings content and calms them again. The beings on the planets Venus and Mercury are reduced far below the

    perfection of human nature.

    In the conclusion The conditions of human beings in the future life, observing firstly that we do not know what human beings

    are now, much less what we will become in future, Kant speculates about the future hope for human beings in terms of inter-

    planetary space exploration possibilities for materially embodied souls from beyond the grave:

    Is the everlasting soul for the full eternity of its future existence, which the grave itself does not destroy but only

    changes, always to remain fixed at this point of the cosmos, on our Earth? Is it never to share a closer look at the

    rest of creations miracles? Who knows whether it is not determined that in future the soul will get to know at close

    quarters those distant spheres of the cosmic structure and the excellence of their dwelling places, which already

    attract its curiosity from far away? Perhaps that is why some spheres of the planetary system are already developing,

    in order to prepare for us in other heavens new places to live after the completion of the time prescribed for our stay

    here on Earth.

    Although no one can be expected to ground actual hope on such uncertain, imaginary pictures, they are non the less permissible

    and appropriate as entertainment. Furthermore far from disgrace or dishonour such pleasures are shared with and even necessaryfor the perpetual contentment of the Highest Being as our collective essence strives towards infinity on all levels:

    It is permissible and appropriate to entertain ourselves with ideas of this kind. But no one will ground future hope on

    such uncertain imaginary pictures. When vanity has demanded its share of human nature, then the immortal spirit

    will, with a swift leap, raise itself up above everything finite and further develop its existence in a new relationship

    with the totality of nature, which arises out of closer ties with the Highest Being. From then on, this lofty nature,

    which in itself contains the source of blissful happiness, will no longer be scattered among external objects in order to

    seek out a calming effect among them. The collective essence of creatures, which has a necessary harmony with the

    pleasure of the Highest Original Being, must also have this harmony for its own pleasure and will light upon it only in

    perpetual contentment.

    ' T h e U n i v e r sa l F or m o f a D i le m m a '

    Kant incorporates the generative potential for at least hypothetical disjunctive syllogisms where: dilemmas therefore, thoughconsequential, are very captious or ensnaring - and he does so in a way where the consequential effects specifically invoke the

    disjunction between IF and IF + NEG in creating the logical form of the oscillation between IF and UNLESS, or the difference in the

    statements, as published, between Kant and Johnson. Kant writes in his book on logic of the disjunctive syllogisms of reason:

    In disjunctive syllogisms we argue either from the truth of one member of disjunction to the falsity of the others, or

    from the falsity of all the members except one to the truth of this one. That is done by the modus ponens, this is

    done by the modus tollens.

    Scho. 1. All the members of disjunction, one excepted, taken together, make up the contradictory opposite of this one.

    Consequently a dichotomy, according to which when one of them is true the other must be false and vice versa, has

    place here. (The universal form of this syllogism is, What is A, is either B, or C; A is not B; it is therefore C. ( Logic:

    part 1. 3. 77. p 186)

    In hypothetical disjunctive syllogisms, the consequences we find might theoretically be developed, 'how many members of a

    division soever there may be', from di-lemma through tri-lemma and tetra-lemma to thus mathematically theoretical universal or

    infinity-lemma where Kant writes:

    A dilemma is a hypothetically disjunctive syllogism, or a hypothetical argument, whose consequent is a disjunctive

    judgement. The hypothetical proposition, whose consequent is disjunctive, is the major proposition; the minor affirms,that the consequent is false, and the conclusion, that the antecedent is so.

    (The universal form of a dilemma, tri-lemma, tetralemma, or how many members of a division soever there may be,

    is that, If A is either B or C, or is; but neither B, nor C, nor D is; therefore A is not.). ( Logic: Part 1. 3. 79. p187)

    The oscillation of the IF and the IF + NEG thus presents us with the interchange of IF and UNLESS across the chasm of a

    potentially generative, ever extending or infinity lemma. This is the dance in the infinite play upon play of the possible where the

    interchange of IF and UNLESS emerge out of and into the dual poetics of the lemma and problems in real and other worlds.

    We noted how in the Critique of Judgement Kant described incongruity as the 'sudden' 'snapping of the string'. In terms of

    possible responses or alternatives to the singularity of the UNLESS in this statement, the full lash of the melody becomes

    unleashed into the reality ever unfolding. Where the divisions divide or multiply, the differences of meaning in logic and grammar

    collide into the extending rhythm of the dia-logical exchange in the never-ending conjoinations of Kant and Johnson.

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    9/17

    Poet r y Genera t i on

    Where Kant forms the appendix to section three which treats of the inhabitants of the stars in his Universal Natural History and

    Theory of the Heavens, he theorizes a teleological order of being within a mechanistic universe which opens with a statement

    which by consent seems clearly to function through incongruous formation.

    As with every other philosopher of historical significance Kant positioned incongruity within the category of the aesthetic. In this it

    is useful to compare categories and criteria between passages in the Universal Natur al History and The Critique of Judgement,

    especially with respect to correlations between such terms as spirit, mind, body, judgement, light, fire, centre, sun, quickening,

    sluggish, coarse, elastic, sublime or enlivenment. Kant writes in the Universal Natural History that it is precisely that faculty of

    judgement that functions upon the enlivenment of the body and the soul in the fashion of light and the sun when he writes that

    the coarseness of the material stuff in which his spiritual component is buried operates such that The attempts of reason to

    stand up against this and to drive away the confusion with light from the power of judgement are like moments of sunshine whenthick clouds constantly interrupt and darken their serenity.

    As if in mirror image, in The Critique of Judgement (SS 54) he relates the power of judgement to these moments of sunshine in

    an equivalent quickening effect within the body which proceeds to the refinement of the soul in the comparative harmonies of

    music and humour:

    Music and what provokes laughterare two kinds of play with aesthetic ideas, or even with representations of the

    understanding, by which, all said and done, nothing is thought. By mere force of change they yet are able to afford

    lively gratification. This furnishes pretty clear evidence that the quickening effect of both is physical, despite its being

    excited by ideas of the mind, and that the feeling of health, arising from a movement of the intestines answering to

    that play, makes up that entire gratification of an animated gathering upon the spirit and refinement of which we set

    such store. Not any estimate of harmony in tones or flashes of wit, which, with its beauty, serves only as a necessary

    vehicle, but rather the stimulated vital functions of the body, the affection stirring the intestines and the diaphragm,

    and, in a word, the feeling of health (of which we are only sensible upon some such provocation) are what constitute

    the gratification we experience at being able to reach the body through the soul and use the latter as the physician of

    the former.

    As if through an astonishing development of Kepler's cosmological heuristic harmonics, we might even say that in the openingstatement of this appendix, when situated in the context of Kant's philosophy as a whole, we find as if to enliven our physicality

    and refinement with what sunlight, a passage where the Kantian orchestrated linguistic strings of silent speech resound so

    deafeningly in wit as to blast the heavens with such a Pythagorean Harmony of the Sphere's as even now we could scarcely

    analyze in dialectic or represent in the understanding.

    Where according to legend Aristotle's affirmation of laughter in the Poeticswas removed from the historical record by medieval

    censors and according to the record Kant's intrinsic teleology was suppressed by his own efforts, we can rest assured that no such

    measures are required today in respect to this particular incongruity thanks to the re-configurations of our own times

    mistranslation jockey's. Perhaps as homage to such free-wheeling dissolutions, we might then explore some variations in

    connective hijacking, set in the form of a text-art generator or Infinity-Lemma, so as to furnish those so engaged in this enterprise

    with yet ever wider choices for connective selections in future editions.

    Due to Kant invoking movement of the body as the inevitable consequence of humour - the "animated gathering of the spirit" in

    Kant or the "irruption of the body", as per Mary Douglas's apt phrase - the following piece of artistic endeavour should be

    interpreted as a dialogue between an ex-humed version of Kant and his translator Ian Johnson. Here the dialogue becomes played

    out in the form of a song-bird duet where we can postulate that a script installed on a generative program within a computer is

    transversing the heavens through both the elevating power of hope and the sheer force of the dilemmas in a space craft in the

    form of 'Kant (Immanuel) Space Station with an Infinity-Lemma to the Heavens and the Inhabitants of the Stars'.

    The generation program operates in variations on variations according to the members of the divisions in Kant's universal problem

    formula: If A is either B or C, or is; but neither B, nor C, nor D (etc) is; therefore A is not. If we can imagine something like

    this: Where the variations - which function hereafter as 'universal 'PARTY ON' switch operators' - are generated according to the

    newly juggled and expanding clusters of logical connectives situated between the two clauses of the statement. Such renditions,

    whilst random may also be amusingly ordered into self-referential patterns or otherwise as in:

    ..if

    ..if and when we decide we feel like it maybe(we immediately explain that we are doing this only as an amusement)

    ..If besides maybe (we immediately explain that we are doing this only as an amusement)

    ..If although besides maybe nevertheless still sometimes rather (we immediately explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement)

    ..If accordingly such that often (we immediately explain that we are doing this only as an amusement)

    ..if occasionally at least once or twice (we immediately explain that we are doing this only as an amusement),

    ..if once though not first or forever (we immediately explain that we are doing this only as an amusement),

    ..if oh! but for the heavens! (we immediately explain that we are doing this only as an amusement),

    ..if in the event of 'so on' (we immediately explain that we are doing this only as an amusement), and so on..

    Where such connective clusters are coherently recursive and formed into nested sets, these constellations should be given their

    own proper names per my scheme of referencing. Examples might be in qualifications upon qualifications such as the

    'Kant/Johnson 'if or unless, not unless, if unless, not unless, if unless, not unless (etc) we immediately explain that we are doing

    this only as an amusement'' constellation; or as in either detonative or false alarm potentials, as in the 'Kant/Johnson '.. if in 4hrs

    32 m's; 5/4/3/2/1 sec's potentially we immediately explain that we are doing this only as an amusement'' constellation.

    The most excellent and ever adventurous Ian Johnson, at once torch bearer, fool and savant muse - The Celestial Wicker Man! (le

    this be his character note), albeit it one in flaming pleasures! As ever with changing visages, accoutrements and hilarities and

    represented on the vessel by a clown generator, something of the sort we find on Scott's mind, who we acknowledge as the font

    of our inspiration.

    Kant's corpse -aired out, wigged up and be-decked - with formations generated and delivered by the problem program should be

    seated with an out-stretched arm positioned at a laconic or thoughtful angle, but completely motionless as if deep in

    contemplation. It is left to individuals to decide for themselves where Kant's amusement, much more the everly renewed perpetua

    contentment of the Highest Original Being might be situated relative to this at the completion of every exchange in the dialogue.

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    10/17

    I n c a n t a t i o n s

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if and when we decide we feel like it maybewe are immediately willing to explain that we

    are doing this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if besides maybewe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as anamusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if although besides maybe nevertheless still sometimes ratherwe are immediately willing to

    explain that we are doing this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if accordingly such that often we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this

    only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if occasionally at least once or tw icewe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing

    this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f in the event of 'so on'we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f oh! but for the heavens! we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only

    as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f and in spite of 'so on'we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f and when halfway throughwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this

    only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f not firstlywe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if as thoughwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f and when not quite lastlywe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this onl

    as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling wittydisplays having some apparent truth, if and when lastly or in between we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing thi

    only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if in any eventuality we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, not after if yet nevertheless stil l not yet beforewe are immediately willing to explain that w

    are doing this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a dis-grace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if although perhaps sometimeswe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    11/17

    only as an amusement?

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, not 'as' but as if or as if in some other sensewe are immediately willing to explain that we

    are doing this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, because but not in spite of t he fact that we are immediately willing to explain that we are

    doing this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f before if not after yet between forever and thiswe are immediately willing to explain thatwe are doing this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, even if we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f in order not such that we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f once though not first or foreverwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing

    this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling wittydisplays having some apparent truth, provided that we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, rather thanwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, since nowwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, such that we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, though in amazement we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, until when at least the axe fallswe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this

    only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, when or ifwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling wittydisplays having some apparent truth, where accordingly we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, whereas whenever lastly we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only a

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, wherever in an instance we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, in spite of t he fact that we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    12/17

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, whether or not sincewe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, while occasionally we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, even thoughwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as anamusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, notwithstandingthat we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, when belatedlywe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, when accordingly yet not lastly we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this

    only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if perhaps afterwardswe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, when lastly if not neverwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, although sometimeswe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if neverthelesswe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, or but there goes the disgrace! we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this

    only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, but alternatively such that we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only

    as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, since occasionally meanwhile we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this

    only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling wittydisplays having some apparent truth, if however in contrast we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, not least whenever we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, when finallywe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, when similarly after-allwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    13/17

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, untilwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if in a nutshell meanwhile we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only

    as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, therefore we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, consequentlywe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if and when unless but not also we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this

    only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, too if not too oftenwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling wittydisplays having some apparent truth, if similarly in consequencewe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only

    as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if in addition we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, even if although not willingly less than beforewe are immediately willing to explain that we

    are doing this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if indeedwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, let alonewe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, and thereuponwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if however neverthelesswe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f on the other hand we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as anamusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, though in contrast we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, though mom entarilywe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f alternatively w ithout surrenderwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing

    this only as an amusement.

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    14/17

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, whilst yet neverwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, when in fact we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if in fact we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an amusement

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, but that we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an amusement

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, where or whereverwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, besides that we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling wittydisplays having some apparent truth, if anywaywe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f after all thiswe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, as and when for examplewe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only

    as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f for instance thereforewe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, although in other wordswe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as

    an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, but that for ( !) we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, alaswe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, in that we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f f irst of allwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, when for one thing we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, i f in t he first placewe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

  • 8/2/2019 Kant's History and Theory of Heaven

    15/17

    displays having some apparent truth, when to begin withwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, although nextwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, if in sum we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling wittydisplays having some apparent truth, although to conclude thiswe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only

    as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, while immediately at oncewe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only

    as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, therefore as a result we are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only as an

    amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, although pretty much oftenwe are immediately willing to explain that we are doing this only

    as an amusement.

    In my view it is a disgrace to the nature of philosophy when we use it to maintain with a kind of flippancy free-wheeling witty

    displays having some apparent truth, now that we are immediately willing