rigidity, ontology, and semantic structure

22
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Rigidity, Ontology, and Semantic Structure Author(s): Alan Sidelle Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 89, No. 8 (Aug., 1992), pp. 410-430 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2940742 . Accessed: 28/06/2014 22:34 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Upload: alan

Post on 16-Feb-2017

216 views

Category:

Documents


3 download

TRANSCRIPT

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Rigidity, Ontology, and Semantic StructureAuthor(s): Alan SidelleSource: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 89, No. 8 (Aug., 1992), pp. 410-430Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc.Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2940742 .

Accessed: 28/06/2014 22:34

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journalof Philosophy.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

410 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

RIGIDITY, ONTOLOGY, AND SEMANTIC STRUCTURE*

T 1 he notion of rigid designation stands squarely at the inter- face of metaphysics and philosophy of language.' Itself a semantic notion, it is metaphysical in its applications, and in

that whether an expression is rigid depends on whether its reference is in all worlds the same. Rigidity has played an important role in the development of a broad philosophical view that has largely sup- planted the dominant empiricism of the earlier part of this century. On this new view, important questions about what is necessary, what features of things are essential, and what the conditions of identity and individuation are for many things are factual, indeed empirical questions. They require not conceptual or semantic analysis, but are rather to be settled by looking at the world, investigating the objects in question, rather than the expressions used to refer to them. Our findings tell us about the "deep" structure of the world, not about our conceptual scheme. Rigidity plays a central role in all this, be- cause it is the fact that many key terms are rigid which allows us to fix upon an object so as to investigate it with respect to both the actual and other possible worlds. This new view, for which Kripke and Hilary Putnam2 are largely responsible, is partly characterized by the following claims (these may not all be distinct views):

(1) By using expressions rigidly, we can ask counterfactual questions about objects without any a priori specifications concerning the properties of the object of reference.

(2) We can stipulate possible worlds without worrying about or set- tling questions concerning transworld identity conditions.

(3) Our modal inquiries are directed at the objects3 themselves, and in no way concern our concepts or the meanings of words.

(4) Thus, we can make a posteriori de re modal discoveries-we can have empirical discovery of essence. These findings represent lan- guage and mind-independent modal features of objects.

(5) We can form identity statements between rigid designators

* Many people have helped me with the issues in this paper. Thanks to Thomas A. Blackson, David 0. Brink, Berent Enc, Ted Everett, Martha Gibson, Paula Gottlieb, Elliott Sober, Dennis Stampe, and Leora Weitzman.

1 Saul Kripke introduces the notion in Naming and Necessity (Cambridge: Harvard, 1980), pp. 48-9, and provides a fine overview in his preface, pp. 3-15.

2 Putnam's views are presented in many of the essays in Mind, Language and Reality (New York: Cambridge, 1975); "The Meaning of 'Meaning' " is probably the most important.

3 To ease exposition, I shall use 'object' to range over any object of reference or inquiry; it includes, e.g., kinds as well as individuals.

0022-362X/92/8908/410-30 (? 1992 The Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

RIGIDITY 411

(i) if the expressions happen to tag the same object, the state- ment is true, and necessarily so;

(ii) if we can only find out the truth of this statement empirically, we again have a posteriori necessary truths,

(iii) metaphysically and semantically, there is nothing more to the truth of an empirical identity statement than "same thing tagged."4

(1)-(3) contrast with the more traditional view according to which reference is determined through meaning. On that view, one cannot sensibly talk about an object in another possible world except as it satisfies, in that world, the conditions given by the meaning of some word. But then it is specified a priori that the referent of the word, whatever it is, has those properties, and to specify a possible situa- tion is to specify one in which an object with those properties is in some situation, thus settling the issue of transworld identity. And since our possible world descriptions are constrained by the mean- ings of our words, we have no independent grasp of the object to investigate it-all we are really investigating are conceptual connec- tions within our framework. (1)-(3) represent the more "world-" or "object-directed" understanding of these sorts of philosophical in- quiry. (4) and (5) are two more overtly metaphysical features of the new view, exemplified by the purportedly necessary a posteriori 'Water is H20', 'Margaret Truman has Bess Truman for a biological parent', and 'Hesperus is Phosphorus'. The "object-directed" un- derstanding of (1)-(3) feeds the metaphysical, rather than "concep- tual," understanding of these phenomena, as represented in (4) and (5). I shall not discuss or criticize these positions individually; they are introduced here simply to point the reader toward a position that I hope is familiar, and understood to have a great deal of philo- sophical currency.

In this paper, I shall investigate how rigidity plays such an impor- tant role in contemporary metaphysics. I shall argue that the role depends on a certain understanding of rigidity, which I call the metaphysical understanding (sections I, II): this is the view that the semantics of rigid expressions is determined by mind-independent facts of transworld identity. I shall also offer a more semantical understanding of rigidity, with which this may be contrasted (section VI). The metaphysical understanding, I argue, requires a privileged ontology according to which some, but not all, ways of carving up the world get at "real" objects (sections III, IV). The semantic inter-

4 Of course, this is not the content of an identity statement on this view. It is just all that there is to such a sentence's being true.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

412 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

pretation, by contrast, carries no such metaphysical burden. While I shall not argue against privileged ontologies, I think it important to see this commitment. Many who accept the new view may not realize that they are so committed, and may not be inclined to accept such an ontology. Further, anyone who wishes to buy into the currently prevalent picture which (1)-(5) partially characterize must defend this ontology. It is not at all supported, as one might think, by our intuitive judgments about which terms are rigid (section V). Indeed, I hope to show that it is by tacitly assuming such an ontology in familiar presentations of rigidity-supporting intuitions that we are so easily led to this larger metaphysical picture: the ontology, not our judgments of rigidity, does the work (section V). I leave it to defenders of the new view to try to provide the necessary argu- ments; I also hope my semantic account of rigidity will be of interest whatever one's ontological views.

I. RIGIDITY DE JURE AND DE FACTO; REFERENCE THROUGH SENSE AND IDENTITY

An expression is rigid if it has the same reference with respect to all possible worlds (in which it refers). Kripke distinguishes two ways an expression may be rigid, de jure and de facto (op. cit., p. 21 fn.). These correspond to two semantic interpretations for expressions, most easily illustrated with definite descriptions.

The statement 'The President of the U.S. is necessarily male' has two familiar readings: on one reading, it ascribes an essential prop- erty to George Bush; on the other, it states the impossibility of a nonmale attaining to a certain political office. Semantically, 'The President of the U.S.' functions differently in the two cases.5 In the first, the description picks out some individual in virtue of its de- scriptive content, and is understood to refer, in other possible worlds, to that individual (Bush), and its counterfactual properties determine the truth value of the statement. The descriptive content of the expression falls away; it is relevant only in determining an actual referent. So used, we may say that such descriptions gain their referents in other worlds through identity, i.e., through the identity of objects in other worlds with the actual referent.

On the other reading, the description also picks out an individual by its descriptive content, but it picks out individuals in other worlds by the very same content. In each world, the individual that satisfies this descriptive condition (having a certain office) is its referent.

' While one can represent this by a scope distinction, there remains the ques- tion of what in the utterance of a modal sentence with descriptions makes it properly interpreted as having wide or narrow scope.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

RIGIDITY 413

Descriptions so used may be said to gain their referents in other worlds through sense, i.e., through the meaning of the description.

A description that refers counterfactually through identity will obviously be rigid, since the very condition for the expression's ap- plying to something in another world is that that thing be identical to the actual referent. The rigidity of such expressions is rigidity de jure; the function of such an expression with respect to other worlds is precisely to pick out that very object. Descriptions that refer counterfactually through sense, on the other hand, may, and typically will, turn out to be nonrigid, for the objects that satisfy the conditions in various worlds may not all be the same, as with 'The President of the U.S.' In some worlds, it is George Bush, in others, Michael Dukakis or Elizabeth Dole. Now, it can turn out that the referents are all the same, as with 'The sum of two plus two'. Such expressions will be rigid, but, so to speak, by accident.6 Their rigidity is rigidity de facto. The semantic function of the term, as regards other worlds, is given by a descriptive condition-it is not stipulated that the referent in other worlds is to be the actual referent. It just turns out that way.

These distinctions are not confined to descriptions. For any refer- ring expression useable in counterfactual discourse, we can ask how it functions semantically (through identity or sense), and can classify its rigidity, if any there be. Of course, if an expression has no de- scriptive content, no semantic structure, all that can determine its counterfactual reference will be the actual referent itself; such "contentless" expressions will consequently refer through identity and be rigid dejure. According to direct or causal theories of refer- ence, names are like this, and they provide the paradigm of rigidity de jure.

Most philosophers have not taken much interest in rigid de facto expressions. The reason, I think, is that they cannot play the meta- physical role exemplified in claims (1)-(5). Since a rigid de facto expression has its counterfactual reference determined through sense, the answers to important modal questions will be analytic and a priori. When 'The President of the U.S.' is used this way, it is given a priori that the referent in any world will be the president there. This also constrains counterfactual stipulations we can make using

6 One can intend such a description to refer counterfactually through identity, making its rigidity not "accidental," but de jure. With such 'identifying' descrip- tions, we may fail to notice that they can be rigid in both ways. It is easier to see for 'the element with atomic number 79' (assuming that used through sense, this rigidly picks out gold).

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

414 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

such expressions-we cannot stipulate worlds in which the referent fails to have these sense-specified properties. And this constraint is given a priori (unlike our inability to stipulate worlds that violate necessary a posteriori truths). So here, our modal investigations are not so "object-directed" as when reference is through identity. When reference works through sense, even when rigid, our means of getting an object of modal inquiry already build in, in making it the object of inquiry, what counterfactual properties it must have.7 The lack of interest in rigidity de facto is the (implicit) recognition that, for the metaphysics, rigid reference must occur through identity.

And for metaphysics, then, the relevant distinction is not that between rigid and nonrigid expressions per se, but that between expressions which refer counterfactually through identity, and those which refer through sense.8 Names have pride of place because (on the current view) they always refer through identity, while descrip- tions only sometimes do. Note, though, that names need not be wholly without content to be rigid de jure. All that matters is that this content plays no role in determining their reference in other worlds. If names need to, or sometimes do get actual referents by reference-fixing descriptions,9 they will function just like descrip- tions used rigidly de jure: both will have their actual referents de- termined through sense, but their counterfactual referents deter- mined through identity.10

7A "sense" based view can allow some modal questions to be left open-for counterfactual conditions may be specified generally or abstractly (e.g., 'same origin' or 'same deep structure'), leaving empirical investigation to find out what in particular (actually) "fills in" these conditions. This means that a (modified) traditional view can allow necessary a posteriori truths, and "stipulation" of other worlds need not (implicitly) answer all modal questions. But what is left open would have modal import only because of the semantics, undermining the sup- posed metaphysical import of (1)-(5) mostly given by (3), the second sentence of (4), and (5) (iii). For examples of such "general" specification, and more on a "conventionalist" account of a posteriori necessity, see my Necessity, Essence and Individuation (Ithaca: Cornell, 1989), esp. chs. 2, 3.

8 Or, alternatively, between expressions that are rigid dejure and all others. As the mechanism is what matters, I prefer my first formulation. The importance of this distinction is also noted by A. D. Smith, "Rigidity and Scope," Mind, XCII,

369 (April 1984): 177-93. 9 See Kripke, Naming and Necessity, pp. 55-6 for his introduction of the

reference-fixing/meaning-giving distinction. '? Thus, a causal account of reference is not, as such, vital to the "new" meta-

physics. Further, while Kripke has answers to description theorists who claim that names are descriptions which happen to always take wide scope in modal contexts, their position would anyway not touch the metaphysical side of his work, as the senses of such descriptions fall out as irrelevant to determining counterfactual reference.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

RIGIDITY 415

II. THE METAPHYSICAL UNDERSTANDING OF RIGIDITY

The familiar picture of how rigid designation allows for empirical inquiry into necessity and essence actually makes plain that the im- portance of rigidity resides in rigidity dejure and reference through identity. The story is that we introduce a term to refer rigidly to some object. This term then gives us a handle on that entity so we can investigate its properties, not only actually, but also, because of rigidity, in other possible worlds. The subject of our investigation is then that object, and any positive results we find give us modal properties of it."

This picture is, I hope, familiar enough. But as we have seen, if the object is truly to be the subject of our inquiry, it cannot just be rigidity at work here. What is key is not simply being able to refer to some object in other possible worlds, but being able to do so in a way that does not build in whatfeatures it will have in these worlds. We need the object itself, and not some description, to determine the expression's counterfactual reference. Expressions that refer counterfactually through sense do not meet this condition, even when they are rigid (de facto).

Philosophers who do accept claims (1)-(5) then, accept, or are committed to, a particular understanding of how rigidity works, at least in the relevant cases (those in which we get empirical discovery of necessity). We can characterize this commitment first by a nega- tive claim, the descriptionlessness thesis:

DL: (Many)'2 rigid designators have no descriptive content determin- ing (or constraining) their application in counterfactual situ- ations.

Our earlier remarks make clear why we do not say simply 'have no descriptive content'. Descriptive content that merely determines ac- tual reference, as in rigid dejure descriptions, is no bar to the sort of object-directed modal inquiry in which we are interested.

But how, then, is counterfactual application for such terms deter- mined? It is through identity: the counterfactual referent just is the actual referent. I shall call this positive claim the metaphysical un- derstanding of rigid designation:

I Such investigations might have turned up empty. So, as Nathan Salmon has argued (in "How Not to Derive Essentialism from the Theory of Reference," this JOURNAL, LXXVI, 12 (December 1979): 703-25; and Reference and Essence (Princeton: University Press, 1981)), the theory of reference, or the notion of rigidity does not itself give the metaphysical results. But it renders such investiga- tions sensible, whereas on traditional theories, we can only investigate objects as they satisfy the conditions given in the sense.

l The qualifier is just to acknowledge rigid de facto descriptions.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

416 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

MRD: The reference of (many) [see fn. 12] rigid designators in other worlds is given metaphysically-it is whatever object in the world in question is (identical to) the actual object of reference.

I call this the "metaphysical" understanding because once one has determined an actual referent (and perhaps has intended that the expression be rigid), the world takes over-the facts about identity across worlds determine counterfactual reference.

Whether MRD is the same as the claim that many rigid designa- tors are rigid de jure, or have their reference determined through identity, depends on how we choose to use these latter notions.'3 Whatever we decide about that, MRD is worth separate presenta- tion, since it states explicitly what is required for rigidity to do its metaphysical work. MRD asserts not only that some expressions have their rigidity semantically built in, but further, that this hap- pens metaphysically; it is simply the mind/language independent fact that x in wn is identical to y in the actual world that makes x the referent of T in wn. This takes a definite stand both on there being such independent facts, and on our ability to fix our terms' refer- ents without this reference-fixing playing the crucial role in deter- mining counterfactual reference (in some way other than on tradi- tional theories); this is left open, at least on one reading, by the notions of rigidity dejure and (perhaps) reference through identity.

I hope that many readers recognize MRD as the view that they do have about how rigid designation works (except for rigid de facto descriptions); I have mostly just tried to articulate it, and to explain why those who accept the metaphysical view that usually goes with presentations of rigidity are committed to it.

My next task is to show that MRD-and so (1)-(5)-requires a "privileged" ontology, and that the phenomenon of rigidity does nothing to support such an ontology or, consequently, MRD.

'3 Since it is so typically assumed that "nonaccidentally" rigid terms always lack descriptive conditions for counterfactual reference, the issue of whether rigidity de jure is defined by "built-in" rigidity, or also requires nondescriptive reference, does not arise. As we shall see (sec. VI), however, a term can have built in rigidity despite having descriptively determined counterfactual reference. So we shall have to decide. If rigidity dejure is just built in rigidity, then it does not suffice for MRD, and MRD is a theory about how such terms work. If we decide instead that descriptive reference precludes rigidity dejure, it is the same as MRD-though it is no longer "data" that names, say, are rigid de jure. Similar remarks apply for reference through identity.

The important question is: Do names, and expressions that function in modal contexts--like names, have their counterfactual reference determined by mind- independent facts about the identity of objects across worlds? This is the question of whether MRD is true. Whether it is also the question of whether there is in fact rigidity de jure, or reference through identity, is but a terminological matter.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

RIGIDITY 417

III. THE STRANGE AND UNUSUAL

Let me describe a purported entity, which I shall call "The President of the U.S.," or "Prez" for short. Prez is currently composed by George Bush, was composed in 1790 by George Washington, and in 1863 by Abraham Lincoln. In some other worlds, Prez is currently composed by Mike Dukakis, and in others by Elizabeth Dole. A per- son comes to constitute Prez, usually, by being sworn into office, though it may not work this way in all other worlds. Prez bears basically the same relation (at a time) to the people that are (or have been, or could be) Prez that a statue or river bears to the portions of matter (clay, water) that constitute them (at a time).14 Prez is not a mereological sum of the people who have been (are) the president (unless these other entities [statues, rivers] are, which they are not

at least of those things which actually constitute them, supposing mereological sums to have their parts essentially). When someone leaves office, Prez does not go out of existence, but rather, comes to be constituted by another person, as the Nile comes to be consti- tuted by different (portions of) water."5

Of course, Prez differs from statues and rivers in that it is not continuous through space and time-when there is a swearing in, Prez jumps in space to occupy the location of the person who has just been sworn in. Between such ceremonies, though, Prez follows a person-like path of spatiotemporal and psychological continuity. Fully precise identity conditions for Prez would be tricky, but I hope the basic idea is clear. Prez is constituted by, and not identical to, the people who hold the office of President of the U.S. And even in worlds where the presidency is abolished after Washington, Wash- ington would be Prez only in the sense of constitution, as they would still differ modally, and in their identity conditions.

Prez is person-like in that it has mental states and performs inten- tional activities ("The President of the U.S." vetoes bills); however, as just noted, it does not have the identity conditions persons have (say, spatiotemporal or psychological continuity). For a general cate- gory, we may call Prez an "office person"; other office people are "The Owner of the Yankees" and "The Pope." Office people also belong to broader class of (purported) entities, which includes "My Dog," which was composed by Fido, and now by Spot, and "Eliza- beth Taylor's Husband," which I leave to the reader to articulate.

14 On constitution, see David Wiggins, Sameness and Substance (New York: Oxford, 1980); and "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time," Philosophi- cal Review, LXXVII, 1 (anuary 1968): 90-5.

15 The Nile also comes to be constituted by different water, but here I am concerned with the relation between individuals.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

418 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

For reasons which should be plain, I shall call all of these "unusual" entities; for now, it should suffice to say that unusual entities are ones that we do not usually (explicitly, at least) recognize as (single) entities.

Let us call an ontology that recognizes unusual entities a permis- sive ontology, and one that does not restrictive. Further, let us call an ontology that recognizes no objects-one according to which there is stuff in the world, but none of it endowed with the sort of identity conditions we think distinguish objects from mere stuff-a fully restrictive ontology. We may then call an ontology that is nei- ther fully restrictive, nor permissive, a privileged ontology. In a pri- vileged ontology, some but not all ways of carving up the world get at real objects; some but not all proposed identity conditions are the identity conditions for some class of objects.'6 It is this sort of ontol- ogy to which defenders of MRD are committed.7

As I said, I shall not argue against a privileged ontology, but it is incumbent upon the defender of such a view to say what the favored entities have, and unusual ones lack, in a way that neither leads us to wholesale restrictivism, nor just makes us want to introduce a new general term to include both favored and unusual entities. As a middle position, it needs to withstand challenges from both sides, and it is not obvious that acceptable answers to one of the other positions can be made which will not push one to the opposite view. While there are many differences between people and office people, it is very questionable whether any of these has the right sort of metaphysical significance.'8

IV. WHY MRD REQUIRES A PRIVILEGED ONTOLOGY (a) Restrictive ontology. It should be plain that one cannot advocate the metaphysical understanding of rigidity with a wholly restrictive ontology. Since on this view there is no (mind-independent) identity across possible worlds, the facts of identity just are not up to the

16 Of course, everyone agrees that conditions like 'horse with a horn' pick out no real objects. Whether a 'way of carving' gets at real objects rather concerns its individuative force given its actual application. Wholesale restrictivists allow that there are "portions of the world" which are composed of H20, but deny that, mind-independently considered, this condition is individuative, or the es- sence of anything.

17 In fact, their ontology must rule out not only the "unusual" entities under discussion, but quite a few not-so-unusual entities, since any widespread spatio- temporal overlap of objects will raise the problems of indeterminacy to be dis- cussed. Our "unusual" entities just make the problem more vivid.

18 Eli Hirsch offers a thorough challenge to privileged ontologies in "Rules for a Good Language," this JOURNAL, LXXXV, 12 Uanuary 1988): 694-717. A rare explicit defense of a privileged view, or at least, attack on extreme permissivism, occurs in Sydney Shoemaker, "On What There Are," Philosophical Topics, xvi, 1 (Spring 1988): 201-24.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

RIGIDITY 419

task of determining the counterfactual reference of a term- indeed, even actual reference is problematic. If one tried to intro- duce a term as rigid de jure, to refer in other worlds to whatever is identical with the actual referent, the term would just fail to refer in other worlds. And obviously, the metaphysics (1)-(5) characterize could never get off the ground. Put simply, MRD presupposes mind-independent crossworld identity, and with a wholly restrictive ontology, this supposition is false.

Despite this obvious incompatibility of a wholly restrictive ontol- ogy with the new metaphysics, it is worth noting. For if MRD also cannot abide a permissive ontology, then the defender of MRD can- not just defend a restrictive (as opposed to a permissive) ontology, but further, this defense cannot lead back to extreme restrictivism. The metaphysical understanding of rigidity requires a privileged, and not merely a restrictive, ontology.

(b) Permissive ontology. Can rigidity be metaphysically determined in a permissively populated world? I shall first consider the rigidity of descriptions, and then apply our findings to the case of names.

As standardly discussed, descriptions may be used either rigidly or nonrigidly. If 'The President of the U.S.' refers through sense, it will denote Bush nonrigidly; if it refers counterfactually through iden- tity, it rigidly designates Bush. But now suppose we allow Prez in our ontology. Referring through sense will no longer suffice for 'The President of the U.S.' to be nonrigid, for in virtue of its descriptive content, it can pick out Prez just as well as Bush, and if it picks out Prez, it does so in every possible world-for Prez is in every world and always the President of the United States. Indeed, one might think that Prez, if it exists, is the more natural referent of 'The President of the U.S.', so on a permissive ontology, every definite description, if used to refer through sense, threatens to be rigid de facto. For now, though, all that matters is that on a permissive ontol- ogy, descriptions used to refer through sense, without further speci- fication, are indeterminate between rigidly denoting unusual enti- ties, and nonrigidly denoting the particulars that constitute them at a given time.'9

On the other side of the coin, using our description to refer counterfactually through identity leaves it open whether the value of 'The President of the U.S.' in other worlds is Bush or Prez. For again, without further specification, they have equal claim to be the

19 This is not to say such descriptions would always be indeterminate-only that when they are not, it is not just in virtue of intending to refer counterfactually through sense.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

420 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

actual referent of the description, but, of course, they determine different referents in other worlds. To designate Bush rigidly with this description, it will not suffice simply to intend to refer counter- factually through identity.

In both cases, a permissive ontology threatens the determinacy of reference. In the case of referring through sense, this appears as a puzzle about how we can manage to use descriptions nonrigidly; in the case of referring through identity, the problem is determining which of (at least) two things is rigidly designated. Whereas on a wholly restrictive ontology, there are too few mind-independent crossworld identities (i.e., none) for MRD, on a permissive ontology, there are too many. MRD presupposes not only that there are some identities, but, since it asserts that counterfactual reference is deter- mined simply by the fact that some object in another world is identi- cal to the actual referent, that it is possible to refer determinately to some actual object in a way that allows this.

Now, it is possible to get determinate reference even within a permissive ontology. Since the objects the reference hovers between differ in their identity conditions, we can determine reference to one of them by intending to refer to the object with such-and-such identity conditions. Unfortunately for MRD, this is not a way to secure reference which just lets the "facts of identity" determine counterfactual reference-for here, this reference is determined semantically, not metaphysically: the counterfactual referent is whatever satisfies the intended conditions. By associating identity conditions with uses of expressions, we can also make out, despite the above problems, how there can be nonrigid uses of descriptions, even with a permissive ontology. This will be explained in section VI.

It should be clear that these same problems apply when we turn to names. On the standard view, we get a referent for a name-via ostension or description-and then let this referent guide counter- factual reference. Clearly, when a name is introduced by a descrip- tion, our position is just as found above for the rigid use of descrip- tions-simply intending the facts of identity to determine counter- factual reference underdetermines such reference. But the same holds true for more purely ostensive introductions of names. Within a permissive ontology, wherever we point, there are too many over- lapping entities to which we may be referring, entities which differ in their identity conditions and modal properties. Until we specify what is to count as the same thing, we have no determinate refer- ence to any one thing at all. Of course, we do achieve determinate reference with, say, 'Bush'. But this leaves completely open how this

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

RIGIDITY 421

occurs. The argument is not that 'Bush' cannot be determinate and rigid, but only that for it to be so, it must have more semantic content than just its referent. So again, there is no way to let the thing-the referent-determine the counterfactual reference of the name rather than, as in the case of descriptions, the criteria of sameness (identity). For a name to be rigid, it must be associated with a criterion of identity across worlds, and this then serves as the criterion of application for the name. While there can be rigidity, MRD again fails.

To sum up, MRD involves two presuppositions: first, that there are mind-independent facts of crossworld identity; and, second, that we can get determinate reference in the actual world in a way that allows these facts of identity to determine reference in other worlds. On a wholly restrictive ontology, the first (and maybe the second) is false; and on a permissive ontology, the second is false. Both suppo- sitions can be satisfied only within a privileged ontology; conse- quently, MRD, and the philosophical picture that requires it, re- quire such an ontology. Some who accept these views may be happy with this consequence-but the burden is on these "new" metaphy- sicians to defend this ontology. They cannot just say, "Well, since it is entailed by our position it is as well supported as the rest of our view." For the principle evidence for the view starts from our intu- itions about rigidity, and as we have seen, it is not these data them- selves, but their metaphysical interpretation that is the cornerstone of the new view. Since this interpretation presupposes a privileged ontology, one is not entitled to it, or what one thinks flows from it, without first defending the ontology. But one might think this de- fense need not be wholly independent. Perhaps our judgments of rigidity themselves support a privileged ontology. I shall argue in the next section that this is not so.

V. DO OUR DIFFERENTIAL JUDGMENTS OF RIGIDITY SUPPORT A PRIVILEGED ONTOLOGY?

To get people to see the rigid/nonrigid distinction, we ask similar questions about different terms. If we look at counterfactuals using the name 'Nixon', it seems that all are used to talk about "this man"-the same one we speak of in actual situations. On the other hand, if we look at 'The President of the United States', it seems that, in other worlds, it may pick out someone else. Asked, of all the counterfactual referents of this expression, if they are the same, we naturally say "no." In saying no, we assert a nonidentity, and it is a short step from here to supposing that there is no such entity as "The President of the United States." At least, if we accepted a

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

422 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

permissive ontology, would we not be likely to say that 'The Presi- dent of the U.S.' was rigid, that its referents were identical? And if we were restrictivists, would we not deny that 'Nixon' was rigid, that its referents are identical?

Thus, our common judgments of rigidity and nonrigidity might be thought to lend support to a privileged ontology, or at least show that most people accept this ontology. And one might think this at least puts the burden of proof onto the view's opponents.

This argument from our differential judgments about rigidity to a privileged ontology is problematic. I do not think our judgments support the claim that we do accept such an ontology, must less the claim that we should. For one thing, if one were to ask people who make the familiar judgments about nonrigidity whether or not they thought, say, that "The President of the U.S." existed, I think many of them would at least admit that they had no special reason for denying this. "Sure, why not?" would be a common response, I am guessing. They need not be thinking of such entities when the ques- tions of rigidity are raised; one may need to ask explicitly. This might lead them to reconsider their earlier judgments that 'The President of the U.S.' is not rigid, in which case the "phenomena" might vanish. But they need not. One may think that while "The President of the U.S." populates the universe, it is not the referent of many (or any) uses of 'The President of the U.S.' That 'The President of the U.S.' does not always have the same referent-or that we do not think it does-is immediately just a fact about what we are referring to-not what there is (or is not). In section VI, I provide an account of how this description could be used nonrigidly (and rigidly) to denote particular people, even if there were "The President." So judgments of nonrigidity, of themselves, can hardly show that we are committed to a privileged ontology. Further, and perhaps more im- portantly, I think we can give a plausible reason why people would make the nonrigidity judgments they do even if, on reflection, they were the firmest of permissive ontologists (or, suitably modified, the firmest of extreme restrictivists).

The questions we ask when attempting to decide whether a term is rigid or not are not in any obvious way questions about what entities exist. Generally, they are identity questions, e.g., 'Is the same entity present in all relevant situations'? Or 'Is the referent of the term in all worlds the same'? So it should be no surprise, first off, if these inquiries do not pique people's ontological sensibilities. This point is highlighted by other philosophically familiar uses of variables like 'thing', 'object', and 'entity'. Asked flat out, it is familiar that ques- tions and statements involving such variables are deeply ambiguous.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

RIGIDITY 423

'How many things are there on the table'? asked of a table contain- ing a deck of cards, may legitimately receive a number of answers, most obviously 'one'-a deck of cards or 'fifty-two'-cards; or who- knows-how-many combined cards, numbers, spots, etc. These an- swers require no special permissiveness in one's ontology-we all recognize cards and decks as among the world's occupants. But still, to get a definite answer-or ask a definite question-we need some- thing more specific than 'thing'. Interestingly, we use such general terms all the time, successfully and without problem. Particles of dust and cookie crumbs, for instance, are understood not to be counted when one asks 'How many things are there on the table'? This question ordinarily means, roughly, 'How many medium-sized dry goods are on the table'? My not counting cookie crumbs in no way shows that I doubt their existence or status as "things." When we use these most general terms, we have more or less agreed upon "default settings" that specify more particularly the type of thing in which we are interested. We may have different defaults for differ- ent contexts and, certainly, one can specify directly at any time. The important point is that we need not verbally explicitly do so. And because these pragmatic factors can be tacit, our ordinary intuitions about these things hardly show much about our ontology.

Given that we have such conventions, or conversational customs, concerning these most general terms, it is not hard to see how they might enter into our investigations concerning rigidity. Indeed, we need not bring in "The President of the U.S.," and the like, to see that they do. Consider our question of whether the same entity is present in any situation relevant to 'George Bush is necessarily male'. Nobody even thinks to say "Well, there is one collection of molecules the instantiation of maleness of which is actually rele- vant, but in other worlds, there are different such collections." There is no denial implied here of the ontological "thingness" of these collections-they are entities, all right-it is just supposed that we are talking about medium-sized dry goods like the man, George Bush.

Just so, I think it is with our nonrigid inquiries. Consider the reading of 'The President of the U.S. need not be male' which we defend by pointing to a world in which Elizabeth Dole is the Presi- dent. When asked whether this use is rigid-Does the same entity figure in all the relevant situations?-we answer "No," since it is Bush who is relevant in the actual world, and Libby Dole in the world that proves the claim. Does this mean we accept, or would accept if asked, a privileged ontology in which "The President of the U.S." does not appear? No more, I think, than ignoring the cookie

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

424 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

crumbs when counting the things on the table implies a similar re- jection of cookie crumbs. In the context, we naturally interpret the question as 'Does the same person always appear'?-indeed, in prac- tice, the discussion often takes place in these terms: 'The referent is not always the same person'. And to this, the answer is clear. This is also why collections of molecules do not figure in our intuitive rea- soning. (The question of rigidity, however, hinges on sameness of entity; so this finding, however clear, does not even suffice to show that in this sentence the expression is used nonrigidly, much less that a restrictive ontology is indicated.) Thus, I am not at all con- vinced that the fact that people can be led so easily to recognize definite descriptions as nonrigid shows that, at any level, they accept a privileged ontology. It only shows that we are accustomed to speak of a certain subclass of entities-even to the exclusion of other entities that we clearly do recognize.

These reflections upon why we should not make too much onto- logical hay of our ordinary judgments of rigidity-or other judg- ments that may play on our "default" settings for general variables -also help explain why we are so naturally led to a metaphysical interpretation of rigidity and, ultimately, to the new metaphysics. Our ordinary practices-our "default" settings-have us speak, and perhaps believe, "as if" we accepted a privileged ontology. Un- less these conventions are somehow flagged, we make our judg- ments within these practices, and may, without realizing it, incur more blatantly metaphysical commitments-in this case, to a privi- leged ontology.

Now, part of the great elegance and beauty of Kripke's work- especially his discussion of rigidity-is that we are explicitly asked not to "think as philosophers," but to offer our common-sense judgments about how we use names and descriptions. Thus, in get- ting us to see the rigid/nonrigid distinction, and that names, but not all descriptions, are rigid, no "metaphysical flags" are raised. One would have to be predisposed toward ontological axe-grinding to think at that point that the question 'Does "The President of the U.S." always refer to the same thing'? was a "loaded" question. We have not yet incurred a privileged ontology, but our attention is firmly fixed on "usual" entities (people), and not at all on "deeper" ontological questions. As we move on to the metaphysics, and wonder how rigid expressions work, we still avoid the relevant sort of metaphysical flags. Names, we are told, are introduced by osten- sion or description, and are then used rigidly for 'that thing' -what- ever we have ostended or described; ditto for rigidly used descrip-

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

RIGIDITY 425

tions. Now, if we are on our ontological guard, we may at this point complain that ostension or simple description will not suffice to pick out (determinately) a single, modally extended object. But there is no indication yet, nothing really to warn us, that we should be on such guard. Ostension is a perfectly normal practice; we know how, without needing to make a fuss, to identify 'that thing'. This could be because we accept a privileged ontology, but it could as easily be because we have default settings here which we use all the time- without, again, even noticing it. And by now, without having had to confront explicitly any metaphysical questions-just working uncriti- cally within ordinary linguistic practices-we are positioned to start asking modal questions about 'this guy', or whatever our object of reference may be. Without needing to worry about how we have done it, we see ourselves latched onto an object of reference, and ready to ask what its possibilities are. And if the semantic structure of referring expressions is as I shall suggest, we shall find necessary a posteriori truths. If I am right, these truths depend, for their modal status, on our conventions, on conditions we "in default" associate with the expressions. But there is no reason within the inquiry for it ever to occur to us that this might be the case. Once we are onto the rigid/nonrigid distinction, our attention is firmly focused upon ob- jects, not language.

Thus, even if our referring expressions have the sort of semantic structure I suggest, it is perfectly simple and natural for us to go from the initial presentation of the rigid/nonrigid distinction all the way through to (1)-(5) without ever having to reflect upon our ontol- ogy, to address explicitly the question of restrictivism, privileged ontology, and permissivism. But since in our ordinary practice we speak "as if" we accepted a privileged ontology (whether we do or not), it is no big surprise that we can wind up in the position I have urged a defender of (1)-(5) is in-that of really being committed to a privileged ontology. The "as if' character of the linguistic prac- tices combines with the absence of metaphysical flags raised during the investigation, so we in effect assume a privileged ontology in our interpretation of rigidity, and feel unproblematically determinately focused on "usual" modally extended entities.20

Behaving and speaking as if something is true may not amount to assuming or presupposing it. But when this is used-without argu- ments for its truth-in arguments which explicitly commit us to the

20 Of course, some may explicitly accept a privileged ontology beforehand. But the ontology still drives the metaphysics, and requires independent defense for the new metaphysics to stand.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

426 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

view in question, it may more fairly be said that we have presup- posed, or accepted a commitment to it in the course of the argument -and not just as a result of our conclusion. This is what I mean by saying that a privileged ontology is assumed or presupposed in the acceptance of MRD and (1)-(5), and why I am inclined to say that a defense of a privileged ontology is required not only because it is a commitment of MRD and (1)-(5), but because its prior (tacit) accep- tance led to these positions.

The new metaphysics has "seemed" to arise out of mostly linguis- tic considerations. But it has in fact arisen out of prior acceptance of a privileged ontology disguised in linguistic garb. This metaphysical view needs to be evaluated against its competitors with its own face. Privileged ontology is not a commitment of the new metaphysics-it is the new metaphysics. And whatever arguments may be available in their support, the phenomena of rigidity are not among them.

VI. SKETCH OF A SEMANTIC ACCOUNT OF RIGIDITY

I conclude with a sketch of an ontologically neutral account of rigid- ity, which I shall call a semantic account, to contrast it with the metaphysical account we have been considering. It is semantic in that counterfactual reference and rigidity (or not) are determined, more or less (see fn. 26), by conditions analytically associated with referring expressions; so if this account is correct, MRD is false, undermining (1)-(5), and the metaphysical view expressed therein. Aside from seeing how these phenomena can occur within nonprivi- leged ontologies, I hope it will be welcome just to see a semantic treatment presented, as the metaphysical one is usually just assumed.

We begin by considering how there could be determinacy of rigid reference with a permissive ontology, starting again with descrip- tions. Earlier, we saw that on such an ontology, we would need to associate criteria of identity with 'The President of the U.S.' for it to determinately refer to either Bush or Prez, since its "surface" con- tent applies equally to both. If we also allow such associated criteria to determine the reference of the description in other worlds, then we have both determinate actual reference, and rigidity as well. For the description then applies, in any world, to whatever satisfies the criterion of identity-and, so, to that which is identical to the actual referent-in that world. Determinacy and rigidity are handled in one fell swoop. As we noted, this has the consequence that counter- factual reference is determined by semantic conditions associated with the term, not just by 'identity with the actual referent'-for we do not have an actual referent until we have settled on identity conditions. But we are not here concerned to preserve MRD; in-

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

RIGIDITY 427

deed, our semantic account is supposed to highlight how MRD can fail to be the correct account of rigidity, and how it does fail in nonprivileged ontologies.

One might think that, if we fail to associate the criterion of iden- tity for persons with 'The President of the U.S.', the description is not rigid, but refers nonrigidly to Bush. This, however, ignores the fact that, on our specification, 'being President' is associated as a criterion of identity (not just of application), so the referent is Prez, even in worlds where Libby Dole is the President (and so we have rigidity). A more serious worry is that it may now seem impossible- as we earlier worried it might be-to have nonrigid descriptions. If determinacy of reference requires that we associate a criterion of identity with a description, and this criterion determines its counter- factual application, the referents will always be identical, so all de- scriptions will be rigid. The only question is which entity it rigidly designates.

The supposition that an associated criterion of identity must also serve as the counterfactual criterion of application for a term is mistaken. While this is typical as such matters are usually discussed, there is no reason why we might not associate, with a single expres- sion, one condition as the criterion of identity, and a different one as its criterion of counterfactual application. The two, after all, per- form different functions. Criteria of identity tell us under what con- ditions we have the same object as the actual referent. Criteria of application tell us under what conditions the expression in question applies in another world. I suggest that we need to distinguish the two carefully, and that descriptions (and ultimately, all referring expressions) need to be associated with both criteria of application for other worlds and criteria of identity.

Criteria of identity serve not (of themselves) to determine coun- terfactual reference, but actual reference (by distinguishing among the candidates satisfying the "surface" criteria of application, e.g., 'is the President'); criteria of application determine counterfactual reference. When these are the same, as we have seen, the descrip- tions will be rigid-even when the criterion of identity is "un- usual."2' But the criteria need not be the same; we can associate the identity conditions for people with 'The President'-making Bush the actual referent-while using the familiar descriptive content as our criterion of counterfactual application. This results in-and is, I suggest, how we get-nonrigid descriptions: that to which the ex-

21 Actually, it is enough if the criteria entail each other. This may be a better picture of the rigidity of complex expressions for numbers.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

428 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

pression applies in a world can differ from that which satisfies the criterion of identity.22

The associated criteria need not be explicitly formulated. Typi- cally, we recover them from the sorts of counterfactual situations one counts for or against one's statements using these descriptions. As we may postulate an intention to refer rigidly, and so, at least implicitly, through identity, when someone does not count the possi- bility of a Libby Dole election against their utterance of 'The Presi- dent could not have been a woman', so we may postulate a more detailed intention if this is needed to get the reference of their expression to be Bush, rather than Prez. Similarly, our judgments of nonrigidity show that we intend the counterfactual application of the term to be given by conditions other than the criterion of iden- tity (though criteria of identity still need to be associated to make the actual referent Bush rather than Prez), and license a similar postu- lation.

Here is a representation of the semantics of descriptions ('CA' = criterion of application; 'CI' = criterion of identity; '@' stands for the actual world; 'wa' for other worlds; '(v) ' stands for the value of conditions ' ') [this is a first approximation]:

(1) Rigid descriptions (normal) (e.g., 'The President' rigidly designat- ing Bush):23

CA@ = Being the President (one might spell this out further) CAwn = (say) Having the same origin (in wn) as (v)CA@ CI = Having the same origin as (v)CA@

(2) Rigid descriptions (unusual) (e.g., 'The President' rigidly designat- ing Prez)

CA@ = Being the President CAwn = Being the President CI = Being the President24

(3) Nonrigid descriptions ('The President' refers nonrigidly to Bush) CA@ = Being the President CAwn = Being the President CI = (say) Having the same origin as (v)CA@

22 The question of why we might ever give these criteria different conditions is an interesting one, and there are interesting things to be said about why in prac- tice philosophers tend to run them together, but space limitations preclude a fuller discussion here.

23 If (as I think) Keith Donnellan's distinction is genuinely semantic, the actual criteria for "referential" descriptions would be given not by the "straight" con- tent of the description, but by causal conditions (see the account of names below), or some other "intended" content.

24 I realize this does not really have the normal form of a criterion of identity- 'x bears R to y'. The sort of criteria of identity entities like Prez have allow them to be specified nonrelationally.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

RIGIDITY 429

The "surface" sense of a description gives the parameters of the actual conditions of application, the criteria of application for other worlds say what conditions something must meet in another world to be the referent of the expression in that world, and the criteria of identity specify the conditions something in another world must meet to be identical to the actual referent-and thus also determine the actual referent.25 Note that on the usual treatment, we would fill in 'CI', for rigid descriptions, with "Being identical to the actual value of the description." But in a permissive ontology, this will not suffice-for it is not determined whether it is identity with Bush or Prez that is indicated. The identity conditions must at least be speci- fied according to the kind of thing in question, if not more finely.26

In normal rigid descriptions, we let the criteria of identity serve to determine the counterfactual criteria of application. This is the ker- nel of truth, in a permissive ontology, in the idea that we can refer through identity: we can refer through criteria of identity, so it is "built in" semantically that the expression has the same reference in all worlds. To this extent, descriptions can be rigid de jure (see fn. 13).27 But since descriptive conditions, rather than the metaphysics of identity determine the reference, MRD fails here.

This, in brief sketch, gives our semantic account of rigidity. The rules of reference, for both rigid and nonrigid descriptions, are

25 Criteria of counterfactual application mentioning (v)CA@ do not quite just plug in the actual value of the descriptions (for the CA@ do not of themselves determine an actual value), but are more like functions from the "actual" content and identity conditions to objects in other worlds-and the criteria for the actual world may be seen either as providing ambiguous actual reference, or better (at least usually), as functions from "surface" content and criteria of identity to a referent. This is why the above sketch is a "first approximation." Criteria of identity could thus be considered as part of the criteria of actual application, but it is useful to distinguish their contributions. Note that criteria of identity play the same role in getting determinate reference in other worlds. In theory, there is room for distinct criteria of identity for the actual and counterfactual referents (when CAwn is not given by CI). But I am not aware of any expressions that actually function this way.

26 I mean here to reemphasize that the criteria need not fully specify the fea- tures counterfactual referents of rigid terms must have (see fn. 7)-(1) above leaves open what the origin is, and so what it is in other worlds (though not that it is the same in all worlds)-thus allowing for necessary a posteriori truths ('Bush's origin is '). But it would be misleading to speak of this as the empirical discovery of essence, for what is empirical is just the value of parameters, the essentiality of which is set by the language, and a priori.

27 Within this framework, then, the de jure/de facto distinction becomes blurred, or imperspicuous. If we identify rigid dejure expressions as those which are descriptionless, as in MRD, then there are no such expressions. If we require only that rigidity be semantically built in, there is really no rigidity de facto. Perhaps the intuitive distinction divides terms where the criteria are the same from those which imply each other.

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

430 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

given semantically, not metaphysically. Because of this, the account can also work within a restrictive ontology. In this case, one might say that it is not the metaphysics of identity which determine the counterfactual referents of rigid terms, but rather, the semantics of rigidity which determine what is to count as identical across worlds. And while in a privileged ontology, rigidity can be determined meta- physically, there is nothing to rule out the semantic story being just as I have outlined it. Thus, the semantic account of rigid designation is neutral with respect to our three "worldviews," while the "meta- physical" account can work only within a privileged ontology. This, I believe, provides some ground to prefer my treatment whatever one's metaphysics-for while the metaphysical questions are mat- ters for dispute, it hardly seems a real matter of dispute whether we can and do use expressions rigidly.

Finally, back to names. For a name to be rigid, it must be asso- ciated with a criterion of identity across worlds, and this then serves as the criterion of application for the name, viz:

(4) Names ('Bush'): CA@ = Description/ostension/causal relation CAwn = Whatever satisfies Cl in wn CI = (say) Having the same origin as (v)CA@

Names, then, like rigid descriptions, are rigid not by lacking descrip- tive content, but because their criteria of application are the same as (given by) their associated criteria of identity. This allows us, in theory anyway, to identify a possible nonrigid use of names in which these two are separated ('Superman' or 'Mr. President' are possible examples). We may think of such names as disguised descriptions; the point is just that nothing prevents "ordinary names"-linguistic items with no surface syntactic or semantic structure-being non- rigid. We simply do not ordinarily so use them.

To restate my main contention: once we distinguish the phenome- non of rigidity from its metaphysical interpretation, and see that the latter hinges on just the metaphysical view the phenomena are thought to support, we can refocus the debate at the metaphysical level, where it belongs. The "new essentialism" is nothing more nor less than advocacy of a privileged ontology, and needs to be de- fended as such-as a metaphysical view that neither flows from nor is supported by the fact that some, but not all expressions are rigid. By now, it is probably clear that I am rather skeptical about the possibility of a successful defense of this view. But arguments await another occasion.

ALAN SIDELLE University of Wisconsin/Madison

This content downloaded from 109.124.179.166 on Sat, 28 Jun 2014 22:34:17 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions