ordinary property and identifying property wh-words: two kakoj-s in russian igor yanovich moscow...

27
Ordinary property and identifying property wh- words: two kakoj-s in Russian Igor Yanovich Moscow State University FSIM 2, April 15, 2006

Upload: porter-birt

Post on 15-Dec-2015

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Ordinary property and identifying property wh-words: two kakoj-s in

Russian

Igor YanovichMoscow State University

FSIM 2, April 15, 2006

Roadmap

1. Russian -to and -nibud’ and the kakoj-to problem.

1. Traditional theories: inconsistent meanings for kakoj-to.

2. Yanovich 2005: consistent, but clearly wrong meanings for kakoj-to.

2. The solution: two kakoj-s.

3. Deriving the right meanings for kakoj-to.

kakoj-to and kakoj-nibud’

kakoj ‘what/which’

wh-adjective

+

-to / -nibud’

indefinite pronoun series marker

=

kakoj-to / kakoj-nibud’

adjective indefinite pronouns

-to and -nibud’

It is uncontroversial that the import of -to and -nibud’ markers is somehow “related to” reference.

(1) Kto-to prišel.

who-TO came

‘Someone came.’

With -to added, “who” becomes “someone”.

-to and -nibud’

Just for comparison: other series markers

(2) Mnogo kto prišel.

Many who came

‘Many (people) came.’

(3) Nikto prišel.

NEG-who came

‘No one came.’

-to and -nibud’

Traditionally, it is established that both -to and -nibud’ pronouns contain (something like) an existential quantifier.

(4) a. Petja xočet, čtoby kto-to prišel.

‘Petja wants that someone came.’

b. Petja xočet, čtoby kto-nibud’ prišel.

‘Petja wants that someone came.’

-to and -nibud’: the difference

The difference between the two is that a -nibud’ pronoun needs a (c-commanding) licenser, while a -to pronoun does not:

(5) a. Kto-to prišel.

b. *Kto-nibud’ prišel.

-nibud’ licensers

Licensers:

• quantificational DPs (every boy);

• quantificational adverbs (always);

• intensional verbs (want);

• if-clauses…

Important: not negation!

See Padučeva 1985, 2004, Yanovich 2005.

-nibud’ licensers

A -nibud’ pronoun may not scope over its licenser:

(6) Každyj mal'čiki budet rad

Every boyi will be glad

esli i vstretit

if [hei] will-meetkogo-nibud' iz svoix odnoklassnic.who-NIBUD' of the girls in his class

Wide: * > > ifIntermediate: OK > > ifNarrow: OK > if >

-to and -nibud’

This basic distributional difference between the two series was captured by all traditional accounts – though in an unprincipled manner, that is, in the form of a filter on possible meanings for sentences containing -to and -nibud’.

However, leaving that aside, there is a purely internal problem for traditional accounts, concering kakoj-based pronouns.

The problem with kakoj

Traditional accounts assign to (7) meanings as in (8):

(7) a. Každaja devočka uvidela kakogo-to kotenka. Every girl saw which-TO kitten.

b. Každaja devočka uvidela kakogo-nibud’ kotenka. Every girl saw which-NIBUD’ kitten.

(8) a. Wide-scope reading, OK for (7a) only: ∃x: kitten(x) y: girl(y) ∀ [saw(x)(y)]

b. Narrow-scope reading, OK for (7a,b): ∀y: girl(y) x: kitten(x) ∃ [saw(x)(y)]

The problem with kakoj

The problem is that to derive (8), we must accept that the interpretational import of the whole kakoj-based pronoun is equal to the import of the series marker in all other pronouns:

(7) Každaja devočka uvidela kakogo-to kotenka. Every girl saw which-TO kitten.

(8) Wide-scope reading: ∃x: kitten(x) y: girl(y) ∀ [saw(x)(y)]

(9) Každaja devočka uvidela kogo-toEvery girl saw who-TO. ∃x: human(x) y: girl(y) ∀ [saw(x)(y)]

The problem with kakoj

Padučeva 2004: «местоимение типа какой-нибудь выражает квантор существования в контексте подчиняющего оператора» [“A pronoun of the kakoj-nibud’ type expresses an existential quantifier in the context of an embedding operator”.]

But just the affix -nibud’ makes the same thing!

A theory?

Of course, a beautiful theory would assign unified meanings to the series markers, and different meanings for whole pronouns, such as kakoj-nibud’.

E.g., Yanovich 2005 does just that (it may be not very beautiful, though).

A choice-functional theory

Y1: WH-roots denote sets of Hamblin alternatives

Y2: -to and -nibud’ denote (Hamblin) Choice Functions.

Y3: -nibud’ denotes an already skolemized Choice Function (cf. Kratzer 1998). Its licensers are quantificational expressions (be it quantification over individuals, situations, or worlds.

A choice-functional theory

However, there is a problem for a beautiful theories addict: this theory cannot get the meanings in (8)! It predicts the following:

(10) a. OK for (1a):

∃p such that for every girl y, kitten(x) & p(x) & saw(x)(y).

b. OK for (1a,b):

For every girl y, ∃p such that

kitten(x) & p(x) & saw(x)(y)’.

Traditional view vs. “CF” view

(7) Každaja devočka uvidela kakogo-to kotenka.

Every girl saw which-TO kitten.

Wide-scope reading

Traditional accounts: There is a kitten such that every girl saw it.

Yanovich 2005: There is a property P such that there is a kitten and the girl saw it.

Traditional view vs. “CF” view

While Yanovich’s 2005 theory provides a more principled analysis of these pronoun series than the traditional accounts, it is not consistent with the speaker’s intuitions – at least, at first sight.

More puzzles: Most speakers accept that (7) may have only the meaning as in (8). However, there are some, that allow both for (8) and (10), though (8) is definitely more natural even for this group.

The solution

The solution I propose will not allow Yanovich 2005 to directly derive (8), but it will be possible to derive meanings which entail (8).

The idea: let there be two kakoj roots.

(11) [[kakoj1]] = {p et} – the set of all properties

(12) [[kakoj2]] = = {p et | x p(x) & (¬ y p(y) & x ≠ y)} ∃ ∃

– the set of all IDENTIFYING properties

Different kakoj-s in questions

kakoj2 is stronger (=more restrictive) than kakoj1.

A question with kakoj1 is about all properties some object has.

A question with kakoj2 is only about those properties that uniquely identify the individual of which they hold.

Two kakoj-s in indefinite pronouns

(13) Kakuju žizn’ ty xočeš prožit’?

‘What life [do] you want to live?’

=> (more probably,) kakoj1

(14) Kakuju knigu (iz etix dvux) ty xočeš?

‘Which book (of these two) [do] you want?’

=> (more probably,) kakoj2

Different kakoj-s in questions

(15) IDENT =def {pt: x p(x) & (y p(y) & x y)}

(16) [[kakoj2]] = IDENTe

[[to]] = P.f(P), P set of alternatives, f a choice function (from Yanovich 2005)

[[kakoj2-to]]et = f(IDENTe)

[[kakoj2-to mal’čik]] = x.f(IDENTe)(x) & boy(x),

f a choice function =

= ‘true of all individuals who are boys, and of which an identifying property chosen by a choice function f (supplied by the context) holds.’

What do we get?

(7) Každaja devočka uvidela kakogo-to kotenka.

Every girl saw which-TO kitten.

Wide-scope reading for (7):

(17) [ x kitten(x)] y: girl(y) [ x kitten(x)] ∃ ∀ ∃(f(IDENTe))(x) & [saw(x)(y)]

Important: it does not matter where x (=the whole ∃indefinite DP) scopes! Because even if it is under , all ∀properties that f(IDENTe) may choose are true of only one individual.

What do we get?

(17) Our new kakoj2 wide-scope meaning for (7): [ x kitten(x)] y: girl(y) [ x kitten(x)] ∃ ∀ ∃

(f(IDENTe))(x) & [saw(x)(y)]

(8) The traditional wide-scope meaning for (7):∃x: kitten(x) y: girl(y) ∀ [saw(x)(y)]

When (17) is true, the context provides a function that chooses an identifying property p which holds of some kitten x, and every girl saw a kitten x of which p holds. Since p holds of only one individual, all kittens seen by different girls are in fact the same kitten. Thus (8) holds.

(17) => (8)

What do we get?

(18) Our new kakoj2 narrow-scope meaning for (7): [ x kitten(x)]∃[ x kitten(x)]∃ y: girl(y) [ x kitten(x)] ∀ ∃

(f(IDENTe)(y))(x) & [saw(x)(y)]

(8-1) The traditional narrow-scope meaning for (7):∀y: girl(y) x: kitten(x) [saw(x)(y)] ∃

When (18) is true (on the narrow scope of the kitten DP), the context provides a function f that chooses for every girl y an identifying property py = f(y) which holds of some kitten x, and every y saw a kitten x of which f(y) holds. Thus (8-1) follows, but (8) does not, as f(y) may choose different x-s for different y-s.

(18) ===> (8-1) (18) =/=> (8)

Conclusion

Just as I promised, we were not able to directly derive the readings in (8), but we have generated readings that entail (8)-style readings, using kakoj2.

On the other hand, if we would use kakoj1, we would end up with meanings such as those in (10).

Thus if we accept that there are two kakoj-s, we can both maintain a principled account of -to and -nibud’ meanings, and to make predictions that are consistent with speakers’ intuition for kakoj-sentences.

Thank you!

[email protected]