revista david laibson

Upload: rlr92

Post on 06-Apr-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    1/35

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING*

    DAVID LAIBSON

    Hyperbolic discount functions induce dynamically inconsistent preferences,implying a motive for consumers to constrain their own future choices. This paperanalyzes the decisions of a hyperbolic consumer who has access to an imperfectcommitment technology: an illiquid asset whose sale must be initiated one periodbefore the sale proceeds are received. The model predicts that consumption tracksincome, and the model explains why consumers have asset-specific marginal pro-pensities to consume. The model suggests that financial innovation may havecaused the ongoing decline in U. S. savings rates, since financial innovation in-

    creases liquidity, eliminating commitment opportunities. Finally, the model im-plies that financial market innovation may reduce welfare by providing toomuch liquidity.

    I. INTRODUCTION

    Use whatever means possible to remove a set amount of money

    from your bank account each month before you have a chance to

    spend it

    advice in New York Times Your Money column [1993].

    Many people place a premium on the attribute of self-control.Individuals who have this capacity are able to stay on diets, carrythrough exercise regimens, show up to work on time, and livewithin their means. Self-control is so desirable that most of uscomplain that we do not have enough of it. Fortunately, there areways to compensate for this shortfall. One of the most widelyused techniques is commitment. For example, signing up to givea seminar is an easy way to commit oneself to write a paper. Such

    commitments matter since they create constraints (e.g., dead-lines) that generally end up being binding.

    Strotz [1956] was the first economist to formalize a theory ofcommitment and to show that commitment mechanisms could bepotentially important determinants of economic outcomes. He

    *This work has been supported financially by the National Science Founda-tion (SBR-95-10985) and the Alfred P. Sloan Foundation. I am grateful to OlivierBlanchard for posing the questions that motivated this paper. I have also bene-fited from the insights of Roland Benabou, Ricardo Caballero, Robert Hall, Mat-thew Rabin, an anonymous referee, and seminar participants at the Universityof California at Berkeley, Boston University, the University of Chicago, HarvardUniversity, the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Northwestern University,Princeton University, Stanford University, and the University of Pennsylvania.Joshua S. White provided excellent research assistance. All mistakes should beblamed on my t 1 period self.

    1997 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute

    of Technology.The Quarterly Journal of Economics, May 1997.

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    2/35

    showed that when individuals discount functions are nonexpo-nential, they will prefer to constrain their own future choices.Strotz noted that costly commitment decisions are commonlyobserved:

    . . . we are often willing even to pay a price to precommit future

    actions (and to avoid temptation). Evidence of this in economic and

    other social behaviour is not difficult to find. It varies from the gra-

    tuitous promise, from the familiar phrase Give me a good kick if I

    dont do such and such to savings plans such as insurance policies

    and Christmas Clubs which may often be hard to justify in view of

    the low rates of return. (I select the option of having my annualsalary dispersed to me on a twelve- rather than on a nine-month

    basis, although I could use the interest!) Personal financial manage-

    ment firms, such as are sometimes employed by high-income profes-

    sional people (e.g. actors), while having many other and perhaps

    more important functions, represent the logical conclusion of the

    desire to precommit ones future economic activity. Joining the army

    is perhaps the supreme device open to most people, unless it be

    marriage for the sake of settling down. The worker whose income

    is garnished chronically or who is continually harassed by creditors,and who, when one oppressive debt is paid, immediately incurs an-

    other is commonly precommiting. There is nothing irrational about

    such behavior (quite the contrary) and attempts to default on debts

    are simply the later consequences which are to be expected. Inabil-

    ity to default is the force of the commitment.

    Strotzs list is clearly not exhaustive. In general, all illiquidassets provide a form of commitment, though there are some-times additional reasons that consumers might hold such assets

    (e.g., high expected returns and diversification). A pension or re-tirement plan is the clearest example of such an asset. Many ofthese plans benefit from favorable tax treatment, and most ofthem effectively bar consumers from using their savings beforeretirement. For IRAs, Keogh plans, and 401(K) plans, consumerscan access their assets, but they must pay an early withdrawalpenalty. Moreover, borrowing against some of these assets is le-gally treated as an early withdrawal, and hence also subject topenalty. A less transparent instrument for commitment is an in-

    vestment in an illiquid asset that generates a steady stream ofbenefits, but that is hard to sell due to substantial transactionscosts, informational problems, or incomplete markets. Examples

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS444

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    3/35

    include purchasing a home, buying consumer durables, andbuilding up equity in a personal business. Finally, there exists aclass of assets that provide a store of illiquid value, like savingsbonds, and certificates of deposit. All of the illiquid assets dis-cussed above have the same property as the goose that laidgolden eggs. The asset promises to generate substantial benefitsin the long run, but these benefits are difficult, if not impossible,to realize immediately. Trying to do so will result in a substantialcapital loss.

    Instruments with these golden eggs properties make up theoverwhelming majority of assets held by the U. S. household sec-tor. For example, the Federal Reserve System publication Bal-ance Sheets for the U. S. Economy 194594 reports that thehousehold sector held domestic assets of $28.5 trillion at year-end 1994. Over two-thirds of these assets were illiquid, including$5.5 trillion of pension fund and life insurance reserves, $4.5 tril-lion of residential structures, $3.0 trillion of land, $2.5 trillion ofequity in noncorporate business, $2.5 trillion of consumer dur-ables, and at least $1 trillion of other miscellaneous categories.Finally, note that social security wealth and human capital, two

    relatively large components of illiquid wealth, are not included inthe Federal Reserve Balance Sheets.

    Despite the abundance of commitment mechanisms, andStrotzs well-known theoretical work, intrapersonal commitmentphenomena have generally received little attention from econo-mists. This deficit is probably explained by the fact that commit-ment will only be chosen by decision-makers whose preferencesare dynamically inconsistent, and most economists have avoidedstudying such problematic preferences. However, there is a sub-

    stantial body of evidence that preferences are dynamically incon-sistent. Research on animal and human behavior has ledpsychologists to conclude that discount functions are approxi-mately hyperbolic [Ainslie 1992].

    Hyperbolic discount functions are characterized by a rela-tively high discount rate over short horizons and a relatively lowdiscount rate over long horizons. This discount structure sets upa conflict between todays preferences, and the preferences thatwill be held in the future. For example, from todays perspective,

    the discount rate between two far-off periods, t and t 1, is thelong-term low discount rate. However, from the time t perspec-tive, the discount rate between t and t 1 is the short-term high

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 445

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    4/35

    discount rate. This type of preference change is reflected in manycommon experiences. For example, this year I may desire to startan aggressive savings plan next year, but when next year actuallyrolls around, my taste at that time will be to postpone any sacri-fices another year. In the analysis that follows, the decision-maker foresees these conflicts and uses a stylized commitmenttechnology to partially limit the options available in the future.

    This framework predicts that consumption will track income.Second, the model explains why consumers have a different pro-pensity to consume out of wealth than they do out of labor in-come. Third, the model explains why Ricardian equivalenceshould not hold even in an economy characterized by an infinitelylived representative agent. Fourth, the model suggests that fi-nancial innovation may have caused the ongoing decline in U. S.savings rates, since financial innovation increases liquidity andeliminates implicit commitment opportunities. Finally, the modelprovides a formal framework for considering the proposition thatfinancial market innovation reduces welfare by providing toomuch liquidity.

    The body of this essay formalizes these claims. Section II lays

    out the model. Equilibrium outcomes are characterized in SectionIII. Section IV considers the implications of the model for themacroeconomic issues highlighted above. Section V concludeswith a discussion of ongoing work.

    II. THE CONSUMPTION DECISION

    The large number of commitment devices, discussed above,is good news for consumers. They have access to a wide array

    of assets that effectively enable them to achieve many forms ofcommitment. However, from the perspective of an economist, theabundance poses a challenge. It is hard to model the institutionalrichness in a realistic way without generating an extremely bur-densome number of state variables.

    I consider a highly stylized commitment technology that isamenable to an analytic treatment. Specifically, I assume thatconsumers may invest in two instruments: a liquid asset x andan illiquid asset z. Instrument z is illiquid in the sense that a

    sale of this asset has to be initiated one period before the actualproceeds are received. So a current decision to liquidate part orall of an individuals z holding will generate cash flow that can be

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS446

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    5/35

    consumed no earlier than next period.1 By contrast, agents canalways immediately consume their x holdings.

    Consumers in this model may borrow against their holdingsof asset z. Like asset sales, such borrowing takes one period toimplement. If a consumer applies for a loan at time period t, theassociated cash flow will not be available for consumption untiltime period t 1.

    In later sections I embed consumers in a general equilibriummodel in which prices will be endogenous. Now, however, I con-sider the consumer in isolation, and assume that the consumerfaces a deterministic sequence of interest rates and wages. Forsimplicity, I assume that asset z and asset x have the same rateof return.2

    The consumer makes consumption/savings decisions in dis-crete time t {1, 2, . . . , T}. Every time period t is divided intofour subperiods. In the first subperiod, production takes place.The consumers liquid assets xt1 and nonliquid assets zt1bothchosen at time period t 1yield a gross return ofRt 1 rt,and the consumer inelastically supplies one unit of labor. In thesecond subperiod the consumer receives deterministic labor in-

    come yt and gets access to her liquid savings, Rt xt1. In the thirdsubperiod the consumer chooses current consumption,

    c y R xt t t t

    + 1.

    In the fourth subperiod the consumer chooses her new asset allo-cations, xt and zt, subject to the constraints,

    y R z x c z x

    x zt t t t t t t

    t t

    + + +

    0.

    ( ) ,

    , =

    1 1

    The consumer begins life with exogenous endowments x0, z0 0.The consumer may borrow against her illiquid assets by giv-

    ing a creditor a contingent control right over some of those assets.In exchange, the consumer receives liquidity that can be con-sumed. Such a loan is formally represented as a reallocation ofassets from the illiquid account to the liquid account. I assumethat a loan, i.e., asset reallocation, which generates consumableliquidity in period t 1 must be initiated in period t. Specifically,

    1. One could alternatively assume that instantaneous access to asset z ispossible with a sufficiently high transaction cost.

    2. The qualitative results do not hinge on the identical returns assumption.

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 447

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    6/35

    the asset reallocation occurs in subperiod 4 of period t, therebyproviding consumable liquidity in period t 1. Such asset reallo-cations are subsumed in the consumers choice ofxt and zt in sub-period 4.

    In the framework introduced above, an uncollateralized loanhas occurred if an asset reallocation leaves the illiquid accountnegative. Creditors are unwilling to make such loans because aconsumer who received such a loan would not have an incentiveto repay. Hence, I assume that zt 0.

    Finally, the constraint xt 0 rules out forced savings con-tracts. If the consumer could set xt to any negative value, thenshe could perfectly commit her future savings behavior and henceher consumption level (or at least commit to any upper bound ontomorrows consumption level). For example, if she foresaw ahigh level of labor income next period, she could set xt negativeto force tomorrows self to save some of that income (recall thatct1 yt1 Rt1xt). A negative xt value would be interpreted as acontract with an outside agent requiring the consumer to transferfunds to the outside agent, which the outside agent would thendeposit in an illiquid account of the consumer.3 The constraint xt 0 effectively rules out such contracts. Two arguments supportthis implicit assumption against forced savings contracts.

    First, such contracts are susceptible to renegotiation by to-morrows self, and in any finite-horizon environment, the contractwould unwind. (In the second to last period renegotiation wouldoccur, implying renegotiation in the third to last period, etc.) Sec-ond, such contracts are generally unenforceable in the UnitedStates.4 To make such a contract work, tomorrows self must beforced to pay the specified funds to the outside agent or be penal-

    ized for not doing so (note that the transfer is not in the interestof tomorrows self). However, U. S. courts will generally not en-force contracts with a penalty of this kind.5

    3. Mortgage payments are an example of a contract that xt 0 rules out.However, even though mortgage payments may be interpreted as forced savingscontracts, they do not have the necessary flexibility to achieve the full commit-ment solution. Mortgage contracts generally do not make mortgage payments con-tingent on the level of labor income flows.

    4. I am indebted to Robert Hall for pointing out this fact to me.

    5. U. S. contract law is based around the fundamental principle that thelaws goal on breach of contract is not to deter breach by compelling the promisorto perform, but rather to redress breach by compensating the promisee [Farns-worth 1990, p. 935]. Hence, courts allow contracts to specify liquidated damageswhich reflect losses likely to be experienced by the promisee, but courts do notallow penalties which do not reflect such losses.

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS448

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    7/35

    At time t, the consumer has a time-additive utility functionU

    t

    with an instantaneous utility function characterized by con-stant relative risk aversion . Consumers are assumed to have adiscount function of the type proposed by Phelps and Pollak[1968] in a model of intergenerational altruism, and which isused here to model intrapersonal dynamic conflict:6

    (1) U E u c u ct t t t

    T t

    +=

    +

    =

    ( ) ( ) . 1

    I adopt equation (1) to capture the qualitative properties ofa generalized hyperbolic discount function: events periods awayare discounted with factor (1 )/, with , 0.7 This classof discount functions was first proposed by Chung and Herrnstein[1961] to characterize the results of animal behavior experi-ments.8 Their conclusions were later shown to apply to humansubjects as well (see Ainslie [1992] for a survey).

    Hyperbolic discount functions imply discount rates that de-cline as the discounted event is moved further away in time[Loewenstein and Prelec 1992]. Events in the near future are dis-

    counted at a higher implicit discount rate than events in the dis-tant future.

    Given a discount function (), the instantaneous discountrate at time is defined as

    Applying the principle of just compensation for the loss or injury actuallysustained to liquidated damage provisions, courts have . . . refused enforce-ment where the clause agreed upon is held to be in terrorema sum fixed asa deterrent to breach or as security for full performance by the promisor, notas a realistic assessment of the provable damage. Thus, attempts to secure

    performance through in terrorem clauses are currently declared unenforce-able even where the evidence shows a voluntary, fairly bargained exchange[Goetz and Scott 1977, p. 555].

    In our case, the promiseethe outside agentexperiences no loss if the con-sumer fails to make the payment. Hence, penalties or liquidated damages speci-fied in such contracts are not enforceable, so the contract is incapable ofcompelling tomorrows self to make the payment. For a more extensive discussionof these issues, see Farnsworth [1990, pp. 93546], Goetz and Scott [1977], andRea [1984].

    6. Zeckhauser and Fels [1968] provide an altruism-based microfoundationfor the Phelps and Pollak preferences. Akerlof [1991] analyzes a special case ofthe Phelps and Pollak preferences ( 1). Akerlof assumes consumer myopia,while my analysis assumes that consumers foresee their future preference

    reversals.7. See Loewenstein and Prelec [1992] for an axiomatic derivation of this dis-count function.

    8. Chung and Herrnstein claimed that the appropriate discount function isan exact hyperbola: events periods away are discounted with factor 1/. Thiscorresponds to the limiting case .

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 449

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    8/35

    f f( ) ( ). /

    Hence, an exponential discount function,

    is characterized by aconstant discount rate, log(1/), while the generalized hyperbolicdiscount function is characterized by an instantaneous discountrate that falls as rises:

    / +( ).1

    Psychologists and economistsnotably Ainslie [1975, 1986,1992], Prelec [1989], and Loewenstein and Prelec [1992]haveargued that such declining discount rates play an important role

    in generating problems of self-regulation.When 0 1, the discount structure in equation (1) mim-ics the qualitative property of the hyperbolic discount function,while maintaining most of the analytical tractibility of the expo-nential discount function. I call the discount structure in equa-tion (1) quasi-hyperbolic. Note that the quasi-hyperbolicdiscount function is a discrete time function with values {1, ,2, 3, . . . }. Figure I graphs the exponential discount function(assuming that 0.97), the generalized hyperbolic discount

    function (assuming that 10

    5

    , and 5 103

    ), and the quasi-hyperbolic discount function (with 0.6 and 0.99). The

    FIGURE IDiscount Functions

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS450

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    9/35

    points of the discrete-time quasi-hyperbolic function have beenconnected to generate the curve in Figure I.

    The preferences given by equation (1) are dynamically incon-sistent, in the sense that preferences at date t are inconsistentwith preferences at date t 1. To see this, note that the marginalrate of substitution between periods t 1 and t 2 from theperspective of the decision-maker at time t is given byu(ct1)/(u(ct2)), which is not equal to the marginal rate of sub-stitution between those same periods from the perspective of thedecision-maker at t 1: u(ct1)/(u(ct2)).

    To analyze equilibrium behavior when preferences are dy-namically inconsistent, it is standard practice to formally modela consumer as a sequence of temporal selves making choices in adynamic game (e.g., Pollak [1968], Peleg and Yaari [1973], andGoldman [1980]). Hence, a T-period consumption problem trans-lates into a T-period game, with Tplayers, or selves, indexed bytheir respective periods of control over the consumption decision.(Note that selft is in control during all of the subperiods at timet.) I look for subgame perfect equilibrium (SPE) strategies ofthis game.

    It is helpful to introduce some standard notation that will beused in the analysis which follows. Let ht represent a (feasible)history at time t, so ht represents all the moves that have beenmade from time 0 to time t 1: {x0, z0 , (c, x, z) t11}. LetSt represent the set of feasible strategies for selft. Let S

    Tt1 St

    represent the joint strategy space of all selves. Ifs S, let s|htrepresent the path of consumption and asset allocation levelsfrom t to T which would arise if history ht were realized, andselves t to Tplayed the strategies given by s. Finally, let Ut(s|ht)

    represent the continuation payoff to selft if selft expects the con-sumption and asset allocation levels from t to T to be given by

    s|ht.

    III. EQUILIBRIUM STRATEGIES

    This section characterizes the equilibrium strategies of thegame described above. Recall that the agent faces a deterministic(time-varying) sequence of interest rates and a deterministic

    (time-varying) labor income sequence. Unfortunately, for generalinterest rate and labor income sequences, it is not possible to usemarginal conditions to characterize the equilibrium strategies.This nonmarginality property is related to the fact that selveswho make choices at least two periods from the end of the game

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 451

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    10/35

    face a nonconvex reduced-form choice set, where the reduced-form choice set is defined as the consumption vectors which areattainable, assuming that all future selves play equilibriumstrategies. The nonconvexity in the reduced-form choice set of selfT 2 generates discontinuous equilibrium strategies for selfT 2, which in turn generate discontinuities in the equilibriumpayoff map of selfT 3. This implies that marginal conditionscannot be used to characterize the equilibrium choices of selvesat least three periods from the end of the game.9

    I have found a restriction on the labor income process thateliminates these problems:

    (A1) u y R u y tt t i

    it

    ( ) ( ) , .1 += +

    1

    This restriction constrains the sequence {yt}tTt1 to lie in a band

    whose thickness is parameterized by the value of; the closer is to zero, the wider the band. Calibration of the model revealsthat A1 allows for substantial flexibility in the deterministic in-come process. Ainslie [1992] reviews evidence that the one-yeardiscount rate is at least 1/3. This suggests that should be cali-

    brated in the interval (0, 2/3) (assuming that is close to unity).To see what this implies, consider the following example. Assumethat Rt R for all t, R 1, and u() ln(). Then A1 is satisfiedif, for all t, yt [y, (1/)y]. If 2/3, this interval becomes [y, (3/2)y], and as falls the interval grows even larger.

    Before characterizing the equilibria of the game, it is helpfulto introduce the following definitions. First, we will say that a

    joint strategy, s, is resource exhausting ifs|hT1 is characterizedby zT xt 0, for all feasible hT1. Second, we will say that a

    sequence of feasible consumption/savings actions, {ct, xt, zt, . . . ,cT, xT, zT} satisfies P1P4 ift t,

    P max

    P max +

    P

    1

    2

    3

    1

    11

    u c R u c

    u c R u c c y R x

    t T t t iit

    t T t t iit t t t t

    ( ) ( )

    ( ) ( )

    }

    }

    > =

    +=+

    +=+

    {1,...,

    {1,...,

    uu c R u c x

    u c R u c

    t T t t iit t

    t T t t iit

    ( ) ( )

    ( ) ( )

    }

    }

    + +=+ +

    + +=+ +

    =

    >

    1 1 11

    1 1 11

    0

    4

    < max

    P max

    {1,...,

    {1,...,zzt .= 0

    9. For an exposition of these problems see Laibson [1993]. Related issues arealso discussed in Peleg and Yaari [1973] and Goldman [1980].

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS452

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    11/35

    Finally, we will say that a joint strategy s S satisfies P1P4 iffor any feasible history h

    t , s|h

    t satisfies P1P4.

    It is now possible to state the main theorem of the paper.This theorem establishes that the consumption game has aunique equilibrium, and the theorem characterizes thisequilibrium.

    THEOREM 1. Fix any T-period consumption game with exogenousvariables satisfying A1. There exists a unique resource-exhausting joint strategy, s* S, that satisfies P1P4, andthis strategy is the unique subgame perfect equilibrium

    strategy of this game.(All proofs appear in the Appendix.) Theorem 1 implies that theequilibrium consumption path is resource exhausting and satis-fies P1P4. It is straightforward to see why the equilibrium pathis resource exhausting: the final selfselfTconsumes all liq-uid resources in period T, and selfT 1 makes certain that allwealth is liquid in period T(i.e., zT1 0). Hence, no wealth goesunconsumed in equilibrium.

    Properties P1P4 are also intuitive. It is important to inter-

    pret them in light of the strategic self-control behavior that arisesin the intrapersonal consumption game. In this game, earlyselves prevent late selves from splurging. Self t 1 uses theilliquid asset zt1 to limit the liquidity available for consumptionin period t. Note that selft cannot consume the illiquid asset dur-ing its period of control, ct yt Rt xt1. On the equilibrium path,each self is endogenously liquidity constrained by the allocationchoices of earlier selves. Property P1 is simply a standard Eulerequation relation for an environment in which liquidity con-

    straints exist. The inequality arises because marginal utility canbe too high relative to future marginal utilities, but it cannot betoo low since consumers always have the option to save. PropertyP2 reflects another standard Euler equation intuition: when mar-ginal utility is strictly too high, the liquidity constraint must bebinding. Properties P3 and P4 reflect the strategic decisions thatselft makes when it chooses asset allocation levels (xt and zt). P3implies that selft will limit selft 1s liquidity as much as pos-sible (xt 0) if consumption at time t 1 is expected to be high

    relative to what selft would prefer it to be. P4 implies that selftwill not limit selft 1s liquidity at all (zt 0) if consumption attime t 1 is expected to be low relative to what selft would preferit to be. Note that the equations associated with P3 and P4 donot contain the term. This omission arises because, from the

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 453

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    12/35

    perspective of selft, utility trade-offs between period t 1 andany period after t 1 are independent of the value of.

    IV. ANALYSIS

    In the following subsections I discuss several implications ofthe golden eggs model. Some of the applications consider theinfinite-horizon game that is analogous to the finite-horizon gamediscussed above. When doing so, I will focus consideration on theequilibrium that is the limit (as the horizon goes to infinity) ofthe unique finite-horizon equilibrium.10

    A. Comovement of Consumption and Income

    There is a growing body of evidence that household consump-tion flows track corresponding household income flows tooclosely, generating violations of the life-cycle/permanent-incomeconsumption model. In particular, household consumption is sen-sitive to expected movements in household income: e.g., Hall andMishkin [1982], Zeldes [1989], Carroll and Summers [1991], Fla-vin [1991], Carroll [1992], Shea [1995], and Souleles [1995].11

    Many of these authors find that consumption tracks expected in-come changes even when consumers have large stocks of accumu-lated assets.

    Several models have been proposed to explain the consump-

    10. For the infinite horizon game, a joint strategy, s, is resource exhausting ifthe continuation paths after all histories imply that the intertemporal budgetconstraint is exactly satisfied:

    z x R y R ci

    tt i

    tt

    i

    t

    i

    t

    0 0

    1

    1

    1

    11 1

    + += =

    = =

    = .

    For the infinite-horizon game, I will focus on the equilibrium that satisfies thefollowing infinite-horizon analogs of P1P4:

    P sup

    P sup +

    P < sup

    1

    1

    1

    1

    2

    3

    1

    11

    1

    u c R u c

    u c R u c c y R x

    u c R

    t t ii

    t

    t t ii

    t t t t t

    t t

    ( ) ( )

    ( ) ( )

    ( )

    > =

    += +

    += +

    + +

    ( )( )

    iii

    t t

    t t ii

    t t

    u c x

    u c R u c z

    =+ +

    + +=

    + +

    =

    > =

    ( )

    ( )1

    1

    11

    1

    0

    4 0

    ( )

    ( ) ( )

    P sup .1

    11. Although Runkle [1989] is unable to reject the permanent income hy-pothesis, there are reasons to believe his test lacks power (see Shea [1995]).

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS454

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    13/35

    tion-income comovement. Carroll [1992] proposes a buffer-stocktheory of savings in which impatient consumers with a precau-tionary savings motive hold little wealth and choose optimal con-sumption policies in which consumption and income movetogether over the life-cycle. Gourinchas and Parker [1995] simu-late an extended version of this model. Attanasio and Weber[1993] argue that demographic dynamics explain much of theconsumption-income comovement.

    The golden eggs model provides a new explanation for theobserved comovement in consumption and income. In the model,selft 1 chooses xt1 to constrain the consumption of selft. Inthis way early selves manipulate the cash flow process by keep-ing most assets in the illiquid instrument. Hence, at any givenmoment the consumer is effectively liquidity constrained, thoughthe constraint is self-imposed. In equilibrium consumption is ex-actly equal to the current level of cash flow: ct yt Rt xt1 (seeLemma 3 in the Appendix for a formal proof). However, this doesnot imply by itself that consumption will track labor income. Notethat xt1 is endogenous, and in equilibrium xt1 covaries nega-tively with labor income. Selft 1 varies xt1 to try to offset the

    predictable fluctuations in yt. When yt is large, self t 1 willmake xt1 small in an effort to prevent selft from overconsuming.

    However, there are limits to the ways in which early selvescan constrain the choices of later selves. Selft 1 can only denyself t access to assets that have been accumulated in the past.Selft 1 cannot deny selft access to yt, labor income at time t.So when yt is particularly high (i.e., cash flow at time t is particu-larly high), consumption at time t will also be high. This impliesthat on the equilibrium path, predictable movements in income

    will tend to be reflected in movements in consumption.An example may help to make this more concrete. Let the

    horizon be infinite. Assume that labor income follows a trendinghigh-low process: yt ye

    gt when t is odd, yt yegt when t is even.

    Assume that the interest rate is constant and exp(g) R. (Thislast relationship is motivated by the steady state results below.)

    Assume that {yt}t1 satisfies A1. Finally, assume that x0 0, z0 0, and z0 not be too large relative to the labor income variability.Specifically, z0 must satisfy the relationship,

    u y Ru y e z e R e g g g ( ) (_ ( ) ).+ / 0 2 21

    Then the equilibrium consumption path is

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 455

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    14/35

    c

    y

    y z e R e

    t

    tt

    t

    t g gt

    + /

    if odd

    if even.=

    0

    2 21( ) .

    Figure II graphs the labor income path and equilibrium con-sumption path, using parameter values, 0.6, R 1.04, g 0.02, y z0/3 1, and y 0.8.

    12 Two properties stand out. First,the illiquid asset is exclusively used to augment consumption inthe even periods, i.e., in the periods with relatively low labor in-come. However, this increase is not sufficient to smooth consump-tion. A regression of ln c

    ton ln y

    tyields a coefficient of .40.

    Since the income process is completely deterministic, this impliesthat predictable changes in income are associated with changesin consumption. Hence, consumption tracks income despite thefact that the consumer in this example controls a substantialasset stock (K/Y 3).

    B. Aggregate Saving

    In most intertemporal rational choice models, high discountrates are a necessary condition for consumption-income comove-ment. Such relatively high discount rates, however, tend to implyrelatively low levels of capital accumulation in general equilib-rium (see Aiyagari [1992]). The golden eggs model generates con-sumption-income comovement even when actors are wealthy.This is because in equilibrium decisions to dissave out of the illiq-uid asset stock do not depend on . Selft is not able to consumethe illiquid asset immediately, so self t does not consider trade-offs between consumption today and consumption tomorrowwhen dissaving from the illiquid instrument. Instead self t con-siders trade-offs between consumption at t 1 and consumptionat periods after t 1. The value of is superfluous for such adecisionfrom self ts perspectiveand hence the steady statecapital stock is independent of.

    The following general equilibrium analysis formalizes thisintuition. Assume that there exists a continuum of individualagents indexed by the unit interval. Individual decision and statevariables are represented with an i index (e.g., ct(i)). Consider astandard Cobb-Douglas production function with aggregate capi-tal Kt , aggregate labor Lt , and exogenous productivity At:

    12. The remaining variables, and , may take on any values that satisfythe steady state condition: exp(g) R.

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS456

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    15/35

    FIGURE IIConsumption and Labor Income

    Y A K Lt t t t

    = 1 .

    Aggregate capital is composed of the liquid and illiquid capitalholdings of individual agents in the economy:

    K x i z i dit t t

    +0

    1

    [ ( ) ( )] .1 1Recall that labor is assumed to be supplied inelastically, so L(i) 1, and

    L L i dit t 1.0

    1

    = ( )In competitive equilibrium labor receives its marginal product,so labor income of agent i at time period t is given by yt(i) (1 )Yt. Competitive equilibrium also implies that capital re-ceive its marginal product, so Rt 1 Yt/Kt d, where d isthe rate of depreciation. Liquid and illiquid gross asset returnsof agent i at time period t are, respectively, Rt xt1 and Rt zt1.Finally, At is assumed to grow exogenously at rate gA, so in steady

    state, capital and output must grow at rate gA/(1)

    g.PROPOSITION 1. In the economy described above there exists a

    unique steady state that satisfies A1. In that steady state

    (2) exp( ) g R .=

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 457

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    16/35

    The important property of the steady state identified inProposition 1 is that the parameter does not appear in the equa-tion relating the discount rate and the growth rate. So can becalibrated to generate excess sensitivity (i.e., consumption-income comovement), while can be calibrated to match the his-torical capital-output ratio of three. If is in the interior of theunit interval, then the equilibrium path will exhibit consump-tion-income tracking (e.g., see the example in previous subsec-tion). Meanwhile, can be chosen to satisfy the equation,

    (3) g r Y K d/ , = ( ) ( ) ( )1 1

    which is a log-linearized version of equation (2). Setting 0.98rationalizes K/Y 3, assuming that the other parameters in theequation take standard values: 1, g 0.02, 0.36, d 0.08.

    C. Asset-Specific MPCs

    Thaler [1990] argues that consumers have different marginalpropensities to consume for different categories of assets. For ex-

    ample, he presents evidence that an unexpected increase in thevalue of an equity portfolio will have a very small effect on con-sumption, while an unexpected job-related bonus will be immedi-ately consumed. Thaler divides consumer wealth into threecategories: current income, net assets, and future income. Hecites a wide body of evidence which suggests that the MPC from[current income] is close to unity, the MPC from [future income]is close to zero, and the MPC from [net assets] is somewhere inbetween. Thaler explains this behavior by postulating that con-

    sumers use a system of nonfungible mental accounts to guiderule-of-thumb decision-making. By contrast, the golden eggsmodel predicts that even fully rational consumers will exhibitasset-specific MPCs.13

    In the golden eggs model the current self is always endoge-nously liquidity constrained on the equilibrium path. So the MPCout of current cash flow is one. Proposition 2 formalizes thisclaim.

    13. Laibson [1994b] proposes another hyperbolic discounting model that gen-erates some mental accounting behavior. In Laibson [1994b] rational consumersset up a system of self-rewards and self-punishments to motivate later selves toexert high effort. Laibson [1994b] discusses effort-related mental accounts, whilethe current paper discusses liquidity-related mental accounts.

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS458

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    17/35

    PROPOSITION 2. Fix a consumption game in which inequalityA1 is strictly satisfied. Let c

    t

    ct

    (Rt

    xt1

    , Rt

    zt1

    ) represent theequilibrium (Markov) consumption strategy of selft. Then,

    =

    c

    R xtt

    t t( )11 2,

    when the partial derivative is evaluated on the equilibriumpath.

    In this subsection I contrast this MPC with its analog forilliquid assets. At first glance it is not clear how to best make this

    comparison. I will consider two approaches.

    PROPOSITION 3. Fix a consumption game in which inequality A1is strictly satisfied. Let ct(Rtxt1, Rtzt1) represent the equilib-rium (Markov) consumption strategy of selft. Then,

    =

    c

    R ztt

    t t( )10 2,

    when the partial derivative is evaluated on the equilibrium

    path.

    This result is not surprising, since on the equilibrium paththe individual always faces a self-imposed liquidity constraint.Small perturbations to the illiquid asset stock are not sufficientto stop the current selfs liquidity constraint from being binding.

    A more interesting question to ask is how a perturbation to zt1affects the choice ofxt. Recall that liquid assets set aside at timet will be completely consumed at time t 1. Unfortunately, the

    value ofxt/(Rtzt1) can take on any value between zero and one.For example, the partial derivative is equal to zero if the equilib-rium value ofxt is equal to zero. The partial derivative is equal tounity ift is the penultimate period of the game. It would be help-ful to develop an MPC measure that provides a representativevalue ofxt/(Rtzt1). The following proposition introduces such ameasure, by considering the geometric average of MPCs over adeterministic business cycle of duration .

    PROPOSITION 4. Fix any horizon consumption game with Rt R t. Fix a particular value of 1. Assume that {yt}t1satisfies A1, and yt exp(g)yt, t 0. Assume thatexp(g) R. Let xt xt(R xt1, R zt1) represent the equi-librium (Markov) consumption strategy of selft. Let

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 459

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    18/35

    1 110

    1

    1/

    +

    + =

    MPC

    x

    Rztz t i

    t ii ( )

    evaluated on the equilibrium path. Then,

    MPC MPC R ttz z 2.1/= 1 1( )

    Note that Proposition 4 assumes that the growth rate of la-bor income is related to the return on capital by the steady stateequation in Proposition 2: exp(g) R. Note also that the re-sulting measure of the marginal propensity to consume, 1

    (R1

    )1/

    , is equivalent to the marginal propensity to consume inthe standard Ramsey model with no liquidity constraints and ex-ponential discount function t. For all reasonable parameter val-ues MPCz is close to zero. Recall that the first proposed measureof the MPC out of illiquid assets (i.e., the MPC measure intro-duced in Proposition 3) was exactly equal to zero. Finally, con-trast these proposed measures of the MPC out of illiquid assets(which take values close to or exactly equal to zero) with the unitymarginal propensity to consume out of liquid assets.

    D. Ricardian Equivalence

    In the economy analyzed in this paper, the sequence of exoge-nous cash flows matters, in a way that is independent of the pres-ent value of those cash flows. This is immediately apparent fromFigure II. Because taxation schemes affect these exogenous cashflows, Ricardian equivalence will be violated. Moreover, themodel generates such violations even when the consumer has alarge asset stock at all times. Hence, Ricardian equivalence is

    violated for all agents, whether or not they hold substantialwealth.

    E. Declining Savings Rates in the 1980s

    The golden eggs model may help to explain the decline inU. S. savings rates during the 1980s. I pursue two approaches inthis subsection. The first explanation is driven by the fact thatduring the 1980s a relatively large proportion of national incomewas realized as cash flow to consumers. However, I am unsatis-

    fied with this first story for reasons that I describe below. Hence,I focus most of my attention on a second explanation that isdriven by developments in the consumer credit market.

    Hatsopoulos, Krugman, and Poterba [1989] document the ob-

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS460

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    19/35

    servation that cash flow to consumers (as a percentage of NNP)was high during the 1980s relative to the 1970s. They report thatfrom 19701979 cash flow averaged 77.9 percent of NNP, whilethe corresponding number for the 19801987 period was 80.8 per-cent. They trace this increase to several sources, notably higherinterest income (4.5 percentage points), higher transfers (2.2 per-centage points), and higher after-tax cash from takeovers (0.6percentage points).14

    Using aggregate data, Hatsopoulos, Krugman, and Poterba[1989] estimate a high marginal propensity to consume out ofcurrent cash flow. Coupling this result with the higher cash flowlevels, they are able to explain most of the savings decline in the1980s. However, they do not explain why consumers should havesuch a high propensity to consume out of cash flow. The goldeneggs model complements their analysis by providing a model thatexplains the high MPC. However, note that the golden eggs modelcan only explain the high MPC out of cash flow; the model cannotexplain why the cash flow was high in the first place. Hence, ap-plication of the golden eggs model may only relabel the puzzle,changing it from a consumption puzzle to a cash flow puzzle.

    The golden eggs model suggests a second explanation for thelow level of savings during the past decade. The 1980s was a pe-riod of rapid expansion in the U. S. consumer credit market.Increasing access to instantaneous credit has reduced the effec-tiveness of commitment devices like illiquid assets. The goldeneggs model predicts that the elimination of commitment deviceswould lower the level of capital accumulation. I will show that ifthe credit market were to become sufficiently sophisticated thatconsumers could instantaneously borrow against their illiquid

    assets, then the steady state capital-output ratio would fall. Icalibrate this fall at the end of the subsection.

    The rapid expansion of the U. S. consumer credit market pro-vides the starting point for the argument summarized in the pre-vious paragraph. One example of the expansion in instantaneouscredit has been the growth in credit cards.15 In 1970 only 16 per-cent of all U. S. families had a third party credit card (e.g., prede-

    14. Offsetting falls in cash flow occurred in labor income (0.3 percentage

    points), noninterest capital income in disposable income (2.0 percentage points),and taxes (2.1 percentage points).15. Another important development in the U. S. credit market has been the

    expanded use of home equity lines of credit. Before the mid-1980s home equitylines of credit were almost unheard of. By 19931994 8.3 percent of homeownershad a home equity line of credit. See Canner and Luckett [1994], p. 572.

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 461

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    20/35

    cessors of current cards like Visa and MasterCard). By 1989 54percent had one.16 During this same period credit card acceptanceby retailers also increased dramatically. Large retailers did notaccept credit cards during the 1970s. In 1979 J. C. Penney brokeranks with its competitors and became the first major retailer toaccept third party credit cards. By the end of the 1980s almostall large retailers accepted third party cards. The growth of ATMs(automatic teller machines) augmented the impact of the creditcard expansion by enabling credit cardholders to readily receivecash advances. Regional and national ATM networks first beganto form in the late 1970s and early 1980s.17 Altogether thesedevelopments led to an explosion in revolving credit, which isprincipally composed of credit card debt. From 1970 to 1995, re-volving credit grew from 3.7 percent to 36.3 percent of total con-sumer credit.18 No single year stands out as the date at whichmost consumers experienced a sharp increase in their personalaccess to instantaneous credit. However, it is safe to say that bythe mid-1980s most families had a third party credit card, andthis card could be used in most large retail stores, or could beused in ATMs to receive cash advances to make purchases in the

    stores that still did not accept credit cards. Together these obser-vations suggest that the mid-1980s represents the first time thata representative U. S. family had instantaneous access to con-sumer credit, or could rapidly apply for such access.

    Introducing instantaneous credit into the golden eggs modeldramatically changes the equilibrium analysis. (Recall that theoriginal model had credit which could be accessed with a one-period delay.) In the original model consumption was boundedabove by cash on hand:

    c y R xt t t t

    + 1.

    With instantaneous access to credit, consumption is now con-strained to lie below the sum of cash on hand and the value of allcredit lines that can be instantaneously set up or are already set

    16. See Canner and Luckett [1992], p. 656.17. See Mandell [1990] for a short history of the credit card industry.18. Consumer credit includes automobile loans, revolving credit, other in-

    stallment credit, and noninstallment credit. Other installment credit includesmobile home loans and all other installment loans not included in automobile orrevolving credit, such as loans for education, boats, trailers, or vacations. Theseloans may be secured or unsecured. Noninstallment credit is credit scheduled tobe repaid in a lump sum, including single-payment loans, charge accounts, andservice credit [Economic Report of the President 1996, Table B-73].

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS462

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    21/35

    up. I assume that the value of these existing and potential creditlines is approximately equal to the value of the illiquid assetsheld by the consumer. Hence, consumption is now constrained by

    c y R x R zt t t t t t

    + + . 1 1

    In all other ways the model remains the same.

    PROPOSITION 5. Consider the general equilibrium economy ana-lyzed above, but now assume that consumers can instantane-ously borrow against their illiquid asset. This economy isequivalent to one in which there is no illiquid asset (i.e., x is

    the only asset). In such an economy there exists a uniquesteady state, and in that steady state,

    (4) exp( ) ( ) exp( ). g R g+= 1

    COROLLARY. In the steady state characterized in Proposition 5the capital-output ratio is less than the steady state capital-output ratio in the economy with the commitmenttechnology.

    Table I reports the magnitude of the reduction in steady statecapital that occurs when financial innovation moves an economyfrom a golden eggs financial technology to a new financial tech-nology in which it is possible to instantaneously borrow againstthe illiquid asset (i.e., when financial innovation eliminates theilliquidity that makes partial commitment possible). The entriesof Table I are derived in five steps. First, I assume that the U. S.economy has historically been a golden eggs economy, with 0.36, d 0.08, g 0.02, and K/Y 3. Second, I calibrate prefer-

    ence parameters and based on equation (2) (the steady stateequation in golden eggs economies) and the competitive equilib-rium condition, r Y/K d (0.36)1

    3 0.08. (Recall that equa-

    tion (2) is independent of.) These equations jointly imply that

    (5) exp( ( . )) ( . ). 0 02 1 04=

    Third, I take the set of preference parameter values derived instep 2 (i.e., defined in equation (5)) and plug that set into equa-tion (4), the new steady state equation (i.e., the steady state equa-

    tion associated with the economy in which consumers caninstantaneously borrow against their illiquid assets). This yieldsthe following constrained steady state equation that holds inthe new economy:

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 463

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    22/35

    TABLE ISTEADY STATE INTEREST RATES AND CAPITAL-OUTPUT RATIOS IN ECONOMIES WITH

    AND WITHOUT PARTIAL COMMITMENT

    With commitment Without commitment(i.e., no instantaneous (i.e., instantaneous

    credit) credit)

    rK

    Yr

    K

    Y

    0.2 0.040 3.00 0.119 1.81 0.4 0.040 3.00 0.070 2.40 0.6 0.040 3.00 0.053 2.70 0.8 0.040 3.00 0.045 2.88 1.0 0.040 3.00 0.040 3.00

    (6) 1 04 02. )exp(. ).+ (1= R

    Note that this constrained steady state relationship is indepen-dent of and , and depends exclusively on and R. Fourth, Ivary , the only free preference parameter in the constrained newsteady state equation, and calculate the corresponding capital-

    output ratios (again using the competitive equilibrium relation-ship r (Y/K) d). Fifth, I compare these new capital-outputratios with the historical capital-output ratio.

    Note that when commitment is available, the steady stateinterest rate and capital-output ratio are independent of thevalue of (see Proposition 1). Now consider an example of a tran-sition from a commitment economy to an economy without com-mitment. For a value of 0.6, elimination of the commitmenttechnology raises the steady state real interest rate 1.3 percent-

    age points. This corresponds to a reduction in the capital-outputratio of 0.3.

    These results should be compared with actual U. S. experi-ence during the 1980s and 1990s. The model predicts that capitalaccumulation should have fallen at the same time that consum-ers gained access to instantaneous credit (approximately the mid-1980s). All measures of capital accumulation show a markeddownturn that starts in the 1980s and continues into the 1990s.For example, U. S. personal savings as a percent of disposable

    personal income fell from an average of 7.3 percent from 19461984, to an average of 5.3 percent from 19851994. The 19851994 period had the lowest average saving rate of any ten-year

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS464

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    23/35

    span in the postwar period.19 The ratio of national net worth togross national product (i.e., the U. S. capital-output ratio) fellfrom an average of 3.2 from 19461984, to 2.8 in 1994. The 1994value is the low point for the series in the postwar period.20

    F. Welfare Analysis of Financial Innovation

    The introduction of instantaneous credit increases consum-ers choice sets. Standard economic models imply that this devel-opment might lower levels of capital accumulation, but wouldraise consumer welfare. Yet, in the United States, policy-makersand pundits are concerned that instantaneous credit is somehowbad for consumers.

    The golden eggs framework provides a formal model of thecosts of financial innovation. By enabling the consumer to instan-taneously borrow against illiquid assets, financial innovationeliminates the possibility for partial commitment. This has twoeffects on the welfare of the current self. First, the current self nolonger faces a self-imposed liquidity constraint and can thereforeconsume more in its period of control. Second, future selves arealso no longer liquidity constrained and may also consume at a

    higher rate out of the wealth stock that they inherit. The firsteffect makes the current self better off. The second effect makesthe current self worse off (since the current self would like to con-strain the consumption of future selves). Under most parameter-izations the impact of the second effect dominates, and thewelfare of the current self is reduced.

    Formally, I measure the welfare loss by calculating the mini-mum one-time paymentpaid to a representative consumerwhich would induce the representative consumer to switch from

    an infinite horizon golden eggs economy to an infinite horizon in-stantaneous credit economy. (Using the notation of Section II, thehypothetical payment that induces indifference is made duringsubperiod 2 of time t, and the indifference is from the perspectiveof self t.) I assume that the representative consumer starts in

    19. National Income and Product Accounts, Table 2.1, Bureau of EconomicAnalysis, U. S. Department of Commerce.

    20. National net worth is calculated from Tables B.11 and B.109 in BalanceSheets for the U. S. Economy 194594, Board of Governors of the Federal ReserveSystem. National net worth represents the sum of lines 1 and 30 from Table B.11added to the difference between lines 43 and 42 from Table B.109. Gross nationalproduct is calculated by the Bureau of Economic Analysis, U. S. Department ofCommerce.

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 465

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    24/35

    the steady state of the golden eggs economy; this steady state ischaracterized in Proposition 1. The representative agent remainsin that steady state if she remains in the golden eggs economy.By contrast, if the representative agent switches to the instanta-neous credit economy (i.e., if she switches to the economy inwhich it is possible to instantaneously borrow against illiquidassets), then the new economy asymptotically converges to thesteady state characterized in Proposition 5. The starting pointfor this convergence is the golden eggs steady state capital stockaugmented (depleted) by a payment at time period one.

    I calibrate this exercise with 0.36, d 0.08, g 0.02, 0.98 and 1, and I assume that the golden eggs steadystate is characterized by the historical capital-output ratio K/Y3. Note that these values are consistent with the steady stateequation for the golden eggs economy (see Proposition 1).

    The convergence path for the economy in which instanta-neous borrowing is possible is characterized by a nonstandardEuler equation derived in Laibson [1996]:

    (7) u c R u ct t t

    ( ) ( )[ ( ) ],+= + +1 1 1 1

    where is given by21

    (8)

    =

    1

    1 1( ).

    Note that when 1 this Euler equation reduces to the standardcase. To solve for the convergence path conditional on a startinglevel of financial wealth, it is necessary to search for the uniquesequence {ct, Rt}t1 that is 1) consistent with the nonstandard Eu-ler equation given above; 2) consistent with the dynamic budget

    constraint; 3) consistent with the capital market competitiveequilibrium condition; and 4) consistent with asymptotic conver-gence to the steady state characterized in Proposition 5. Identi-fying this sequence can be reduced to a one-dimensional searchover values ofc1: start with a guess of the equilibrium value ofc1;combine this value ofc1 with the dynamic budget constraint andthe competitive equilibrium conditions to generate R2; use thenonstandard Euler equation to calculate c2 as a function ofc1 and

    R2; iterate the last two steps to generate a sequence {ct, Rt}t1that can be checked for asymptotic steady state convergence; ifthe sequence does not converge, start with a new guess for c1.

    This algorithm provides a way of calculating the convergence

    21. The derivation for uses the calibration assumption 1.

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS466

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    25/35

    path given any level of initial financial wealth in the instanta-neous credit economy. Once this has been done, it is straightfor-ward to calculate the level of initial financial wealth in theinstantaneous credit economy that induces indifference withthe level of initial financial wealth in the golden eggs economy.The payment level is the difference between these two financialwealth levels. The payment level is reported in Table II, where itis normalized by the level of output at time of payment.22 Note

    that a positive payment implies that the consumer needs compen-sation to induce her to willingly switch to the instantaneouscredit scenario. Hence, if payment were withheld, the consumerwould be worse off in the instantaneous credit scenario. Table IIreports these normalized payments for a range of values.

    Note that when 1 there is no welfare loss. When 1,the consumers preferences are not dynamically inconsistent, andthe consumer has no need to constrain her future selves. By con-trast, for the other cases, ( {0.2, 0.4, 0.6, 0.8}) the consumeris made worse off by financial innovation. Being able to borrowagainst illiquid assets is welfare reducing. However, note thatthis is not always the case. For values sufficiently close to zero,the consumer is made better off by being able to splurge almostall of her financial wealth immediately. However, for the range ofreasonable values reported in Table II, the consumer is alwaysmade worse off by financial innovation.

    Of course the costs of financial innovation explored abovemay be offset by unmodeled gains, like being able to consume in

    unforeseen emergencies (which are ruled out in the deterministicframework of this paper). The point of this subsection is to dem-

    TABLE IIPAYMENTS TO INDUCE INDIFFERENCE

    BETWEEN GOLDEN EGGS ECONOMYAND INSTANTANEOUS CREDIT ECONOMY

    Payment aspercent of output

    0.2 69.6 0.4 29.5 0.6 9.0 0.8 1.6 1.0 0.0

    22. Note that output at time of payment is the same under the two scenarios,since output at any given period is determined by capital put aside in the previ-ous period.

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 467

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    26/35

    onstrate that there are potentially important costs that accom-pany those other well-known benefits of extra liquidity.

    V. EVALUATION AND EXTENSIONS

    I have analyzed the consumption problem of a dynamicallyinconsistent decision-maker who has access to a crude commit-ment mechanism. The model helps to explain many of the empiri-cal puzzles in the consumption literature, notably consumption-income tracking and asset-specific MPCs. However, the modelhas several drawbacks that suggest four important areas to pur-sue extensions.

    First, the golden eggs model does not explain how consumersaccumulate assets in the first place. Note that consumption isalways greater than labor income on the equilibrium path. How-ever, this is less of a problem than it might first appear. Althoughthere is evidence that individuals often consume less than theyearn in labor income, most of this saving is nondiscretionary (e.g.,pension contributions, life-insurance payments, mortgage pay-ments, and other payments to creditors). Bringing such nondis-

    cretionary savings into the model can be done very simply. Forexample, the consumer could elect to take on a 30-period mort-gage obligation at time zero, represented by a mortgage paymentof m for the next 30 periods. Then the consumers cash flow attime t 30 would be yt Rtxt1 m, which would be less than

    yt ifm were greater than Rtxt1. A related way to model nondiscre-tionary savings would be to let the consumer set xt1 itself lessthan zero, (e.g., x xt1, where x 0).

    A second problem associated with the model is the anoma-

    lous prediction that consumers will always face a binding self-imposed liquidity constraint. For example, the golden eggs modelpredicts that after making their consumption choice, consumersshould have no liquid funds left in their bank accounts. This pre-diction contradicts many consumers experiences. However, thisproblem can be readily addressed by introducing a precautionarysavings motive for holding liquidity. For example, consider acontinuous-time analog of the golden eggs model, and assumethat instantaneous liquidity needs arrive with some hazard rate.

    Then in equilibrium the consumer will only rarely completely ex-haust her liquidity.

    A third problem with the golden eggs model is that some con-

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS468

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    27/35

    sumers may not need to use external commitment devices (likeilliquid assets) to achieve self-control. Consumers may have in-ternal self-control mechanisms, like will power and personalrules. In Laibson [1994a] I analyze an infinite-horizon consump-tion/savings game with no external commitment technology andfind a multiplicity of Pareto-rankable equilibria. I interpret thismultiplicity as a potential model for self-control and willpower.However, this approach raises problematic and as yet unresolvedequilibrium selection problems. More work is needed to developtheoretically robust models of internal self-control mechanisms,and to empirically validate such models.

    The fourth problem with the golden eggs model is that someconsumers may have access to an array of social commitmentdevices that are far richer than the simple illiquid asset proposedin this essay. In Laibson [1994b] I analyze the problem of a con-sumer who can use social systems like marriage, work, andfriendship to achieve personal commitment. Future work shouldtry to identify the most important mechanisms that consumersuse to overcome the self-control problems induced by hyperbolicpreferences.

    APPENDIX

    Theorem 1 is proved with four intermediate lemmas. Theselemmas apply to the game described in Theorem 1.

    LEMMA 1. Let s be a resource-exhausting element of the jointstrategy space S. Assume that s satisfies P1P4. Then for allhistories ht, strategy s implies that ct yt.

    Proof of Lemma 1. Use induction to prove result. Fix a periodt and feasible history, ht. Let s|ht {cAt, xAt, zAt}Tt0. Assumethat ct yt 1. By P1, u(ct) max{1, . . . ,Tt(i1Rti) u(ct). If this inequality is strict, then P2 implies thatct yt. So WLOG assume that u(ct) max1

    (i1Rti)u(ct):

    u c R u c

    R u y

    u y

    t T t t iit

    T t t ii t

    t

    ( ( )

    ( )

    (

    }

    }

    ) max by assumption

    max by assumption

    ) by A1.

    =

    +=+

    += +

    {1,...,

    {1,...,

    1 1

    1 1

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 469

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    28/35

    So u(ct) u(yt), and hence ct yt. After confirming that cT yT(by resource exhaustion), the proof is completed by applying astandard induction argument.

    LEMMA 2. Let sA and sB be resource-exhausting elements of thejoint strategy space S. Assume that sA and sB satisfy P1P4.Let {cAt , xAt , zAt }Tt1 and {cBt , xBt , zBt }Tt1 be the respective paths ofactions generated by sA and sB. Fix a particular value of t,and assume cAt c

    Bt 1, with cAt cBt for at least

    one 1. Then cAt cBt .

    Proof of Lemma 2. By P1, u(cA

    t ) max{1, . . . ,T 1}

    (i1 Rti) u(cAt). If this is satisfied with equality, then

    u c R u c

    R u c

    u c

    tB

    T t t iitB

    T t t iitA

    tA

    ( ( )

    ( )

    (

    }

    }

    ) max by P1

    max by assumption

    ) by assumption.

    =

    +=+

    +=+

    {1,...,

    {1,...,

    1 1

    1 1

    Hence, u(cBt ) u(c

    At ), implying that c

    At c

    Bt . So WLOG assume

    that u(cAt ) max{1, . . . ,Tt1} (i1 Rti) u(c

    At). By P2, c

    At yt

    Rtxt1. If t 1, then cAt c

    Bt , since c

    B1 y1 R1x0 c

    A1 . So

    WLOG assume that t 2. IfxBt1 xAt1, then c

    Bt yt Rtx

    Bt1

    yt RtxAt1 c

    At . So WLOG assume x

    Bt1 x

    At1 0.

    0 111

    1

    11

    1 1

    < by assumption

    by Lemma 1

    + + by res. exhaust.

    R c c

    R c y

    R x z c y

    R

    t ii

    T t

    tA

    tB

    t ii

    T t

    t

    A

    t

    t tA

    tA

    tA

    tA

    t

    +

    ==

    + +

    +

    ==

    + +

    =

    =

    ( )

    ( )

    ( )

    z z c y R xtA

    tA

    t t tA

    =1 1as + .

    So zAt1 0, and,

    u c R u c x

    R u c

    u c z

    tB

    T t t iitB

    tB

    T t t iitA

    tA

    t

    ( ( )

    ( )

    (

    }

    }

    ) max by P3 and 0

    max by assumption

    ) by P4 and

    >

    +=+

    += +

    {1,...,

    {1,...,

    1 11

    1 1

    1AA 0.>

    Hence, u(cBt ) u(cAt ), implying that c

    At c

    Bt .

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS470

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    29/35

    LEMMA 3. Let s be a resource-exhausting element of the jointstrategy space S. Assume that s satisfies P1P4. Let {c

    t

    , xt

    ,zt}Tt1 represent the path of actions generated by s. Then ct yt Rtxt1 t 2.

    Proof of Lemma 3. Suppose that ct yt Rtxt1 for some t 2and look for a contradiction. By P1 and P2, u(ct) max

    {1, . . . , Tt1} (i1 Rti)u(ct), so u(ct)

    max{1, . . . ,Tt1} (

    i1 Rti)u(ct). Hence, by P3, xt1 0. So ct yt, which contradicts Lemma 1.

    LEMMA 4. Let {ct, xt, zt}Tt1 be a solution path to the followingproblem:

    max ) +

    subject to, 0 1

    + 1

    + + + 1

    {c x z

    T

    t t

    t t t t

    t t t t t t t

    t t t tT

    u c u c

    x z t

    c y R x t

    x z R x z y c t

    x

    , , }( ( )

    ( )

    = =

    +

    =

    1

    11

    1

    1

    1

    1 1

    0

    ,,

    { , , }

    z

    x zc x z

    T T

    t t t tT

    0

    2

    0

    fixed

    satisfies P1 P4.

    = ==

    Then satisfies P1 P4.{c x zt t t tT, , } = 1

    Proof of Lemma 4. The first step in the proof is to show thatthe solution set of the program above is a subset of the solutionset of the program below.

    max ) +{c x z

    T

    t t t tT

    u c u c, , }

    ( ( )= =

    +1

    11

    1

    1

    subject to

    x z t

    c y R x t

    x z R x z y c t

    x z

    x zc y

    c y R x t

    t t

    t t t t

    t t t t t t t

    T T

    t t t t

    , 0 1+ 1

    + + + 1

    fixed

    +

    =

    = ==

    1

    1 1

    0 0

    2 2

    1

    0

    ( )

    ,

    3.

    Henceforth I will refer to these, respectively, as program I andprogram II. Note that program II is a convex program with linear

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 471

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    30/35

    constraints, so the Kuhn-Tucker first-order conditions are neces-sary and sufficient for a global optimum. I will return to this factlater in the proof.

    The following notation will be used to prove the lemma. Let represent the set of all real vectors, {ct, xt, zt}Tt1. Let CI (CII ) represent the subset of vectors in which satisfy theconstraints of program I (II). Let C*I (C*II ) represent thesubset of vectors in that are solutions to program I (II).

    The first step in the proof is to show that CI CII. Fix any CI, and let {ct, xt, zt}Tt1. Note that the first five constraintsof program I are identical to the first five constraints of programII. Also note that if{ct, xt, zt}Tt2 satisfies P1P4, then by Lemma1, c2 y2, and by Lemma 3, ct yt Rtxt1 t 3. Hence, CII, implying that CI CII.

    The next step is to show C*I C*II. Fix any C*I . Fix any C*II, and let {ct, xt, zt}Tt1. Define x1 such that c2 y2

    R2x1. Let be equivalent to except that x1 is replaced by x1,and z1 is replaced by z1 z1 (x1 x1). Let U() represent thevalue of the objective function evaluated at . Consider the fol-lowing two properties of: CII, U() U(). Recall that C*II. Then must also be an element ofC*II. Hence mustsatisfy the Kuhn-Tucker conditions of program II (since the con-ditions are necessary and sufficient). Using the Kuhn-Tucker con-ditions and the definition of, it is straightforward to show that CI. Note that C*II and C*I CI CII imply thatU() U(). Note that C*I and CI imply that U() U(). Hence, U() U(), which implies that U() U(). So C*II and C*I CI CII imply that C*II. Hence,C*I C*II.

    I am now ready to complete the proof of the lemma. Let bea solution to program I, and let {ct, xt, zt}Tt1. So {ct, xt, zt}Tt2satisfies P1P4. Since C*I C*II, must also satisfy the necessaryand sufficient Kuhn-Tucker conditions of program II. Combiningthese constraints, it is straightforward to show that {ct, xt, zt}Tt1satisfies P1P4.

    Proof of Theorem 1. Suppose that there exist two resource-exhausting joint strategies, sA, sB S, that satisfy P1P4. Fix any

    period t, and any feasible history ht. Let sA|ht {cAt, xAt, zAt}Tt0, sB|ht {cBt, xBt, zBt}Tt0. By resource exhaus-tion and Lemma 2, cAt c

    Bt

    0. Hence, by Lemma 3, xAt x

    Bt 0. This in turn implies that zAt zBt 0, as

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS472

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    31/35

    a result of the savings constraints. Because the proof started witharbitary h

    t

    , we can conclude that sA sB proving that there existsa unique resource-exhausting joint strategy, s* S, that satisfiesP1P4. The second part of the theorem follows from this unique-ness result, Lemma 4, and a standard induction argument.

    Proof of Proposition 1. If a steady state satisfies A1, thenexp(g) R. Moreover, it is easy to construct a steady state atwhich exp(g) R. Suppose that there exists a steady stateat which exp(g) R. Then by P1P4, limtzt limtxt 0,which implies that no such steady state could exist.

    Proof of Proposition 2. By P1, u(ct) (i1 Rti) u(ct)

    t 2, 0. Suppose that this inequality is satisfied exactly forsome t, pair. Then xt1 0 by P3. Hence,

    u y u c

    R u c

    R u y

    t t

    t ii

    t

    t ii t

    ( (

    ( )

    (

    ) ) by Lemma 3

    by assumption

    ) by Lemma 3.

    =

    =

    +=

    +

    += +

    1

    1

    But u(yt) (i1 Rti) u(yt) violates A1, (since A1 is as-

    sumed to hold strictly). So WLOG, assume that u(ct)

    (i1Rti) u(ct) t 2, 0. Hence, for sufficiently small || 0, u(ct)

    (i1 Rti) u(ct) t 2, 0. So by P3 andthe uniqueness result of Theorem 1, in the subgame starting afterany sufficiently small perturbation to the liquid asset stock, theequality ct yt Rtxt1 continues to hold, and hence, ct/((Rt

    xt1)) 1.

    Proof of Proposition 3. WLOG, assume that u(ct)

    (i1 Rti) u(ct) t 2, 0 (see Proof of Proposition 2). Hence,for sufficiently small || 0, u(ct)

    (i1 Rti)u (ct (i1Ri)) t 2, 0. So current consumption does not change

    when zt1 is perturbed.

    Proposition 4 is proved with two intermediate lemmas.

    LEMMA 5. Fix the economy described in Proposition 4. On theequilibrium path of this game u(ct) (R)

    u(ct) t 2.

    Proof of Lemma 5. Suppose that u(ct) (R)u(ct) for some

    t 2. Then P3 implies xt1 0, implying that

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 473

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    32/35

    u y u c

    R u c

    R u y

    t t

    t

    t

    ( (

    ( ) ( )

    ( ) ( )

    ) ) by Lemma 3

    by assumption

    by Lemma 3.

    =

    =

    +

    + +

    1

    Note that u(yt) (R)u(yt), follows from the assumptions. So

    the previous inequalities imply that xt1 0, which togetherwith P3 implies that u(ct) supn1(R)

    n u(ctn). In addition,xt1 0, implies that zt1 0, which together with P4 impliesthat u(ct) supn1(R)

    n u(ctn). So there exists a finite t {t 1, t 2, . . . , t 1}, such that u(ct) supn1(R)n u(ctn).Hence, by P4, zt1 0, contradicting the result that xt1 0.

    LEMMA 6. Fix the economy described in Proposition 4. On theequilibrium path of this game xt exp(g)xt, zt exp(g)zt, t 1.

    Proof of Lemma 6. By Lemma 5, u(ct) (R)u(ct) t

    2. Combining this with Lemma 3 implies that u(yt Rxt1) (R)u(yt Rxt1). The assumptions, exp(g) R and

    yt exp(g)yt, can be used to simplify the previous equation,

    yielding, xt1 exp(g)xt1 t 2. Note that resource exhaus-tion and Lemma 3 together imply that zt

    i1 R

    ixti t 1.So zt

    i1 R

    ixti i1 R

    i exp(g)xti exp(g)zt t 1.

    Proof of Proposition 4. To prove this proposition, I considertwo games: an original game, and a perturbed game. The per-turbed game is identical to the original game except that in theperturbed game illiquid assets are higher at time zero. Let arepresent the difference between variable a in the perturbed

    game and variable a in the original game. Then Lemma 3 im-plies that

    z R zx

    Rz

    x

    R zt t

    t

    t

    t

    t

    +

    +

    +

    =

    1 1

    1

    1

    2

    1 1( )( ) ( )

    L

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS474

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    33/35

    for all t 2. Hence,

    1 1 1

    1

    0

    0

    0

    1

    1

    2

    01

    1

    1/

    1/

    =

    =

    =

    +

    +

    +

    MPCx

    Rz

    x

    Rz

    z

    z R

    g

    R

    tz

    zt

    t

    t

    t

    zt

    t

    lim( ) ( )

    lim

    exp( )

    L

    == ( ) , R1 1/

    where the second to last equality follows from Lemma 6.

    Proof of Proposition 5. Laibson [1996] analyzes the economywithout the commitment technology. I show that the infinite hori-zon equilibrium which corresponds to the limit of the finite hori-zon equilibria is characterized by constant proportionalconsumption of the wealth stock, where wealth is defined as thesum of financial assets and the discounted value of future labor

    income. Let represent the coefficient of proportionality; I showthat is given by

    + 1/= 1 1 11[ ( ( ) )] .R

    With proportional consumption the steady state condition is

    R g( ) exp( ).1 =

    Solving these equations to eliminate yields equation (4).

    Proof of Corollary to Proposition 5. Let R* represent the

    steady state gross interest rate in the economy with commitment.Recall Proposition 1: exp(g) R*. Using Proposition 5, it fol-lows that RR* (rg)(1) 0 as r g is required for theexistence of a steady state.

    HARVARD UNIVERSITY

    REFERENCES

    Ainslie, George W., Specious Reward: A Behavioral Theory of Impulsiveness andImpulsive Control, Psychological Bulletin, LXXXII (1975), 46396.

    , Beyond Microeconomics. Conflict among Interests in a Multiple Self as aDeterminant of Value. in The Multiple Self, Jon Elster, ed. (Cambridge, UK:Cambridge University Press, 1986).

    , Picoeconomics (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1992).Aiyagari, S. Rao, Uninsured Idiosyncratic Risk and Aggregate Saving, Working

    Paper 502, Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis, 1992.

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 475

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    34/35

    Akerlof, George, Procrastination and Obedience, American Economic Review,LXXXI (1991), 119.

    Attanasio, Orazio P., and Guglielmo Weber, Consumption Growth, the InterestRate, and Aggregation, Review of Economic Studies, LX (1993), 63149.

    Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System, Balance Sheets for the U. S. Economy 194594 (Washington, DC: 1995).

    Canner, Glenn B., and Charles A. Luckett, Developments in the Pricing of CreditCard Services, Federal Reserve Bulletin, LXXVIII (1992), 65266.

    Canner, Glenn B., and Charles A. Luckett, Home Equity Lending: Evidence fromRecent Surveys, Federal Reserve Bulletin, LXXX (1994), 57183.

    Carroll, Christopher D., The Buffer-Stock Theory of Saving: Some Macroeco-nomic Evidence, Brookings Papers on Economics Activity (1992:2), 61156.

    , How Does Future Income Affect Current Consumption? Board of Gover-nors of the Federal Reserve System, 1992.

    Carroll, Christopher D., and Lawrence H. Summers, Consumption Growth Paral-lels Income Growth: Some New Evidence, in National Saving and Economic

    Performance, B. Douglas Bernheim and John Shoven, eds. (Chicago, IL: Chi-cago University Press, 1991).Chung, Shin-Ho, and Richard J. Herrnstein, Relative and Absolute Strengths

    of Response as a Function of Frequency of Reinforcement, Journal of theExperimental Analysis of Animal Behavior, IV (1961), 26772.

    Farnsworth, E. Allan, Contracts (Boston, MA: Little, Brown and Company, 1990).Flavin, Marjorie, The Joint Consumption/Asset Demand Decision: A Case Study

    in Robust Estimation, NBER Working Paper No. 3802, 1991.Goetz, Charles J., and Robert E. Scott, Liquidated Damages, Penalties and the

    Just Compensation Principle: Some Notes on an Enforcement Model and aTheory of Efficient Breach, Columbia Law Review, LXXVII (1977), 55494.

    Goldman, Steven M., Consistent Plans, Review of Economic Studies, XLVII(1980), 53337.

    Gourinchas, Pierre-Olivier, and Jonathan Parker, Consumption over the Life-

    Cycle, MIT mimeo, 1995.Hall, Robert E., and Frederic S. Mishkin, The Sensitivity of Consumption to

    Transitory Income: Estimates from Panel Data on Households, Economet-rica, L (1982), 46181.

    Hatsopoulos, George N., Paul R. Krugman, James M. Poterba, Overconsumption:The Challenge to U. S. Economic Policy, American Business ConferenceWorking Paper, 1989.

    Laibson, David I., Notes on a Commitment Problem, MIT mimeo, 1993., Self-Control and Saving, MIT mimeo, 1994a., An Intrapersonal Principal-Agent Problem, MIT mimeo, 1994b., Hyperbolic Discounting, Undersaving, and Savings Policy, NBER Working

    Paper No. 5635, 1996.Loewenstein, George, and Drazen Prelec, Anomalies in Intertemporal Choice:

    Evidence and an Interpretation, Quarterly Journal of Economics, CVII(1992), 57398.

    Mandell, Lewis, The Credit Card Industry (Boston, MA: Twayne Publishers,1990).

    Peleg, Bezalel, and Menahem E. Yaari, On the Existence of a Consistent Courseof Action When Tastes Are Changing, Review of Economic Studies, XL(1973), 391401.

    Phelps, E. S., and R. A. Pollak, On Second-Best National Saving and Game-Equilibrium Growth, Review of Economic Studies, XXXV (1968), 18599.

    Pollak, R. A., Consistent Planning, Review of Economic Studies, XXXV (1968),20108.

    Prelec, Drazen, Decreasing Impatience: Definition and Consequences, HarvardBusiness School Working Paper, 1989.

    Rankin, Deborah M., How to Get Ready for Retirement: Save, Save Save, New

    York Times, March 13, 1993, p. 33.Rea, Samuel A., Jr., Efficiency Implications of Penalties and Liquidated Dam-ages, Journal of Legal Studies, XIII (1984), 14767.

    Runkle, David E., Liquidity Constraints and the Permanent-Income Hypothe-sis, Journal of Monetary Economics, XXVII (1991), 7398.

    Shea, John, Union Contracts and the Life Cycle/Permanent-Income Hypothesis,American Economic Review, LXXXV (1995), 186200.

    QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS476

  • 8/3/2019 Revista David Laibson

    35/35

    Souleles, Nicholas, The Response of Household Consumption to Income Tax Re-funds, MIT mimeo, 1995.

    Strotz, Robert H., Myopia and Inconsistency in Dynamic Utility Maximization,Review of Economic Studies, XXIII (1956), 16580.

    Thaler, Richard H., Saving, Fungibility, and Mental Accounts, Journal of Eco-nomic Perspectives, IV (1990), 193205.

    Zeckhauser, Richard, and Stephen Fels, Discounting for Proximity with Perfectand Total Altruism, Harvard Institute of Economic Research, DiscussionPaper No. 50, 1968.

    Zeldes, Stephen P., Consumption and Liquidity Constraints: An Empirical Inves-tigation, Journal of Political Economy, XCVII (1989), 30546.

    GOLDEN EGGS AND HYPERBOLIC DISCOUNTING 477